The Refutation of Callicles in Plato’s ’Gorgias’
George Klosko
Greece & Rome, Second Series, Volume 31, Issue 2 (Oct., 1984), 126-139.
Stable URL:
htp://links jstor.org/sici2sict=0017-3835% 28 1984 10%292%3 31% 3A2%3C 126%%3ATROCIPS%3E2.0,COW3B2-4
‘Your use of the ISTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR’s Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
hhup:/www.jstor org/about/terms.html. JSTOR’s Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you
have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and
you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.
Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the sereen or
printed page of such transmission.
Greece & Rome is published by The Classical Association. Please contact the publisher for further permissions
regarding the use of this work, Publisher contact information may be obtained at
hutp:/www jstor.org/journals/classieal html
Greece & Rome
(©1984 The Classical Association
ISTOR and the ISTOR logo are trademarks of ISTOR, and are Registered in the U.S. Patent and Trademark Office
For more information on ISTOR contact
[email protected],
(©2003 JSTOR
upswww jstor.org/
‘Tue Apr 22. 09:45:44 2003Greece & Rome, Vol. XXXI, No, 2, Otaber 1988
THE REFUTATION OF CALLICLES IN PLATO’S GORGIAS
By GEORGE KLOSKO
In a well-known article appearing in 1967, E. L. Harrison examines
Plato's manipulation of Thrasymachos in the first book of the Republic.
Harrison looks into certain peculiarities in the argument between
‘Thrasymachos and Socrates and explores motives that may have led
Plato to have Thrasymachos develop his doctrine in this particular
fashion.’ Though Harrison’s conclusions are widely discussed and
frequently accepted,” it strikes me as interesting that little scholarly
attention has been focussed on equally striking features of the debate
between Socrates and Callicles in the Gorgias. For I believe it can be
shown that Plato’s presentation of Callicles contains numerous
peculiarities of its own, that the powerful, vigorously argued doctrine
of immoralism enunciated by Callicles in a celebrated portion of the
dialogue is actually infected with glaring weaknesses. I do not believe
that these weaknesses have been satisfactorily accounted for, nor has the
possibility been explored that Plato could have put them there inten-
tionally.’ The purpose of this paper, then, is threefold: (a) to examine
the nature of these flaws in Callicles” position; (b) to demonstrate their
apparently odd and gratuitous character; and (c) to explore possible
reasons Plato may have had for incorporating them into his presentation
of Callicles in the Gorgias.
1
‘What Callicles is best known for is the moral position advanced in his
great speech at Gorgias 482c486d. The speech is composed of three
parts: a statement of Callicles’ ethical views; then a description of his,
opinion of the limited usefulness of an education in philosophy; and
finally an exhortation for Socrates to give up his life dedicated to
philosophy, in order to follow more practical pursuits. In this paper I
will be concerned with only the first portion of Callicles’ speech, the
doctrine of immoralism presented in 482c484c. But equally important,
I will examine the arguments that Socrates brings forward at the close
of his speech in order to overthrow and refute him. What is of special
interest is the series of modifications and transformations Callicles is
forced to make in order to withstand Socrates’ dialectical assault. I
believe it will be seen that some of these are uncalled for, while the
specific form that particular ones take should most probably be viewed
as nothing less than Plato’s sabotage of Callicles.
The heart of Callicles’ doctrine of immoralism is presented in the‘THE REFUTATION OF CALLICLES IN PLATO'S GORGIAS. im
incomparably vigorous passage from 483b~484c. Callicles begins by
making the well-known distinction between ‘nature’ and ‘convention’
(physis and nomos). He argues that the predominance of existing moral
customs and conventions (and the political laws as well, which are also
included under the term nomoi) are not rooted in ‘nature’ but are the
result of agreements, compacts, made by the weaker and inferior mem-
bers of society in order to promote their own interests. Anticipating the
claims of Nietzsche, Callicles accounts for the equality legislated by the
many as arising from ressentiment.* The many, who are naturally weak,
are afraid of being taken advantage of by those stronger than them-
selves, and so call such self-aggrandizement disgraceful and unjust;
they are well content to see themselves treated equally, when they are
actually inferior. According to the morality of nature on the other hand,
the strong should rule over the weak and have more. To substantiate
this view, Callicles cites as natural the way things work in the animal
kingdom and in the arena of international affairs. Finally, he describes
the process through which the many are able to tame and enervate those
who are naturally powerful, and to enthrall them with their talk of
equality, However, when one of these is able to burst the bonds that
hold him, to cast aside conventional laws and norms and to rise from
being held down beneath the many to become their master, ‘there
dawns the full light of natural justice’ (484a-b)..
‘Once Callicles has outlined this conception of natural justice,
Socrates attacks it by focussing upon its least clearly developed aspect.
Callicles has used a variety of terms to refer to the ‘powerful’,* and so
Socrates demands clarification.® Callicles is led eventually to reveal the
powerful as ‘those who are wise as regards public affairs and the proper
way of conducting them, and not only wise but manly, with ability to
carry out their purpose to the full, and who will not falter through
softness of soul’ (491b). Strength, then, for Callicles is described as a
special combination of political talents, not unlike Machiavelli's virtw.
Socrates begins his attack on Callicles’ revised position by shifting
from the question of how according to natural justice the powerful will
rule over others to whether they will rule over themselves. Socrates
raises this question with a suddenness that causes most commentators
to take notice. But more surprising than this shift in Socrates’ line of
enguiry is the nature of Callicles’ response.
In attempting to reply, Callicles has trouble understanding what
Socrates means by ‘one who rules himself. Socrates explicates this as
‘merely what most people mean’, one who is temperate and master of
his pleasures and desires (491d-e). Given this description of self-
mastery, it is not surprising that Callicles rejects it; he sees temperance
as merely another form of the subordination of physis to nomos, ofbs ‘THE REFUTATION OF CALLICLES IN PLATO'S GORGIAS
natural morality to the morality of the many. Callicles makes this case
in a second highly impressive speech (491¢-492c), which we will
examine. But what is important to note here is that Callicles does more
than reject the temperance of the many; he rejects the restraint of desire
altogether. This is the first of a series of such apparently gratuitous
overstatements on Callicles’ part. Needless to say, insofar as his dialec-
tical confrontation with Socrates is concerned, these responses are not
only uncalled for but unwise. They present openings which Socrates is
only too happy to exploit.
Callicles’ speech here contains three basic points. First, he rejects the
notion of temperance entirely. A man cannot be happy if he is a slave
to anyone including himself. Thus it is just and noble according to
nature (to kata physin kalon kai dikaion) to allow one’s appetites to grow
as strong as possible and not to restrain them, provided one has the
wherewithal to be able to satisfy them when they are at their height.
According to Callicles’ second point, which recalls the thrust of his
original speech, the many do not have the means to satisfy developed
appetites. Thus, out of resentment, they legislate their impotence into
‘moral law in the form of temperance. They call licentiousness ignoble,
and so enslave the better type of men, as Callicles had said earlier.
Finally, in his third point, Callicles declares his contempt for those
fortunate enough to be able to rise above temperance and justice but
who do not do so. The examples he mentions are possessors of political
power. He says that for those with absolute power to be bridled by ‘the
law, the talk, and the rebuke of the multitude’ would be disgraceful and
unjust. For according to genuine morality: ‘luxury and licentiousness
and liberty, if they have the support of force, are virtue and happiness,
and the rest of these embellishments ~ the unnatural convenants of
mankind — are all mere stuff and nonsense’ (492c). We turn now to the
implications of Callicles’ position.
1
Though much of what Callicles says in his account of temperance is,
consistent with his earlier arguments and also tactically to his advan-
tage, I think it is clear that he also makes some rash and damaging
statements, which we will examine in detail. However, before proceed-
ing, it is perhaps advisable to say something about the status of the
claims that will be made below.
I think it should be made clear from the outset that in the following
pages I am in no way attempting to unearth Callicles’ ‘true position’,
‘The Callicles of the Gorgias is Plato’s character and the only positions
he espouses are those Plato has put into his mouth. If Plato wishes for
him to give voice to some foolish arguments, there is little the commen-‘THE REFUTATION OF CALLICLES IN PLATO'S GORGLAS ne
tator can do but report them. However, I think it is also important to
indicate exactly where Callicles goes wrong. I think it can be seen that
his major problems stem from errors of exaggeration and overstate-
ment, and by toning these down in apparently slight and undramatic
ways, he would be able to modify his position in fundamental respects,
with the result being a view that is no easy prey for Socrates’ refutations.
By looking at some of these possible modifications, we will be able to
see how unfortunate the direction in which Callicles chooses to go really
is, In the next section we will also enquire into possible reasons Plato
may have had for having Callicles develop his arguments as he does.
Returning to Callicles’ speech, we have noted that the position to
which he commits himself on the question of temperance is the rejection
of all restraint of desire. He says that the powerful man should let his
desires grow ‘as strong as possible’ (hs megistas, 491e9; and 492d6-7),
as long as he possesses the resources to minister to them. His meaning
becomes fully clear in subsequent exchanges, when he says that his
conception of the happy life involves having and satisfying hunger and
thirst ‘and all the other desires’ (tas allas epithumias hapasas, 494b-c)
= an ‘all’ which both he and Socrates take literally.
‘Admissions such as these are by no means inadvertent on Callicles’
part, and under Socrates’ questioning he assents to a number of
similarly extreme propositions. Callicles’ overall moral view is nowhere
explicitly set forth in his exchanges with Socrates, and it is not possible
to reconstruct its precise logical structure, But a broad outline of it is
something along the following lines.
Callicles is a hedonist. He has a view of pleasure to back up his view
of temperance. When Socrates asks him if someone who has many
appetites which he must constantly strive to satisfy, does not find
himself in a painful state, Callicles replies that someone who is no longer
in need, who has taken his fill once and for all, no longer experiences
the pleasure that accompanies the satisfaction of appetites. Making the
assumption that the satisfaction of appetites gives pleasure (see 494a),
Callicles argues that having large appetites is necessary for the enjoy-
ment of great pleasures. He states this too in an exaggerated form. He
declares that a pleasant life consists in ‘the largest possible’ (ids pleiston)
amount of inflow (494b). Basing his position on the further assumption
that pleasure is good — and is in fact identical with good” — Callicles is
not able to differentiate between good and bad pleasures (495a, 495d).
Because he believes that pleasure comes from the satisfaction of
appetites, he is logically committed to the view that the satisfaction of
ail appetites is good (494c). Accordingly, he believes that the strong
man’s appetites should be allowed to grow as strongly as possible.
Callicles’ views justify his rejection of any restraint of appetite. By130 ‘THE REFUTATION OF CALLICLES IN PLATO'S GORGIAS.
restraining any desire whatsoever, the powerful individual would be
depriving himself of a source of pleasure.
‘Thus when Callicles’ view is brought to its conclusion, it is seen to
be an exaggerated form of hedonism. Callicles is allowed to make no
distinctions between pleasures; his strong man is committed to a cease-
less quest for every and all forms of pleasure. This is of course an
extreme position, and unfortunately for Callicles, because he has com-
mitted himself to it the striking and provocative immoralism enunciated
in his original speech is able to be brushed aside, and Socrates is able
to deal with him as simply a radical - and somewhat simpleminded —
hedonist.
Given the nature of the position Callicles now occupies, it is not
surprising that Socrates is able to crush him with a series of dialectical
arguments (495e-499b). These need not be examined here,* but it is
important to note that the target of Socrates’ attack is Callicles’ identifi-
cation of pleasure and the good. By 499b this position is overthrown.
Callicles is forced to admit that some pleasures are bad, and so that the
good and the pleasant are not identical. Having dispensed with
Callicles’ moral position in this way, Socrates is able to goon and devote
the remainder of the Gorgias to developing the outlines of an alternative
view, which prefigures the central political teaching of the Republic.
As should be clear at this point, I believe it is somewhat unfair on
Plato’s part to dismiss Callicles’ immoralism in this fashion. Though
not without inconsistencies and other flaws, it is doubtless a serious
moral position that is worthy of serious consideration. Though
Callicles’ immoralism can no doubt assume a form in which it is closely
connected with hedonism, this connection is by no means necessary,
while even if one were to espouse immoralism in connection with
hedonism, I see no reason why this hedonism should be of the extreme
form advocated by Callicles. Thus I believe that the inexorable process
through which Callicles is led to divulge his deepest convictions is in
actuality anything but inexorable. Callicles is repeatedly induced to
reveal more of his basic assumptions. On each of these occasions he has
the opportunity to offer a variety of responses to Socrates’ questions,
yet each time he makes an unfortunate choice, with the cumulative result
{as we have seen. The most important concessions Callicles makes can be
expressed in the form of propositions to which he commits himself:
(C.1) Any restraint of desire is undesirable for the strong man.
(C.2) The strong man should allow his desires to grow as strong as
possible.
(C.3) The strong man should allow all his desires to grow.
(C.4) The satisfaction of ail desires is pleasant.°
(C5) Pleasure is identical with good.‘THE REFUTATION OF CALLICLES IN PLATO'S GORGLAS 1
It seems to me that by modifying these propositions in some fairly
obvious and commonsensical respects, Callicles would be able to
improve his resulting moral position considerably. For reasons of space,
1 will concentrate on (C.1)-{C.3), which bear more intimate con-
nections with Callicles’ immoralism than the hedonism expressed in
(C4) and (C.5). As Plato has presented Callicles, his adherence to
(C.1)-(C.3) rests on his commitment to (C.4) and (C.5). However, if
(C.1), (C.2), and (C.3) were toned down in some appropriate manner,
(C.4) and (C.5) could be dispensed with, with the resulting moral view
representing a far more defensible position than the one Callicles
actually espouses.
Before proceeding to examine (C.1)-(C.3) in detail, it is necessary
briefly to say something about (C.4) and (C.5). The point to note here,
which is powerful evidence of Plato’s manipulation of Callicles, is the
unsophisticated nature of the hedonism Callicles presents. For it is so
obviously wrongheaded that Callicles himself is presented as not really
adhering to it (495a-c, 499b).
According to Callicles’ hedonism, the satisfaction of all desires is
pleasant and so good. As Socrates points out, Callicles is unable to
distinguish between good and bad pleasures (495a) ~ and so good and
bad desires. What is important to note is that in the Protagoras, which
most scholars believe to predate the Gorgias,4° Plato presents a detailed
account of how good and bad pleasures can be distinguished, and does
so without departing from an overall framework of ethical hedonism.
‘The argument in the Protagoras is based on a crude felicific calculus.
The Socrates of the Protagoras explains how what are ordinarily taken
to be bad pleasures, e.g., eating sweets, are actually unpleasant over the
long run. Eating large quantities of ice cream, for example, might seem
pleasant for the moment, but since it leads to indigestion, tooth decay,
and overweight in the future, it gives more pain than pleasure over the
course of time - which accounts for its bad reputation. Along similar
lines, the good pain, e.g., trip to the dentist, yields more pleasure than
pain over the long run. Callicles’ view, however, is less developed. He
Pays no mind to Bentham’s familiar variables — intensity, duration,
etc.'? Caring only for the brute existence of pleasure, Callicles holds
that the satisfaction of any desire, no matter how fleeting, is pleasant
and good, regardless of consequences. Socrates does not hesitate to
point out the absurdity of this view (494b-e). To go Socrates one better,
Callicles is committed to the view that drinking cyanide is pleasant and
g00d, provided one has a craving for the taste of bitter almonds.
I think it is clear, then, that Callicles’ hedonism is an extremely poor
position, which Plato has foisted on him. Had Plato wished to streng-
then his position, he had only to allow Callicles to use portions of the132 THE REFUTATION OF CALLICLES IN PLATO'S GORGIAS
felicific calculus presented in the Protagoras. But Plato obviously did
not wish to do so, and we will discuss possible reasons for this below.
Returning to (C.1)-(C.3), the connection between Callicles’ posi
on temperance and his immoralism has been seen. Just as he casts aside
the many’s conception of justice as an artificial imposition of nomos
upon physis, so he rejects conventional temperance too as an attempt to
bridle the naturally powerful individual, which is rooted in the weak-
ness of the many. The similarity between conventional temperance and
conventional justice is pointed out in Callicles’ speech (492a-b), and so
in light of his commitment to natural morality, Callicles has sound
reasons for rejecting the restraint of desire advocated by the many.
‘The mistake Callicles makes, however, is rejecting the restraint of
desire altogether. (C.1)is by no means the sole alternative to the many’s
conception of temperance. Any conception of temperance entails two
things: (a) that certain desires must be restrained; and (b) a specification
of which these are, and which other desires should be allowed to grow
and be satisfied. Insofar as the many understand temperance to entail
a specific mode of life, Callicles’ strong man should reject it. The many
live as they do because they have no choice. The strong man, who does
have a choice, would be foolish to settle for the appetites they allow
themselves. Thus the many’s view of permissible appetites should be
rejected. But having rejected this, Callicles has numerous possibilities
as to what to put in its place, and the choice he makes, (C.1), is extremely
poor. An indication of how poor it is is seen in Irwin’s recent attempt
to defend it. In response to the question why anyone who rejects
conventional justice must also accept Callicles’ conception of a good
life, Irwin concludes:
Perhaps Plato believes that someone who rejects nomos and its conception of justice as
awhole can justify himself only by advocating the complete self-indulgence supported
bby Callicles. Plato does not show that Calliles’ ground is the only reasonable ground
for a general criticism of nomos; iis up to Plato's opponent to find a more defensible
around if Callicts i refuted.!®
‘This is notably weak. Rather than pointing out the connections between
Callicles’ views, Irwin (a) suggests that Plato may have believed there
were such connections; (b) says that Plato has not shown them; and (c)
leaves it to some future opponent to discover these and restate Callicles’
case. I think it is clear that Irwin is not able to give a satisfactory
explanation for Callicles’ strategy.
In order to demonstrate just how odd Callicles’ position is, I will
show how easy it is to modify it to make it stronger. The general thrust
of the modifications I have in mind strikes me as so obvious that the
fact that Plato does not have Callicles assume this sort of position seems
to me to require explanation. To begin with, I believe it would be to‘THE REFUTATION OF CALLICLES IN PLATO'S GORGIAS 133
Callicles’ advantage not to espouse (C.1), but rather to choose a some-
what different proposition such as the following, which I construct for
the purpose:
(C.1 mod.) The restraint of desires as prescribed by the many is
undesirable for the strong man.
Though I do not contend that this is the only alternative open to
Callicles, or necessarily the best, (C.1 mod.) seems to me to possess the
advantages of (C.1) without its grievous disadvantages. Similarly, the
exaggerated view of desire presented in (C.2) and (C.3) is gratuitous and
foolish. Callicles believes that, because of their weakness, the many are
forced to restrain numerous desires they would rather indulge. He also
believes that the strong man is in the enviable position of being able to
indulge himself; he can afford to have desires that are stronger than the
many’s and a variety wider than the many’s. But the strong man has no
reason to commit himself to the satisfaction of every conceivable
passion, each of which is brought to its strongest possible state. This
would be merely to substitute the tyranny of (literally) unbridled
passion for the tyranny of conventional morality. Instead, Callicles
could easily choose principles such as these (again constructed for the
present purpose):
(C.2 mod.) The strong man should have desires that are stronger than
those of the many.
(C.3mod.) The strongman should have more desires than the many have.
‘The position represented by these two propositions fits together neatly
with (C.1 mod.), and all three taken together seem to me to accomplish
Callictes’ main end. He believes that pleasure comes from the satisfac-
tion of desire, and that a life filled with great pleasures is worthy of
choice. Accordingly, in (C.1 mod.) he sets aside the strong man’s
limiting himself to the desires permitted by the many. In (C.2 mod.)
and (C.3 mod.) he advocates the strong man’s being equipped with a
large variety of strong desires. Since he has the means to satisfy these,
the strong man will enjoy a life filled with delights. And he will do so
without being forced to give equal time to the hideous desires Socrates
is able to call forth.
It seems to me that if Callicles had responded to Socrates with a
position constructed from these modified propositions, he would have
been far better able to withstand Socrates’ dialectical assault. Moreover,
this strikes me as a plausible position for Callicles because it is able to
fulfil one function that the position he actually assumes is not. Accord-
ing to Socrates, Callicles’ statements concerning desire express what the
rest of the world also thinks but is not willing to say (492d). However,
the rest of the world wants something closer to the modified position
T have sketched than to Callicles’ own.13 ‘THE REFUTATION OF CALLICLES IN PLATO'S GORGIAS
‘A wonderfully clear account of the aspirations of ordinary men is
given by Glaucon in Book 2 of the Republic. Glaucon’s remarks are, of
course, presented in the role of devil’s advocate, attacking justice.
Having described the origin of justice — in a contract for self-protection
not unlike the one Callicles describes in his opening speech - Glaucon
goes on to argue that all men abide by this agreement unwillingly. What
interests us in Glaucon’s presentation here is his description of people’s
desires. He says that people practise justice unwillingly, from want of
power to commit injustice with impunity (Rep. 359b). Had they this,
power, they would behave after the manner of Gyges; each would take
what he wished from the marketplace, have sexual relations with whom-
ever he wished, and slay and loose from bonds whomever he wished
(Rep. 360b-c), Similarly, according to Glaucon, the benefits the per-
fectly unjust man enjoys are success in business, marrying well, and
having his children marry well, good reputation, and the ability to
reward and punish whomever he pleases (Rep. 362b-c). Glaucon says
that anyone having the ability to commit injustice — and reap its rewards
= who refrained from doing so must be mad (mainesthai., Rep. 359b).
‘Thus, according to Glaucon, the happiness that power brings lies in
its giving its holder more of the good things in life. It is important to
note that the goods represented by Glaucon as the objects of people’s
wishes are those commonly regarded as such - money, honour, sexual
pleasure, etc. Glaucon does not say anything about people wishing to
satisfy all their appetites; people simply want more of what satisfies their
existing appetites.'*
One other aspect of Glaucon’s view bears mention. Commentators
have frequently noted that Callicles seems in various ways close to
Plato’s heart. According to these scholars, though Plato doubtless dis-
approves of much of what Callicles stands for, he presents Callicles with
such vividness as to betray a certain sympathy.'’ There clearly are
numerous respects in which Callicles and Plato hold similar views. Like
Callicles, Plato stands opposed to conventional morality and advocates,
in its place the propagation of supremely desirable human qualities —
though of course the qualities he has in mind are different. Plato too
believes that the individuals with these traits, in his case the philoso
phers, should rule. Moreover, in the Republic, not only are the philoso
phers to rule over others inferior to themselves, but the inferior must
be ruled as slaves (Rep. 590c-d). The similarity between Plato and
Callicles breaks down here in that Plato holds that such rule is necessary
in order to benefit the inferior, while Callicles has quite different plans
for the lesser folk. But again the overall nature of his moral position has
these similarities with that of Plato.
‘There is one other possible similarity to which I would call attention,‘THE REFUTATION OF CALLICLES IN PLATO'S GORGIAS Bs
though this is not pursued by Callicles. It seems to me that Callicles
very well could ~ and, I believe, should ~ take his stand upon a certain
conception of moral autonomy. As we have seen, he rejects the choice
of desires recommended by the many, in favour of the indiscriminate
pursuit of all desires. What I think Callicles should stress instead is that,
his way of life allows the strong man to reject the desires advocated by
the many in favour of those he chooses to indulge. This seems to me to
be the sentiment secretly harboured in the many’s hearts, to which
Callicles supposedly gives voice (cf. 492d). As evidence for this, a look
at Glaucon’s view shows that the ring of Gyges gives its possessor the
ability to appropriate what he wishes from the marketplace, to have
sexual relations wich whomever he wishes, and to slay and free whomever
the chooses (Rep. 360b-c). Similarly, according to Polus, the tyrant’s
power is supremely desirable because it allows him to do whatever he
thinks fit in his city (Grg. 466646725 esp. 46722).
That this is similar to one of Plato’s cherished moral ideas is clear.
In the Crito Socrates declares his moral independence as follows (46b):
“Lam not only now but always a man who follows nothing but the logos
which on consideration seems to me best.’ Similarly, I believe Callicles
should emphasize his strong man’s independence. Rather than living as
the multitude dictates, the strong man does as he pleases. He recognizes
no principles higher than those he chooses to follow. And whereas
Socrates’ independence is in the final analysis backed up only by his
willingness to die for his convictions, Callicles’ strong man can exercise
unaccountable power, doing as he pleases, while being safe from the
onslaughts of resentful others.
‘Thus according to the modification of Callicles’ view I have set forth,
the strong man uses his power to get more of life’s goods. He does not
have to settle for the allotments offered by the many. He takes what he
pleases from whomever he pleases and allows his desires to grow, secure
in his ability to satisfy them. Because all his appetites are not given free
rein, he stands immune from Socrates’ initial line of attack (494b-c).
‘The course he chooses is not a plover’s existence, buta life of unexcelled
delights.
Had Callicles chosen this view, Socrates would have had no easy time
refuting him. Socrates’ most obvious line of attack is that such a life
must lead to a chaos of competing, insatiable appetites, as the life of the
democratic man described in Republic 8 inevitably bears fruit in the
hellish condition of the tyrannic man described in Book 9. But this
argument depends upon a number of complex assumptions about the
nature of pleasure and desire that Socrates would have no easy time
proving (on this more below).
‘That a man could live enjoyably giving in to whatever desires he136 THE REFUTATION OF CALLICLES IN PLATO'S GORGIAS
chose is not obviously absurd, while the fact that such a life expresses
the aspirations of the many can only make it more plausible. Portions
of Callicles’ remarks are in fact similar to this view (esp. 492b-c), while
earlier in the Gorgias Polus expresses what is clearly the true state of
affairs when he says that almost nobody would prefer the Socratic
alternative of having wrong done to one to a life of such rewards, no
matter how unjustly earned (471a~474b)."” Thus it is not easy to know
how Socrates could proceed. Through his use of the elenchos, Socrates
is able to refute people in either of two ways. He is able to focus on
inconsistencies in the opinions they hold; or he is able to draw conse-
quences from their views that are otherwise unacceptable, generally
because they seem obviously absurd. '* Callicles would be able to resist.
both strategies. The majority of Socrates’ interlocutors are ignorant
about moral questions and, never having thought seriously about such
matters, can be led to contradict themselves quite easily. Callicles, on
the other hand, has been exposed to a philosophical education (see
485a-c). He has thought about moral questions and has developed his
inctive brand of immoralism. Thus, holding what appears to be a
reasonably consistent moral view, Callicles would not simply stumble
into self-contradiction. Moreover, unlike Gorgias and Polus, who are
unwilling to admit the full implications of their views and so fall into
contradiction out of shame, Callicles has no shame. He is willing to say
what other people think but dare not admit. Pethaps Socrates could
attempt to force Callicles to specify the desires his strong man would
indulge, hoping thereby to show some unfavourable consequences from
these, perhaps that no one who hoped to rule others could at the same
time afford to indulge his appetites. But Callicles could easily resist this
line of attack. It is conventional political wisdom that the successful
ruler must avoid certain passions and excesses that are capable of
bringing him to ruin.*? And someone of the kind Callicles has in mind
—not only knowledgeable about political affairs, but resolute of purpose
and not soft of soul (491b) — would not so indulge. Barring this,
Callicles’ modified position seems strong. To sum up, then, the line of
defence sketched here, which seems to me an obvious one, presents itself
as an attractive alternative to the view Callicles actually chooses and
would seem to cause Socrates formidable dialectical difficulties. I do
not believe we would be amiss in wondering why Callicles does not
pursue it
m1
‘Though most scholars view the different portions of Callicles’ position
as fitting together to form an organic whole,” I think it has been seen
that there is no necessary connection between his immoralism and his‘THE REFUTATION OF CALLICLES IN PLATO'S GORGIAS 137,
views concerning temperance and pleasure. As the weakness of Irwin’s
attempt shows, Callicles’ distinctive brand of hedonism cannot be
justified as necessary to support his immoralism, and so his reason for
holding it must be sought elsewhere, most likely in Plato’s literary
intentions in the Gorgias. Two considerations especially spring to mind,
and I will discuss them briefly, as a conclusion to this paper.
First, I think it is probable that Plato has Callicles develop his views
as he does, in order to enable Socrates to connect up with and elaborate
upon important themes discussed earlier in the Gorgias. As scholars
have long noted, the Gorgias revolves around two different questions:
(@) the nature of rhetoric and its connection with democratic politics;
and (b) the nature of the moral life, i.e., how we should live." The basis,
of Socrates’ definition and criticism of rhetoric in the earlier portions
of the dialogue is that itis a form of ‘flattery’ (kolakeia); itis an inferior
technique, aiming at what is pleasant not what is good. Once Socrates
hhas defined rhetoric in this way, the topic of the dialogue becomes its
value and gradually evolves into a discussion of how men should live.
This, of course, is the topic of discussion between Socrates and Callicles
30 far as we have followed them. The connection with the earlier
portions of the dialogue is established, then, by making Callicles a
hedonist. If rhetoric is an art aiming only at pleasure, the worth of
pleasure must be discussed. And so in criticizing Callicles’ hedonism,
Socrates is able to return to his denunciation of the false politics of a
democratic system, in which the rulers pander to the masses by offering
them what is pleasant, not what is good.
But even more than this it seems to me that Plato reveals Callicles as
an extreme hedonist in order to enable Socrates to deal with hedonism
effectively. It seems clear that, at least through the middle dialogues,
Plato is firmly convinced that ethical hedonism is false. Plato believes
that pleasure is not the good, and he is convinced that a life of physical
pleasure cannot possibly be a happy one.?* In close company with these
beliefs, Plato thinks that physical desire is by its very nature insatiable,
that any attempt to satisfy it must be futile. This belief finds graphic,
mythic expression in the Gorgias, in Socrates’ parables of the water-
carriers and of the leaky jars (493-494a). Accordingly, Plato believes
that insofar as Callicles’ strong man will live a life of physical pleasure,
he is destined for unhappiness. In the terms used earlier in the Gorgias,
his power will give him ‘only what seems best to him’, not ‘what he
actually wishes for’ — what is truly in his interest (see esp. 467b). The
problem, however, is that the Gorgias is not the place to prove all of this.
A proof that a life of physical pleasure is less happy than a just life would
be a long and difficult argument, requiring detailed discussion of
‘numerous complex moral and psychological matters. Even if Plato had138 ‘THE REFUTATION OF CALLICLES IN PLATO'S GORGIAS
all of this supporting material worked out when he wrote the Gorgias,
which is not certain,?* in the Gorgias he has other fish to fry. And so,
in order to allow Socrates to demonstrate the unsatisfactory results of
a life of physical pleasure, Callicles is led to hold an extreme and
indefensible doctrine in support of such a life. A more detailed and
rigorous discussion of the comparative advantages of lives devoted to
physical appetite and to justice must wait until the Republic.
NOTES
1 ‘Plato's Manipulation of Thrasymachus', Phoenix 21 (1967); similarly, J. P. Maguire,
“Theasymachus or Plato”, Phronens 16 (1971),
2. See, e.g Maguire, 142 n. 3;cf. W. K. C. Guthrie, A History of Grek Philwophy (Cam-
bridge, 1962-8i), TIT p- 96.
53 See below n. 20
4. See the Appendix in E. R. Dodds, Pato: Gorpae (Onford, 1959) "Socrates, Calicls, and
Nietrsche
‘5. E,gbeltion, ameindn,ichurotron,hritn; fora bref explication of these, see Dodds,
Gorgias pp. 284-85
(©, Esp, 489c4-7; G. Santas Socrates: Philosphy in Plato's Early Dialogues (London, 1979),
pp. 261-06 is especially good on the argument in 4886-1912
17. See T. Irwin, Plato: Gorgias (Oxford, 1979), pp. 197-200, for as precise an account of,
CCallicle’ hedonism ss can be given.
‘8. They are carefully analysed bs Irwin (Gorgias, pp. 201-8) and Santas (Socrates, pp- 266-86)
and shown tbe fallacious by both.
'9, Imconstructing (Ca), {combine two propositions that pleasure comes from the satisfaction
of desires, and that the strong man should satsy all his desire; both are found in 494.
10, See Dodds, Gorgas, pp. 21-22; Guthrie, Hisory, IV. p. 214; both of these contain
‘numerous futher references fA. E. Taylor, Plato: The Man and His Work, 6th ed. (Cleveland,
1956), p. 235; G. M. A. Grube, Plato’ Though (1935; rp. Boston, 1958), px
11 See Protagoras 333e~3554; on this see C. C.W. Taylor, Plato: Provagoras (Oxford, 1978),
pp. 174-19; ct. Irwin, Gorgas, pp. 196-59,
12. J Bentham, The Principles of Morals and Legislation, Ch. 1V.
15, Tewin, Gorgas, pp. 192-93; se also pp. 196-97; and see below n. 20,
14 Similarly in the Nicomachean Ethics, Aristotle gives the desire for mote ofthe goods men
covet ‘those they pray for and pursue (1120b4) ~ asthe motive for injustice. These goods are
Such things as honour, money, and security (1130432-b5). CE the aspirations sean in Pols!
emarks at Grg. 466 and in those of Thrasymachos at Rep. Sib
15. See, eg, W. Jaeger, Paidea (Oxford, 1939-15), I. 324; J. Skemp, Plato's Statesman
(London, 1952), p. 28.
To, Ta 4obd Burnet changes the generally accepted reading, ou moron mor 0 ou nun proton;
sce his note, law's Euthyphro, Apology of Socrates, and Crito (Oxford, 1928, ad loc. Cl eB
J- Adam, Platonis Grito 2nd ed. (Cambridge, 1891), text and ad le.
7. Cf. Callicles remarks at 4832-6,
18, On the elenchor ree R. Robinson, Plato's Baler Dialectic, nd ed (Oxford, 1953), Ch
n
19, A numberof examples of princes brought down by their passions are collected by Aristotle
fn the Poitier, Bk. 5, Ch, 8; see 131Tb40-1312a14) 1312017-25; ef. 131428-36,
20. See, eg, Jaeger, Paidta I- pp. 140-4; P. Friedlander, Plat (Princeton, 1958-69), 1.
1.262: E. Barker, Greck Political Theory, p. 16. Dodds (Gorgas, p. 291) sees the immoral
{nd view on temperance as linked by oppesiton to conventional morality. Attempts to demonstrate
theconnectionaremadeby Santas Socraresspp 256-57, 206 and Irwin{ Gorgias pp. 192-93,196-97)
(Gee above,p. 132. The difficulty of proving this is cen inthe weakness of Irwin's arguments, Of
‘commentators Ihave consulted, only T. Gomperz, (The Grech Thinkers (London, 1001-12))seems‘THE REFUTATION OF CALLICLES IN PLATO'S GORGIAS 139
fully aware of the arbitrary connections in Callices' position; see 1. pp. 405-75 1. pp. 335,
351-52. Had Gomperz consolidated these findings, he would have come close to the argument of
is paper. The arbitrariness is noted in passing by, e8., Grube (Plato's Thought, 9.50.1) and
Taylor (Plato, p. 116). H- Racder notes the suddenness ofthe sift between immoralism and
temperance, though without noting any dificulies in Callices' doctrine (Platonrphilosphiche
Entachlung (Leipzig, 1905), p. 119)
21. On these see Dodds, Gorgias pp. 1-4
22. AsP. Shorey says one of Plato's fundamental ethical doctrines is the ‘negativity of sensual
pleasure’ (Whar Plato Said (Chicago, 1933), p. 14).
723. There is good evidence that, by the ume he wrote the Gerriay, Plato had developed the
moral prychology of the middle dialogues, For the moral prychology of the early dialopoes, of
"Socrates, sce G. Klosko, “On the Analysis of Prtagora: 351B-360E', Phoonis 34 (1980). For
‘non-Socrtie elements in the Gorgas, see Irwin, Gorgas, on 491d, 4932, 499-5002, 5036-<,
5o7acb. It is argued by many scholars that the peychologicl views presented in the Gorgas are
intended as a direct criticism of the views presented in earlier works; se, eM. Pohlenz, Aus
Platos Werdesit (Berlin, 1913), pp. 156-57.