Mulamadhyamakakarika of Nagarjuna
Mulamadhyamakakarika of Nagarjuna
of
Nagarjuna
THE PHILOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE WAY
DAVID]. KA.LUPAHANA
ISBN: 81-208-0774-x
MOTILAL BANARSIDASS
41 U.A. Bungalow Road, Jawahar Nagar, Delhi 110 007
8 Mahalaxmi C hamoor, Warden Road, Mumbai 400 026
120 Royapettah High Road, Mylapore, Chennai 600 004
Sanas Plaza, 1302, Baji Rao Road , Pune 41 l 002
J 6 St Mark's Road, Bangalore 560 001
8 Camac Streel, Calcutta 700 O17
Ashok Rajpath, Pama 800 004
Chowk, Varanasi 221 OO I
PRINTED IN IND IA
BY JAINENDRA PRAKASH JIN AT SHRI JAINENDRA PRESS.
A-45 NA.RAINA, PHASE I, NEW DELHI 110 028
AND PUBLISRED BY NARENDRA PRAKASH JAIN FOR
To Profcssor N . A. Jayawickrcma
(yo) 11c11n'yo 'h osi mam' atthak.amo
U 5.~0)
PREFACE
Almost teo years ago, I undertook a new transation of Candrak.Irti's encydopaedic work the Pt4S(lnnapadi, a commentary on Nagarjuna's
primary philosophkal treatise, the Mu/41114dhyamak4kirikii. Meer 1 bad
completed nearJy ten cbapters, 1 'learoed through one of my scudents about
a similar attcmpt by Professor Marvin Sprung. I was about to give up my
project, when my student, who -had prviously srudied under Professor
Sprung, shared wltb me a copy of Ptofessor Sprung's ttanslatioo of the fitst
cbapter. Comparing his and my translations, I discovered that Professor
Sprung's translation was to some cxtent influenced by Stcherbatsky's wotk
(The Conception of Buddhist Nirvana , 1927). I fet then that my effon
would not be in vain, cspecially because l had expressed strong disagreement with Stcherbatsky's interptctation of the Buddhist philosophical tradicion (5ce my C4usality, The Cen/rai Philoiphy ofB11ddhism. 191)).
To my surprise 1 Professor Sprung's ttanslation) consiting of only seventeen chaptcrs (induding an incomplcte rendering of Chapter I), appeated in
1979. As I plodded along through my own labocious work, I began to
reaize how CandrakTtti was gradually leading me away from Nag~juna's
phllosophical standpoint. My suspicioos wece sucngthcned in 1981 when I
visited Jndla oo a Smithsonian gtant. Meeting with some scholai:s who were
brought up in the Vedantic uadition, I found them to be extremcy comfonable witll]'rgarjuna as intetpreted by Candrak.Trti and less impressed by the
tcachings -of early Buddhlsm as recorded in the Nikayas and the Agamas.
My suspkion tbat Nigarjuna and Candrakirti were ~pholding two differeot
philosophical standpoints compeUed me to take a fresh look at
Kumarajrva's Chung-lun, which is at least two ccncurics prior to Candrak.Ttti. Translating the entire Chung-lun into English an.d compating it
witb Nagarjuna's origioal Sanskrit text, I was pleasaotly surprized by their
similaries:. I found no justiflcation whatsoever in l~oking at Nagarjuna
through Candrakttti's eyes when there was a more faithful and doser disciple of Nagarjuna in Kumarajrva. This discovery diminished my enthusiasm
for deaning up my English ,:endeting of the Fraran1111p11dii for possible
publication.
Mter translating botb the Sanskric and the Chinese versions of Nigirjuna's tteatise, 1 proceeded to annotate both according to my understan.d ing
, of carly Buddhism as well as later Buddhist ttiditions before Nagirjuna.
The annotation of the Sanskrit tei alone turned out to be moce extcnsive
viii
PREFACE
ix
dha's teachings, especially at a time when he realized that che probJems were
crcated not only by metaphysicians like the Sarvastivadins and the
Sautrantikas>, but also by morc popular religious ceachcrs like Avaghosa, who
over--emphasised the function of "faith" in the emerging bdief in a traosccndeoc Buddha. A careful rcading of Nagarjuna's rceatise will reveaJ that he
was. critical of both these trends. If Buddhagbosa wcre to be coosidered the
model of a Thcravadin and Candrakfrti or Santideva were to be looked upon as
idea MahayanistS, oeither the Buddha, nor Moggaupotta-tissa, nor Nigarjuna
would fit into thcir shoes.
The prcsent worlc may come as a surprise to many who arc familiar with my
prcvious publications, espccially bccause it repudiates many i:.hings chat I have
said about Nigarjuoa. Io those earlier works, my major eodeavot was to show
how the Buddhism of the Buddha diffcred from both Sthaviravada and
Mabayana, and the Jatter ioduded philosophers like Nagacjuna. My main contention with scholars Jike Stcherbatsky and Murti has been in regard to the_
manner in which the for.mer equated Sarvastivada with early Buddhism and che
latter portrayed the Buddha as a half-hearted rnctaphysician incroduciog a
theory of dcments char carne to be rejccted by Nagarjuna. I was preparcd co accept Murti's ioterpretation of Niigarjuna, white struggling to find ways in
which that interprl:tation could be justified without sacrificing the cmpiricism
of the Buddha. Amore detailed study of both Magarjuna and Candrak!rti has
convioced me that the former stili rcmains faithful to the Buddha, while the
lattec has moved more cowards a Vedantic inrerprctation, chercby initiating a
proces~ that culminated in the disappearance of Buddhjsm as a distinct..
ideology from the Indian scene a few cenruries later.
ABBREVIATIONS
(Consult Kenneth Inada's Niigiirjuna, for-a detailed
juna and the Midhyamika school.)
bibiography
on Nagar-
AA
Ahh11t
AD
Adv
AK
Akb
Abhidharmakoa- bha!a,
Buddhay~as.
Ch'ang
Tairho No . .1.
Chung
PIJ
DhsA
DhsT
It
Karika
Kp
Kiiyapapari1111rta
xu
MIDDLE WAY
Mi/n
of Niigiirjuna with the commentary; Prasannapt1'1ii by CandraRirti, cd. P. L. Va.idya, Darbhaoga: The Mithila
lnstiruce, 1960.
PEW
PTS
Sdv
Sdmp
Saddharmapu'!<fe'ika-siilra, cd. H. Kern and B. Nanjio, St. Petersburg; The Imperial Acadcmy of Scieoces, 19 12.
Sn
Taisho
Thag
Thig
See Thag .
Tsa
Tseng
Ud
VbhA
tr. Gur,iabhadra,
Taisho No.99.
ABBREVIATIONS
Vin
xiii
Vism
CONTENTS
Preface
Abbreviations
vtt
xi
lNTRODUCTION
Dedicatory Verses
1
2
5
8
9
11
16
20
23
24
26
31
81
99
101
CiAPTER
1.
2.
(Cakfur-indriya-pafi~ii)
105
118
132
140
147
153
159
180
xvi
WAv
22.
23.
24.
25.
26.
INDEX TO THE
188
195
206
211
217
224
2.28
235
243
263
275
280
292
302
312
326
355
370
377
393
393
402
406
INTRODUCTION _ _ __
samuppida).
The practica middle path as enunciated in the famous Dhamffl(lcakkappavattana-sutta, which is complementary to or based upon the
philosophical middle path referrcd to above, was mote susceptible to varia
tions. The analysis of the wide variety of religous practices th;n emerged in the
two ttaditions, Theravada and Mahayana, which appear to be contrary to the
middle pach enunciated in the above discourse may require aseparate volume.
The present treatmenr will therefore be confined to the philosophical middle
path and its ~urvival, in spite of the heretical interpretations tbat occasionally
appeared in the Buddhist tradition. The survival of that middle position in
philosophy can be atttibuted to reformers lilce Moggaliputta-tissa (litde known
among the Western scholars of Buddhism, in spite of the important role he
played in the Buddhist council held during the re.ign of the Emperor Asoka of
Jndia) and Nagarjuna. Such personaitics bave emerged from time to time and
they have been responsible fot the continuacion of the Buddha's message. The
activities of such reformets have eitber been igoored, as in the case of
Moggaliputtatissa, or exaggerated, as in the case of Nigarjuna.
The present essay is not intended as an attempt to bighlight the conuibutions of the less ~nowo figures- like Moggalrputta-tissa.. whose famous
treatise, "The Points of Conuoversy" (Kathii.vatthu),3 awaits a ca.refu! and sympathetic treatqient by Buddhologists. On the contrary, this will be an attempt
to put into perspective the pbilosopbical and spiritual stature of Nagarjuna,
wh1ch has been cxaggerated beyond limit.S, more by modern scholars chan by
the classical Buddhiscs.
lNTRODUCTION
c:d spirituaJ attainments white leading a form of life infetior to that of ordinary
lay people. Such monks were reported even from the time of the Buddha. The
Vinaya-pifaka8 as well as the Kif.Jyapararivarta9 generate no sympathy for such
miscreant monks, the latter branding them as a pack of dogs fighting cach
other for a morsel of food thrown at them.
Such sdfish and dishonorable behavior on th(' part of certain monks may
hve been counter productive. Self-sacrifice and absolute altruism could
emerg~ as noble ideaJs in sucha context. However, such actions and reactions
need not be a reason for condemning even the immediate disciples of the Buddha, l!rahanlr like Sariputta, Moggallana, and Kassapa, as people of "low
aspirations" (liin'iibhirafii), 10 and forcing them to discaim thc:ir attainmc:ncs in
order to accept a new idea, an idea] certainJy contrary to the "middk path"
enunciated by the Buddha in his very first discourse to the world. It is by
folowing a "middle path" avoidiog the rwo extremes of self.induJgence and
self-destruction that the discipes of the Buddha attained the state of freedom
called " the appeasement of dispositions" (sakhara-samatha) and continued to
work for the welfate and happiness of mankind. Very authentic records
avaitabe in the Thera- and Then-g'iithas bear ample testimony to the idea of
the ~arly discipes, and it is also an idea! recognized' by Nagarjuna, the champion of the ''middle way" (XVII. 1).
While ~he Theravad~ns elevated the Abhidhamma to an exalted position
without devaluing the ideas emhodied in the carty discourses, the S11ddhar~
mapu(llnka appears to have gone much funher in dealing with this eotire
Buddhist phiJosophical and religious tradition beginning with the Buddha
himself. It is responsible not only for condemning the early disciples, but aJso
for down-playing the value of the carty discours.es. The discoutses included in
the Nikayas and the Agamas were considered to be inferior in content. The
argument presented is that because the immediate disciples could not understand the deeper doctrioe the.Buddha had to preach an jnfecior and unsatisfattory doctrine to .suit their incelectual capacity. Such a statemeot, however, has
a hidden implication, nan1ely, that the Buddha lacked the capacity to teach the
deepcr doctrines in a way that would be intelligible to the people who were in
his presence. -In the Mahayana traditioo, the stage was thus made ready for a
philosopher li.kc Nagarjuna, who is supposed to have best expouoded the doctrine, to be eevated to the level of a second Buddha, nay, even to the starus of
a supreme Buddha more exalted chan Slikyamuoi. Thus 1 it is not surprizing to
find some modern commentators prodaiming the view that the locus bud that
appeated in the world with che binh of the Buddha grew up and blossomed
forth with the appearance of Nagatjuna. In fact, a scholar like T. R. V. Murti
has maiotained that che Buddha even suggested a "theory of elements'' (dharma), which carne to be be rejected by Nagarjuna when the latter presented his
lNTI\ODUCTION
N AGARJUNA:
time to exorcize the terms Theravada and Mahayana from our vocabulary. A
major obstacle co the elimination of this distinction is the manner in which
Nagarjuna's phiosophy has com e to be expoundcd by a majority of modern
scholars. The presenc cranslation of Nigarjuna's Kiinka and commentary upon
cach of che vcrscs therein are inteoded as a correctivc to this intcrprctation.
A carcful study of the docuines in che cxteosivc corpus of Buddhis~ literature
indicates ve.cy dcarly how certain fundamental idcas have survived, in spite of
the occasional appearance of concepts chat conflict with the basie teachings of
che Buddha and thus produce controversies among the Buddhist thinkers.
Without undertaking a careful study of such insta.nces, scholars have rather uncriticaUy lumped together the early discourses of the Buddha and the summaries of their conten ts chat came to be preserved in the so-caJled Abhidharma,
togcther with all d1e interpret.ive cexts compiled by some of the later commentators, either in the form of vibhiif'ii or a!(hakatha, and criticized trus whole
corpus as being representacive of Theravada or Hrnayana. The same is clone
with some of the Mahayana discourses (sutra) and the treatises (fastra). The
contents of d1e discourses as well as of the Abhidharma literature arc examincd
only in the light of such commentarial explanations and not independent of
them. Modern scholarship has thus failed to extricate itself from commenta.riaJ
traditions. There seems to be oo justification for coosidering the discourses and
even the eady Abhidharma literature as sectarian works of the so-called
Thecavada. Theravada or Sthaviravada in genera , and Sarvastivada and
Saucrantika in panicular, may be considered sectarian, but their sectarian views
arc found not in the discourses and the Abhidharma but in the commeotarics
tbat carne to be compied on these two bodies of literacure. The elevation of the
Abhidharma to the level of a supreme body of litera tu re, moce exalted chan the
discourscs, is the work of these later commentators and not of the compiets of
chose Abhidharma texts. The Mahayanists themselves, bothered by the
substantialist thought of the Sarvastivada and Sautrantika schools, endeavored
to prcserve the eady teachings by emphasizing the negative aspect of the Buddha's doccrioe, especially the doccrine of emptiness (fUnyalii) . The
Kiifyapapari11arta as well as the early Pcajfiapararnita literarure represent tbis
reacrion co the substantialism of atce Buddhism and t.h.is literacure shouJd be
dissociated from the sectarianism chat cmerged as a result of the arcempt at
unificacion in treatises like the Saddh11rmapu11tfonka.
An attcmpt will be made in the followiog pages to show that even somc of
the moce prominent philosophers of Mahayana wece really trying to overcome
such sectarian ioterpretations and go back to the non-sectarian form of Buddhism as embodied in the early d iscourses, without rcjecting either the
canonical Abhidharma texts that embody posicive teachings or the early
Mahayana su tras that emphasizcd the ocgative aspect of the Buddha's docrrine.
[Nrn.OOUCTION
oot fouod in the Nikayas and the Agamas. Nagarjuoa was probably aware of
the existence of both these versions and he understood their implicatioos. His
Kiin"kti was an attempt to explaio the docuioe without rejectiog the contents of
any one of them. However, his refcreocc to Kacyayana, instead of Kayapa, is
extremely significant, in that be was conversaot with not onJy the contencs of
~e Ratnaku{a versions but also the version included in che Nikayas and che
Agamas. For this reason the analysis of Nagarjuna's philosophy as embodied in
the Kiirika will be undenaken with a view to locating the sources of those ideas
that arc accepted by him and those thar arc criticized and rejected by him.
lt is anticipaced that an analysis of the Kiin"k.a in relation to the "Discourse
to Katyayana" as well as ocher discourses iocluded in the Nikayas and the
Agamas will lead to a better understanding of the Buddha's philosophy
wichout exaggeracing the so-called Hlnayana-Mahayana discinctioo .
1NTRODUCTION
NAGARJUNA'S BUDDHA
Nagarjuna's Buddha was no doubt Gautama (see KJirikii XXVIl.30), the
prince from che Sakyan coupcry (p(esently pan~ of Nepal) who attai.oed
enlightenment and rorned out to be the most formidable opponent of almost
every major philosophical idea that came to be presented by the lndians. In
fact, as will be explained below, the phiJosophical atmosphere was so confused
during the Buddha's day thac sometimes be was fo.cced ro coin new terms to ex-
press his thoughts.
Two of the major philosopbical theories that dorinated the Indian scene
during this time were (1) existence (sat, astitva), proposed and developed for
centuries by Indian chinkers since the time of the eady Vedas, and (2) nonexistence (a.sat, 11iiistit11a), presented by the Materialists reacting against the
craditional metaphysics . Existence or astitva was no ordinary empirical existeoce
b ut the existence ofa permanent and eternal substratum in man as well as in all
aspeccs of nature. In man. it was the immutable self (atman) that remained in
boodage to the impermanent psychophysical personaity and which returns to
its ultimate abode, the universal self (Atman), once it is freed from thar bondage and reaches its ultimate moral status (Brahman) . Attempting to eicplain
the origin of this reality in man as wel as in oature, some of the craditional
philosophers setcled for a conception of a creator god. As it is, this may not
have generated much protest from tte Buddha. However, the Indian
philosophers wece not satisfied with the simple aorion of a creator god. At a
very eary stage, they asserted chat this self (at1nan) was created by a god or gods
who dete.r mined that it beloogs to one or the other of the foursocial classes: the
priestly (brtihmatJa), the warrior (k1atriya) , che merchant (vaiya), and the ser\rant (iidra). 21 Thus, cach individual's :a arus was predetermined and unchangeable. It was th is particular idea of creation that elicited rhe most vehement criticism both from the Materialists as well as from the Buddha.
Denying such a metaphysi<ial self, the Materialists moved to the other extreme of advocatiog the annihilatioo of the human personaliry aftec death, and
then aso denied any mral responsiblicy for human actions. Instead , they propounded a theocy of the indestructibilicy of matter. 22
JO
Kaccayanagotta-Sutta
The Buddha's discourse to Kaccaya.na, a discourse wbose authority was
recognized by aJmost aH the major philosophica1 schools of BuddhJsm,
becomes mea.oingful only in the context of the philosophica.l views mentioned
abovc. Following is the complete text of the discour:se as reponed by Ananda:
Thus have I heard: The Blessed one was once living at Savatth.i,
in the monastery of Ana(hapiJ:l<;ika, in Jeta's Grove. At that time
the venerable Kaccayaoa of that dan carne to visit bim, and
saluting him, sat down at one side. So seatcd, he questioned che
ExaJted one : "Sir [people] spcak of 'right view, right view.' To what
cxtcnt is therc a right view?"
"This world, Kaccayaoa, is generally indined towards two
[views]: cxistencc and oon-cxisrencc.
To him who perceives with right wisdom the uprising of the world
as it has come to be, the ootioo of non-existence in the world does
not occw. Kaccaya.na, to him who perceives with right wisdom che
ceasing of the world as it has come to be, the ootioo of existeoce in
the world does not occur.
The world, for the most part, Kaccayana, is bouod by approach,
gra.sping and inclinacion. And he who docs not follow chat approach and grasping, that determinacion of mind, chat inclination
and disposition, who does not eling to or adhere to a view: 'This is
my self,' who chinks: 'suffedog chat is subject to arising ariscs; suffcring chat is subjcct to ceasing, ceases,' such a person does not
doubc, is not perplexed. Herein, his knowledge js not othcrdepeodenc. Thus far, Kaccayana, thcrc is 'right view.'
'Bverythiog exists,' - this, Kaccayana, is one excreme.
'Everything does not exisc,' - rhis, Kaccayana, is the second extreme.
Kaccayaoa, without approaching either extreme, the Tathagaca
teaches you a docrrine by the middle.
Dependent upon ignorancc arise dispositions; dependent upon
dispositions arise consciousness; dependent upon consciousncss
arises the psycbophysical personaJicy; dependent upon the
psychophysica.l persona.lity arise che six senscs; dependent upon the
six senses arises contact; dependent upon contact arises feeling;
dependent upon feeling arises craving; dependent upon craving
arises grasping; dependent upon ,grasping arises becoming; det>endent upon becoming arises birth; dependent upon birch arise oJd
age and death, grief, Jameotation, suffering, dejection and dispair.
Thus arises this encire mass of suffering. However, from the utter
lNTRODUCflON
11
12
in th.is instance, refer to a special or unique form of insight not shared by the
ordinary people. What makes the difference is "r.ight knowledge" (sammappanfia, or simply panifii), and that difference is then explained in the next
paragraph.
The perceptions or sense experieoce of the ordinary person in the world are
geoerally "bouod by approach, grasping and inclination" (upaya-upadiinaabhinive.rt.i-vinibandha). They arc colored by one's prejudices, by one's likes
and dislikes. lf a person is ab le to avoid such approach, grasping-and inclinatioo, if he does not follow his dispositions, chen that person would not cake a
detecmined stand and say: "This is my [per.rnanent] self." He would perceive
phenomena in the world as arising and ceasing.
The perception of arisiog and ceasing of phenomena conditioned by various
factors is availablc even to ordinary people who have not been able to completely
free themselves from prejudices. Thus, there is a common denon1inator ber;ween the perceptioos of an ordinaryperson and those of the enlightened one.
H owever, the ordinary person continues to worry about a permanent and eteroal substance behind phenomena or about a supreme being who is the author
of all that happens in the world. He is assailed by doubtS about wbat he
perceives. One way of overcoming such doubts is to confine oheself to what is
given, chat is the causa! dependence ofphenomena, without rrying to look for
something mysterious. The Buddha realized that "Wheo phenomena (rlhamm'ii) appear befor<: the brahman who is ardenc and contemplative, his doubts
disappear, as he sees their causal natute. "2 >
According to the Kaccayanagotta-sutta, if a person does no_t make up his
mind that there is a permanent and eternal self and continue to look for it, but,
instead, merely uderstands things as they have come to be (yathabhUta'f(J), as
for example, understands suffering (dukkha) as something that arises depending upon conditions, then he does not fa11 into doubc. In other words, instead
of look.ing for mysterious causes one should start with whatever .cases one can
discover that are cootributory to each siruation. Of course, in most cases. past
experiences arc a good index. Thus, in order to attain such knowledge one does
not have to go around looking for a teacher who would transmit that
knowledge in a sec ret session or in some mysterious way .. His knowledge would,
in chat case, 'not be other-dependent (apara-paccaya fla1Jam ev 'as.ra etI ha hott).
On the basis of such knowledge and experience, one is said to have "right
view" (samm'ii-diftht). "Right view'' in early Buddhism is cot.rasted with
"wrong view" (mz~cha- rlitthz) . These ewo ace oot contrasted in the way truth
and falsehood are contrasted in the pre-Buddhist cradicion. In the latter case,
what is true is considered to be what exists (.rat). Whatever ex.ists, is real, and by
definition whatever is real caonot be othcrwise. According to this a pn'ori
definition, "truth" has to be something that exiscs dlway.r. Yet, what is given to
JNTRODUCTION
13
the sense expedences is nor available always. Hence it was assumed that what is
true is something other than what is given to the sense experiences, and that re
mains always (saisata) and in everything. lt is the ontological truth (atman) as
welJ as the mora.I truth (brahman) in evcrything.
As mentioned earlier, ::. theory of existence or a theory that says "everything
exists' (sahba1{1 pttht) is wrong, not becausc it can be proved to be false, but only
in the sense that it does not take into consideration the empii:ically gi'ven fact of
cessation (nirodha). Hence, it is characterized as "confusion" (musa, Sk. mrfii),
not as "non-existent" or "un-rruth" or "falsehood" (P-satya).
Avoidance of the theory that ''everything exists" docs not, according to the
Buddha, make the opposite view, narody "everything does not exist" (sab6P1{1
n 'fJttht), any tnore true. The reason for this is that this latter theory implies
much more than a simple denial of a pcrmanent and eteroal substance in man
(atman) or in the universe (btahman) . 1t implies complete discontinuii:y in.
phenomcna or their annihilation (uccheda), and this too is a wrong view, not
bec.ause, like the for mer, it can be proved to be false, but because it is partia! in
rhat som~ aspecrs of experience like arising (samudaya) cannot be accounted for
by such a view.
The Buddha did not worry about discovering strictly Jogical arguments to teject aoy one of these views. He merely avoided these two theories in his explanation of existence. Hence his statement: "Without approaching either excreme, the Tathagata teaches you the doctrine by the middle" (ete te ubho ante
14
lNTRODUCTION
I)
{l )
(2)
(3)
(4)
16
THE
W AY
tha) to bring out the pragmatic meaning of dhamma. For the Buddha.
whatever is true or real (bh'Uta, taccha) is alo what produces result (atthasa'f?lhita).36 This pragmatic definition of truth or reality was moce often used in
expJaining mora! phenomena. Hence the reference to the three types of results
or consequences or fruits:
1)
2)
3)
While the term dharma, in the four contexts referred to above, may be takeo
as implying empiricaJ truths, a more compreheosive use of the term is also
available. In rhis case, the dharma (or sad-dharma) expresses the ootioo of
"true doctrine," and without any hesitacion this may be explained as a "true
st~temeot ,'' a use that may be most appealing to the modern linguistic
philosopher who is generaUy averse to met.aphysics and insists that "truth" pertains to statements. The use of the term dharma in this sense at ooce renders
futile any attempt to speak of a lioguistically transcendent truth or reality in the
Buddhist cootext.
Dependent arising is the middle path presented by the Buddha between the
extremes of etetnalism and annihilationism, of strict determinism and chaotic
indeterminjsm, of absolute. reality and niliilistic unreality, of permanent ideotity and absoute difference. Considedag the mann.er in which he explained the
middle position between these extremes, no one could maintaio that this middle position is beyond linguistic descciption or uaoscends any forn1 of verba! expression. In fact, the two terms that are generally utilized in the absolutistic
sy~tems of Indian tbought to presentruch a standpoint, namely ''indescribable"
(avacya) and "indefinable" (anirv~antya), do not occur in the.early discourses
of the Buddha. The ter:m "undeclared" or "unexplained" (avyakata) occurs, but
it ~ used to refer to problems such as the duration and extent of the universe,
the identity of or the difference betweeo che soul and the body, as wel as the
status of the tathagata after death- these beiog pcobJems that could not be explaioed on the basis of any empirical evidence.~8 For the Buddha, whatever is
empirically giveo is also describable or defiaabte without having to Msume
!Uetaphysical standpoints.
INTRODUCTION
17
18
lNTROOl)CTION
19
termed 'it will be' (bhavissatz) and it is not reckoned ;is 'ie eidsts (atthi) or as 'it has been' (ahost). , .. Whaeevet materia form has
arisen, and has manifested itself, is called , reckoned, or tecmed 'ie
exists' (atthi), and it is not reckooed as 'it has been' (aho!z) nor as 'it
wiH be' (bhavissatt).'6
The Buddha advised his disciples "not to eling to dialectical usage nor go
beyond the .imlts of linguistk convention" (janapada-nirultif!t nabhinivese.yya
i?imafJfzaf?l natidhaveyya). 47 Such being the middle position adopted by the
Buddha regardiog linguistic conventioo, it would be an extreme position to
maintain that language is either utimately real (as it was the case with the Indians who made vae a supreme god) or that it is useless when it comes to expressing ultimate reality.
For the Buddha, language derives its "meaoing" (attha) when it is able to
p.roduce results (attha). and thus what is true (bhuta, taccha) is that which bea.rs
results (attha-sarp,hita). 48 The Buddha did not recognize anything rhat is fase
to be productive of results. Truth in this sense can be equated with "me.aningful" language. Thus, linguistic expressions that imply permanence and annihilation would be "meaningless" (an-attha) in that they do not commu"nicate
anything thac is given in e.xperience (dhamma), where experience is understood
in terms of the felt results (attha) rather than in terms of an indefinable
ultimate reality.
Having thus rejected the two views, namely, the traditional Indian view that
che human personality consists of a permanent and eternal spirirual ent'ity
(atman) and the Matetialist view the denied such a spiritual entity and
recognized maccer (body) to be the only real~ty, the Buddha continued to speak
of the psychophysical personality (nama-~pa), referring to ie with such tetms
as "I" (aha'!IJ) and "you" (tvarp,) and even the term "self' (atta) when speaking of
that personality.
With the emergence of Buddhism as a formidable phiLosophicaJ and
spiritual movement that undermined the very foundations of che tradirional
Indian phjlosophy and religion . Indian thinkers reformulated their substaotialist world-view, presenting it in a morc subte and appeaJing form in the
Bhagavadgzta. The notion of dharma embodied in this t ext may be analysed in
terms of the three Buddhist categories presented above, namely, an-flrtha, ctrtha and pararrUirtha, Iastead of the pragmatic definitions of the Buddhists, the
Indian thinkers were presenting a moce substantialisr incerpretation where,
1)
20
2)
3)
attha
WAY
Thus was inaugurated an enormous controversy becween Buddhists and Indian philosophers that continued to rage for severa! cenruries until Buddhism
completely disappeared from the Indian soil as a philosophlcal and spiritual
force around the seventh and eighty centurie.s, only to survive and flourish in
the countries souch and southeast of India as well as in the Far East.
The survival of a pragroatic philosophy in the face of an extremely absolutistic tradition such as the one cmbodied in. the Bh4ga11adgT/a was not
easy . One of the ways in which the Buddhists responded to thac philosophy
was by compiling the now famous Buddhist classic, tbe Dha1tJmapad11. As
the citle indicates, it was an attempc to counter the Indian absolutist and
substantialist definition of dhamma. The Buddhist philosophers, confronted
by the onslaught of Indian thinkers asserting the reality of the self (atman),
spent most of their time analysing what they called dhamma in o.rder to
show that there was no permanent and eternal self. As Kenneth lnada has
rightly remarked , this represented 1'the most active, highly vibrant and compecidve age in Buddhist bistory known as the Abbidhaana period . ... lf there
arc high watermarks to be considered in Buddhist bistory, the Abhid.harrna
period certainy ta.ces a very high leveJ, a level of great fermentation and
flourishment pf Buddhist thought. IdeologicaJly speaking, no ocher period jn
Buddhist bistory, whether of the Tberavada or Mahayana, or even national
Buddhist developments such as in T'ang Dynasty China, could ever match, or
come up to the level of activiry as recorded during this period. " 49
Two complete sets of Abhidharma texts compiled during this period are
available to us. One is preserved by tbe Theravadins consisting of the foHowing
texts;
l. - Dhammasangani,
2
Vighanga,
lNTRODUCTION
3.
4.
S.
6.
7.
21
Dh111ukath'1i,
Puggalapanatli,
Kathavatthu,
Y1111111/a, and
Pauhana.
The other version was preserved by the Sarvastivada schoo and comprises
one major work and six ancillary texts. They are as folows;
1.
2.
3.
4.
s.
6.
7.
That the Theravada and Sarvastivada schools preserved these two bodies of
literarure does not make them sectarian, any more chan t_he discourses, preserved by any school, could be branded as such. Athough the treatment of subjectmatter io these two sets of works differs widely, the subjecr-matter is pract.ically
the same. Both deal with the categories into which the human personal.ity as
well as human experience carne to be aoalysed in the early discourses where
tbey receive amore discursive treatment. The analysis of human experience into
aggregates, eleme.nts, and faculties , all of which were considered to be dharmas
~r elements of existence, seems to be the first and foremost concern of the
Abhidharmikas. Undoubtedly, the purpose of this analysis is co dcmonstrate
the absence of a self or substance in these phenomena. Exhaustive analyses of
the various types of relations tbat obtain among them wece also undertaken,
providing a sort of scholastic ad:v.ancernent in the study of such phenomena,
but sti11 not deviating fro.m the fundarnental teac.hings of eady Buddhisip. Examination reveals that these two processes in some way representan atte.mpt to
deal wich the same issues that the Buddha was concerned wich, namely.
"dependently arisen phenomena'' (pa{iccaiamuppanna-dhamma) and "dependent arising" (paficcasa1nuppada). The knowledge of these two processes was
looked upon as right understanding, which utimately leads to the attainment
of freedom (niniiif!a) .
Unfortunacely, ew.o of the schools thar were involved in this Abhidharmic
enterprise were driven roo far in tbeir academic study of the 4hfJN1UIS, probabJ.y
by the unrelenting criricisms evelled against Buddhism by the traditional
22
schoos
INTROOUCTION
23
24
THJ!
The same text highlights anorher controversy that was beginning co ntl1e the
minds of Buddhist thinkers ducing the rhird cen rury BC and which became the
topie of a heated debate during the fust and second ccnmries AD. This pertained
to the questioo whether the Buddba is transcendent (lokutlara). Moggauput
tatissa rejected the view. gradually gaining ground in the Buddhist tradition,
which favored craoscendence.'9 The biographies of the Buddha, like the
Mahavastu 1 were probably not yet wricten . Mahayana, with its conception of a
coropletey transcendent Buddha, had not come into existence by that cime.
The Saddharmapu't/anka , which is resp onsible for condemning the miscreant
monks (bhik!u) as wdl as the ideaJ of a saint (arhant) in eiuly Buddhism, in"
dicates a gradua growth wich the fina version assigncd ro the third century
AD. In the earliest versions of some of the early Mahayana sutras, such as
Vajracchedika-prajnaparamita and the Kiiyapa-panvarta, there is no mention
of a bodhisattva. 60
.
What sort of Mahayana can chere be without the conception of a ctanscendeot Buddha and the notion of a borihiJattva? lt certainly ought to be differeot
from the kind of Mahaya na that one comes across in che avaiab le versins of
lNTRODUCTJON
25
N!igafjuna 1s Mifsion
Nagarjuna , wbo lived at a time when the Theravada-Mahayana conflicc had .
not degenerated to the level that is presented in the SadclharmapurJt/aiika,
26
THE
PHILOSOPHY OF TI-IE
MtDOLE WAY
therefore had an already different mission. It was indeed not the least different
from the mission chat lay before Moggailputtatissa, to expose the untenability
of certa.in heretical views chat were gradually becoming popular in the Buddhist
uaditioo . A careful reading of the Kiirikii will ccveal the fact that Nagarjuna
had all the help he needed to achieve this cask. As mentioned before, even after
the transference of the Pali canon to Sri Lanka, che discourscs and the
Abhidharma texts survived in lndia. Thus the discourses of the Buddha as well
as the traditioo of the disciplcs (fravaka) were available to Nagarjuua. The
humilicy with which Nigacjuna bows down to the BuJdha and the respect with
which he treats the Buddha's disciples (Jravaka) 61 are in complcce contrast to
the unsympathetic attitude of the later Mahayanists toward the eatlier Buddhist cradition.
In the foUowing analysis of che Kiirika, it will be shown char Nagarjuna actempced to discredit heterodox views, especialy those of the Sarvastivadins and
che Sautrantikas, and establish the non-substantialicy of all dharmas (Chapcers
III - XV) as wel as the non-substantiality ofpudgala (Chapters XVI - XXl) and
therc:after to explicate che positive doctrioes of che Buddha as embodied io the
early discourses like the Kaccayanagoita-sutta.
The present analysis is, tberefore, conuacy to the more popular incerprecacion of Nagatjuna espoused by commentators like Candrakirti who emphasized
the reductio ad abstJrdum (prasangika) metho~. lt will be moce sympathetic co
the interpretations offered by Nagacjuna's disciples like Bhavaviveka and the
moce positive thiokers of the Midhyamika school. While highlighting the iogenuity and philosophical marurity cf Nagarjuna, the preseot analysis wil at
the same time be unsympathetic toward the mych that Nagarjuna was a second
Buddha.
STRUCTURE OF THE
KARlKA
IN1'Rooucr10N
27
provide a complete and accurate picture of their ideas. Sometimes they are c.o nsidered to be essential secitons or cbapters, the implication being th.at the rest is
inessential. 6' This undoubtedly has conuibuted to a great deal of
misunderstanding and sometimes deliberate distortion of the author's ideas.
Coo.sidering the unsatisfaccoriness of such a method, the present analysis of
Nagarjuna's thought will be presented on the basis of an examination of his
Kiin'k'ii taken as a whoe, with ever,y word, every verse, and every chapter in it
created as in integraf part of that work. This is done in the absence of any concrete evidence that some portions of this work are not by Nagarjuna.
A supetficial reading of this work, with 448 vetses divided into 27 chapters,
could leave the reader with the impression chat the text is repetitious. This
wrong impressioo will disappear like a mirage if one keeps in mind the circumstances that led to the complication of this work, the motivation for writing
it, the background in which it was written, and the goal that was to be achieved,
Such considerations will enable one to see a carefully execuced plan or structure
in the Kiirika. In order to highlight di.is Stf\.lcture, the Kari/iii will be aoalysed
hece into four major .sections, withouc changing the sequence either of the individua! verses or of the cbapters.
Section I
This first seccion includes Chapters I and II. which deal with the most fundame.ntal doctrines of Buddhism , causatioo and change. The problem of causarion or "dependent arising" is taken up io the first of these. If this were a cext
writteo during the Buddha's day , this cbapter would undoubtedly have dealt
with theories of e.xistence presented by the traditional schools of Indian
philosopby advocating the reality of a permaneot self (atman) and the
Materialist school that denied such a self (an-atman) thereby denying the concinuity of the human person as wdl as his mora! responsibility. 'HoweveI,
Nagarjuna was living in the second century AD and his problems, as mentioned
earlier, were created more by the Sarvastivadins and the Sautraotikas than by
the non-Buddhist schools. Th.is is dearly evidencfrom the way in which Nagarjuna begins his first chapter.
The first verse in this chapter refers to four different theories of causatioo or
arising: (i) self-causatlon, (ii} external causation, (iii) both self- and external
causation , and (iv) arising out of a non-cause. After enumerating four such
theories, any further explanatio would naturally commeoce wi th an analysis of
the first of these four theories, sef-causatioo (svata.utpattt) . Thus , the four .
types of relations (pratyaya) referred co in the next verse shoud be takeo as ex-
28
W/I Y
1iiida).
Sectzon II
The second section includes thitteen chaptets, begioning with an examination of sense faculcies (lndriya, Chapter ITI) and ending with an examination of
lNTRODUCTION
29
Kaccayanagotttz.sutta.
Section III
The third secrion indudes eleven chapters from XVI to ~I. lt is a section
chat has caused confusion in the m inds of m any who wrote on Nagarjuna's
thought. First, many of the topics dealt with in the previous section arc again
analysed here. Thjs gave the impression that the text is repetitive and therefore
it is possible to ignore som e of its parts when presenting Nagarjuna's
philosophy . For example, the examination of action and agent (karma-karaka)
was attempted in Chap ter VIII , and a longer chap ter (XVII) on the examioation of the fruit of action (karma-phala) is induded in this seccion. Secondly,
rhis particular chaptcr (XVII) deals with the docttine of karma in a moce
positive way, asserting the existence of a moce appropriate view than the one
criticized at the beginning of the chapcer. Such ao assertion seems to go against
not only the doctrine of emptiness (uyata), as it is geoerally understood by
modern schola.rs, but also the view chat neither the Buddha nor Nagarjuna had
a view to propound.
H owever, reading the eleven chapters one cannot help comiog to the condusion that they were incended to establish the non-substanciality of the individual (pudgala-nairalmya) but not to eliminate the cooception of an individual or person a ltogether. The conception of the individual involves the
problems of bondage and freedom (bandhana-mo/qa) .ind, after defining
these , five chapters arc devoted to the problem of bondage. These five chapters
are undoubtedly commentary po a verse chat seems to have been excremely
popular among the Buddhists and which both Nagarjuna and Vasubandhu
wece cooversant with, for we find the latter composing a whole treatise caUed
Karm4Iiddhiprakara11a.6 > This verse is quoted by CandrakUci 'in his commentary, and runs chus:
30
The deoia of a permanent self (atman) by the Buddha prompted his critics
to insist that the Buddha coud not satisfactoriJy explain the problem of mora
responsibility. The present verse is only a summary of the Buddha's causa.I explanation of the doctrine of mora responsibility, not an admission of a permaoeot and eterna karma. In fact, the determinism that may appear with the
reading of the fust line, is immediately corrected with the conditionality
specified in the second line. Three mai n topics are dealt with here: the imperishability of karma (aviprat{iia) , the harmooy of t onditions (samagfi) and
the appropriate time (kala). It is therefore not surprising to see Nagarjuna inserting two chapters oo "harmony" (samagfi. XJX) and time (kala XX). after
stating the "imperishability" of karma (XVII) and denying the existeoce of a
permanent and eternal "self' (atman , XVIII). To eliminate any one of these
chapters as inesseotial co the underscanding of Nagarjuna's thought is,
cberefore, hlghly unwatranted.
Mter a clarification of the meaning of bondage (bandhana) in the context of
a human beiog who is without a permanent and eteroal self and who still concinues to wander along experiencing births and deatbs, happiness and suffering, Chapter XXII takes up a person who has attained freedom (mokfa), who
has "thus gone" (tathagata) without'having to waoder along as a person in bond~ge . No other issue in Buddhist thought has been as misunderstood and
misinterpret~d. not only by the non-Buddhists, but also by the Buddhists
themselves, as the conception of tathagata. Probably for this reason, Nagarjuoa
felt the need to begin his discussion of freedom witb an examination of the
conceptioo of tathiiggta. It will be shown that Nagarjuna's arui.lysis follows exactly the method of analysis given by the Buddha. The chapter that follows explaios the reasons for such misconcepdons (viparyiisa, XXJII).
Modern scholarship on Nagarjuna has empahsizcd the cooception of two
uuths to the c.oroplete oeglect of his explanation of the fout truths as enunciated by the Buddha. It will be shown that the two truths in Nagarjuna are not
an improvement on the four noble truths, nor a spccial insight on the part of
Nagarjuna, buc an understanding of a doctrine that is already clearly expressed
in the early discourses. This lengthy chapter (XXIV) concludes with a recogni-
INTROOUCilON
31
tion of the four noble truths and the docuine of dependent arising chat is the
foundation of the four noble truths.
The chapter on 111niii11a (XXV) is a refutation of the absolutisc interpretation
of the notion of freedom and a determined attempt to go baclc to the nonabsolucist form of Budchism enunciated in the early discourses.
Conuary to the view ot most modern scholars of Nigarjuna's thought,
Chapter XXVI (Dvadailingapankf1i) is hece presented as an eaboration of the
Buddha's owo conclusion in the KJUcayanagotta-sutta. lt deals with the Buddha's positive explaoation of how a human beiog in bondage cin free himself
from the mass of suffering.
Section IV
Nigarjuna could have concluded his ueatise with the previous secdon.
However, he was aware that his most favoritc discourse-che Kaccayanagottasutta- began with che queston regarding " right view (sammad1/th1) . Nigarjuna has already explained almost every aspect of the Buddha's doctrine and
sbown what conscirutes a "right view'' as against the "wrong or confused views"
(micchadiflht) chat appeared in the Buddhist tradition. Yet there wece some
views that che Buddha lefc aside without either asserting or denying them.
These penained to the cen, and sometimes fourteen, unexpJaioed or
undeclared questions (avyakata, Sk. avyakrta). A treatment of these questions
was nceded bcfore Nigarj_una could make a fina comme.nt about the attitude
of the Buddha, the "freed one" (nibbuta), with regard to aJI varic:ties of vicws,
whether they be right or wrong. One could hardly cxpect a better condusion co
a tcxt intended to bring about freedom from all obsessioos (prapancopaiama)
than this last chapcer. lt represcnts an expJanation of the higbcst form of
frecdom, chat is. freedom from ideoJogical cooscraints, thac che Buddha as well
as his disciples (Jravaka) had actained and wbich made Buddhism one of the
mosc tolerant religions ever to appear on earth.
32
33
lNTROOUCTION
What son of argument does Nagarjuoa present in order to deny the existence of self-nature? Murti and others who saw in Nagatjuna's method a
dialectic eomparable to that of Immanual Kant have considered self-nature
(111abhava) and other-nature (parabha11a) as antinomies. This may be true.
first refiitation of the
H owever, such a dialectic is not used by Nagarjuna in
nocion of self-nature. Nagatjuna rejects self-nature, not because ie is relative to
other-nature, but: because it is not evident (na 11idyate). The argument from
relativity is utilized'. to reject other-narure ony and not self-'natuce. ("In the
absence of self-nature, other-nature is aso not evident.") What is found hece is
a simpJe and sttaighdorwatd denial of self-nature on epistemologicaJ grounds,
even though h e does not elaborate upon tbat epistemology at this point.
Throughout the text, one finds Nagarjuna using the negated verb, na vidyata,
and somecimes the ptesent participle, avidyamiintJ. The former is often
rendeced as "not found ," and in our ttanslation preference is given to the more
epistemologically oriented rendering; "is not evident." This emphasis is dearly
evident from the manner in which he rejects "self-nature," as explained above.
In other words, Nagarjuna appears more as an empicicist than as a diaecti
ciao who merely utilizes reason. Thus, the text begin.s with a simple denia of
self-narure as something that is not evident. What Nagarjuna m eans by
evidence will be expained later oo in this essay. If this point ls kept in mind, it
becomes rather easy to understand the rest of Nagarjuna's analysis of condiuons.
Thus, in the verse that follows (1.4), Nagarjuna speaks of action (kriya) and
conditioo (pratyaya). In this case, neither the action nor the condition is
denied. What is denied is the sort of 1elatiooshlp that is assumed between
them, that is, ioherence which emphasizes identity. The denial of identity is
prompted by the fact that it is equated with "sdf-nanue'' (wabhava) which , in
its turo, was looked upon as a permaneot entity. Difference was likewise denied
because it was perceived as other-nature, which implied annihilation or lack of
any continwty.
Verse 5 takes up the definition of a coodition. A condition is such because
depending upon it others arise. However, the teason why Nagarjunarejects this
definition is not that it is not empiricaly valid, but that there j5 a rider attached
to the definition, That rider impUes that this dependence is eteroa and permanetlt. ln other words, that which is dependent and that upon which it depends
a.re substaotially coOI)ected through a telation of inherence. Hence,
Nagarjuna's queston "So long as it [the effect] does not arise, wby is it Ithe
cause] not coosidered to be a non-condition?"
Verse 6 completes Nagarjuna's genera criticism of eonditions. Most modern
translators have failed to bring out the significance of this verse, primarily
because the term artha ( = effect, fruit , result, rendered into Chinese as kuo)
his
34
failed to attra.c t their attencion. What is denied is, therefore, not the arising of
an effect as ordinarily understood, but the arising .o fan effect that is already ex
istent (sato arthmy11) or one that is non-existent (asato arthtJJya). These again
represent the identity (1atkarya) or the oon-identity (a..ratkarya) theories of
causation presented by the Sarvastivadins and the Sautrantikas.
Verses 7-10 represent the criticism of the four types of conditions referred to
at 1. 2 as interpreted by the Sacvastivadins and the Sauttantikas. If the 1at ( existent) and a1at ( non-existent) qualifying dharma (phenomena) are undetstood
as implying "the substantia1ly (1vabha11ato) existent and oon-existent," a
quatification that Nagarjuna often make~. then it will be easy to understand
the nature of Nagarjuna's criticism. This is especiaJJy so in verse 10 where, on the
surface, it appears that Nagarjuna was criticizing the Buddha's owo statement:
"When that exists, this comes to be," (t1Jmi'f?'l .rafidam bhavatt). However,
Nigarjuna was very careful in dealing with this stacement, for in the first line
he was explicit with regard to the sort of existence he was criticizing, that existence being none other that "substancial existence" (sat-ta).
Verses 11-14 deal with severa! other aspects of the theo.ry of causacion such as
the arising of an effect from a combination of conditions. lt is indeed the coocluding line of the last verse ( 1.14) that possibly can give rise to all the
inisunderstanding regarding Nagarjuna's analysis of causa! conditions. "In the
absence of the effect, whence can thece be a condition or a non-condition." lt is
easy to interpret this statement to-meao that Nagarjuna did not accept either a
cause or an effect that is dependent upon a cause. To take it as a sirople deniaJ
of cause and effect would be to ignore evetytbing that Naga.rjuna has beeo t.ty
ing to say earliet in the chapter, regarding self-nature (s11abhava) or substantial
or permanent ex.isteoce (sal). Thete seems to be no tationae fot interpteting
this statemeot independent of the basie premises with which he set out on his
examinacion of conditions. To conclude; Whar is denied bere is not the simple
effect that depends upon the condltion or conditions for its acisiog, but an effecr rhat is either pre-existent, and therefore permanent, or oon-existent
because ie is not pre-existeot. It is also teasonable to assume that a siroilac
denial pertains not to a simple cause or condition but to a cause or condition
that produces an already existent or non-existent effect.
"Dependent arising" or casuaJity (pratftytZJamutpada) was, to reiterate , the
principle in terms of which the Buddha was able to explain the funccioning of
phenomeoa (dharma) without resorting to a conception of permaoent and eternaJ entity (nitya atman). In other words, dependent arislog explaios the impermanence (anityata) of phenomena that are dependently arisen (pratftytJJam1ttpanna) without which no identification of "dependent arising" is possibJe .
Bccause such phenomena acc dependently arise, they acc rmpecmanent
(anitya). Impermaneoce involves change and movement.
lNTRODUCTION
36
and from which we look into two directions into time. The unit of
composition of our perception of time is a duration. with a how and
a stera, as it were-a rearward- and a forward-Jooking end. 69
The very first verse in Chapter II suggests the kind of movement or motion
that is under ctiticism: "What has. moved is not being moved."
For someone ro daim t~at what: has already moved ( =present), the underlying assumption is that eveo though there is a distinction in terms of temporality,
there is indeed the sense in which what is being moved in the present is not different from what, on an earlier occasion, was also in a state f moving. This can
easiy give rise to the view that phenomeoa are in a constant flux, a continuous
uninterrupted flow (santatz). While such an explanation may account for the
continuity of phenomena tha.t are analyscd into discrete events, it aL50 explains
the ideotity of cach inruvidual stream (santiina) . This latter idea, carded to its
extrernes, led to the roetaphysical notion of a subtle but substantial pcrsonality
(pudgala), neither 1dential nor differentfrom the a,ggregates (skandha). This is
the school of "pcrsonalists" (pudgalavada).
Thus, following the same method chat he adopted in criticizing the substantialist ootion of causality, Nagarjuna focuses his attention on the metaphysical
interpretacions of ideas of change and movement, without atternpting to deny
the cooccpts such as "the moved" (gata) , "the not moved" (agata), or "the present moving" (gamyamana) per se. After a detailed analysis of the unhealthy
consequences of such metaphysical interpretations, Nagarjuna, in che end,
specifies the sort of view he is criticizing when he maintained:
An existing mover does not carry out the movement in any of the
three ways. Nei~er aoes a non-existiog mover carry out the movement in any of the three ways. Nor does a person carty out a movement, both existing and non-existing, in any of the ee ways.
Therefore, neither the morion, nor the mover, nor the space moved
is evident. (Il.24-2~ . )
INTRODUCTLON
37
Part II (Dharma-nairatmya)
As mentioned earliec, Cbapters lll and XV deal with almost all the major
Abhidharma categories that are treated under general rubric "dharma." Of
these various categories, the most irnportant are aggregates (.rk.andht1) .
faculties/spheres (indriyalayatana), and elements (dhiitu). T~is is the order iJ
which these are normally eoumerated. However, Nagatjuna was interested in
epistemoJogy, and therefore ie is natura! for hlm to take up the faculties (indriya) for examination at the very outset.
3. Faculties (indriya). Chapter !Il, verse 1, refers to the six faculties and their
spheres. Yet, there is oo denial of any one of them. This roay be compared with
Nagarjuna's statement in Chapter 1, verse 1, chat refers to the four causaJ
tbeories, all of which were iostantly deoied. H owever, in verse 2, Nagarjuna
criticizes a parcicular defu1ition of ''seeing'' (darfatJa) and that definition involves "the perception of itself" (.rvat1!J(Z11af!J daranaft') . This undoubtedly is
the Indian version of the Cartcsian ':c;ogito" which led to the belicf in a perma
nent and eternal self during the period of the Upani!ad.r; 0 and continued to
flourish in the speculations of the later Indian philosophical schools.H lt rs the
defioition that p.coduced the most roetapbysical of ideas, such as the conception of the "inner controller" (antaryiimin) chat tums out to be the permanent
and eternal self or souJ (atman). Any form of perceptioo, fot them, involved
self-awareness as a necessary pre-condition, after which every ocher form of activity follow~. In fact, ater oo Nagarjuna devotes an entire chapter (IX) to an
examination of this notion of an antecedent self. Whether this view influenced
the Yogacara conception of "self-perceiving consciousness" (s11a.raf{1vedaka11ijfifina) remaios to be scen. For Nagarju.na, however, sucha defioition was not
sat:isfactory, sioce it implies the conception of a substantia entiry.
Here again. after ma.king a categorical denial of "eeing" as "seeiog itsef,"
Nagarjuoa procecds to draw the implication, as he did in his criticism of othcrnature (para-bh'iiva, 1.3) , that "if seeing cannot see itself, how caQ it see .
another?" Such a cridcism on the part of Nagarjuna would srill Jeave inract che
Buddha's owo expianatioo of perceptual experience in terms of the pciociple of
dependence (prafitya.ramutpada). Cn fact , it is for this reasoo that ater on
38
fNTRODUCrJON
39
it would imply thar macerial form is without a cause (ahet11ka) ." However,
Nagarjuna's empiricist and analytical approach does not allow him to recognize
an effect (artha) which is without a cause (ahetuka).
Existence (bh'ii11a), wbich Nagarjuna was ofreo criticizing iroplied selfexistence (s11ahha11a). The fact that the Sarvastivadins defined not only materia
form, but also the other four aggregates-feeliog, perceptioo, disposition, and
consciousness-as self-exiStent entities (bh'iiva) is evident from Nagarjuna's
statement at IV. 7. Thus, Nagarjuna's basie criticism of the Sarvastivadins in
this chapter is that they could not consistently speak of a unique cause
(karar,a), while at the same time recognizing a cause and an effect that arc
related by way of self-nature (svabhava). In other words, the notion of selfcausation (svatotpath) contradicts a "unique cause" (kara?Ja) , for it is anythlog
other than itself.
5. Elements (dhatu) . In the early Buddhlst tradition, the psychophysical personality was ~ysed into five agg,regates (skandha) in order to show that there
was no permanent spiritual entity or self (atman) as recognized by the traditional Indian phllsophers. Therefore, rhe psychic part of the personality was
analysed in detail. In order to refute the view of the Materialists that the eternal
entity is matter, not a spiritual or psychic entity, the Buddha once again analysed
the human personality in to six elements ( dhatu) with a detailed examinatioo of
the physical part of the persooality. 'rhus we have the category of eements consisting of earth {Prth111) , water (apm) , fue (tejm), air (vayu) , space (akafa) and
consciousness (vijiina).
While the cooceptlon of a "unique cause" (karafa) was iotroduced in the ex.
amination of the aggrcgates (skandha), the notion of "characteristics" (lakf al'Jtl)
is brought into the analysis of elements (dhatu}. Though the term
"characteristic" (Pali lakRhaf!a) occurs in the eady discourses, there it is not used
in the rnetaphysical sense in which it carne to be empoyed by the Sarvastivada
school. For t he Sarvastivada, a characteristic (lak,aa) represented the changing
. aspect of an entity (dhtlf'l1t4), while self-nature (svabhiiva) stood for the un
changing and eternal aspect. This particular notion of "charactetistic" needs to
be kept in rniod when analysing the cootents of Chap ter V.
A "characteristic" is cvaluated here in relation to an existent (bhiva) which
posscsses self-nature (svabhava) . For the Sarvastivaclins, this existent was a
dharma. Hence, very often we find Kumarajfva utilizing the tecm fa ( = dharma), in its restricted sense, to render bhava(yu), which is an indication that he
too was aware of the nature of the concept analysed by Nagarjuna. Nagarjuna's
major endeavor hece is to demonstrate the difficulties that ar.ise when speaking .
of charact.eristics (lak,a11a) in relatioo to eternaJ or absolute existence (bh411a} as
well as nihilistic non-existencc (abhava).
40
WA y
This analysjs becomes all the more 'important because of the way bhava and
abhava are treated hece. Nagarjuna's condusion is sigi:iificant: "Those people
of itde inrelligence who perceive the existence (t11tilva) as we11 as the nonexistencc (nastii-va) of existents (bhava) do not perceive the peaceful appeasement of the object (dratfavya)"(V.8).
In .the Buddhist text:S, including the Karika, we read more often about the
appeasement of obscssion (prapaflcopasama) . However, for the first time,
Nigarjuna introduces the nocion of the appeasement of the "object"
(dra1tavyopaiama). Why?
It was mencioned eadier that the Buddha's ruscourse oo the aggregates (skandha) was incended to refuce the nocion of a spiritual self (atman) and the
discourse on eemencs (dhatu) was meant to reject the notion of.a materia self
or eteroal matter. If this supposition is correct, we have no difficulty in
understanding the reasons fot Nigatjuna's introduction of the idea of appeasing the object. The objects of perception associated with the first five sense
faculties a.re materia!. If the Materialists wece looking for a self (atman) in matter and the Sarvascivadins wece looking fr .a seJf-narure (svabhava) in the
same, the best advice a oon-substantialist like Nigarjuoa could give such pe~
ple is to "vaporize or liquify" the object, and avoid grasping afcer ie. For Nigarjuna, there was no difference becween self (atman) and self-nature (svabhava).
While they carry the same philosophical impUcatioos, their praccical consequences are also similar, in that both lead to grasping and, therefore, suffering.
Abandoning grasping (upadana) for the object, one elin1inates the
metaphysical beliefs pettaining to eternal existence ("stitva) and oihilistic nonexistence (nastat1111). Hence the emphasis on che appeasement of the object. l ndeed, "the appeasement of the object" (drartavyopafama) is the means by
. which one can realize the ''oon-substantiatity of phenomena" (dharmanairii.tmya) and it does not mean the eiminatioo of the object.
Unles one were to keep in mind this particular cootext in which Nagarjuna
was emphasizing the "appeasement of the object," ie would be easy to assume
that here Nigarjuna was justifyiog idealism (11ijfiana11ada). Candr~rci's comments, unfortunately, lead to such unwarranted condusioos.n
6. Lust (raga) . The Buddha coosidered lust (raga) to be the cause of most of the
llls of life, the worst of these being bondage. Freedom (niroaf!a) was th'us defined
as absence of Just (vairagya). Not ooly did he speak of !ust and absence of Iust,
he also often spoke of people who are lustful (rakta) and free from lust
(virakta). Yet, all such statements were made with no assumpcion of a co.ocealed
substaoce (svabhava) or of a mysterious spiricual or materia! personality . The
analyscs offaculties (indriya), aggregates (skandh4) , and elements (dhatu) we re
. .intended to demonstrate rhe futility of such assumptions. However. the Sar-
INTRODUCTION
41
42
8. Action and agent (karma-k11mka). While "depenaently arisen (pratTtytJJamutpanna) phenomcna imply a process of natura1 occurence "uncondfrioned by dispositiooaJ teodencies1' (tJJaf!Jskrta) on the part of human
beings, "dispositiooally conditioned" (s(J1(Zskrta) pbenomena are the .results of
human deliberations (saf!Zskiira) or accions (karma). For this reason, after clari:fying the notions 9f the "conditioned" and the "unconditioned," it was natu.tal
for Nagarjuna to take a look at the notions of action (karma) and agent
(k"iirt1ka) . If these two wete found to be real in a substantialist sense, theo the
lengthy analysis of "conditioned" phenomeoa in the previous t.hapter would
appear faulty.
.
Therefore, Nagarjuna begins with a substa.ncial agent (sadbhuta kiiraka) who
performs a substantia11y existing action (sadbhuta karma) and his analysis
demonstrates chat such an agent as well as such an action, in face, logicaily lead
to a denial of action (kriy'ii) , agent (kartr) as well as a cause (kiiraf/a).
lNTRODUCflON
43
The statement at Vlll.12 that both action and agent arc dependenty
(pralitya) acisen and that there is oo other perceivable mannec in which these
could be' estabished (nanyat pajiimaf? siddhikaraf!af!J) stands as an eloquent
testimony to Nagatjuna's vindication of the empirical standp.oint of the Buddha and of eary Buddhism.
'
9. Antecedent stale (of the self) (purva). If there were to be no subscantial ac:
cioo and agent, exc:ept the empirically gjven action and agent which are the
results of dependence, ho\V is it that metaphysicias carne to assume the existence of such an eteroal self or persooality?
Io Chapter IX, Nagarjuoa uodertakes to show how the belief in a pecmanent
and eternal entity arises as a result of the recognition of the exiscence of a person.ality prior (purva) to his experieoces such as seeing, heariog, and feelings
(IX.1). In other words, the Buddhist metaphysicians, foUowiog a method
similar to tbat adopted by Descartes in Western phiJosophy, were positjng a
substantiaJ eatity and theu p.rocecding to attriburc the funccions of seeing and
hearing to tbat entity. It is hard to believe that a philosopher like Nagarjuna
was unaware that the Buddha's notion of non-substaotiality (anat1114n) was the
direct result of his rejeccion of such a perspective, vety clearly expressed by the
Buddha in a passage in the Sutta-nipata: "Let bim' destroy the eocire root of
obsession, [oamely, the belief) 'I think, [therefore] I am," (mantii asm"itz). 80
This indeed is an unequivocaJ rejectioo of the ucogito ergo sum" (1114ntfi
asmz) wbich contrihuted to the substantialist thought of the Upani/ads as well
as later Indian thought. Nagarjuna's arguments shows how self-destructive
such an assertioo is. The implication of this assertion, as Nagarjuna perceives, is
that such a personality has to be separated from the experieoces that emerge
subsequently. Nagarjuoa wants to know how sucha personaity could be made
known (parjfJapyate) independent of such experiences (IX.3) thus implying
that the sum (aham a.rmz) is tlependenc. If rhese experiences can be separated
from the personaity, it follows that they could occur eveo witbout sucha persooaity (IX,4).
Having explained cettain ocher implications of this metaphysical position, aJJ
of which he considers to be uosatisfactory, Nagarjuna maiotains tbac with
44
regard to such a personality the concepts of existence and non-existence are not
validly applicable.
10. Fire and fuel (agritndhana). The futility of employing the example of the
fire (agnt) and fue (indhana) in order to ilustrate the relationship between a
substantial action and a substantial agent is shown in Chapter X. It is indeed
the. most important metaphor used by the substantialists to establish the conception of a metaphysical person. The manner in which che Pudgalavadias
utilized this metaphor is explained .in detail by Vasubandhu in the final
chap ter of his Abhidharmakoa- bh'?i!Ja (see annotation on Chapter X). Finally
he refuses to recognize those who admit the reality of a self (atman, pudgala) as
weU as those who uphold discrete substaorial entities (bhava), as people who
are conversant with the true meaning of the Buddha's teachings (X.16). It is
elear that the reference herc is not to the non-Buddhist metaphysicians, but
rather to the Buddhist metaphysidans who claimed themselves to be the tt:ue
interpreters of the Buddha-word, oamely the Sautrantikas ( =pudglavadins)
and the Sarvastivadins ( =svabhavavadins).
11. Prior and posterior ends (p'iirv'iiparako{t). The refutation of the prior existence of a substantial being or entity would stili leave open the question
regard.ing the beginning and end of things. Speculations regarding the beginning (purva-koti) wd the fina end (apara-ko) have occupied the atteation of
phiJosophers from the dawn of bistory. These speculatioas have given risc to a
wide variety of beliefs, one of which is the substantial cxistence of a being (such
as God) or an ultimate entity (such as pricnordial maner, pr~rti, sometimes
referred to as svabhava).81 Realizing the epistemological problems involved in
these speculations, the Buddha refraioed from mak.ing an.y state01ents regard~
ing such issues.
Chapter XI ,is i tended to explain the Buddha's attitude towards such ques
tions. Nagarjuna was aware that the Buddha refused to make any statements
about the prior end of the life-process. Hence his statement: "The Great Sage
has dedared that the prior end of the life-process is not known" (XI. I).
However, the Sanskritization of the Prakrit cerm anamalagga ( = "inconceivable
is rhe beginnmg") as t1na11aiiigra ( = "wirhout beginning and end") had already
appeared in the Buddhist texts that Nagarjuna was familiar with. 82 Taking this
lattet version of the Buddha's statemeot, Nagarjuna maintains that there is
neither a beginning nor an end, whereas the Buddha's own statement perta.ined to the epistemologica1 difficulties.
Yet, Nagarjuoa's ingeouity was such that he was able co indicate the Jogical
difficu1ties involved in any denial of either the beginning or the end. For he
finds that "no middle can be conceived of chat which is without beginning or
INnoouCTioN
45
end" (XI. 2). Because of such logical difficulties, he maintains that prior and
posterior as well as sjmultaneous srates (of SPf!l-s'iira) arc not appropriate, These
logkal difficulties arise primarily becauc entities are conceived of in. a rather
substantialist way. Thus, if birth were to be considered as being prior to old age
and death, and birtb as well as old age and death are substantial, thar is, existiog in their owo nature (svabhava), then there will be birth without old age
and death, which implies immorrality (XI.3). Moreover, if they were to be se!fex.istent, there would be no causa! connection between them (Xl.4). Similar
logical difficulties arise if they wete considered as being simultaneous.
While the Buddha was unwilling to cliscuss the absolute origin and end of
the life-process (saf!J-sara) and yet continued to speak of things arising and passing away on the basis of causa! dependence, Nagarjuoa bad to deal with che
notion of the life-process interpreted in a more substantialist way by the Buddhist metaphysicians. Thercfore, after ma.king the remark that the prior end of
s<1f!1-satt1 is not evident, a position upheld by the Buddha himself, Nagarjuna .
proceeds to maintain that "the pciot end of all existents is also not evident"
(sarve1am qpi bh'iivfinaf!J-pur:v'ii ko# na vidyate, Xl .8), theteby rejecting all the
views of the substanriaJists.
12. Suffen'ng (du'1kha). After analysing the nature of e.xistence and a.doping a
middle position between the two extreme views presented by his fellow Buddhist phi1osophers, Nagarjuna focussed his anention on the problem of human
suffe.ring (duf7kh11). Herc again, it is difficult to believe that Nigarjuna was
unaware of the statements of the Buddha as .recorded in the Nikayas and
Aga.mas. His analysis of suffering follows ex:actly the line that was followed by
the Buddha in the Acela-kau11pa-sutt11 of the Samyutttt-nikaya. 0 Herein, when
a disciple by na.me Kassapa quesd.oned che Buddha as to whether suffering is
self-caused (sayat?t kataf!l- dukkhaf!J-), the Buddha, without saying: " l t is not so"
(no h'etaf!l-), wbich is a formal negation, merely remarks that "he should not
speak so," or "shoud not put it that way" (ma h'evllf!J). Kassapa elicits the same
response from rhe Buddba when he questions him as to whetber "suffering is
caused by another" (paraf!l- kataf!J- dukkhaf!l-) or whethet it is "caused by both
self and other'' (sayaf!l- katan ca paraf!J- katan ca) or whether it is "caused neither
by oneself nor by another" (asayaf!J-k'ifraf!J- aparaf!l-k"iiraf!J-) and, therefote, of
"spontaneous origin" (adhiccasamuppannar?Z)
The reason why the Buddha d iscoutaged Kassapa from reflecting oo the
cause of suffering in this manrlet was that he felt thac the first two views led to
beliefs in permanence (sassata) and anojhiJation (11cch~da) respectively. In the
background in which the Buddha preached , to say that "one acts and the same
person experiences the consequences" (so karoti so pafis1111P11ediyat1) implied the
46
THE
existeoce of an eternal soul or self, and to maintain that "one acts and another
expedences the coosequences" (afJo karoti ano parisa111vediyatt) was taken to
mean annihilation, that is, absence of any connection between act and consequence. This was tantamount to a denial of mora responsibility. Avoiding
these two extremes, the Buddha explained the rdation between action and consequences as one of dependence.
lt wouJd be necessacy to keep in mind that in the above context the Buddha
was not denying the four theories of the causation of suffering. H e was merely
stating that the theories as presented were not sacisfactory, because of the implications drawn by the metaphysicians. However, a.ter warn.ing that one
should avoid such implications and explaining the dependence f such
phenomena, the Buddha used similar linguistic expressions in order to explain
his view of the causation of suffering. Recognizing one's responsibility for one's
owo actions, he was even wiling to say: ''An action is performed by oneself'
(attan'li va kataf!t kammaf!t) 184 so long as one does not assuroe the existence of a
metaphysical agent or ignore any other factor chat contributes to the situation.
Following the same method, Nagarjuna (Xll. l), instead of denying these
possibilities, merely says that tbey are not proper (na yujyate). The reason for
this is that "if [suffetlngJ were to be considered self-caused, theo ie will not be
dependeotly arisen" (Xll.2). Here then is a distinction between self-causatioo
and dependence, a distinction based upon the assumption or the nonassumption of a metaphysical agent respectively . Therefore, Nagarjuna maintains: "These aggregates appear dependent upon these other aggregaces."
However, this latter view should not be takeo as meaning "enernal causation"
(parakrta).
lNTilODUCTlON
47
can
48
is the litera! meaning of sa'T!"Riira), our interests play a dominant role. lncerests
arc easily converted to likes and dislikes, and tbese lattet arc causes of most
human suffering. We are, therefore, in a double-bind. We need the S!Jf!Jsliiiras
in order to live. On the contrary, they can contcibute to most of out sufferLng
(du/?kha).
Realizing this face, the 'Buddha emphasized the need to pacify our dispositions rather than eliminate them competey. Thu~ , on the basis of expericnce
we come to know that things arc "depcndenty arisen" (prafftyasamutpanna)
and then adopt the view that in the dim past this may have been the case and
thac in the future it may be che case.
In the cyes of the Buddha this represencs a moce comprcheosive and,
thereforc, amore appropriate view (samyag-dr1ti) rathcr than the morc limited
views: (1) which says: "Suffering is self-caused" (svayaf{Jkfla'f?i), which is the
resut of our believing in a self (atman) to the exdusion of every other factor,
and (2) which says: "Suffering is caused by another" (dul/khaf!J parakrtaf!J),
which is, in somc sense, the rcsult of out reluctance to admit our own rcsponsibility. ln both cases, out likes and dislikes havc domioated our dispositions,
and heocc our pcrspeccivc~ push us in two cliffctent d.irections. Such dispositioos1 domioated by our lik.es and dislik.es, evenrually misead us regarding
many of our experjences and thereby contribute to out suffedng and frustta
tions. In the Buddha's Yiew, therefore, the cessarion of sufferiog is synonymous
with ''non-grasping" after views89 which comes about as a result of the appeasement of dispositions.90 Cessation of suffering is not synooymous with not having views or not having dispositions. Ratber, it is synonymous with the appeasement of dispositioos.
lt is very appropriate, therefote, that Nigarjuna decided to wcite f chapter
on the dispositions (sa1!1-Skara) after his analysis of suffering (duh.kha).
However 1 what is m oce important is that this chap ter is eotirely devoted to an
examination of "views" (dr'!tc) as we as of the condition that give rise to
"wrong-" ot "coofused views" (mithya dr1ft), narody, confusion (mrfii). In
fact, the term saf!Jskara ~curs in the first verse only.
The encire chapter is devoted to an examination of the notions of the "existent" (bhava), the ''non-existent" (abhiiva), "self-nature" (111abha11a), etc. and
the mannet in which these could be avoided by adopting the conception of
"emptiness" (Junyafii), wfrhout allowing that notioo of emptiness to be an
obsession. Heoce his condusion; "The Victorious Ones have announced that
emptiness is the reinquishiog of all views. Those who are possessed of the view
of emptiness are said to be incorrigible."
We have rendcred the tetro ni4sara1}a occurting in the above verse as "relinquishing" in order to bring out the specific meaning that Nagarjuoa probably
had in miod. Many ioterprcters of Nigarjuna havc explained "erriptiness"
INTRODUCTIO!ll
49
~o
together into association (saf?Zsatga) the objecc (drlJ.!favya) and the subject
(draf!r) in order to have a visual perception (darana)? Nigarjuna begios this
chapter with a denial of sucha possibility. Io doingso he is specifically denying
the possibility of an association of evencs that ace considered to be ucimacely
distinct, and this idea is being emphasized in Kumarajiva's translation of
XlV. 1. The problems of idencity and difference chat arise as a result of such a
reductive analysis are once again deatly brought our in this chapter.
15. Selfnature (s11libh1111a). The problem of associacion (saf'!JJarga), discussed
above in the specific context of seer, objecr of seeiog, and seeing, arose as a
result of admittiag a self-nacure (svabhava) in each one. of these phenomena.
This provided Nigarjuna with an opportunity to come into grips with the most
difficulc issue he had to deal with, self-nature or substance. In our earier
discussions we have shown how the Sarvascivadins utilized thls conception to
explaio the relationship between a cause and an effect, Nagarjuna's basie argument against this notion of self-nature js that it contradicts the conceptioo of
the occutrence (saf!Jbhava) of an event depending upon causes and conditions
(bett~, pratyay4). Nagarjuna's understanding of self- namre is that it is not
made (akrtaka) by anything clse. It is not dependent upon causes and conditions for its existeoce; hence independent. A "caused substaoce," according to
bim, is a contradiction in terms. This analysis should, therefore, be suppleme.nted by bis analysis in Chapter I. As we have pointed out there, Nagarjuna was not denying eithe.r dependently arisen pbenomena or dependent atising. He was merely showing the inconsistency in explaining causaly conditioned
phenomena in terms of self-natute. lt is in the present chapter tbat he is giving
a definition of self-nature that contradicts the ootlon of dependent arising or
causation. He says: "lndeed, an unmade self-nature is also non-contingent
upon another," (akrtn'm.al/ svabhavo hi nirapekfai{ paratra ca) (XV.2). The
argument in Chapter I is tben repeated to show that in the absence of selfnature, thete can.not be other-natute (parabhava). Buddha's faroous discourse
to Katyayana, discussed at length at the beginning of this lnrroduction, is then
quoted in order to reject the "existent" (bhiva) or "self-nature" (svabhava) and
the "non-existent'' (abhava) or "other-nature" (parabh1iva). These thcn arc
aligned with views regarding existence (astitva) and non-existence (nastitva) .
Existence (astitva) is funher defined as the original or primordia existence
(prakrtt), a conception developed in the Siinkhya school of Indian philosophy
which had close affinity, if not identity, with the Sarvastivada conception of existence . The empirical and logicaJ difficulties iovolved in this conception are
then laid bace. Reiteration of the face that the beliefs in self-nacure and other:nature, in the ccistent and the non-ex.isteot. in existence and oon-existence,
lNTRODUCTION
)1
lead to bcliefs in permanence and aonihilation respectively provides a co.ntlusion to this rather significanc chapter.
The topics taken up for discussion in this seccion (Chapters Ul-XV), as
pointed out above, deaJ with elemencs of experience (dharma) which were
originaly explained in terms of dependence , but which were complicated by
the introduction of the notions of self-narure (svabhava) and other-narure
(parabh'iit!a), of metaphysica identity and absohae difference, by some of the
. later Buddhists. Nagarjuoa's attempt in this section was mainly difected at get
ting rid of the cooception of sclf-nature or idcotity (the notions of other-nature
or differcncc falling apart as a result). This is the way in which he attempted to
estabish the noo-subscantiality of clements (dharma- nairatmya). The nonsu bstantiaicy of the human personalicy (pudgala-nairalmya) turns out to be his
next cooccrn.
52
THE
humans can escape. The present chapter, therefore, focusses its attention on
this bondage to the life-process.
Wh.ile the discussion of the Sarvastiviida conceptio~ of sclf-nature (wabhava)
1ingers along in the ncxt few chapters, the Sautrantika theory of a
transmigrating personality (pudgala) emerges into prominence in the present
section. When it is said that ''dispositions transmigrate" (.raf!U/iaral/ saf!Uaranft), what is assumed is chat there is a subtle essence in the dispositions that
enabe them to be perpetuated. Niigarjuna's argument herc is more diaectica.
lf dispositions arc permanent, then therc is oo point in speaking of their
transmigration. For, transmigration implies moving from one position to
anothcr, disappearing in one place and appearing in another. If something is
permancnt, it is always present and thcre- is no quescion of its ceasing and arising. On the conuary, if thiogs arc impermanent, in the sense of being compkcdy destroyed (11ccheda), they will never transmigrate. Nagarjuna,
therefore, .maintains that jf a human being is Jooked upon in the above manner. ir is not possible to speak of his 'cransmigration (XVI.1).
The impression one gets from the available uaoslatioos of XVI. 2 is that
Niigarjuna rejects the theories ofaggregatc:s (skandha), faculties (fiyata.na), and
elements (dhitu).94 Yet, what is <leady stated herc is che early Buddhist posi
tion: "lt may be assumed that a person transmigrates. Yet such a person,
sought for in the flvefold way, in the aggregates, spheres and dements, does
not exist. Who then will transmigrate?"
Thus, the transmigration chat is denied is chat of a subte personality.
However, if transmigracion is understood as the contiouation of the faccors of
the human personality on the basis of causal dependcnce, Nagarjuna may not
have any objection against it.
The notion of bondagc that is ,criticizc:d tutns out to be the bondage of a
substaotfaJ entity to such things as dispositions. Jt is similar co che ootion one
finds in the Indian tradition where the permaoeat "self' (atman) is said to be
in bondage co the psychophysicaJ personality which is impermanent. Hence
Nagarjuna's argurilent that anyth.ing that is of the nature of arising and passing
away (utpada-vyaya-dharmin) is ncither bound nor rcleased. What is being
criticized herc is not the simple notions of bondage and release but those that
takc into considcration a substancial subject and its attributes.
The cooclu~g v~rse could easily lead to much misuoderstanding if the
significance of the relativc terms "whcrc/ there" (yatra/ tatra) are ignored. The
context specified herc with these teative terms is what ca.me to be discussed
befre, namely, the assumption of a substantial su,bject and the attribution of
various attributc:s to it. Thus, in a context where,some substantial subject is at
tributed with something called freedom (nirvi~a samliropa) or is strippc:d of
the lifepr91=ess (st1f?Zfarapdar1a'!a), therei there is no sense .in mllkiog._a
lNTllOOUCTION
53
d.iscrimination (11ikzlpr1) bctween frecdom and bondagc, for what is real, namcly,
the substancial subject, will rcmain the same. Or else, where nirvana is "teified"
(sam'iirop11) and the life-process is eliminated (apakar1a1Ja), therein too there is
no sense in ma.king such discrimina.tions. These being totally different from
one another, the knowledge of one would have oo relevance to the understanding of the other.
qucnces or fruitS (phala), a substantialist could not resist asking the question:
"Yet, does not the effect (phala) pre-ex:ist, before karma reacbes its matur ity?"
Such metaphysical inquiries, as pointed out earlier, Jed to the belief in ao
underlyiog substance (wabha11a) , which was criricized and rejected by Nagarjuna in Chapter I. And hece Nagarjuna is ooce again asserting the view that
such inquiries lead to the beJief in permanence (niiya~) . If one were to reject
sucha notion of permanence, theo karma and effect are separated in sucha way
that once the karma ceases, ie will not producc any consequeaces (niruddhaf!J
sal kif!l phalaf!l janay#yatt) . Thus we are back again in the permanenceannihilation (fiif11ata-uccheda) syndrome.
Verse 7 introduces the notion of a scries (saf!ll'iina) upheld by the atomistic
Sautrantikas, and the difficulties this generates are chen examioed in che few
verses tbat follow .
lt is rather uofonunate that this new situation arisiog from the metaphysicalJy
oriented q ucstion raised in verse 6 came ro be igoored by those who dealt with
verse 12. The term efa (this, such) in XVll.12 refers specificaJly to the sort of
thinking (ka/pana) involved in XVII .6 and Nagarjuna maintains that such
thoughts engeoder a multitude of insuperable difficulties (ba4a11rli ca mahata
ca dofiif!). lt is this particular way of thinking chat is considered to be inappropriate (nopapadyale) .
lndeed, at XVll.13, Nagarjuna suggests anotber way of thinking (ka/pana)
which is more apptopriate and which was extolled by the Buddhas, the
Pratyeka-buddhas and the Sravalcas: Lilce an imperishable promissory noce, so
is debt as well as action. lt is fouold in terms of realms and indeterminate in
terms of prima! oarure. "
According to this, karma is imperishable like a promissory note. Ooe's debt
(rtJa) remains effective at least as Jong as the promissory note lasts. Even though
there is no continuiry of karma (and, it in this case, borrowing), that is, it does
noc contioue in any subcle or substantiaJ way, the responsibility for that karma
cannot be deoied once that karma is performed . The Buddha, the early Buddbists, and Nagarjuna were not prepared to say that the promissory note one
signs is uruea and therefore to be igoored. The responsibiliry and commitment
remains long after the docurnent is sigoed (maybe even if the document were to
be lost or desrroyed).
The idea that one is responsible for one's own actions has been emphasized
by the Buddha. A statement in the Dhammapada reads: "Neither in the sky
nor in the middle of the ocean nor haviog entercd into a cleft of the mountains
is tbere a place on earth scen remainiog where a person would be releascd from
his cvil actioos, "97 The cxistence and the popularity of a sirnilar statcment
amoog the Buddhists who preserved their literature in Sanskric has aJready
been referred to. The.re is itdc doubt that Nagarjuna was aware of this st:ttement. This conception of the imperisbablc nature of karma thus turns out to be
lNTRODUCTION
55
56
lNTRODUCTION
57
from this conteit is to make it not ooly "nihiliscic" (ucchedt1, XVIII.20) but
aJso absoJutistic and hence a metaph)'skaJ "view" (drffi, XVIII.8).
A super:ficiaJ glance at XVIII.6 may leave the impresion tbat Nigarjuna
viewed truth or reality as being beyond conceptualization. However, a more
careful consideration of the contents, especiaJly in the light of the teachings of
the Buddha as embodied in che ''discourses" would indicate that this is not the
case, Nigarjuna seems to have been fully cognisant of the Buddha's use of the
term "self'' (Pali, atla; Sk. 'iitmt1n) to explain individuality, and his atcernpt to
reject a metaphysicaJ entity when he spoke of "no-self'' (Pali, flmlllfl, Sk.
anatman). This does not involve two languages: a ptovisional ot ordinary and
philosophical.99 Tt is a question of two definitions. lf the "elf' ' is defined as a
permanent and subStaDtiaJ entity, the Buddha was ready to negate it with his
conception of "no-self'' (11n'iitman). lf it was not defined as such, he bad no difficulty in utilizing that conception in his discourses. Nigarjuna's understanding of the Buddha's intentions is clearly demonstrated in the first line of
XVUI.6, when he said: "The Buddha's have made known the conception ofself
and taught the doctrine of no-seJf." When, in the second line, Nigarjuna
maintained: "They have not spoken of something (kafcit) as the self or as the
non-self," he was certainly denying the conceptions of self-natute (svabhava)
and other-nature (parabhiva) of phenomena admitted by the Sarvastivadins
and the Sautrantilcas respectively.
With the above statement Nagarjuna couJd have concluded his chaprer on
the "self' (atman). However, there was one mote significant issue to be resolved. Up to this point he was discussing an embodied self, a self assoc.iated wirh a
psychophysical personality. The question regardiog the self that is freed from
the psychophysical personality aso had to be examined, for it was the belief of
the substantialists tbat when a person attains freedom his permanent and eternal self, dissociated Erom the psychophysicaJ personaUty, concinues to exist after
death. The two verses that follow (XVIIl. 7-8), therefore, arc iotended to oplain the Buddha's view regarding the nature of a person when be attains
parinirv'iir,a.
What happens to the freed person al death was clearly expressed by the Buddha. He ceases to exist, is not rebom, his birth has waned (khi'!'ii j'iitt), and there
is no further existence for him. 100 Yet, if someone were to ask him the question
as to whetherthat person exists in some form after death (param marmfa), the
Buddha was not willing to say anything, primatily because there was no
episcemological l>asis oo which'any predication can be made. 101 With verses 7
and 8, Nigarjuna is attempting to state this very same idea. "When the realm
of thought has ceased, that which is to be designated aso bas ceased."
"ReaJm of thought" (ciJltlgocara) that has ceased (nivrtta) can refer to the
pc~son who is frecd (Pali parinibbultl, Sk. pari-nirvrta) without his thought being (e-established (appati{(hitena cittent1). 102 The difficulties that would arise if
58
someone were to ask the further question as to what happcns co him when his
thought proccss has ceased or is not re-established is thcn e.xplained. "That
which is to be designated has also ceased." This is ideocical with the Buddha's
statement: "That by which one shouJd spea.k of him does not cxist for him"
(yena naf!l 1)(Jjj"u laf!l tarsa n' aJtht). 0~ Indeed, the term dharmata is used in the
verse to refer to the narure of the freed one who has passed away. lt is not possible to ~en whether he has ariseo (utpanna) after death or whethcr he has ceased
to e.xist (niruddha) after death.
One of the epithets by wh.ich the "enlightened one" (buddha) carne to be
described is tathagata, mcaning "one who has thus gone." This term gave rise
to much controversy probably because of the metaphysical implJcations of the
term "thus'' (tatha). And it is interesting to note chat in the early discourses
whenevcr the qucstion regardiog the nacure of the freed one after death is raised
the term used to rc:fer to him is tathiigala.
The term tatha ("thus" or "such") involves the epistemologicaJ problem of
"reality," as opposed to no tatha ("not thus"). Hence the sccondary derivative
taccha (Sk. tathya) carne ro be used in the sense of what is true or reaJ. 04 Jt is,
therefore, not surprising to see the term tathiigata being utilized when ever the
quesrion regarding the de1ti'ny of the freed one is raised, 1os for in the eyes of the
ordinary man no ocher question would be more important thao the ultimate
de.rtiny of the freed one. AJ; meotioocd ear iec , for cpiscemologica rcasoos, the
Buddha cefused to make any assertions, either positive or negarive, ccgarding
this problem. Nigarguna's application of the fourfoJd negation (catu1kot1) to
the conccption of "suchoess" (tathya) comes immediately after his discussioo of
the nature (dht1rmal4) of the frced one who has rcached his fina destiny. It is
the same context in which the Buddha himself applied the fouod negation.
The four-corncred negation is always uscd by the Buddha to avoid metaphysics,
and the desciny of the lalhiigata was one of thosc popular mctaphysical isrues.
Nagarjuna could noc have been uoaware of the metaphysical assenions of the
prc-Buddhist thiokers who assumed chat a "freed self' ('iitman) becomes uoited
with the all-pervading universaJ self, the reality in cverything (saroattt). The
dangcrs involved in the Sa,-vastivada concepcion of substaoce (1vabbava) in
everything (saroaf?Z) and how such an idea could influence the intcrpretation of
a ta1hagata or tathya was, indeed, evident to Nagarjuna. Thus, we have ewo
metaphysicaJ issues combined herc-one of "everyching'' (1ar11"f!l) and the
othcr of tathya-aod the fourfold negation was the only reasonable soJucion
that Nagarjuna could provide. To explain the conception of "suchness"
(lathya) going beyond the context of the problcms of "everyching" and che
"thus gooe one" (talhiigata) after death would undoubtedly lead to a discortion
of the philosophicaJ standpoint of Nagarjuna.
1NTRODUC1JON
59
As mentioned befote, the Buddha was not williog to speculate on the nature
of the freed one afcer death (param-marafa) but that he was willing to speak
positively about what happens to him at death. In a passage in the Agutt4ra
nikaya the Buddha's understanding of this state is succincntly expressed in the
following verse: "This is the last body and is the essence of the higber life . In
regard to that this perfect knowledge has arjsen without depending upon
another." (Asekhafiii'f!ll'f(l uppana'l(J antimo ya'f!' samussayo, yo saro
brahmacariyassa tasmzftJ. aparapaccgya.) 106 This realization is elsewhere explained
in a stock passage: "Birth has been eliminated, the higher life has been lived,
clone is what needs to be done and there is nor aoocher of this flife) ." 107
This is the highes.r realization that one can attain and is referred to in the
discourses as anfUi. 10s lt is the result of the moraJ perfection one attains by be
ing freed from the three poisons: greed, hatred, and confusioo . lt is fina nirvana, and may jusdy be called the ultimate mora truth about the world (see p.
15 above). As such it is to be realized by oncsolf and is not a state to be known
by depencling upon another (aparapaccaya ).
When, therefore, concluding the discussion of the freed one after death,
Nagatjuna proceeded to speak of tattva ("reality"), he was not refeniog to an
"ultimate truth" per se but to the realization and attaioment of freedom from
birth. Hence he asserts that the knowledge of this truth is not dependent on
another (aparapratyaya). lt is peaceful (fiinta), uoobsessed by obsessions
(t1prapancita). and, hence, non-cliscrimioacive (niroikalpa) and noncontradictory (ananartha) . Nirvikalpa does not necessarily mean the absence of
t he subject-object discrimination. It means the abseoce of any discrimination
based upon one's likes and dislikes, one's obsessions. Conceptions of identity
and difference, permanence and annihiliation arc theri rejected as beiog part of
the Buddha's teaching. This is because thiogs arc recognized as being
dependencly areisen (prafitya ... bhavatt).
The conclusion of the chapter represeots Nagarjuna as one who remains
aloof from the so-called Hlnayana-Mahayana conflir.t. He asserts that in the
noo-emergeoce of the Buddbas and the waoing of the Sravakas, the knowledge
of the "truth" continues co be perpetuated by the Pratyeka-buddhas , even
without association with the Buddhas. The need to depend p,rimarily upon an
unbroken tradition or an uninterrupted line cf pacriarchs for the perpetuation
of the "true docttine" is discounted hete.
19. Time (kala). Io the discussion of the notion of imperishable action (atlipraf!'iifa-karma) discussed above, .two more conditions relevaot to tbe fruitioning of karma were mendoned, namely, time (kala) and harmony (fiimagff).
60
These two topics constitutc the subject mattcr of the next ewo chapters.
Time was conceivcd in a moce empirical way in the early discourses. Itnpermanence (aniccafii) was explained there in terms of the temporaHty of evcnts.
As meotioncd in the analysis of the conditioned (VII). such temporality was
understood as arising (uppiida), ceasing (vyaya) , and change of what cndures
(thitassa aflfJathatta). However, the problems created by the Sarvastivadins and
the Sauuantik:as by their analysis of time and temporaity have already been
aluded to (sec the discussion of the "Condicioned" above). There, the focus
was more on the substantiality of eventS (conceived as bhii11a) and the difficulties that arise as a result of attcmpting to place such "existents" (b/J4va) in
the context of tempol'ality. The present chapter is devoted to the conception of
cime itself, especially time as analysed by the metaphysicians into discrete
moments (k!M!tl). Nagarjuna's analysis brings out the disastrous implications
of such a notion of time and could approptiatdy be compaced with an analysis
provided by E. R. Clay and enthusiastically adopted by William James in
Westetn philosophy. Examining the ordioas:y notion of cime, Clay says:
The relation of cxpcrience to time has not been profoundly
studied. l ts objects arc givcn as bcing of the ptesent, but the part of
time referrcd to by the daturo is a very different thing from the conterminous of the past and future which philosophy denotes by the
oame Present. The present to which the datum refers is teally a part
of the past- a recent past - delusively given as being a time that intervenes between the past and the future. Let it be named the
specious present, and et the pas't, that is given as being the past, be
knowa as the obvious p ast. All the notes of a bar of a song seem ro
the Hstener to be contained in the present. All the changes of place
of meteor seem to the beholder to be contained in the present. At
the instance of the termination of such a serie~. no part of the time
measured by them seems to be past. Time, then, coilsidered
relative to human apprehension, consists of fout parts, viz,, the obvious past, the specious present, the real present and the future.
Omitting the specious present, it consists of three . .. noneotities- the past, which does not exist, the future which does n ot
exist, and their contetcnlnous, the present; the faculry from which
it proceeds lies to us in the fiction of the specious present. 109
Nagatjuna's analysis indicatcs, in a similar way, how a metaphysical notion
of time would lead to the abolition of the very notion of time as "specious."
Furthermore, the metaphysical notion of time, as propounded by the Satvastivadins and the Sautrantikas, also involved the conception of substantial ex-
61
lNTitOOUCTION
istence (bhtiva), the de nial of which would resut in the deniaJ of that panicular
conception of time.
20 . H4rmony (s/if!JtJgn). The anaJysis of the causal process in terms of discrete
momentaiy event.s eliminated the possibility of explaining harmony as part and
parcel of the eventS that combine to produce the effect. With such discrete.
events harmony becomes an attribute. Such a problem was not faced by the
Buddha wheo he expiained dependence of events because such events were
recognized as related events rather than discrete ones. Thus, the Buddhist
metaphysicians were compelled eithcr to accept an immediately contiguous
cause (samanantara.pratyaya} where each event is caused by an immediatdy
preceding event, or make barmony an attribute of such discrete events so that
their assemblage could provide.a rationale for the production of the effect. The
problem of causation recciYed the foremost attention of Nagarjuna, as is evi- .
dent from Chapter I. The difficulties involved in explaining the arising of the
fruit or effect (phala) on the basis of a metaphysical nocion of harmony _are further elaborated herc. Once again, what is denied is not the arising of the fruit
or effect, for that was the central philosophy of Buddhism, but only the mannet in which such arising is described by the metaphysicians. Hence
Nagatjuna's conclusion: The effect is not made by the harmony, nor is it made
by a oon-harmony. "Where can there be harmony without an effect?" (XX.24).
62
W/\Y
(becoming) and was contrasted with the Indian notion of life as eternal ex
istence (atthit'ii, Sk. astilva) .
While the concepts of atlhiflz (existetlce) and n' atthitii ( non-existence) wece
. used in the pre-Buddhist literature, the Buddha, realizing the rnetaphysical
implications, avoided them and instead utilized the notion of bhava (becom
ing). No sooner than the Buddha explained the human personality as a process
of becoming, the metaphysidans of che traditional schools of Indian
philosophy began speaking of bhava (instead of astitva) and abha'Va (instead of
n'iistitva) when speaking about . existence and oon-existence respectivey. ewo
terms which wece not popular in the Indian tradition before rhe Buddha.
The Sarvastivadins and the Sautrantikas, who were lured into this substan
tialist trap as a result of their analysis of the process of becomlng (bhava) ioto
discrete moments, formulated che notion of a "secies of becoming" (bhavaIa'f?Zf4tt), instead of the "stream of becorning" (bhava-sota) referred to in the
early discourses. Buddhaghosa, who introduced these different interpietations
ioto the Thervada tradition in the South and South East Asian countries (circa.
sixth cenwiy AD), discinguished between three different nocions of the present:
,,
li
111
l NTRODUCTION
63
follow deal with the non-substantiality of the person who has attained
freedom .
22. "Thus Gone One'' (tathagata). A host of epithets wete used to desr..ribe the
attainments of the person who was able to understand the narure of human existence and overcome the , sufferin~ associated with it. Two of therp. stand prominent. These were buddha or the "enligbtened one" and tathigata or the
"thus gooe one," and even these two terms were used synonymously. The first
of these describes the ideal achieved by one who was aspiring for knowledge or
unde.rstanding, an aspiration cleady expressed in the famous Upani~adic
statement: "Prom darkness, lead me to light," (tamaso miir{J jyntit gamaya). 112
In the Upani/ads, this enlightenment was nothing short of"omniscience" (satvajfia),t19 even though this term was not used in a technical sense. For the llud- .
dha, enlightenment is attained as a result of the realization of the means and
limits of knowledge (see the above analysis of the Kaccayanagotta-sutta).
The second cpithct, ltTthagata, led to morc misunderstanding and rnisinterpret1nion in the Buddhist context. As the term impues, it cxplains the ultimate
goal to be achieved by such enlightenment. lt represents an attempt t o answer
the aspirations of the human beings who were looking ft>r immortality avoiding
the endless cycle of births and deaths. In the Upani.fads it is expressed in the
staternent: "From death, lead me to immortality," (mrlyor maf?t amrtaf?t
gamaya). 11 ~ According to the Upani.fads, the "enlightened ooe" who under
stands the nature of the real self (atman), upon the dissolution of the
psychophysical personali ty, is united with the universal idea! self (brahman)
and thereby enjoys eternal life. The Buddha, who was not willing to admit the
cxistence of sucha state, merely maintained that the "enlighteoed one" (b11dt/ha) is also freed from continuous becoming (bhava). Hence, the tathagata or
the "thus gone one" is conuasted with one who is subjected to becoming
(bhava) or re-becoming (punabbhava).
With the attainment' of enlightennleOt and freedom from grasping
(upadiina), the freed one leads a happy and contented life, white at the same
time not longing for a future existence. Enlightenment (bodht) is synonymous
w.ith waning of craving (laf!hakkhaya) , However, the unenlightened person,
bound by craving and grasping,, not only looks for eternaJ life beyond the grave
(param marat{a) , but a1so expects to sec something more mysterious and aweinspiring (acchanya-abbhuta) iri the life of a freed one who is alive. It is for this
reason that two major questions were raised in relation to the conception of a
tathagata. The first is the question as to whether the tathagata is identical or
differeot from the psychophysical pers0oality . 11-' The second is the question as
to whether the tathagata survives the destruction of the psychophysical per~
sonality. 11 ' This may explain why, in th.e early discourses, whenevet such ques-
64
tions wece taised they wece raised more in relacion to a iathagata thao in connection with a buddha.
Thus, after a detailed examioation of the problems of human existence,
problems sucb as action, mora responsibility, or becoming, it was natural for
Nagarjuna to direct his attention to the questioos pcrtaining to the cooception
of ultimate goal as envisaged in Buddhism. In doing so, he was compelled to
deal, first of all, with the meaning of the concepi tathagata.
Nagarjuna's examination of the lathiigala follows the line of analysis found
in the early discourses. While early Buddhism coofronted pcoblems relating to
the tonception of tathagata because it was understood 1n terms of the notion of
a permanent and eteroal self (atman), Nagarjuna is hece struggling with the
same conception as explained in relation to the notion of a real subsance
(s11abha114). Nagarjuna was not willing to consider the tathagata, conceived in
such a metaphysical way, as identical with the aggregates (skandha). Th.is was
the Sarvasdvada position which Nigarjuna was rejecting (XX.Il.2). Nor was he
prepared to accept the alteroative suggcsted by the Sautrantikas, who emphasized non-identity or difference~ The notion of anatman (no-self) referred
to at XXII. 3 is really the coo(eption of ''other-nature" (parabhava) that was
propounded by the Sautrantikas. loada'.s explanation that "the vse of the term
anatman hece is not to be confused with the cardinal Buddhist doctrioe by the
same term,"116 therefore needs to be qualified as the "cardinal early Buddhist
doctrine." for the Sautrantikas we re guilty of propounding a tbeory ofanatman
which emphasized real difference. Nagarjuna was therefore ready to assert that
a tathagala conceivcd in terms of cithcr "sclf-naturc'' (svabhiiva) or "othernacure" (parabhava) is not evideot.
The question whether the Jathagata is dependent is taken up next. Its
dependence or independence is then rejected prirnarily because once again it is
understood in terms of substantial dependence (svabhiivata upadanatp,) or
substantial independence (which is the implicacion of "otber-nanue" or
parabhava)(XXlI.9). Views of tathigata as "empty" (u11ya) or "not empcy"
(au11ya) are coosidered, and these again are particular view ( expressed in the
iii-formula) and are therefore rejected.
How the notion of a living tath'iigala, conceivedof io a rather metaphysical
way. leads to the belief in a tathagata after death is explicity stated by Nagarjuna at XXII. l3. Nagarjuna's argument is that jf the tathagata were to be conside.red empty in terms of self-nature (svabhavatal/) , any thoughr of his beiog
existeot or oon-existent after death (para'(J-nirodhat) is not appropriate. This,
indeed, is the view expressed by the Buddha in the early discourses. 11 1
The concluding- statement of this chapter is rather significant, especially in
view of the narure of the "freed one" (nibbuta) or "freedom" (nibbana) as
enunciated in the early discourses. We have already pointed out that freedom
INTRODUCTION
65
23. Confusions (11iparyasa). The reasons for the misunderstaodings that prevail
rcgarding the narure of the enlighten.ed one (buddha) or the "thus gone one"
(tathagata) as weU as aoyching that takes place in the universe (jagat) are then
raken up for examination. Once agaio the nucleus of the chapter can be traced
back to the early discourses.
A discussion of the four types of confusions ( 11ipalliisa) relacing to perceptions
(sanna), thought (citta) , and views (diffht) is met with in the Aguttar.a
nikaya.118 The basie confusions rclatiog to thesc three differeot functioos are
given as follows:
1.
2.
3.
4.
The first three of these, in that particular order, arc generally .referred to as
the three characteristics (lakkha11a) of human existence, that is, impcrmanence
(anicca), suffec.iog (dukkha), and oon-substantiality (afllltta). Nigarjuna has
already dealc with these concepts at length (see Chapcers 11, Xll and XVlll).
Hence, he begins his analysis with the last, namely, the pure (Jubha) and impure (afubha). Thesc indced are value judgmeotS made by the human beings
and scrve as the foundacion of the reli.gious and spiritual life. However, in the
eyes of the substantialist phllosophers, these were ulrimate qualities, each having its owo narure (.rvabha11a) . With the first rwo verses, Nigarjuna sets the
tone of his criticism of tncse qualities, which aJlows hirn to move on to ocher
types of confusions subsequently. Whilc the interplay berween the qualities of
Jubha and aubha arc mentioned in verse 11, Nigarjuna's refuration of the
66
ultimatc reality of thcsc qualitics is bascd initially upon his rccognition of the
dependent arising of both.
The notions puricy and imputity, ike any other entities, have no ultimate
substaotial standing. Thcy are based upon lust (riiga), hatred (d11e1a) , and con.fusion (moha), wbich io turo arc the productS of thought or conccptualizatioo
(sarrz~pa) . The ccssation of Just, ha.tred, and confusion is generaly equaced
with "frcedom" (nifflaa). Hcncc, ie is geocrally assurocd that nirvt11!a is
beyond any conccptualization or thought. Tbis seems to be the manner in
which the notion of a "non-conceprual" and ultimatc reality (paramiirtha)
carne to be attributed to Nagarjuna and, hcncc, to all Madhyami.ka philosophy.
Early Buddhism refers to two forms of thought or conceptualization
(sa1r1kappa), che more comprehensive and, therefore, right rhought or conceptualization (sammii-sa1r1kappa) and the moce rcsuictcd and, thcrcfore, wrong
thoughc (micchii-sQtrJkappa). This is in no way different from whac Nagarjuna
discusscd in Chaptcr:XVIJ {12-13). wherc he distinguished thoughts(k.alpana)
chat arc pro~r (yojyale) from those chat arc inappropriate (nopapadyale).
In many instanccs, "thoughts" (sa1r1kalpa) and "dispositioos" (saf!l.Skii-ra).
two terms chat are semantically related, function in simiar ways. This is artcsted to by Nagarjuna's treatment of them. We have alrcady notcd how be
characterized "dispositions" as "confusions" (mr,r.i){XIII.1 - 2). This definition
was, in face, attribuced to che Buddha himself. In the presenc concext, speaking
of "confusions" (11iparyasa) , Nagarjuna introduces the notion of sa1r1kalpa and
proceeds to defrne it io terms of its consequenccs, namely, tbe generation of
Just, etc,
A carefuJ analysis of the notioos of sa~alpf1 and Jaf!l.Skiira in relation to
frecdom or ninili11a may clarify an importaot epistemological problem, l:roth in
early Buddhism and in Nagarjuna. We bave already referred to che fuoction of
dispositions (sankhara) in the context of cary Buddhism. They cannot be
eliminated exccpt at death, and arc, thcrefore, to be appeased (samalha,
upasa,na). This process of appeasement is to be acbieved by not clioging on to
any of che past disposirions whcn one has co deal with the problem of underscanding any situation . Hence, nibbana carne to be designatcd asankhata.
When speaking of the thoughts or concepts (sa1r1ktdpa), however, we are
prcscnted with two types, che right and che wrong. The right ones are to be
cultivated and the wcong ones eliminaced, a process not recommended in relatioo to dispositions. This dichotomy betwcen right and wrong thougbts could
have unsatisfactory implkations. Right choughts may be takeo as pointing to
true events ot phenomena, white the wrong ones ma.y indicate che absence of
such events or phenomena. This , indeed. was che subsrantialist trap which both
the Buddha aod Nagarjuna were anempcing to avoid. Therefore, without takiqg right choughts in the sense of absolutey uue ideas correspoading te
lNTROOUCTrON
67
24. Truth (satya). Thus we are led to the most important discussions in Nagatjuna, namely , the conception of the fout noble uuths (arya salya). The contents of this chapters have generared much discussion as well as controverty during the centuries that foowed its compilation. t the same time, this chapter,
more than any other, will serve as a glowing testimony to the fact that Nagarjuna was simpy restating the ideas expressed by the Buddha in the eacly
discourses, rather tban bringing <.i.bout a Copernican revolution in Buddhist
thought.
In the early. discourses, the fou r noble truths were meaot to explaio the
nature of human ex.istencc., bth in bondage and in freedom, avoiding the extrems of permanent existence (atthitii) and nihiListic non-exisrence (n'
atthita). The difficulties encountered by che Buddha in ma.king this view of existence iot.etligible to the substantialist thinkers of India are evident from the
kind of criticism thcy levelled against the Buddha. Very ofteo they criticized
him as a nihilist (n. 'atthikt#ilida, ucchedavada), insiscing that he advocated the
annihilation and destruction of che conscious being (s11to sattaua uccheda?!J
viniisaf!i pannapett). 11 9 This was not because the Buddha denied the existence
of conscious human beings, but because he was notwillingto accept an cternal
and immutablc self (attnan) in them. For he often insisted th.at a conscious
human being is empty (sunna) of a permanent and eternal self (atta) as well as
anything penaining to or bclonging to a sdf (attan-iya). 1l 0 The <lenia of sucha
self or substantiality was not ony in relation to a human personali cy but also in
connection with any experienced phenomena (.rabbe dhamtnli artatt"ii). 121
Nararjuna was placed in an identkaJ situacion as a result of his rejection of the
Sarvasdvada conception of self-narure. (s11qbhat1a) and the Sautrii;ntika theory
of other-nature (parabhiiva). The theoty of nn-substantiality (anatman) or emptiness (funyatii) that he attempted to explain in the ,prev.ious chapters was not
68
Nagarjuna had aJready devoted twenty one chapters (I-XXI) to the cxplicatioo of the first of these truths. Causaliry, space, time, motion, the human personality, action, consequence, good and bad-all of chese have been deat wich
ac lcngth . Explanations of these in terms of absoluce existence or nihiiscic nonexistence were rejected in favor of dependence (pratityasamutpada) and ,
therefore, of emptiness (funyatii). Artha or fruit of existence, wh.ether that be
good or bad, was rccognized. Attempts oo che part of the metap\ys icians who
wanted to perceivc with absoluce certainty how a cause produces an effec;c were
abaodooed, sincc such attempts Led to the recognition of unacceptable entities
such as self (atman) oc substance (111abha11a). The abandoning of such attempcs
lNTRODUCTION
69
did not lead l'fligarjuna on to the other extreme of denying any connection between cause andeffect, action and consequence. The element of uncertainty involved in the cause-effect relationship made him moce cautious tban either the
Sarvastivadins or the Sauttantikas, and hence he was mote defeosive and
negative in his descriptioru. Yet in no way did he want to abandon that princi
ple of explanation, Chapter XVII on "The Examination of Action and Consequence" (K11mra-phala-paiikfa) being the most illustrative example.
The fact that a human being, having understood the nature and functioning
of phenomena (dharma/;), attempts to achieve various desired results (artha) by
manipuJating such phenomena, was well known to Niigarjuna when he spoke
of both Ja?(lsliiiras and sa'(Jkalpas, However, the possibility of achieving
ultimate freedom (ni1'1l'ii1Ja) or the ulcimate fruit of existence
(paramiirtha)(somecimes referred to by the Theravada tradition as aggaphala,
Sk. agra-pha/4124), has now been questioned by _his opponents. Again, withouc
falling ioto the extremes of existence and oon-exiscence and recogniziag the
emptiness of all dependently arisen phenomena, Nagarjuna had to explain the
fruits (artha) as well as the ultirnate fruit (ptTramiirtha) of eidstence, fa speaking
of these rwo truths, if he had assumed that the latter traoscended the former ,
ht> would be presenting the ideas atttibured to the so-called Mahayana, rather
than quoting the ea.tly discourses or refening to the teaehings of the Buddhas,
Pratyeka-buddhas and the Sravakas. This, however, is not the case, for his explanation of artha as well as paramiirtha is couched in the same anguage, and
that was the Janguage of dependeoce and empriness. Hence his famous dicrum: "Withour rdying upon convcotion , the u1timate ftuit is not taught.
Without understanding the ulcimate fruit , freedom is not anained"
(XXJV.10).
.
Artha as well as paramartha are tru.ths (satya)~ The for.mer is not presented as an
un-trurh (a-satya) in relation to the latter, as it would be in a.o absolutistic
uadition . Neithet is the form er sublated by t he latter. There is no indication
whatsoever thac these are two truths with different standing as higher and
Iower.
The fruits of ordinary human cxistence (artha), understood in terms of t:Jermanent existence (svabh?i11t1) conflicred witb everything in expe.deoce: "If you
perceive the existence of the existence i n terms of self-nature, then you will also
perceive these a non-conditions" (XXfV. 16). This would lt>ad to a denial of all
phenomena such as effect (karya), cause (kara11a), agent (kartr), doing
(karatfa), action (kriya) as well as arising (utpada), ceasing (n.irodha), and fruit
(phala) (XXIV. 17). This compelled h.im to make the most famous of his
staements: "We state that whatever is dependent arising, that is emptine.ss.
That is dependent upon conventioo. That itself is the middle path''
(XXIV.18). Everything is placed in one basket, the basket of "dependent aris-
70
ing'' (prafityasamutpada). "A thi:ng that is not dependently arisen is not evident. For that reason, a tbing that is non-empty is, indeed, not evidenr
(ibid. 19).
With that analys.is, Nagarjuna was ready to defend the four noble truths,
reconciling it with his cooception of emptiness (ibid . 20-21). 'Whoever
perceives dependent arising also perceives sufferiag, its arising, its ceasing and
the patb [leadiog to its ceasing]," (ibid 40).
Buddl:ta's statement in the Majjhima-nikaya: "He who perceives d~pendent
arising also perceives the dh111nma," could not bave received better confumation from a disciple who was removed from the Buddha by ar least six centuries.
2S . Freedom (ni1iiina). This is undoubtedly the most significant chapter in the
book. The interpretacion of the contents of this chapter by Stcherbatsky12' has
d~minated the Western understanding of Madhyamika thought for a considerable pedod of time. Elsewhere, we have disagreed with Stcherbatsky's interpretation of early Buddhism, allowing hi:m his interpretation of
Madhyamika phiosophy. Since Stcherbatsky's perception of Nagarjuna was
colored by his understanding of carly Buddhism, the rejection of the latter
shoud mean the rejection of the former too, if we are to consider Nagarjuna's
philosophy as a continuation of the ideas of early Buddhism. Without devoting
much time to an examination of Stcherbatsky's views at this point, we will present the conrents of Ch?-pter XXV in the light of the analysis of Nagarjuna's
ideas that we have already presented.
Other modern scholars have rejected Stcherbatsky's ideas and have presented
views about nirvana that do not appeac to accord with what Nagarjuna has said
in the previous chapterse.. One of these is the view presented by Inada that nirvana represencs the ''uncreated realm'' (as4'(Jskrt4). 126 The view that nirvana, as
tJS4f!lJkrta, belongs to the "uncreated realm," a view which is popular with both
the so-called Theravada and M9.Myana interpreters (especialy of the modern
world), may lose its tenab,ility if the cootents of this chapter are analysed in the
Jight of what went before rather than in isolation.
Th~ attempt to explain Nagarjuna's conception as one that is found in the
Mahayana tradition is based upon a complete misreading of Chapters XVI-XXI
of the Kiin'k'iis that deal with the notion of the human person~ity, human
behavior, and mora responsibility. Such a misreading compels Inada to reject
the va!ue of the two chapters (XXVI-XXVU) that follow the chapter on nirvana
(XXV), saying: 11With the discussion of Nirvana in the last chapter the treatment from the standpoint of Mahayana had basically come to a close. In this
chap ter and the fina one to follow , Nagarjuna goes into the analysis of the
Hlnayana 4ctrines."121
lNTRODUCTION
71
Our aaalysis of the Kiin'kii1 so far did not reveal any specific Mahayana doctrine presented by Nagarjuna chat may be contrasted with the so-called
HToayana, and we have therefore no reason co look at Nagaruna's cooception
of nirvaoa as chat of Mahayana or reject the last two chapters of the ueatise as
being cepresentative of the Hlnayana docuines. In fact, to assume that such an
outstanding philosopher as Nagarjuna, who presented the world with such a
beautifuly executed philosophical classic, could simply add two chapters utterly irrelevant to the basie theme of his work does not contribute either to the
understanding of his philosophy or an appreciation of his genius.
Nagarjuna begins his analysis of nirvana anticipating the same kind of objection that the substantialist raised againsc reconciling "empciness" with the four
noble truths. "If alJ this is empty, there exists neither arising nor ceasing. [As
such) through the relinquishing or ceasing of what does one expect freedom? "
(XXV.l).
l t is necessary to keep in mind herc the conception of a thing (dharma) that
the substantialist envisaged, which was the main subject of scrutiny on the part
of Nigarjuna. The substantialist had cliffi.c ulty with the conception of empcioess (unyatii) primarily because an existent or phenomena (dharma) for him
was one that posscssed sdf-oature (111tZbha11a). As emphasized earlier, if not for
that assercion of the substantialist, Nigarjuna had no reason or provocation to
compose the present treatise. This is dearly evideot from Nigarjuna's immediate response to the substantialist: ''If all this is non-empty , there exists
neither arising nor ceasing. Through the relinquishing and ceasing of what does
one expect freedom?" (ibid. 2).
For N:igarjuna, to say thac soroething ~ not empcy (fZfUnya) means that ie has
subscantial existence (s-v11bha11a) du ring the past, preseot and future, and if so it
would be meaningJess to speak of its arising and ceasing. This would certainly
rcnder "freedom" impossible.
Once again, keeping the substantialist view in mind, would it be possible to
speak of "freedom" (nirva'!a) as the relinquishing of something that is
substa.cial and the attainment of someching completely new or different. This
was another importanc assertion of the substantiaJist. For him, "freedom"
represented a ~otaly different state of cxistence (astilva), an existence that is
not only perrnaneot and eternal but also perfccdy blissful and happy. Freedom
or niroatfa tbus curns out to be a metaphysical notion, like the Hindu
brahman, uncaused, uocreatcq and, therefore, beyond aUspadaJ and tempora!
determination. Consideriog these two views, namely,
1.
2.
72
73
INTRODUCTION
3.
used in any meaningful sense, did not signify either a complete interruption or eternality.
Non-ceased and non-arisen (aniruddham anutpannam)~ lt is
neither ceased nor arisen. Considering this pair of com- .
plementary characteristics independently and in isolation
from everything that has so far been said by Nagarjuna, it
would be very easy to assume that nirvana, in his view,
trancends all descriptions and characterization. However, if
wbat has been said about arising and ceasing, espedally the
chapters on "The Examinacion of Causality" (Chapter I) as
well as in "The Examination of Dispositions" (Chllpter VII)
were to be tak.en seriously, one would refrain from such
generalizatlons. Instead, the conceptions of arising and ceasing, as weU as the arisen and the ceased, would be placed in
the context of a substantialist view of either exitence (astitva)
or oon-existence (nastitva) .
, Just as much as ordinary existeoce (bhava) and its fruits (art/Ja) cannot be defined utilizing the substaotialist conc;eptions of arising and ceasing. even so existence.(bha11a) and its
ultimate fruit (pata1'iiirtha) cannot be expla.ined on the basis
of a simiar conceptual framework.
in
74
TuE
PHllOSOPHY OF THE
Mloou:
way
(punabbhava).
Afcer having rcjected the conception of self (iitmart) understood as permaneot existence (atthifii. astitva), the Buddha used the term bhava to explainthe
proccss of becoming. The metaphysicans, as pointed out before, immcdiacely
brought back the nodon of atman or astitva into the Buddhist doctrine when
they began speculating on bhava, two species of which were "self~nature"
(s1111bhiiva) and "other-nacure" (parabhava). Nagarjuna seems to havc bcen
wel aware of the Buddh'as discourse on becoming (bhava) and other-becoming
(11ibh(1vt1). He realized that this was the life process or the wanderi.ng (sa'f!ZI'iira)
that the Buddha spoke of. In addition, he was also aware chat, while eocouraging the people to abandon both becoming and other-becoming, the .Buddha
did not preseot a per.mancnt and eterna life (bhava, M#tfla) or complete an-
INTRODUCTION
75
nihilation (abha11a, n'iistiffla) as "freedom'' (niroaa). This awareness is succincdy presented in X:XV. I quoted above.
lf Nagarjuna's analysis of bha11a-11ibhava and bhava-abhava is compacible
with the Buddha's own analysis of bhava-vibhava and atJhilii-n 'atthilii (astil11a11iistit11a), Nagarjuna will be confonted with the same set of problems that the
Buddha faced in explairung freedom Thus, after rejecting the explanation of
free.dom in terms of bha11a-11bha11a or a combination or denial of both
(XXIV.11-16), in the next rwo verscs Nagarjuna refuses to use such terminology
to cxplain the freedom attained by the enlightencd one, either while he is stili
alive (ti[fhamiina = sop'iidise1a-nibbana) or when he passes away (para<f!Z
nirodhad = anupadisesa-nibbana) (XXV .17-18) .
. This leads Nagarjuna to make a remark which elicited two polar inrerpretaooos:
76
the objects of sense that had to be abandoned, but the se1lSes or the objects of
sense themselves. Freedom was thus reached on the basis of a non-sensuous insight, and the "freed one" (nibbuta) js one who has developed a form of knowing that transcends all forms of sensory perception, including the duality of
subject and object. This was the state of nzf'liiit!a enjoyed by the "freed one" as
long as hi~ body, together with the senses lasted . However, when tbat
psychophysical personali ty is destroyed at death, the "freed one" enters into the
stare of eternal and blissful life (brahman). Secondly, since such an absolute
distinction between sa'f!IS"iira and nirv"iif!a could not explain how one could
reacb a state that is qualitatively distioct, the essentialists also had to believe
that underlying sa'l(liiira is the reality (atman) that reaches nirvaf!a.
Oo the one h;uid, there is a point at whid, a ttansition is made from boodage
to freedom, a transition from one state of existence to something that is compJetel'y and absolutdy differeot, so much so that the one has nothing to do with
the other. Oo the otber band, there is a subtle personality (at1nan) that concinued from che time of the ocigio of existeoce and which lay concealed within
the psychophysical personali ty.
With the developmeot of metaphysical speculations in Buddhism, it was not
surprizing to see two similar conclusions reached by these metaphysicians,
especially the Sautrantikas. On the one hand, the Sautraorikas emphasized
distinctions (11iefa11a) in order to reject a permanent and eternal substance
(svabhava). Yet, when the oeed arose for an explaoation of the identity of
bondage andfreedom, they insisted upon a "seed of release" (mok1q.mja) (sec
anootation of X:XV.19-20). Thus, the first of these ewo verses (19) is intended
to reject the Sautrantika notion of distinction (11ie1af!aL while the second (20)
purports to deny tbeir concepcion of "the seed of re lease". which is not at a
differentfiom the Sarvastivada conception of substancc (svabhiiva).
Before and during Nigarjuna's day, uaditionaJ Indian phiJosophy was also
dominated by two similar essentialist enterprises, namely, detetcnioing identity
(sariipya) and differences (vie/an,a). The specu ations of the Siokhya school
concentrated on the problem of idencity-. The possible influence of this school
on the Sarvastivada theories has already been noted elsewhere. 128 The Vaise~ika
school, as its name implies, focussed on the distinccions (Yisep1~a) in the hope
that such a process would evenrually lead to the discovery of the nature of
ultimate reality. Some of the specuJations of the Sautrantika school reflect this
trend. The notions ofself-nature (svabhava) and other-narure (parabhava) were
the direct results of such an esseotialist search .
Thus, when Nagarjuna says: "The life-process has nothiog that distiogu.ishes
it from freedom. Freedom has notlllng that distinguishes it from the 1ifeprocess" (XXV. 19). to assume that he was presenting an identity of sa'l(liijra
lNTRODUCTION
77
lak.faf!a) .H~
26. Human persoMlity and its survival (di1'iidmaga) . Any reade.t who has
ploughed his way through the preceding chapters of Nigarjuna will certainly
be baffied by ~he conteots of Chapter XXVl on the "Examinatio.o of the Twelve
Factors" (Dvad4iii11ga-pank.ffi). By the time he ompleted {eadiog the first
twenty-five chapters, wherein t he conception of "emptiness" (iinyatfi) occurs
in aJmo.st every other verse, he would be imbued with that concept to such an
extent that it would become a dogma, a dr..f!i, rather than a merc method of
analysis. Therefore, Chapter XXVI would make no sense at all. Thus he would
get the impressioo that ir merely deals with the Hlnay~na docuine, having no
reevance to the basie teaching~ of Nagarjuna and, therefore, of Mahayana.
TUs is confirmed by the fact that there is no negative comment made anywbere
in the chapter and no mention of the famous doetrine of emptiness. Another
person can come to a roore drastic concusion. He may assume that this chapter
is ike an "illegitimate child" and could not be the work of Nagarjuna.
Contr.uy to all these widely held opinions, we teod to look upon this and
following chapter as the actual conclusioo of this most valuable treatise. They
78
arc intcgtal parts of the work, and without them one gets only a distorted view
of Nagarjuoa's thoughts.
It was mentioned earlier that the onJy d~coursc that Nagarjuna mentins by
name is the KiiJyayanavavada, and the significance of this fact cannoc be over
emphasizcd. Herc the Buddha was rcsponding to the question raised by Kaccayana as to what "right view" (sammii-dit1h1) is, compared with "wrong view"
(miccha-diftht). Nagarjuna has devoted most of his energy trying to darify
what "wrong views'' arc and occasionaUy spoke of "right views" (sec malysis of
chapter XVI!). If he bad concluded his treatise with Chapter XXV, he would
have rcad ooly a section of the Buddha's discourse to Kaccayaoa and ignored
the Buddha's owo ~ conclusioo in that discourse. The two extreme views of
existence and noo-existence were rejected by the Buddha, not because he
had oo views to propound, but because he had a betrer or more appropriace
one to offer. And this appropriate view is explained in the conclusion to that
discourse.
The appropriate view is the middle position specified as dependent arising,
which is iotcnded as an explanatioo of how a human beiog, conditiooed by
various factors, attempts to bccome this or that and wanders aJong in a ceaseless
process of birtbs and deaths. The cheory of personality consiscing of the twelve
factors cxplaining such bccoming thus curns out to be the philosophical middle
position, and the noble eightfold path (magga), avoiding the two exuemes of
behavior, represencs the practical middle patb inteoded to achieve the cessation
of that process of becoming (bhava) and sufferiog (dukkha).
If the Kiityayanavavada served as che foundation of Niigarjuna's philosophy ,
and there does not seem to beany doubt about it, it would have been impossible for him to overlook the conclusion of that discourse. This indeed is rhe rationale for a whole chap ter on the concept of a person explaioed in terms of the
twclvcfold formula of causation.
Part IV (Conclusion)
27. Views (diftht). Buddha's deniaJ of a permanenc and eccrna.I self (alman)
and his expla.oation of the human personality and its survival of death io terms
of the docuine of dependent arisiog have remained unpaJacable co most
philosophers ever since he presented them. Veridical memories of past existences being connected with prcseot cxpcriencc as a result of meditation, as in
the case of the Buddha and many othcr ascetics, and sometimes without any
such practice or effort, ui have received a cwo-fold interpretation in the hands
of these philosophers. Some have assumed che existence of a permanent and
eternal self or subscracum to account for such phenomena, even in the absence
INTRODUCTION
79
1.
2.
"Did 1 exist in the past or no.c?" (Ahosif?Z nu kho afitam addhanatp,, na nu kho ahoJif?l afitam addhanaf?l). This, accordiog to the Buddha, pertains to the prior end of existence
(pubbanta), and is pcompted by a desire to know the first
beginn.ig of things, including oneself.
"Will I exist in the future or not?" (Bhavissami nu kho
anagakJ'I?' addhtina?!J, na nu /ho bha11is.rami antigtitdf?l addhana'f!J) . This i>ertains to the future and is prompted by a
3,
The Buddha felt that such speculations 1ed to a wide variety of views (dt{(ht),
sixty-t:Wo as specified in the Brahmajiila-suttanta, 133 of which permaoent ~x
istence (althila, sassata-dt/!ht) and annihilation (n'atthita, uccheda-dif(ht) are
foremost. Even though the Suddha recognized veridica memocies of past existences, yet because of the absence of any empirical evidence to support the
hypotbesis of a permanent and eu:rnal substratum as wel as the difficulties involved in predicting future ev~nts with absolute cerrainry. the Buddha questiooed his disciples as to whether it is appropriare for them to " brood over the
past" (pubbarllaf?Z pafidhaveyyath,a) or long for the future (r1paranla'f!t
'iidhaveyjiitha) or be unnecessarily skeptical about the present (paccuppannaf?l
addhanaf?l a1jhattaf?Z kathaf?lkatlii assatha) . He advised them that instead,
with the resources available, they shou1d. try to understand rhings as they have
80
INTRODUCTION
81
The above anaysis of the cootents ofNagarjuna's Kiinliii and the annotatioo
of individual verses d1at follow provide ample evidence to support the view that
his pcimary objective was to reject the substantialist or essentialist thoughr that
emerged in the Buddhist philosophical ttadition as a rcsuk .o f the speculations
of the Sarvastivadins and the Sautrantikas. The fact tbat he depended upon the
teachings embodied in the early discourses, or the fact chat che Kiirika is hece
looked upon as a grand commentary on the Kaccayanago1ta-111tta, in no way
minimize his contribution to the bistory of Buddhist thought. What is most
significant is the manner in which he proceeded to examine the subtle and
complex metaphysical issues that blinded che Sarvastivadins and the
Sautrantikas in a background in which speculative philosophy had reached a
high watermark, both among the Buddhists and the ttaditional Indian
philosophers. Ni.garjuna probed into almost every aspecc of thefr speculations,
whethet relating to epistemology, ontology, mora philosophy, or philosophy
of language. He linked disjointed concepts and dissolved the hardened and the
solidified. Concepts of identity and difference, substance and qualiry; selfnature and other-nature, permanence and annihilation, ven in thei( most subtle and imperceptible forms. never escaped his penetrating intellect. lt seems as
if he had read the Buddhist discourses, manuals, and commentMies, examining
every sentence, every word, and every syllable. Even if one cannot discover any
tangible evidence to provide that he was a "freed one". a nirvr.ta, the Kiin'kii,
indeed, bears ample testimony to .liis supreme intellectual starure.
Epistemological Jnvestigations
Nagarjuna was an empiricist par excellence. H owever, .the fundamntaJ
metaphysical assertion of most rationalists, and even the empiricists during his
day. was the cogito, the atman that sees itself before it comes to perceive
anything eJse. Nag;irjuna had oo hesitatioo in demolishing this metaphysical
idea at the vety outset. "Seeing oneself' (svatmiinaf!Z daranaf!Z) is rejected, not
on the basis of any di.alectical argument, but simply on the grounds of its nonavailability (flT.2). Comparable to the manner in which David Hume refused to
accept the notion of a cogito, Nagarjuoa proceeds to sl!ow that the so-called
process of "seeing oneself' is do more than "the arising of consciousness
depending upon the eye and visible form" (cak1u-rupe prafityaivam ukto
vijfziina-Jaf!lbhavaf?). III. 7). that is, a perception of some color, shape, etc.
Howevcr, Nagarjuna differs from Hume in not recognizing these ,perceptions
82
of
}NlJlODUCl'ION
83
Onto/ogy
Just as much as the assercioo of a cogito led to the belief in a substantial
agent, a pudga/a, the lop-sided attempt to dissolve that coacept insisting that it
is dependent upon the elements of experience (dharma) led to a substantia!lst
84
view reeating to the objective world. The conception of a person was replaced
by a substanciaJ worJd. The Buddha bad spoken of obsession (prapaflca) as che
reason for sucn world-views. Hence his emphasis on the "appeasement of obsessions" (prapacopaiama) as a means of overcoming metaphysic;s. Looking at the
philosophical background in which the objective world bad replaced the cogito
as an ultirnate reality, Nagarjuna was more specific. in insisting upon the "appeasement of the obje~ (drfl.!ftWyopaiama) as a means to attaining true
knowledge (V.8).
In fact, the Sarvastivadins and Sauuantikas, whiJe denying the substantiality
of che human person (pudgala), had rnoved to the other extreme of adroitting
the substantiality of elements . (dham111). This problem being foremost in
Nagarju na's mind, he devoted the second part of his treatise to its refutation.
Io this case, he reaJized that even ccitical philosophy bad fallen prey to the ot.
dinary human search for security and absolute certainty whea philosophers,
compe1led to give up something that provided them with some sort of certainty
(and in chis case the cogito), wece clinging like leeches to an objective wocld as
an ultima te reality.
1f Nigarjuna were to be an empiricist Jike the Buddha, he could not confine
hiroself to a world of abstract ideas . He knew that the Buddha was a ''verificationist" (ehipassika) and that this invoJved concrete "identificacion" (co use ct
term popular in modern philosopby). 1 n Thus, che conception of a person
begins with an identifiabJe and rc-identifiable "form" (rupa). Whilc the ud
dha recogni:zed the possibility of experiencing formless (artip11) states, it is not
very dear whether he bad accepted "forroless" persons. However, unlike some
modern philosophers who would consider the "body" or materia form to be
fundamental and, therefore, ulcimately real, leaving a1l otber conscituets as
being secondary, the Buddha wouJd merely look upon che "body" as a
necessary but not sufficient part of the human person. For him, feeling
(vedana) , perception (1afla) , dispositions (1ailkli?ir11), and coosdousness
(vinfiii'IJll) were as important as the materia body in making any identi.fication
or re-identification. Thus, the eliminacion of the oogito by expJaining it as
something that is dependently ai:isen (pa{icc4.Iamuppanna) did not mean the
recognition of the uJcimate reality of thesecondicions upon whic.h it depeoded.
Hence the Buddha's famous dictum: "Al1 things are non-substantiaJ" (1abbe
dhamma anatta).
For this reason, Nagarjuna's first major enterprise in the Kiirikii is to
escablish the non-subscantialicy of the elements (dharma-nairatmy11) . This cal
ed for a cririque of the Sarvastivada conception of substance (svabhava). As
mencioned earlier, che epistemologicaJ mechod by which he tried to achieve
this was "appeal to"experieoce" . In othet words, he was calling for identifi1tion
of substance, which nooc of his opponents were able co do.
However, Nigarjuna believed chat an ideutification of an eventcan be made
l.NTRODUCTION
85
on .the basjs of "fruit" or "effect" (arlha), for, according to bim, io the absence
of a fruit, one cannot speak of a condicion or non-condition (1.14). This is a
pragmatic theory of truth or reality. However, jf his substantialist opponenrs
substaoce can be identified through irs fruit ot effect,
were to insist tbat
Nagarjuna's immediate response is that the fruit or effect is dependent upon a
condition (or a set of condfrions), whereas substance is not. The definirion of
substance (s11abhava) as "having its owo (svo) existence (bhavo)" stood in the
way of Nigarjuna accepting his opponenes explanation. "How can a substance
be condicioned?" (s1111bh'iivaf? krklko nama bhavt~yali puna!? katha~ . XV.2)
grumbled Nagarjuna. For him, the conception of a "dependent substance" was
no mote t~an a ~elf-cootradictioo (XV. I).
Having criticized the substantialist theory of elements (dharma) , Nigarjuna
had to teturn once again to the cooccption of a person, evcn though he bad
begun his treatment of the non-substantiality of elcments by rejecting a.
substantialist conception of a person (Chaptei: Ul). The reason for this is not far
to seek. The Sautrantikas, who had themselves tejected the Sarvastivada on
ception of substance (s11abha11a), were surrepcitious1y iotroduciog a subtle personality (pudgala) to account fot human behavior, ~oraJ responsibility, bondage: and frecdom. Chaptets XVI-XXVI were, therefore, dcvoted to the expJanation of the human personality without falling into the substantialist trap.
Unlike some of his predecessors and most of his .modern day admirers,
Nigarjuna was indeed cogoisaot of the possible dangers involved in a "noosubstantialist discoutse ." He was aware that t he idea of non-substantiality could
eliminate even the empirical conception of a person (pudgala) and of elemcnts
(dharma) and enthrooe itself as the ultimate truth or reality. Hence his rather
bold dedaration: "Those who arc possessed of the view of emptiness are said to
be incorrigible." (Xlll.8)
An abso utistic view of emptiness would certainly contradict his empiricist
method that calls for identification as a test of uutb or reality. "Non
substantiality" (nairatmya) or "emptiness" (funyata) , taken in rhemselves,
would be as absuact and uoidentifiable as a substance (s11abha11a). lndeed , as
pointed out earlier, the notion of a substance was rejected because it could nor
be identified with anything in experience. Therefore, there was no excuse what
soever for replad ng "subsrance" wich an equally undefinabe or unidentifiable
coocepdon of "emptiness" or "nothingness. " "E.mptiness!' (flir!yata)
distinguished from "the empcy" (funya) , "non-sul>stantiality" (nairatmya)
separated from "the non-subst'antial'' (nairatmya-dharma) or "dependent arisi.ng" (pratityaramutpada) differenciated from "the dependently arisen"
(prafftyasamutpanna-dharrna) \\muld be as unidentifiable and therefore
nonsensical as any other metaphysical conception thar Nigarjuna was
endeavoring ro refute.
Thus, for Nigacjuna, emptiness (Junyata) was no more than what is implied
the
86
wAY
in the scacement: "All this is empty" (sllf'tlam ir/af?J Junyam) . The scatemeot,
"All this is empty ," is not idencicaJ with the scatement, "All is empty," (saroaf?1
funyam). In face, as pointed out in the anootacion, nowhere in the Kin'kii can
one come across an absolute statemcnt such as "All is empty." lt is iodeed
significant that even when malcing a universalized stacemeot Nagarjuna retains
the demoostracive "this" (idaf?J) in order to elimioate the absolutist scing.
The question whether one can speak of "empciness" (JUnyat'ii) of
"emptiness" (Junyat7i) is often raised in discussions of Nagarjuna's "middle
way." Por example, one could maintain chat "emptiness" itself is an idencifiable parcicular on the basis of which a universaJ "empciness" coud be idencified. The language udized by N:igarjuna docs nor permit sucha fligbt into
the realm of the Absolute. His conception of "the empty" (fUnya) is a particular. Yec this particular is not equivalent to a parricular "empciness"
( unyatii) abstractcd from a concrcte situacion. To movc from "the empty" to
"emptiness" is an altogether differeot process. The former is grounded in an cxpcrienced situation of an eveot with a charactcristic, while the later begins wich
a characteristic sans the event.
This careful avoidance of any absolutism or substantialism in reJacion to the
conceptioo of "dependent arising" (prafftyasarnutpada) as well as "emptiness"
(Jiinyatii) was dedared by Nagarjuna as the "middle path" (ptaJipat saiva
madhyamii, XXIV.18). That "emptiness" is a "dependent convencion"
(upadiiya prajnaptt), for it is dependent upon and, therefore, identifiable in
cetms of, "the empcy" (fUnya). Nagarjuna assercs that- ''emptiness" so identified would elimioate aoy dogmatism or obsession (adhilaya) and, aJong with
it, any erroneous views (do1a-pra.raga, XXIV.13).
This, undoubtcdly, is a beautiful rcscoration of the Buddha's conception of
"non-substantiality" (anatttJ). However, the modern interpretacion of Nagarjuna seems to move in a totally different directon. Modern scholars, favoring an
interpretacion by Candrakrti made knowo to chem by T. R. V. Murci. insist
chat Nagarjuna had no thesis of his own (svapak/a) to present. This Vedantic
incerpretation prescnts Nagarjuna as a critical or analyticaJ philosopher whose
sole funcicon was to crit:icize or analysc (vigraha) views presented by others
without having to recognize or uphold a view of his own. Such an interpretatioo has led to two more related theories being attribured to Nagarjuna. The
fi.i:st is the admission of the ioadequacy of conceptual thinking, and therefore
of language, to express the ultirnate truth. The second is the aruibution of a
coacept of ultimate truch in the form of "absolute emptiness" or "absolute
nothingness" inexpressible through otdinary human linguistk apparatus,
Thus, we are led to one of the most troublcsome quescions relating to Nagarjuna's philosopiicaJ enterprise.
Io che annotation of the dedicatory verses of thcKiirikii, we have suggesced a
different rcading which would make ie possible for Nagarjuoa to make the
lNTRODUCTION
87
claim that he is presencing a right view (1amy(lg-drf!t) when refuting the inappropriate views advocated by his opponents. Furd!ermore, Nigarjuna clearly
indicate that philosophicaJ enterprise consists not only of analysis (vigraha) but
aJso explanation (vj"iikhjiin11) (IV.9). This would provide legitimation for the
most positive explanation of the Buddha1s view in Chapter XXVI, in- addition
to ocher positive statements made by Nagiirjuna elsewhere (e.g Chapter
XVU).
However, the two most troublesome questions regarding ultimate re~ity and
the inadequcy of language still remain, primarlly because of the manner in
which the Vedantic scholars interpreted three related terms utilized by Nagarjuna. These arc praftiiirtha, nirvikalpa, and sa'l!,Zvrti.
For most scholars who have been nurtured in a predominantly substantialist
philosophkal or religious tradition, paramartha means ''ultimate reality," nirvikalpa iroplied "the non-conceptu1 ," and Jaf!lvrti stood for "lar:iguage." In
understanding these three terms in this maooer, did modern translators and interpreters impose theiI owo substantjafut outlook on Nigatjuoa's thought?
The first test of the validity of such translations would be a comparison of the
implications of these three traoslations with the Buddha's own conceptions of
"dependent arising" (prafftytJJamutpada) and "non-substantiality" (anatman),
all of which Niigacjuna ac<!epted with reverence.
Philosophy of Langu4ge
The term 1af!111rti (Pali, sammult) was never used in the earJy discourses
to refer el(clusively to language. Analysing the Buddha's philosophy on the
basis of the early discowses, it was pointed out that sammuti, voh'iira, and
pa~fiatli were terms used to refer co any convention, not merely linguistic convention. T)le specific terms used by the Buddha to refer to language are nirutti
(etymology) and adhivac4na (definition or St!mantics). Nagarjuna's use of the
term abhidheya, meaning "that which is to be designated,'' (XVIIl.7) would
provide us with a term that he may have used if he bad a need for refercing to
Janguage. Such :i term would be adhidhana and would not be semancically
much different from the tetm adhivacana used by the Buddha.
However, for Nagarjuna, the abhidheya or "that which is to be designated"
ceases with the cessatioo of citta-gocart1 ("the ojbect of thought"). Thus,
anything that is not the object of thought, that is non-conceptual (ni'.rvi.kalpa) ,
is also not describable. If so, Niigarjuna had no reason to compose more than
four hundred verses rryiog to explain the indescribablc. It would be a fruitless
attempt on the part of any philosopher, let alone one who is extoled as an
"enligbtened one" (budt/h4) .
88
lf Nigarjuna was ttying to explain soroething and in that pcocess was utiliziog language, he would be dealing with the conceptual or the object of thought
(citta-gocara). Accordingly, anything that is conceprual would aso be the object of thought, and the noo-conceprual (nif"IJika/pa) could not be an object of
thought. A truth that cannot be thought of, let alone one chat cannot be
spoken of, would be as metaphysical as the conception of atman in the
Brahmanical speculatlons. Nirvikalpa would, thetefore, mean something else.
In the course of the analysis of the Kiirik.ii, it was pointed out that Nagarjuna
was critical of a spedfic form of discrimination, a discrimination that produced
polarities in human thinking. These coosisted of existence and non-existence,
substance aod quality, self-narure and other-nature, permanence and annih i a
tion. In such a context, nirvikalpa would refer co polar discriminations, not any
and every form of discrimination.
This lcads us to one of the mosr conuoversial discriminations that the
metaphysicians of the Buddhist tradition as wel as their couoterparts of other
substaotialist traditions made with regard to bondage and freedom . Chapter
XXV of the Kiin"k'ii is devoted to an analysis of tbis metaphysical issue. In
Chap ter XXIV, when Nigarjuna spoke of saf!'vrti and 11ya11ah'iira oo the one
band and paramiirtha on the other, be was paving bis way for a discussion of
the discrimination between bondage and freedom.
Nigarjuna, who provided every indicacion that he had read the early
discourses, could not bave been unawarc that the Buddha used the terms sammuti and 11ohara (11y1111ahara) moce ofcen in the sense of mora conventions.
Tbese mora convencions pertained to good (dharma) ~od bad (adharma) .
Thus, whenever he used the term 11ya11ahara, Nagarjuna was referring co the
mora convcncions of good and bad (dharma-adharma) (XXIV.36) or merit and
deroerit (p1''!-Ja-papa) (XVU.24). These moral conventions are accepced not
because they are mere conventions agreed upon by consensus but because they
work. They are pragmatically grounded. They produce fruits or conseuences
(artha). Such convencions provide a basis for idea~ conventions referred to as
paraiiirlha ("highcst fruit or consequence") . Yet, to safeguard the idea from
becoming a merc idea and not a fact, Nagarjuna insists upon the
dependence of the idea on the concrete. A quotacion from William J ames,
eveo though extensive, seems to be relevant herc.
If the cthical philosopher wece only asking after the best imaginable system of goods he would indeed have an easy task; for aU
demands as sucb are pnma facie respectable, and the best simply
imaginary world would be one in which every demand was gratified
as soon as made. Such a world would, however, have to have a
physical constitution entirely different from that of the one which
!NTilODUCTION
89
we inhabit. It would need not only space, but a time, of n-climensions, to include all the act:s and experiences incompatible with one
another here below, which would then go on in coojunction -such
as spending our money, yet growing rich; ta.king a holiday, yet getting ahead with our work; shooting and fishiog , yet doing no hurt
to the beasts; gaining no end of experience, yet keepiag our
youthfuJ freshaess of heart; and the like. There can be no question
chat such a system of things, however brought about, would be the
absoluteJy ideal system; and that if a philosopher could create
universes aprion', and provide all the mechanical conditions, that is
the sort of universe which he should unhesitatingly create.
But this world of ours is made on an entirely different pattero,
and che casuistic question is herc most tragically praccical. The acrually possible in this world is vastly narrower than all thac is
demanded; and there is always apinch betweeo the jdeal and the
actual wbich can only be goc chrough by leaving pan of the idea
behind. 1!
In a similar way. Nagarjuna, following the pragmatic teachings of the Buddha, could not clivorce paramarlha from Jaf!111rti (i.e., the ultimate fruit from
the fruit of cveryday life of a h11012n being). Just as much as "emptincs.5" is based
upon "the empty," even so paramiirlha bad to be based upon the Jllf!l11(1i.
Without any reference to the concrete concepcs of good, any notion of ultimace
or ideaJ good would be not only meaniogless but aJso "fruitess'' (an-artha) and
tcrribly harmful (as proven by many such instances in the .bistory of mankind).
Thus, for Nagarjuna, ultimate good is not one chat transcends ordinary notions
of good, but merely an cxtension of the so-called goodness rccognized in evcryday ue (11yavahara).
The sharp clichotomy between the orclinary ootion of good and the ideal
good is thus brokeo down. lt is significant to noce chat wheo speakJng of two
truths Nagarjuna utilized the terms sa?'(Jvr# and paramartha. Yet, when he
proceeded to explaio cheir reationship , he utilized the term 11yavahara, thereby
establishing the synonymiry of Jflf!Jvrfi and 11yariahara. The fact that Nagarjuna
was not prepared to create an unbridgeable chasm betwecn Jaf!111r1i or
vya11ahiirt1 on the one hand and paramarlha on the other is clcarly exprcssed in
his famous statement that without the farmer the latter is not expressed
(11yava/iiiram arziiritya paramiirtho na deyate , XXIV.10).
Sinl.ilarly, without understanding the ultimace fruit, freedom is not obtained
(paramiirtham anaga11zya niniiif!tJ'f?l nadhigamyate. ibid. ). This would meao
that frecdom (niniiif!a) itself is not something to be sharply distinguished from
Iaf!jsara or ordinary human life, even though they are not idencical. Freedom
would not be absolute freedom that has nothing to do with human life. lt is no
90
more than the absence of certain coostraints (such as greed, hatred, and confusion) in the life of a human being. It is, therefore, the life of an ordinary
human being that is gradually transformed , through the cutivatioo of mora!
precepts, into one of mora petfection. This transformation (ratber than
transcendence) is what is implied by nirrlii'fll.
Mora/ Philosophy
The mora life that leads to the transformation of the human personality is
cleady explained by Nagarjuna in Chapter XVII. The absolutistic interpretation
of Nagarjuna's conception of "emptiness" constrained many of his modern admirers from discussing his views regarding karma and survival,
even though these were part and parcel of the Buddha's teachings. The discussion of karma and survival in the Kiiriliii was thus considered to be
"HJnayanistic," having nothing to do with the so-called Mahayana. As such,
the Buddha's owo views regarding these issues turo out to be "J-ITnayanistic" or,
at least, were intended for those low-witted disciples who surrounded him.
Con traty to this view, our analysis of the contents of Chapter XVII , placed in
t he background in which Nagarjuna lived, shows that he was more positive
than his modern day disciples in his treatment of karma and survival. Nagarjuna's major endeavor in this chapter is to rescue the Budda's discourse on
mora responsibility from the ha:voc created by the substantiaist thinkers who
assumed karma to be either substantial or performed by a subsrantial agent.
His was not an attempt to dissolve the conception of karma in favor of an absolutistic notion of "emptiness,"
lndeed, the chapter begins with a reference to the Supreme Sage (paramar!t)
whose docuine he was about to expound. Speaking of the morally good life,
Nagarjuna uses the term dharma, instead of karma, and this may have confounded the modern interpreters. The term dharrna, as explained earlier in the
discussion of the Buddh~$ philosophy, was used both in an ontologica sense
and in an ethicaJ context. Nagarjuna h imself followed this P.ractice, as indicated in the annotation of the Kiirikii (see XXIV. 36). Thus, in the present
context too, dharma me.ans good karma and these are identified as (i) selfrestraint, and (ii) benefitting others. Nagarjuna's selection of these two types of
action as the foundation of mora behaviot is significant: They are an echo of
the Buddha's own first sermon to the world that advocated a middle path be
tween two extremes of self-indulgence and self-mortification. The ''Middle
Way" (miidhyamika) philosopher par excellence could nof have ignored the
1N1"RODUCI10N
91
ethical middle path of the Buddha. He knew the implications of that fi.est sermon. Self-restraint, but not self-mortification or sclf-immolation, c-0nstitutes
one of the foundations of mora life. In this regard, Nigarjuna was not advocating the extremist form of behavior sometimes extoled as the ideal of a
bodhisattva both in the Theravada and in the Mahiiyana. Sef-rcsttaint is a
nece$ary prercquisite for any akruistic activity, which .is the second of the virrues extoled by Nigarjuna as a "friendly way" (m11itrat?Z dharma'!J).
The irnplicacions of the maral Jife recommended herc should not go unnoticed.
In spite of the exceedingly popular theme emerging among the Buddhists during Nigarjuna's day that emphasized extreme altruism, Nigarjuna seems to be
playing a rather moderate tune recognizing the Buddha' own words in the
Dhammapada (166): ''One should not neglect one's own welfare through ex~
cessive altruism. Having understood one's own welfare, one should be devoted
to true welfare."
A reader of the early cliscourscs. cannot but be impressed by the idea of
human behavior advocated by the Buddha:. The noblest person according to
the Buddha is one who avoids suffering for himself as wel as others (attabyabadha; parabyabadha). 139 Thus, a noble action should be one that contrib1;1tes to one's own happiness as well as the happiness of others. This invoves
(he recognition that, while abandoning a belief in a metaphysical self, one has
ro cutivate compassioo for one's own person. At the same time such compassion should be extended to others as well. Nagarjuna seems to have picked up
th.is theme well when, unlike many Buddhist writers of his day, he emphasised
that self-restraint and benefitting others are both acts offriendliness (maittam) .
He was simply insisting: "Be a friend to yourself and be a fricnd to others." This
would certainly be opposed to the idea that caUs for complete and unqualified
self-sacrifice, including self-immolation . Thus Nigarjuna, the founder of the
''Middle Way" (Miidhyamika) school, could not have recommended amore
sober mora life t han one which avoids the rwo extremes of destroying onself
and destroyiog others .
. These two friendly way'5 are recommended by Nigarjuna because they arc
fruitfuJ not only in the present life (iha) but also in an after-life (prelyt1). There
could be no doubt tbat herc he was recognizing the possibility of human survival. The st1rruara or "life-process" referred to at XXIV.10 need not be confined
to this prcsent life ~lone. On the cont.rary, it refers to the continuity of te li.(eprocess through scveral births and deaths, refetred to as pu""1bbharJa in the early
discourses. That continuity, along with its attendant suffering, is to be
eliminated by the development of.wisdom (jfl'iina) which for Nigarjuna consists in the avoidance of all metaphysical views (dr1ft).
92
lNTRODUCTION
93
from that I woud iocur such error. Oo the coouary, I do not have a commiuneot.
Therefore, there is no error on my part."
The term that occurs herc is pratijfla, which has beeo translated as a simple
proposition or statemeot. lt is much more thao a simpe proposicioo or statement. lt is a commitment and should be contcasted with vyiik.hy1in(I, "explanation ," (IV.9). While avoiding the former, Nagarjuna continued to resort to the
fatter (see aso XVII.13, etc.). As such , it would be highly inapprop.riate to
compare Nagarjuna's philosophicaJ method with that of Ludwig Wittgenstein,
fot example by quoting bim as follows: "Philosophy simply puts everything
before us, and neither explains nor deduces anything. -Since everything lies
open to view, there is oothing to explain.''1 1 In fact, this quotacion
misrepresents Wittgenstein's owo approach to metaphysics: The most important part of the statemenr has been omitted . lt reads: "For what is hidden, for
example, is of no interest to us." If this c.tucial statement is retained, then Wittgenstcin's thought can certainly be comparcd with Niga.rjuna's or even the
Buddha's. This oroitted part of the statement makes it abundantly elear that
wbat Wittgenstein was not willing to cxplain is "wha~ is hidden," and this
"something'' is, indeed, comparable to what Nagarjuna was rcfcrring to as
kif!'Cit or kaicit, -that is, the hidden substance in phcnomena. Neither "the
empty" ("iinya) nor "emptiness" (Hi11yata), neithcr "the dcpendently arisen"
(ptalftyasamutpanna) nor "depehdent arising'' (prafityfl!4mutp4tla) represeot
a hiddeo something whkh Nagarjuoa was rcluctant to explain. On the con
trary, if it an be shown that Wittgenstein did not provide any explanatiorz of
experience, or did not attempt to formulate in linguistic terms w hat a tcue experience is, as opposed to a confuscd one, then he could certainly be enlightened
by the language of "emptiness" or of ''dependence" adopted by the Buddha
and Nagarjuna.
94
NOTES
1. S 2.16-17; T.ra 12. 19 (Taisho 2.85c).
2. S 5.420-424; Tsa 15.17 (Taisho 2.103c).
INTRODUCTION
95
27 . Ud80.
28 . M 1.262-264; S 2. 28, 70, 96; Ud 2; Tsa 10. 7 (Tais/Jo 2.67a); 14.16
(Tai.Iho 2. lOOa), etc. See Kalupahana, Causality, p .9.
29. S 2.18.~ Tsa 12.20 (Taisho 2.86a); sec also Kalupahana, Ct1us4'ity,
p.5-6.
30. Ibid .
31. Ibid .
32 . S 2.25; 3.3-4; Tsa 12.14 (Taisho 2.84b).
33.
34.
35 .
36.
37.
38.
39.
40.
41.
42.
Thag 304.
M 1.395; also 3.237.
Sn 68.
See Kalupahana, Cau.sality, pp.177-183.
55. T. I. Stcherbatsky, The Central Conception o/Btt:ddhi.rm and the Meaning of the Term 'Dharn14 London: Royal Asiatic Society, 1923 , pp.37-38;
Buddhist Logic,Leningrad : Academy of Sciences of The USSR, 1930. I .4-5.
56. Jayawickrema, KtJth'iiv1111huppakarllf!t1a(!hakatliii1 London: ?I'S, 1979,
1 '
p.X'V.
61 . Kp 52.
96
INTRODUCTJON
97
106. 3.83.
107. M 1.184; Tsa 39.1 1 (Taisho 2.286a).
108. See Kalupahana , "Anna," in Encyclopaedia of Budt/h1:S1n, cd. G. P.
Malalasekera, Colombo: Government of Ceylon . 1961,- 1.693-696 .
109. James, Tlie Pn.nciples ofPsycho/ogy , vol. I , p. 609.
110. D 3.80 ff.; ChiJng 6.1 (Taisho l.36b).
1 l l. DhsA p.421 ; see Ka1upahana, "Schools of Buddhism in Early Ceylon,"
The Ceylon Journal of the Humanities, Peradeniya: University of Ceylon, 1
(1970):1 59-190.
112. Brhadaraf!yaka Upan1jad 1.3.28.
113. Ibid.
114. S 3.110; Tsa 5.2 (Taisho 2.3la-b) .
115. Ibid .
116. lnada, Niig'iitjuna , p . 132.
117. S 3.110; Ts. 5.2 (Taisho 2.31a-b) .
118. A 2.52.
11 9. M 1.140.
120. S 3.54: Tsa 9.4 (Taisho 2. 56b).
121. M 1.228; S 3.133; 4.401 ; A 1.286; Thag 678; Dhp 297; Tsa IO. 7
(Taisho 2.66b-67a) ; Tseng 32.4 (Taisho 2.668c).
122. The Giindhan Dharmapada, ed.]. Brough, London: Oxford Uoiversity
Press, 1962, 190. (also see p . 240).
123. D 1.51; Ch'ang 17. 1 (Taisho l.I07a ff.) .
124. Petavatthu, ed. Minayeff, London: PTS, 1888, 57; Apadana, ecl . M. E.
Lilley, London: PTS, 1925-1927, 395.
12 5. The Conception ofBuddhist Nirvana, Leningrad: Academy of Sciences
98
SANSKRIT TEXT,
TRANSLATION AND
ANNOTATION _ _ __
DEDICATORY VERSES
102
a)
D EOICATORY VERSES
b)
c)
103
(milhya-dr:1t1), primlllily the theories of substantial existence (as#lva) and nihilistic non-cxistence (n'1islil11a), that is, the non-ceasing
(aniiodha'!') of a substantial entity and the non-arising (anutpadaf!J) of a non-existcnt cntity. Indeed, the non-ceased (aniruddhaf!') and non-arisen (an111pannaf?J) arc cquivalcnt to the nonempty (tliinya), a term used to refer to substance (wabh'iiva)
(XX.17). Hence these negations appear in couplets and could be
considcrcd as another w:ay of ptesentiog the non-substantiality
(anatman) not onJy of phenomena but al~o of those vicws. They arc
noo-substantial in the sense that thcy arc not absolute, as they were
assumed to be by their proponents.
''Dependent aris.ing" (prafityasamutpada) would then stand for the
midcJe position, which is the right view (samyag-dr:!ft) on the basis
of which the wrong views arc criticized. "Dependent arising" is considered to be the right view, not because it is an absolute trutb, but
because it allows for possible explanations of phenomcna not permitted by thcories of absolute existeocc and nihilistic nonexistence.
"The appeasement of obsessions" (prapalcopaama) and "the
auspicious" (fi11a) would be the result of adopting the middle position. This is freedom or nirvana.
CHAPTER
ONE
Examination of Conditions
(Pratyaya-partk.[ a)
I.
Na wato
The four types of events referred to here are comparable to those m~ntioned by
the Buddha at S 2.19-20, namely saya1pkata1{t para1{tkata'f! sayaf!Zkatafl ca
paraf!Zkatrzfl. ca, and asaya?[Zkaraf!Japaraf!Zkaram adhiccasamuppannaf!Z. Instead
of the term utpanna (arisen), which occurs only in the last phrase, herewe find
the occurrence of che term kata (Sk. kr ta). "done," primarily because in the
Upanifads, which served as background to che Buddha's teach ing, the substaotial self(atman) was 1ooked opon more as a "personal agent," than as a substantial principle (svabhava, pr4k.rti, etc.) . With the sophistication in philosophical
thinking in che later fndian schools., the "personal agent" wa5 gradually r5placed
by an "impersonal substance'' (svabha11a). The S;uvastivadins, who carne to ~c
cep t a conception of substance while at the sametime rejeccing a "personal
agent" (pudgala), failed to nocice the similarity if not the identity of their implications. In this verse, Nagarjuna present:s his oegative thesis, which io the
dedicatory verse. he expressed with the eight negations. lt is the thesis that he
undertakes to prove in the first twenty-five chapters. He has not provided any
arguments yet, except saying that these four kinds of events are not evident.
Pro,>ably he fet that these events needed furthcr ex:pJanatioo before he proceeds to refute them.
However, Candraklrti is all too impatient. His commentary on this verse is
more than one tenth of his eotire work (almost 65 pages), and it is a stupendous
contmentaty filled with lot of metaphysical trivia and diatribes, mosty directed
at Bhavaviveka and the Svatantrika uadicion. After assumi:ng that Nagarjuna
had "no position" (sec note on the dedicatory verses) with which to criticize
105
106
Tul!
thcsc four theorics, Canc.rakitti: scttlcs down to juscify the reductio ad absurdum
by which the iaherent conuadictioos in a thcsis arc exposcd. He rcalizcs that
sclf-causation (s11ata-utpatl1) is based on the bclief in a permanent and cternal
self or substance (wahha11a). Quoting Buddhapalita, he maintains: '"Things
arc not atisen from self," bccause such arising is meaniogless, (lad utpada11a1yarthyat, p.14).' For, thcrc is oo purposc in the arisiog of things that
arc aJ~dr cxistent. This ccrtainly is Nigarjuna's cricicism of a substantialist
notion of a "condition" (pratyaya) at 1.6. However, in the prcsent verse and at
1.3. Nigirjuna appcars to usc the argument from empicicism to dcny the
su bstantialist view.
Thus, while Nagarjuna was saying that substance is n_ot cvident (na 111dyate)
and. thcrcforc, ioappropriatc (na yujyate), CandrakTrtl was maintaining tbat
substancc is not appropriacc (na yujyate) and , thcrcforc, not evident (na
11idyate). This indced is the diffcrcnce bctwecn cmpiricism and rationaJism, a
differcnce that is soon to lead to the conflict bctwccn the Svatanttikas and the
Prasangikas.
2.
ExAMINATION OF CoNDITIONS
107
In th~ first place. such an intcrpretation would Jcave a rathcr tainted image
of Nigarjuna as an unsystematic philosopbcr, for baving spokeo of four causaJ
theocics beginoing with self-causacion (svata-utpaltt), Nigirjuna is here
representcd as elaborating upon the second, namcly, cxteroaJ causation
(part1fa-utp11t11), ignoring self-causation altogethcr.
Sccondly, wbile the four causal theorics mentioned in 1.1 are catcgorically
deoied by Nigarjuna, oo sucb denial is made of the four theorics of conditions
(pratyaya) . Thus, unlike Candnkrrti, Nigarjuna sccms to have accepted the
Abhidha.rmika theory of four conditions, without characterizing it cithci: as
self-causacion or as externaJ causation. Mter stating the Abhidharma theory,
Nigarjuna then proceeds to analyse .the views of the interpreters of Abhidharma, and, as the ve.tse that immediatcly follows (I. 3) seems to indicate, he found
chat thcse arc the ones who produced theories of self-causacion (wata-utpattt)
and cxternaJ causation (p11rata-11tpa111) out of the Abbidharma theory of conditions (pratyaya).
scf-naturc
These indccd arc the most significant statemeots of Nigarjuna in the present
chapter. The fiest statemcnt is nor a simplc but an emphalic denial (na ht) of
the view that the substancc or sclf-nature (s11a~h'ii11a) of an cxistent is found in
the condition (pratyaya). Since the tbeory of conditioos is primarily a Buddhlst
theory. and since amoog the Buddhlst schools the first to advocate a theory of
substance (Jt111bliiit1a, dravya) at tbis early stagt was the Sarvastivida scbooJ,
therc can be little disagreemcnt that Nigitjuna's statement rcprcscnts a
outright i:ejection of the Sarvastivada intcrpretation of the conditions.
This denial necds to be carefully analyscd. In the first place, as noted carlier,
the phr2Se use to express the deaial is n4 vidyate ("is not evident") and not na
Jujyate ("not propcr") or na upgpadyale ("not appropriatc"). Hence the deoiaJ
should be empirically grounded. Secondly, tbcre is no ouuight deniaJ of the
108
The term kn'yii, used io philosophical discourse, can convey two m eanings.
First, it ca-n refer to an inh erent activity, a power or potentiality (akti) in
something to produce an effect (llrlha) . Activity would then be an embodiment
of a condicion (knja praJyaya11ali) oc a condition would be an cmbodimeo t of
activity (praJyayfi knjiivantal/). In either case, the activicy or the coodition is
said to produce the effccc (artha). This, oncc again, is the substancialisr interpretation of causacion. lf the philosophical explaoation of experience is con. fioed to the two alceroatives. chen the conuasting view would be chat accivicy
is not an ernbodiment of a cooditin (apratyayavali knja) or thac a condirion is
EXAMINATION OF CONDlTIONS
109
~.
These are conditio.ns, because depending upon them these [others] arise.
So long as these [others] do not arise, why are they not non-conditions?
MKV(P) p.81; MKV(V) p.28.
The first line of this verse presents a definition of a condition (pratyaya) that
would satisfy the pragmatic sense referred to eadier and therefo,re would be acceptable to the earJy Buddhist as well as Nigarjuna. However, Nagarjuna
wants to make sure that rhere areno metaphysical interpretations of this definition of conditlon. W oud someone assume chat for this.statement to be true the
dependence has to be invariable and eternal? Infact, the Sarvastivada notion of
sef-nature , in terms of which they defined a condition, implied such eternalism. In spite of the Sarvastivada assertion, no such guarantee can be given
on empirical grounds. [f so, it is appropriate to ask the question as to whet'hcr
the so-caled condition has to be caled a non-condition so long as the effect
does not arise. This means that it is inappropriate to say that a condition is such
by its own naturc (svabhava). Inscead , it bec0mes a condition depending upon
the arising of the effect.
6.
110
A condition of an effect that is either non-existent or trostent is not pcoper. Of what non-existcnt (effect) is a condition? Of what use is a condition of the existent [effect)?
MKV(P) p.82; MKV(V) p.28.
Herc the condition (pratyaya) is exa mined in rdation to che effect (llrtha) . Even
though the criticism up to now has bcen directed on the metaphysical notion of
a subscantial condition, and not on a pragmatic definition understood in relation to the effect, the present verse is intended to clacify the nature of the effect. The question is: In terms of what kind of effect sbould a condition be
defined? An existent effcct or a non-existcnt effect? An effect cxistent in terms
of self-nature needs no suppon for its arising and, as such , a condition would
be meaningless. An effect that is non-existent in the sense of being absolutely
diffetcnt from the condition will not be .telated in any way.to a condicion.
7.
Since a thing that is existent or non-existent or. both existent and nonexistent is not produced, how pertinenc in that context would a- producing cause be?
MKV(P) p.83; MKV(V) p.28.
EXAMINATION OF CONDITIONS
llt
8.
112
ony ed
to the belief in a cogit, thinkiogof its own subject-matter (cllitta) carcying with it all the metaphysical implicacions; but aso raised the question as to
the need for an external object (iilambana) as a support for the concomitants.
While the question regarding the cogito is tak.en up by Nagarjuna in Chapter
III, the need for an exrernal objective support is r~sed in the.present veJ:Se.
Thus . it is recognized by Candrakrrti that the question regarding objective
support is raised by Nagarjuna because those whose views he was criticizing admitted a cogito (athaivam aniilmbane dharme sviitmana prasiddhe kim
asyiilambanayogena pariktllpitena, (P) 84.; (V) 29) This is simHar to the refutation of a "materia! object" by the Western phiosopher George Berkeley. If the
object appears to the perceiving mind in its owo form (i.e. in the form of a
mental imptession) (s1111tma11a prasiddhe) 1 there is no necd for an objective
suppoct(iihmb4114). 1f it docs not appear to be the perceiving mind in its own form ,
itwill never be perceived, since the perceiving mind and the materia object are
of completey different natures (p~-ratman?). This is indeed not a rejection of
the notion of an objcctive support (til"1!Jbana-pratyaya) per se, but -an objcct
that 1s conceprualized in a metaphysical way, that is, as an object constituted
of a materia substance distinguished from a mental substance.
The immediately contiguous condicion (s11ma114ntara-pratyaya) was first formulated by the Abhidharmikas in order to account for cenain kinds of relations
implied in the Buddha's statcmcnts such as: "In this way, monks there is the
immediate (anantara) waning of defiJements ,"' (S 3. 58). The Abhidharmikas,
therefore, specified the relation as one amoog mind and mcotal concomitants
(ciftacaitlii acaramii uppannii~ saman1111taraf?, AK 2.62). With the acceptancc
ofa theory. .of mments (kfaf!a), the interpretcrs of the Abhidharma were faced
wit~ sevcra questions: Does this relation obtain among cvents of a sirnHar
nature (s11aj1Jtt)? How can the cmergence of dissimilat events be explained?
EXAMINATION Of CONDITIONS
11 3
(Akb pp.65-66). The problems arc not different from thosc chat arc associaccd
with the conccpcion of a series (similar to the problems faced by empiridsts like
David Hume). The question as to how one momencar:y event can give rise to
anothet or how one series could pave the way for a different series was discussed, in relatioo to the'problem of knowledge , especially the knowledge of the
future . Some of the interpreters of the Adhidbarma recognized an unimaginable range of compreheosion on the part of the Buddha (acintyo hi
buddliiin'iif!J b11ddhi11i[aya iii, Akb p.66), which was probably a view ad
vocated by the Sarvastivadins, who admitted the possibility of knowing che ex
istence of everything (saffJam astt) bclonging to the past, the present and the
future . The Sauuintikas, who refused to accept such a position , maintained
chat the Buddha follows 'signs' (naimittdo) and that even in the absence of
direct pcrcepcion of future events (na sik/itkinl he is able to predict them on
the basis of "intention" (icchimatrena, ibid.).
Nagarjuna, realizing the difficulcies inherent in such speculations, raises
questions regarding the very cooception of 'arising' in such a cootext. Neither
the momentary eveots 1 nor the substances chat were posited to account for the
continulty of series of such events, according to Nagarjuna, can be describcd as
''arisen" (111panna). 1f they arc not arisen (anulpanna), their cessation is aJSo in
conceivable. Jf thcy were to cease momentarily, thcy could not scrve as con~di
tions (praJyaya).
10.
The notion of dominance was understood in a very generaJ and broad way in
the carly discourscs. For example, oneself (alta), the world (loka). and
rightcousness (dhamma) were considcrcd dominant conditioos_('iirlhip111eyy11)
in the mattcr of refining one's mora li.fe (A 1.147-150). The .Abhidhatmikas
defined the dominant coodition as an active causc (uraf!a-hetu) and this dif.
fcred from the other fivc causes (sec note oo I. 7) because of the dominant cffcct
of this cause. Dominance, of cowsc, can be of diffcrent sort$. For example, a
ll4
seed may be a dominant cause 0f the sprout, just as much as water is. The
Abhidhat.m.ikas cese(Ved the nocion of dominant condition (or active cause) to
explain the latter kind of relationship, namely, t bat becween water and the
sprout. Hence it was defrned as sometbiog "other than fr.self' (svato 'nye, AK
2..50). However, this distinction between self and otber ca.me to be "reified" to
such an extreme that the later interpreters of the Abhidbarma were left with
the notions of self-natute (.wabliiiva) and other-oature (parabha11a). lt became
almost iropossible to speak of 'chis' and 'that' without getting invoved in a
discussion of self-11ature and other-nanue. Therefo.re, when the Buddha's formulation of the genera causa] principle as: "When that tiists, this comes to
be," (asmin .rafidaf'{I bhavah) carne up for discussion, the. metaphysicians were
quick to interpret .rat (occu~ring in the locative absolute construction a.rmin sa)
as substantial existence of the two eocities rcferred to by asmin ( that) and idam
(this).
I
Here too Candrakrrti, in spite of his Jeanings towatds "no views," presents
dependent arisig as a position f.com which to criticize self-nal:!lre or selfexistence (svabhiivl'J). He argues: "Because existeilts are dependently arisen a,nd,
therefore, without sel{-nature, how can tbat statemcnt: 'When that.(exists),' be
intended as an active cause?"' (Bh'ii11an7i7t1- prafitya.ramutpannat1iiit
wabh'iiviibhave kutas tad yad a.rminn iti liiiratJalvena vyapadiyate , (P) 87; (V)
30) . Nagarjuaa's cdcicism, therefore, eaves the Buddha's general formula of
causation untouched, for it was not the Buddba's intentioo to reify either "this"
or ''that."
11.
The effect does not exist in the conditions that are separated or combined. Therefore, how can chat which is not found in the conditions
come to be ftom the conditions?
MKV(P) p .87; MKV(V) p.30.
Once again, the qucstion raised in the second line: "How can that whicb is
not found in the conditions come to be f.com che conditions?'' is grounded on
the asscrtion or premise menrioned in the first line. What is denied in the fust
line is chat the effect is found in the causa! condicions taken either sepatately or
togethet. It does not mean a denial of the statement that the effect comes to be
EXAMINATION OF COND!TIONS
11 5
tlepend;ng upon a coodition or a group of conditions, In other words, it is a rejection of the essentiaist method of looking for the effect even before it comes
to be. A truly empiricist approach would not be concerned with such ao enterpnze .
12.
If that effect, being non-existent [in the conditions] were to proceed from
the conditions, why does it not proceed from non-conditions?
MKV(P) pp.87-88: MKV(V) p.30.
So far, most of the arguments wece directed against sdf-causation and the
substantial ~xistepce of the effect in the condition that gives rise to it. The t>resent verse is a direct refutation of the view chat the effect is different from the
coodicion, that is, the basie premise of the theory of external causation. As implied by Niigatjuoa, in sucha cootext, the term "condition" l'bses its roeaoing,
for jf the cause and effect were sharply distinguished, one could maiotain that
anything can come out of anyching. lt is in, fact, the contrary of the substantialist view: ''Nothing comes out of nothing."
13.
The effect is made of condition.s, but the conditions are themselves not
se1f-made. How can that effect made of conditions [arise] frotn what is
not self-made?
MKV(P) p.88: MKV(V) p.30.
The first line of this verse contains two assertions. First of these is chat "the effect is made of causal conditions" (ph4l41?1 pratyayamayatrt), wbich is already
negated .a t 1.4 (kriyti na pratyayavafi) where the term kriyti is equivalent in
116
meaoing to the term pha/41'(1 in the present context. So does the term
pratyayavafi convey the same roeaning as pratyayamayaf!I. lt is a statement
asserting the identity betweeo the condition and the effect. However, the next
statement impies difference between the condicions chat give rise to the.effect
and those ocher conditions that produce the conditions themselves, fot the
former arc not "self-made" (asvayamm1Jfiih). This, thcrefore, is a theory that
attemprs to accommodate both idencity and difference in the causa} process,
and N:igatjuna sees this as a self-contradiction. lt is indeed a rcfutation of the
third theory of causation negated at 1.1, namely, causation through both self
and other (dvabhya11J).
14.
not evident. Because of the absence of the effect, whete could conditions
01 oon-conditions be evident?
MKV(P) p.89; MKV(V) p,31.
ExAMINATION OF C ONDITIONS
117
CHAPTER
Two
Examination of The Moved and the Not-moved
(Gatagata-parz k.ra)
l.
What has been movcd, in the first instance, is not being moved. What
has not becn moved is also not being moved. Separated ftom what has
been moved and has not been moved, present moving is not known.
MKV(P) p.92; MKV(V) p.33.
The positive stacement: "What has moved is being woved" (gata'f(I. gamyate)
does, indeed, carry the i.mplkation of a permanent substantial entity, an entity
with which movement was associated in the past and whlch is also presently
moving. N:igarjuna's negative statement is, therefore, a denial of such an entity. Yet, this denial may be interpreted as involving the opposite view, naniely ,
that an entity that was previously not associated with movement is at present
movig , that is, the entity that is presendy moving is completely different from
the previous entity.
s
(man moves)
VP
NP
i. (moving) man
moves
jj, (non-moving)man
moves
moves
118'
119
If the two positive assertions: (i) "What has moved is being moved ' and (ii)
"What has not moved is being m011ed," ate accepted, then we have a present
moving which is with and without prior movemenc. This is io a way selfcontradictory. l t is like saying thac "a first cause is both caused and uncaused,"
or chat "a m over is both moved and urunoved." Nagatjuna would appear as a
traoscendentalisc if he had assumed the "present moving" (gamyamiina) which
has the characteriscic of both ''moved and not-moved." The substantialist
petspective was thus contribucory co three views, all of which were not acceptable.
2.
3.
120
MIODLE WAY
As pointed out earlier, the statement "Man moves," can have two possible
metaphysical "deep structures." The same could be said f tbe assertion, "The
s
present moving moves ( = maa moves)
VP
NP
(i) aoa-movlng ( = aoa-moviog man)
hy agamanaf(') .
121
Fot hlm who assens the movement of the present moving; it follows that
there coud be present moving without motion. [However,] the p.resent
ndeed ,
MKV(V) p .43,
5.
A two-foki movetnent is implied in the movement of the J>resent moving: that by which thcre comes to be present moving and, again, the
movement itself.
MKV(P) p.95; MKV(V,l p.34.
6.
122
lf two movements are allowed, it would follow that there would be two
movers. For, separated from a mover, a movement is not appropriate.
(MVP(P) p.96; MKV(V) p.35.
The assumption of two movemencs, as explained in the previous verse, will imply two movers (dvau gantarau). Hece, then, is a basie assertion of Nagarjuna
with regard to language, namely, that one can not speak of, say, movement, in
a vacuum. but ony in relarion to soroerhing tbat is moving (gantr) . This is the
noo-substantialist approach in Buddhism whlch refuses to recognize a sharp
dichotomy between substance (wabhava) and aruibute (lakfaf!a), a dichotomy
that has become an inalieoable part of the essentialist traditions in Indian
philosophy thar are in pursuit of a truy real or uJtimate entity.
This .represents a simple refutation of the essc.> 1tialist view involviog substance
and attribute. If there wece to be no movementseparated frorn the mover, then
in the absence of the movemeot there couJd be no mover. The emphasis here is
on the term tiraskrtya (separaced). When there is no such separation and whe.re
the movement is dependent upon (ptafitya) the mover and vice versa, Nagarjuna sees no difficulty.
8,
123
Nigarjuna's analysis now moves from the present movement to the present
mover. The possible metaphysicaJ implications he perceived in t he statement
"present rooving moves," are not l'ery different from those that may be involved in the assertion that a "present mover rooves" (gantii gacchatt). Yet, the
question raised is in a slightly differeot context from that embodied in Il. I
which refers to the past, that is, the moved or the one who has moved (gata),
whereas the preseot verse relates to a present mover (ganfii). It shows that
metaphysicaJ intetpretations can arise not only regarding che past and the
futuie but also in relation to the present.
9.
lndeed, how appropriate will be the view that a mover moves? For, a
mover without movement is certainly not appropriate.
111KV(P) p.98; MKV(V) p.36.
the
10.
124
WA Y
A mover witbout movement is an entity without an attributc. For the esscntialist uadition, an enci ty is an cntity "in itself' without any atttibutcS, of which at
ttibutes arc predicated. An "cn~ity-in- itself'' thus bccomcs indefinablc and indescribable. Nigirjuna has no interest in such spcculations. No prcdication is
meaningful without the prcdicatcd. These arc mutually dependent (pr11fitya)
and not independent (a-pralitya).
11.
If a movcr wcre to movc, then it would follow that thcre will be two
movcments; one in virtuc of which he is spoken of as a mover, and the
other in terms of which an cxiscing mover is said to move.
MKV(P) p.99; MKV(V) p.36.
This is the conversc of ll .5. The statement: "A movet m ovcs" would imply two
movcments: the first is a movc.r by designation (vyapade1a) and the second, the
really cxistent (sad) mover or " the movcr-in-itself." Whethcr Nigirjuna is
prepared to maintain that all designations arc so wild in thcir impications or
whethcr such is the case with ony some of them needs to be carefully examined, as in the case of concepts of causal depcnrl : nce.
12.
Movemcnt is not bcgun in the moved, nor is it bcgun in the not moved.
Neithcr is it initiated in the prescnt moving. Whcreio is thcn movcmcnt
initiated?
MKV(P) p .100; MKV(V) p.36.
125
13.
Por
Agate gamanll?!J /lula; ("How could there be movement in the not moved?;')
14.
126
WY
and
15.
'
To say that a mover is stationary (gat1.ta ti[thatt) is self-contradittory. To maintain thac a non-mover is stationary (agantii ttj{hatt) is tautological. Looking for
something or someooe (It)(rbhiiva, p11dg11/a) to whkh/ whom the characreristics
of motion. and stasis can be attributcd , one merely ends up conceiving of a
"hare's horn" (aa- vt!a11a) or "crow's teeth" (kaka-danta). Such is the essentialist enterprise. This certainly does not mean the rejeccion of the empirical notioo of telativity or depeodeoce of motion on stasis and vic,e pena, as in the case
of short and long. lt is indeed a simple refucation of the view chat there are independcnr enticies to which the characteristics of motio.n and stasis can be attributed .
EXMJNATION Ol'
16.
127
The argument in the previous verse is made very elear by the present. Empirically, a "mover" without motion is inconceivable, just '1S a pure entity
(s11abli1i11a) without function or characteristics is empirically meaningless. As
such, the statement: "A move(, at the moment, is stationary ," can be made
assuming that the entiry that previousy possessed the characteristic of motion
(gamana) has now abandoned it in order to assume a different characteristic,
narody, stasis. The Sarvastivada theory ofpiiipti and apr1ipti was formulated to
explain such "possessioo'' and "non-possession" after they assumed the
metaphysical notion of a substance or "pure being" (s11qbh'iivt1) (see Poussin ,
AK ii.36).
17.
One does not come to be stationary because one is either moving, or has
moved, or has not moved. Movement, commencement and cessacion {of
movement) arc all comparable to morion.
MKV(P) p .102-103: MKV(V} p.38.
128
18.
The view that movement is identica with the mover is not propcr. The
view that the mover is different from morion is also not proper.
MKV(P) p .104; MKV(v) p .39.
19,
If movement were to.be identical with the mover, it wouJd follow that
there is identity of agent and action.
MKV(P} p. 104; MKV(V) p . 39.
ldentity (ekTbhava) with regard to agent and action is here presented .as a
necessary implication of considering the mover and mocion to be the same. The
non-absoJutism in Naga:.rjuna's way of thinki~g woud leave the agent meaniagless independent of action and vice versa. Nagarjuna will have no difficulty
in speaking of either an agent or an action in an analycical way without reaching
che enremist position of recognizing distinct encities. For him, analysis (vigraha)
was meaningful and practical so long as the limits of such anaysis are observed.
20.
129
This verse specifically lays down the limi t~ to which Niigarjuna was prepared to
go with his analytical method. That is, the analysis should not be carried our to
sucb an extent that Jeaves "mot ion" without a "mover" or a mover without
"morion." Empirical explanation does not allow for such "pure enticies" com
pletely independent of each other.
21.
22 ,
130
MJDOt.E
wAy
23.
The disticcioo becween the "mover" and "mocion" also does not mean ~hat the
"mover'' carries out a _morion chat is different from himself. If sucha distinction
is recognized, then, as explained eadier, there would be two movemeots, the
movement as a result of which one comes to be called "mover'' and the movemeot itself. No such dual motion is found. nor are there two movers correspondiog to the twofod motion . The /act is that it is only one person that moves.
131
An existeot movet docs not carry out the movemeot in any of the thtee
ways. Neither does a non-exutent mover carry out the movement in any
of the thrce ways. Nor does a person carry out a movetnent, both cxistenr
and non-cxistcnt, in any of the three ways. Thcrefore, neithcr motion,
nor the mover, nor the space to be moved is evident.
MKV(P) p.107; ltf.KV(V) p.40.
The conclusion is very specificaJly stated in these two vecses. lt is not any kind of
movet or movement that is cejcctcd as being impossible. lt is the really or
substantially or indepcndencly existent (1ad) mover or movement that is rejected. Th.is is a criticism of etcrnalisrn (iaf11ala-11ada). The opposite view,
namely, a non-rea!, non-substantiaJ and non-independent existence (a1ad) was
the kind of irnpermanence advocated in annihilationism (uccheda-vada)
which, in the Buddhist context, ~ commensu.rate with momentary desttuction
(/qaf!a-bhanga). rather than the impermanence (anitya) advocated by the Buddha on the basis of "dependent arising" (prafftyasamulpada). The coml:?ination of the two metaphysicaJ views of cxistencc and non-existence docs not lead
co a happy synthesis. Change and impermanence undersrood in this
metaphysical way do not con tribute toward a reasonabe and cmpicical explanation of the motion, the movet, or even the space moved.
CHAPTER
THREE
Examination of the Faculty of Eye
(Cakfur-indriya-parz k!a)
1.
Dar(ln(lf!Z ravaf!llf!Z
Seeing, heang, smelling, casting, touching, and mind ace the six
hculties. Their spbeces consist of the object of seeing, etc.
MKV(P) p.113; M.KV(V,) p .43.
2.
133
Sceing does not perceive itself, its own form. How can that wbich does
not pecceive itself, see otbers?
MKV(P) p.113; MKV(V) p.43 .
Nagarjuna was dearly aware of the major contcoversy raging among the
.a dherents of the various "esseoti:is t'! schools regarding the problem of perception. Io their search for certaincy, these essencialist schools assumed char in any
act of perception the "most dear and distinct" is the perceptioo of "oneself."
(see Brhlkliiraf!yaka Upanifad 1.4.1). "I think, therefore, I am'' (cogito ergo
sum) was the premise with which the essentialist thinkers of pre-Buddhist India
began their exposicion of percep tion. The Buddha was himself aware of the difficulties involved in such an assumption when he advised his disciples not to
follow such speculations (mant/i ast1iitisabba1?1 uparundhe, Sn 916). White the
Buddha was willing to recognize consciousness or "sdf-consciou sness"
(11ifJfiiif!a, 11ijnana) as an imporcant constiruent of the human personality as
well as its experiences, he was not willi.ng co assume a metaphysical substracum
such as the "self' or "I" as beiog the objeot of such awareness. He was clearly
aware thac this Jacter episcemological method was the source of most obsessive
conceprions (mu/af!Z papancasakhaya, ibid.). However, the later Buddhist
rnetaphysicians, innocently unaware of the implicatioos of such a method,
seem to havc been led in that direction, thereby dragging themselves into the
quagmire of svabhava-metaphysics from wbich they could not ea.sily get out.
The resuit was the description of perception in the Vibha1aprabli?ivrtti (p.32):
134
While those who accepted the cogito assumed that seeing oneself precedes any
act of seeing, their opponents seem co have used the example of the fire to
maiotain that, Jike fi're which burns cverything but itself, seeing perccivcs
everything else but itself.
The theory of moments (k/af}a) that led to meraphysics in the sphere of
causacion (Chapter I) and cha.age (Chapter Il) did not leave the problem of
perception untouched. lodeed, it was the problem of perception chat was most
affected by a theory of moments, as is evident from the variety of cootradictory
theories of perception presented by the Sarvastivadins, the Saucrancikas and
the Theravadins (sec Kalupahana, Buddhi.It Philosopl{y, pp.97-107).
Being aware of rrus fact , ~garjuna takes the easy route of referring to his
previous refutation of change (Chapter Il) . Hence Candrak:Trci's compositioo of
a verse com para ble to 11.1: What has bee o seen is not being seen; w hat has not
been scen is aso 1:1ot bcing scen. Apart fcom the seen and the not seen , dle prescnt seeing is also not seeo."
The ~ame can be said of that which is puent (dagdhvaf!J), etc. This is what
135
Naga.tjuna means when he says: "That [fi.te] together with seeing are refuted by
[a refutation ofJ the present moving, the moved and the not moved."
4.
NiipaJyamiina~
When some form of seeing that is not perceiving does not exist, how percinent is the view that seeing perceives?
MKV(P) p.1 IJ ; MKV(V) p.44.
5.
Seeing does not perceive, nor does non-seeing perceive. One should admit that a seec is explained by [the aAAysis ot] seeing itself.
MJ...'V(P) pp.115-117 ; MKV(V) p.44.
136
not be established. The rejeccion of the latter follows from the refutacion of the
former. This point is further elaborated in the foUowiog verse.
6.
A seer does not exist either separated or not separated from seeing. When
a seer does not exist, whencc can there be seeit1g and the opject of seeing?
MKV(P) pp.117 118; MKV(V? p. 45.
7.
Just as the birth of a son is said to be d~endenr upon the mother and the
father, cven so, the arising of (visual] <:onsciousncss is said to be depn
dent upon eye and materiaJ form.
MKV(P) p . 118; Ml(V(V) pA~ .
i37
8.
Draftavya-daranabhiivad
vi.fniinat11:catu1!ayaf!t,
niisfity upiidiiniit/ini bhavzjyantz' punal? kathaf{t.
If it is che view that the four factots1 beginnirig with consciousness, do not
138
exist, bccause of the absence of seeing and the object of seeing, how then
can there be grasping?
MKV(P) p .1 19; MKV(V) pp.45-46.
9,
139
Thus, after pointing out the inappropriacness of certain metaphysical views perta.ining to visual perception and having stated the B';Jddha's owo explanation of
perception in terms of "dependent arising" (prafftyasamutpada) , Niga:rjuna
coocludes chat the other five faculties and their objects should be.understood in
the same way as "seeing." This indeed is a very positive explanation of sensory
experience and a faithful representation of the Buddha's teaching as embodied
in the "cliscourscs. "
CHAPTBR
FOUR
Examinacion of Aggregates
(Skandha-parik.fd)
1.
Materia
From amoog the five aggregares (skandha), Nagarjuna selects materia form
(riipa) , aod not one of the expicity psychologica aggregates such as feeling,
perception, disposicion, or coosciousncss. The rcasoo is dcar. He has already
examined the proccss of pcrccption and, rherefore, needs to aaalyse the objecc
of perccption, rather thn perceptioo itsef.
In the discourses, materia from (riipa) was anaysed into the four great
elemeots (catfaro mah<1bhUt"ii) and the elcments derived from these four
(catunnaf!' mahabhuliinarri uplidiiya rupaf!J) (M .87). In their attempc to
decermine whac these derived elementS were, the Abhidharmikas scanned all
the 'discourses looking for any element (dharma) that would be predominancly
materia and compiled varying lists. As a result of speculation on these different
lists, there carne
. ro be a distinccion becweeo gross matter (sthula-fiipa) and subde matter (Jiikpnza-fiipa). Yer, it was assumed chat the four great elements coosticuccd the foundatioo of alJ forms of matter.
When the question regarding the nature of the four great eementS was raised, the Buddha maintained chat chese consisc of hardness and rigidity (kakkhalaf(J' khangataf(J) whieh is earth (pafha11t), watery element (apogata) which
is water (apo), the fiery element (tejogalaf!') which is fire (tejo), and the airy
(11ayogala'f?I) which is air (viiyo) (M 1.421 ff.) . This expains the manncr in
which they are experienced. Howevcr, rhe intetpreters of the Abhidharma
began ro de.fine them as " the four elemencs that support self-narure as well as
derived form" (1va/akta11opadiiyarupad/iiira11ad dhatava/J, Akb p .8). An
~
140
EXAMlb/ATJO.N OF
ACGREGf\TES
141
almosc ide,icical definition was gradually being offered for the concepcion of
dharma (svasiimanyafak1a11adhara11ad dharma!?, Sakv p. 12) where svalak1a11a
refers to self-nature or substance and samiinyalak1a11a
to ' 'genera
characteristics" or ''quality," the atter corresponding in some way to the derived elements. Tbese ideas appeared in the Theravada uadition only in the
Abhidhamma commentaries and the later manuals and sub-commeotarics
(e.g., sabhav11-iiimanna-lakkha11a'f?l dhareliti' dhamma, Abhvt p.11). Thus,
with the Sarvastivada speculation, two new categories wece emerging-substance and charcteristics-whic.h utimately invoved a one-way relationship. The substances serve as the cause (kara1111) of characteristics, but not
vice versa.
Even though these specuations are recorded i.o treacises composed long after
Nagarjuna, they did not originate with such treatises but wece prevaenc during
his day r even before, as is evident from a careful reading of the Kan'kii. lt is
the above mentioned substantialist view of materia form (fitpa) thac is criticized in the present verse. For Nigarjuna (as well as for the Buddha), materia
form discinct from the cause of ma.terial form (ropa-kara11a = mahabhUta) is
not acceptable. Similarly, a cause of materia form distinct from mateti;tl form
is also not experienced . Here there is oo clenia! of materia form , but only a rejection of the idea tbat there is an invisib1e ground of 11111:terial form .
2.
When materia form is. [.considered to be] disrinct f.rom the cause of
matrial form, it follows that materia form is without a cause. Nowhere
is there any effect (arthal/) without a cause.
MKV(P) p . 123; MKV(V) p.48.
I t is the sharp distinction betwc:en materia form and its assumed cause that was
posing an epistemological problem for Nagarjuna. In fact, evidence from a
ater Theravada sub-commentary. sc:ems to lndicate that a school witb
Saucrantika leanings was trying to eliminate the disti'ne::tion between thcse two
ideas. Referring to the definition of dhamma mentioned.in reacion to fV.1. it
is said : "Therc: is no dha1nma over and above the narure of supponiog," [na fa
dhariyamiina.sabhav'ii afio dham1no n'iima atthi, DhsTp.21; see aJso my aniele, "Schools of Buddhism in Eatly Ceyon," in The Ceylon journ11/ of the
142
vid!Jate).
3.
4.
143
144
6.
The view that the effect is identical with the -cause is not appropriate. The
view that the effect is not identical with the cause is aJso not appropriate.
MKV(P) p. 125; MKV(V) p.49.
7.
The method of creatrnent of all existents such as feeling, thought, perception and dispositioru is in every way similar to that of materia form.
The previous comments on the contents of this chapcer would indicace that
Nagarjuna dld not dcny the reality of roateri.l form but only the method ofe:xplaining it. A similar treatment is requested of the othcr a~gregates tao, Note
the use of the term bhava in the present context, which prompts lnada to
fender it a5 "existential actiOflSH (compared wirh its usage at 1.3 wruch !nada
trans la red as "entities").
8.
EX.AMINATlON OF AGGREGATES
14 ~
dress a refutation, all that is left unrefuted by him will be equal to what is
yet to be proved.
9.
These two rubtle and crypcic verses tan best be understood in the context jo
which chey appear. They are placed at the end of an extremdy important
anaysis of die metaphysics relacing co materia form (ropa). As.such they
should be consjdered the conclusion of that analysis.
The basie theme of the chapter has becn the rejection of any metaphysical
substance (svabhava) as the cause of materia! fo (rtipa-k'1ira,,.a). lndeed , there
was no rejection of the cause of materia form, only the criticism of the view
that this cause is an invisible permanent enticy distinct from the perceived
materia! form . This criticism if referred to ac IV.8 as "an ana.lysis in te~ms' of
empciness" (Siinyataya vigrahe krte). lnteresti.ogly, the term "empti1:_1ess"
(funyata) never occurred in char ana.lysis. The ana.lysis was made on the basis of
mutual "dependeiice" of lnaterial form (rupa) and the cause of material form
(rupa-karaf!a). Thus, materia! form and the cause are empty of substance
because they arc mutually dependent. At this scage, if someone wece to present
a refutation of Nigarjuna's view, chat refutatioo wou1d be. iotended as a
refucation of the "mu tual depeodence" of the materia! form and its cause.
However, such a refurarion does not aucomatically p.rove the valiclity of the
metaphysical idea, namely, svabhava chat is being rejecced by Nagarjuna on
che basis of "dependence." The argume~t in favor of dependeoce is experlence,
Hence, che person presenting .a refucation of this idea should be in a position
not only to negace "mu tu al dcpendence" bur also provide evidence for the
establishment of a metaphysical substance (svabhava). This has oot yet been
achieved : Thus, according to Nigarjuna, what stili remains ro be proved
(iiidhya) is the chesis regarding "substance" rather than "mutual dependence."
146
These two verses are very significant in that they seem to admit that the
Madhyamikas have a positive thesis, namely, "dependent arising" which is accepced on the basis of cxperience. The "emptiness" (fiinyalii) they advocate is
simply a challenge for the mctaphysician ro prove his own mctaphysics.
The tWo verses are idenricaJ except for the use of the rwo pairs of terms,
vigraha andpan"haru in the former, and vyakhyana and upala1nbha in the latter. As is wel known, Nagarjuna is also the author of a creatise called Vigrahavyavartai. The term 11igraha means "analysis." On the basis of this work,
modern interpreters of Nagarjuna have assumed that he was merely an
an:ilytical philosopher whose enterprise was confined solely to "analysis"
(vigraha) of opposing views utiiziog the conception of "emptiness" (f'iinyata).
However, IV.9, cast in the same mould as IV.8, raises doubts about the validity
of sucb an interpretation of rhe cbaracter of Nagarjuna's philosophical method .
The use of the term vyakhyana meaning "explanatioo" seems to indicate that,
in addition co "analysis io terms of emptiness," Nagarjuna was aJso providing
an "expanatioo ." That expanacion is once again said to be based upon emptincss (funyatay'ii vyiikhy'ii?Je krte). But as mentioned above, the term "emptiness" did not occur at all in the chapter. lnstead the explanation was provided
on the basis of "dependent arising" (pralityasamutpada). "Emptiness" being
che counterpart of "dependent arising," "explanation in terms of dependent
arising'' would, therefote, be the same as "explanation in terms of emptiness."
Thus, Nagarjuna, even when presenting his posirive theory of "dependent
arising," need not worry about someone censuring bim, for the theoi:y of
"dependence", likc "emptiness," was intended to reject the mecaphysicr of
subsrance, and the responsibilicy once again falls on his opponcnt co prove his
own substance-mecaphysics.
CHAPTER
FIVE
The Examination of Elements
(Dhatu-parz ksd)
l.
p.~l.
As pointed out earlier, the caregories of aggregates, spheres, and elements constituted an important pace of the Buddha's ceachings as well as of the
Abhidharma analysis (UL l ). This early classification was incended to accounc
for che human personality (skandha), its experience ( 12 ayatanas = 6 indn'yas
and 6 111/ayas.) and finally the dements to which this whole experience can be
analysed (18 elemcnts = 6 ayatanas, 6 v1jayas and 6 forms of consciousness).
Howevcr, Nagarjuna does nor cake them in that particular order. Th is is
because of the problems creaced by the ioterprcters of the Abhidharma. They
were more concerned with defining each one of che elements in eacb of the
catcgories without considcring them in the light of other elements within the
category to which ie belongs or in terms of ocher cacegories oucside of
themselves. This led to a wide range of mctaphysical speculations . For example,
one of the elemeots (dh'iit11) chat caused much misunderscanding and led to
many metaphysicaJ ideas is the conception of "space" (iik'iifa) . Although
"space" is not an item included among either che aggregatcs, spheres or
elements (in rhe earlier classificacion), ii indeed was pan of an analysis of che
human personality comparable co the analysis into five aggregates (skandha).
The counrerpart of the skandha-classificarion is the explanation of the human
personality io terms of six elcments (cha-dhatu or !afidhii,tu), one of which was
"space" (akafa) (M 3. 239). At S 2.150, the Buddha specifically recognized che
inrerdependence of material form and "the sphere of space"
148
2.
TH E EXAMINATION OF El.EMl!NTS
149
a tabula rasa, then one also cannot account for adventitious elemeots through
which something comes to be koown. ihis tpresents the second aspect of the
metaphysical definition mentioned earlier-, namely, t he "unobstructed space"
serving as the locale for the appearance of materiaJ form (yq.tm iiiptJJya gatif? =
iiipasya kramata7(J).
3.
L50
The relativiry of concepts, or more spedfically the contextual meaning of concepts, is herc underscored. Definitions may be useful in clarifying the meaning
of terms. Yet these meani ngs are not derived independencly; they occur in conrexts and, as such, any reference to subsrance and attribute shouJd not be taken
co imply distinct or pure referents. What are denied here are not the concepts
of the characterized or of the characteristics, but merely their independent ex1stence.
5.
This is not a blanket denial of the cha.racterized and the characteristic. Rather it
is a denial of these two clements as expajned at V.4, namely, as substance and
attribure conscirucing independent entitics. Therefore, one cannot find any
event, any enci ty, any existence tbac is separated from the characterized and the
characteristic. An existent separated from the characterized as wel as the
charactcristic could turo out to be a "pure entity ," an idea clearly unacceptable
to Nigarjuna.
6.
15 1
Herc again, if we arc to understand "cxistent" (bh7i11fl) wichout takjng inco consideracion the son of "existent" referred to at V. 5, we would be left wich a
universal statement regarcling all "existeots" (bh7i11a). Yet, it is not meant to
be taken that way. The "existent'' referced to herc is already defined at V. 5. It is
an "existent" chat is separated from either the characterised or the characteristic
or both. lt is a "pure existent." Such a pure existent could then be contrasted
with a pure non-existent, and i~ is this sharp distinction or dichotomy chat is
being questioned by Nagarjuna. Indeed , it is significant to note the use of the
term 11i-dharma (whose occurrence in any other text is not knowa to the present
author) in the sense of ''distinct things."
7.
8.
lhose who arc of little intelligence, who percdve the existence as weU as
152
CHAPTER
SIX
The Examination of Lust and the Lustful
1.
lf a lustful one, separated ftom lust, were to exist prior to Just, then
depending upon bim there will be Just. Lust exists when thete is a Justful
one.
MKV(P) p.138; MKV(V) p.55.
.
.
1~4
2.
When a lustful one does not cxist, whence can tbere be lust? Wbether
lust exists or not, the method (of analysis) even of the lustful one would
be comparable.
MKV(P) pp. 138-1:39; MKV(V} p. 5~
Thus. Nagarjuna raises the question as to how there could be !ust in che
absence of a luscful one . This avoids the theoty of a tabula rasa and the adventitious impressions. Lec alooe the exisrence or the non-exiscence of lusc. even
the lustfuJ one has to be analysed in terms of dcpendeoce , not in terms of pure
entities having tbeir own sdf-narure (svabha11a) .
155
Again, the simultaneous occurrences of lust and the lustful one is not
proper. Lust and the lustful one would thcn be mutually non-contingent.
4.
The philosophical probleros created by an over-extended analycicaJ process cannot be resolved by either a cooception of ideotity or of discreteness, The relationship of co-existeoce (1ahabha11a) cannot be established once the analysis
leads to a sharp <;ichotomy becwee~ substance and arujbute.
156
7.
157
If complete separation between ust and the lustful one is escablishcd , for
what pucpose do you conceive of their co-cxistence?
MKV(P) p . 141 ; MKV(V) p .56.
8.
You fancy co-existence assuming that the cliscrete is not establishcd. You ,
again, look for cliscreteness for the purpose of establishing co-existence.
MKV(P) p . 141; MKV(V) p.57.
158
WA Y
10.
On the basis of the kind of discreteness referred to above, one caonot explain
either the association or the non-associa tion of lust and che lustful one. Avoid
the sha.cp distinccioo, the problems are not there to solve. The same can be said
in regard to all phenomena (d}Jarma). Fot this teason, neither absolute identity
nor absolute di.screceness can establish the nature of phenomena.
CHAPTER
SEVEN
I.
160
would apply ro the ideas that carne co be acceprcd by che later Theravadins)
and to reven back to the original teachings of the Buddha.
Once again, the Sarvastivada school was responsiblc for initiating this change
of perspeccive. In the eady discourses, the term Ja'T!Jskrta is used along with the
term pralilyasamutpanna, bur oot as synonyros (S 3.96, 103). While the
former implied "the disposicionally conditioned," the latter was used in the
moce comprehensive meaning of "the dependent." Thus, all dispositionaly
conditioned pheoomena are dependent, but not all dependent phenomena are
dispositionally conditioned. The equatioo of sa'f'(Mkrta and pralitya1am111panna
occurs for the first time in the interpretation of the Abhidharma. 1t was this latter traditioo that Vasubandhu was recording when he said: "Those chat arc made
by the conditions having come cogethcr arc caJled the samsk[tas" (sametya sambhuya pratyayail? krtii iti sa11J1krliill, Akb p.4; see also AA 2.252 , paccayehi
samiigantva kataua). The Sarvastivadins secm to have understood the concept
of sa'T!1Skr1a as a mere refutation of the bdief in the production of an event by a
single cause (eka-pratyaya-janilaf!#, ibid .). Yaomitra, commenting upon this
statement, goes on to say that Ja'f'(Mk('ta and pralityasamutpanna are, therefore,
synonyms (Sakv pp.171-172), thereby bliterating the se ma n tie difference between "made" (krta) and "arisen" (utpanna).
This erroncous simplc equation was to lead to further complicatioos ,
espccially in uoderstandiog the Buddha's characterizatioo of niniiit!a as
tl1t1"!1Jkrta. Eveo though the early discourscs prcsenred ni1'71af!a as an aJaT!JSkrta,
ir was nevcr coosidercd to be an apralityasamutpanna ("independent") . For
early Buddhism. borh sa'T!IJkrta and asaf!'skrta are pralityaJamutpanna.
However. the Sarvastivada equatioo led to the equation of their oegations as
wel . Asa'T!IJkrta secms ro have becn understood i.n the sense of t1prafitya1amutpt1nna, To what extent their perspcctive was dominated by an adherence to the
notion of self-nature (wabha11a), for which they gave no causal explanation at
all ocher thao merely maintaining chat it is permaneot, remains a surmise,
Ie is this Sarvastivada conception of sa'T!1Jkr1t1 as beiog identical wich
pralityaJamutpanna thac is beiog criticized at Vll.1. Nagarjuoa, as indicated in
the first line of this verse, had oo difficuty in assunilog that che Jflf!'Jkrta is
cbaracterized by arising, change, and cwing. This iodeed was a statemeot atttibuted to the Buddha in the early discowses, where it is said: " Monks, there
are these three characteristics of the disposiciooally conditioned . The arising of
that which is dispositionaJly conditioned is evident. l ts cessation is also evideoc.
Change of what has come to eodure is also evident," (A 1.152). Yct if, as explaioed by the Sarvastivadins. sarpskrta is ideotical with pralityaJamutpanna
(the latter also accouoting for arisiog, change and ceasing), then one cannot
peak of thcse tltee characteristics in the contcxt of the asa'T!IJkrta.
It may be of interest co noce that it is not only nirv'ii'!a that came to be included in the cacegony of asa11J1krta by these mecaphysiciaos. Thcy also admit-
161
red "space" (akaa) as an asaf!Jskrta. The implications of that view was examined by Nagarj1,1 oa in Chapte( V.
2.
When t he triad consisting of arising, etc. are. discrete, they are not adequate to function as chara~ecistics of the conditioned. lf they were to be
combined, how can they be in the"same place at the same time?
MKV(P) p. 146; MKV(V) p.59.
Further objections co the Saivastivada and Saurra ntika rheories relaring to the
characteriscics of the conditioned are raised here. The d(screteness of the thtee
characteristics, as envisaged by these two schools, would not allow them to
function as che characteristics of the conditioned. The Sarvastivida theory of an
unqedying substance, which comes to be superficially characterized by rhe
three (or four) moments, as well as the Sautrantika theory that each moment is
inherent in the previous one in the form of pocentiality or seed (akti, bija),
were the direct rcsults of such a pcrspectivc. Furthermore, if rhcse
characcerisrics were disrinct in elation ro both time and space, thcy could not
occur in any one saf!Jskrta at che same time.
3.
Utpada-sthtti-bhaganam
anya1 saf!Jskrta-lakfarJfl'f!J,
asti ced (lnavasthaivaf!J nasti cet te na Ja'l'(lskrtalr
lf arising , stasis, and ceasing are three distinc;t evcnts, chen each one of thcse
wiU require further characterisrics of arjsing, stasis, and ceasing to a.ccou~t for
162
themselves. Thus, the moment of arising will need three f\uther characteristics
of arising, stasis, and ceasing bcfore it could give rise to the next moment,
narncly, stasis. The same applics to stasis and ceasing. This wiJI lead to infinite
regress (ana11asJhi) . On the contrary, if cach of these m oments do not possess
further characteristics, then they cannot be defined as the conditioned.
asing.
Again,
In order to avoid infinite regress, one may assume that the arising of arising is
che primary arisiog (mula-utpada) , and that this latter again causcs the arisiog
of arising. Such mutuaJ action on the part of primary atising and arising of arisiog coul~ climinate infinite regress.
5.
163
lf, produced by the primary, it produces the primary, how can thar
primary, not produccd by it, produce h?
MJ..."V(P) p. 150; MKV(V? p.61.
utpiidaye
tfna'f!J,
164
8.
165
Nagarjuna's criticism of the Sautrantika theory begins here. In order to get rid
of the metaphysics associaced with the Saucriinika cheory of change and
causation , Nligarjuoa begios by quescioning the meaning of the term "illumination" (prakiifa). For bim, light (a/oka) and darkoess (andhaliiira) are
relative ideas. This same idea is expressed by the Buddha at S 2. lSO, wherc it i.s
said: ''This so-called element of light is known through its dependence upon
darkness'' (yayaf(J . , , abhadhiitu ayaf(J dhatu andhakiiraf(J paficca paflfiiiyati;
see also Nagarjuna's discussion in his R.atniiva/i [Ratnava/i of Niigarjuna , ed.
G , Tucci,joumal ofthe Royal Asiatic Society, London, 1934, 1936, l.48]). The
relatonship herc is by way of conrrast; the absence of one means che presence of
che othcr. Thus, "i uminati on" is synonymous with the "destruction of
darkness" (lamo-vadhaf?). one is nor produced by the ocher in any substantiaJ
way.
10.
H ow can darkness be desrroyed by the emergent light , when the e merging Light, indeed , does not teach darkness?
MKV(P} p. 152 : AfA.'V(V) p.62,
i l us trate
che causal relationship berween two momenrary evencs is here showo to be inappropriatc, as
ie cvenrually leads to a rarher substancialist nocion of light reaching up to
d:ukness in order to destroy ie.
11.
p . 15 :\ ~
MKV(J.? p .62
166
Tu PHlLOSOPHY oF THE
Mmo W Ay
12.
If light were to illminate both itself and otherS, then certain.ly darkness
too will .conceal itself and ot~ers.
MKV(P) p.154; MKV(V) p.63.
Taking the acgument of the subsrantialist at VII.8 that light illurninates itself as
well as others, Nagarjuna is herc showing that the same could be said of
darkness too, which would invalidate the meaningfuness of the very example
ilsed by the substantialist.
13.
How can this non-arisen arising ptoduce itself? Hit is the ariseo that pr<>duces, theo being boro, what is it that is produced again?
MKV(P) p .157; MKV(V) p.64.
167
s
Arising produces itself.
NP
VP
i. ( non-arisen) arising
produces itself
produces ltself
The anaysis of present arising (utpadyamana), the atiscn (utpanna), and the
noo-arisen (111'1Utpanna) conceived of in metaphysical terms compares wel with
the analysis. of motion in Chaptcr Il.
15.
When this present arising does not proceed from wichin arising, indeed,
how can the present arising be spoken of as dependent arising?
MKV(P) p. 158; Mk'V(V) p.6j.
168
The first line utllizes the concepcual apparacus of rhe subscantiaists in speaking
of the effect ( i.e .. che present arising. utpadya1nana) as issuing out of the c:ause
(i.e., the arising, utpattt). This is a theory of self-production. As indicated in
1. 7, Nagarjuna rejecrs this causa! explaoacion as meaningless, for there is acrually no production of anything new in such a cootext. lt is mere self-re
production.
If the substancialist were to adopt the cerminology of the Buddha ( utilized so
oftcn by Nagarjuna), theo he could say that the "presenc arising is dependent
(prafitya) upon arising. '' Even though this souods like the Buddha's (and,
therefore, Nagarjuna's) formulation of the causa! principle, yet Nigarjuna is
not willing to recognize it. This is because dependent arising does oot simply
mean the reproduction of the same thing. In che present case, it is an explanation of the present arising (utpadya1niina) on the basis of arising (utpallt),
which is simply tautological with no new informatioo provided . "Dependent
arising" accounts for the arising of something new or differenr, even though
such newness or difference is not emphasized to the complcte neglect of the
cela cionshi p of dependence.
The present verse is indicacive of che manner in which the Saurrancikas,
while trying to explain causation in terms of "associacioo" of discrere momeotary cntities, wece evencually led co a substantialist concepcion causacioo. Eirher
they had co accept self-causation or remain satisfled with rnere self-re
production, the latter providing no explanation of creacivicy at all. "Dependent
arising, on che conrcary. accounts for creacivity without falling in to the
substancialist trap.
16.
p. 6~ .
This singularly imporcanc statemcnt in the prcsent chaptet comes after Vll .-15
where Nagarjuna refused co recognize a form of dependent arising" chat also
169
17.
18.
170
W /\Y
lf arising we(C to produce this prcsent arising, which arising would again
produce tbat arising of that arising?
19.
If this arising were to produce another, arising would turn out to be in-
finite regression. H the non-airising IS arisen, then i.t will produce
everything in tbis manner.
MKV(P) p.162;
MKv(fl?
p.67.
Not only does the Sautrantika theocy lead to infinite regress (anavastha), it also
contributes to the chaotic view that anything can come ~ut of anything, whicb
is the opposite of the Sa..cvastivada v.iew that notUng comes out of nothing._
Causa! unifocmity bas no place whacsoever in che Saucta.n tika scheme of
things. This is another point of comparisoa between the .Sauttaatika and Humean views of causatioa.
20.
Sata ca
As such, neither the arisi.ng ofan existcnt noc the arising ofa non-existent
is pcopec. .Even se is the arising of that whlch is both existent and nonexistcnt,
this has been pteviously explained.
and
171
Neither the identity thcocy of causation nor the oon-identity theocy nor cven a
cornbinacioo of these two will appropriatcly account for all t he issucs rclating to
causation. This idea continucs to be emphasizcd by Nagarjuna.
21 .
Nirudhyamiinasyo1p111Jir na bhavasyopapadyate,
ya c'iinir11dhyamiinas tu sa bh'ii110 nopopadyate.
The asing ofan existent tbat is ceasing is not appropriate. Whatever cxistcnt that is non-arising, that cxistent too is not appropriate.
MKV(P) p.163; MKV('1 p.67.
The theory discussed at VU.20 was the arising of a non-existent entity. The
discussion oow moves oo to the question rcgarding the arisiog of an event that
is ccasing. The Abhidharma interpreters recognized two typcs of causes (helu)
that provide a foundation for the causal efficacy of an cvent that is ceasing
(nirudhyamane k'iirilraf!!- dvau hefii kuruta4, AK ii.63; AKB p.100; also see
definition of k'iiritra at AD 321; Adv p.281). Nagarjuna is reluctant to acccpt
even the fact that an existebt that is on ics way to ceasing can arise. In other
words, cessation and arising cannot be describcd as evcnts taking place in relacion to the same entity. Or moce specifically, a changing substance is unacceptablc to Nagarjuna. Similarly, one cannot speak of an cntity that is not ceasing
(11nirudhy11miina) .
22.
An existent that has endured is not stationary, nor is an existent t.h at has
not endurcd. The presently cnduring is not stationary. What non-arisen
can stay?
A1KV(P) p.164; MKV(V) p.68.
172
23.
Duration of an ~tent that is ceasing is noc appropriate. Whatever existenc chat is non-ceasing is also not .appropriate.
MKV(P) p.164; MKV(V} p.68.
173
When all existents are always of the nature of decay and death, which existents that are without decay and death can stay?
MKV(P) p"l65; MKV(V) p .68.
This is a simple Iejection of any metaphysical idea pettain.ing to the real stasis
(sthitt) of phenomena. This rejection is based upon the empirical notions of
decay and death (jara-maraf!4) emphasized by the Buddha himself.
The interpretets of the Abhidharma seem to have experienced difficulty in
reconciling the Buddha's description of the "dispositionally cooditioned"
(san,iskrta) as having three characceristics (tn11i lak1a11am) (A 1.152; TsenB
12. 5 [Taisho 2.607c)) with chei.r owo theories of momeotarioess. While the Sarvastivadins recognized a fourth moment (caturtham atra vaktavya'f(l syat, Akb
p .75), splitting up "change of what has Iemained'' (thitassa aflfJathatta) into
ewo moments as sc.asis (sthiti) and decay (anyathiitva, jara), the Saucriinrikas admitced ooly two moments rejectiog both stasis and decay. The Theraviidins accepted a thcocy of three moments , once again omitting decay.
The need for recg.nizing stasis o.n the part of the Sarvastivadins and its
denial by the Sautrantikas is discussed at length by Vasubandhu (Akb
pp .75 76). Both schooJs assumed (and this is the case wich the later
Theravadins coo) chat the Buddha's definition of the "dispositiooally conditioned'' in tenns of three Gharacceristics (as arising, decay or change of what has
remained, and ~easing) is for the sake' of the unenlightened (11ineyajan'iirthaf?').
They argued chat it is for this reasoo chat the Buddba utilized the rerm ''appeats" (pannayati, prajnayate) when speaking of these three char.cceristics.
However, chis is not t he case with the Abhidharma theory of moments (na tu
kfa1'!1JJya).
The incerpreters of the Abhidha.rrna (hardly realizing chat the Abhidharma
did not have a theory of momencs) wece making a distinccioo between the
174
25 .
lf stasis (sthit1) we.re to be a distinct event, theo the metaphysicians who needed
to explaio such an eveot in terms of causality will have to maintain that it could
occur either depending upon itself ( = self-causation, svatotpatti) or based upon
another (externaJ causation, para/a JJtpattt) . Both are not appropriate. This is
simiar to the criricism made of arising ac VII .18- 19.
26.
T~t which
has not ccased does not cease. That which has ceased also does
175
not cease. Even so is that which is ceasing. Is it the urtborn that ceases?
MKV(P} p.i67; M.KV(V) p.69.
After analysing the metaphysical concepts of arising (utp'iida) and stasis (1thitt),
Nagarjuna settles down to an examination of the problem of cessacion or
destruction (nirodha, vyaya). 1his criticism follows the method adopted at II. l, ex
cepting the fina question: "Is it the unborn. that ceases?" lf cessation were to be
understood in the sense of momentary cessation, it cannot be explained.
However, if one wece to accept a permanent and eternal substance (111tJbha11a)
which would, at the same time, be unborn (a1izta), as the Sarvastivadins did ,
then that cenainly cancot cease to exist.
27 ,
176
without remaining cven for one moment (k/a11ikasya hi dharmasya 11ina sthitya
11yayo bhavet, Akb p. 77).
28.
lndecd, a certain state [of cxistence] does not cease Crom a state identical
with its owo. Nor docs a state [of existence] cease from another state dif.
ferent &om its own.
MKV(P) p .169; MKV(V) p .70.
The principles of self-causation (siJata-uljJatli) and external causation (paratautpattt), rejected in Chapter I, may have to be adopted in order co explain cessacion itself (nirodha), if the latter were to be uoderstood in the way the Sar
vascivadins and the Saucrancikas conceived of it. Eithcr ccssacion will havc to
occur on its owo, or on .the basis ofanother. Such discussions were rampant
ducing the scholastic period in ~n philosophy ( especially with the domination of the doctrine of mome,N;_armess) whcn it was argued as to whether
dcstruction is inherent in birth or whether,~ is brought about by extcrnal causcs
or conditions (sec Ad11 pp. 106-108). Nigarjuna's rejection applies to both
VICWS.
29.
Indccd, when the arising of all things is not appropriatc, then the ccssation of all things is also not appropriate.
MKV(P) p .169; MKV(V) p.70.
Note chat the term sart1a (all) is uscd as an adjective of dharma, but not utpida
(arising). This means thac Nagarjuna is not rejecting all forms of arising (sariiautpada) as being unsatisfactory. Ratber, he is critical of utilizing the concepcion
177
31.
Nagarjuoa's criticism so far has been confined to arising, stasis and ceasing
metaphysically conceived as events in themselvcs. In the present contexts, he
retums to the criticism of the ccssacion of real existcnts (satal; bha11asya), similar
to the criticism of the real cxistents in Chaptcr I. Neither existence or noncxistence ,- nor a combination of both. arc acceptablc to him.
32.
178
\Y/ A Y
This is the fioaJ criticism of che identity and non-idencity cheories as applied to
the idea of cessation (nirodha). lt is comparable to the criticism of arising (utp'iida) presenced at
l 2.
vn.
33 .
U1p'iida-1thiti-bhaganiim asUlher
n'iisti Jaf!llkrtaf!J,
Sa'f!Jskrtasyaprasiddhau ca kathaf!J setsyaty asa1'(lskrtaf!J.
(asaf!llkrta).
One very significant fact chat caonot escape a careful scrutiny of the contents
of this entire chapter is that , while Nagarjuna has spccifically criticizcd che
tuee kinds of events (arising, stasis, and ceasing), he has made oo criticism
whatsoever of decay (jara). In fact, at VII.24 , decay and death (jari-mararta)
were used as arguments for the rejection of stasis (1thit1). In short, the Buddha's
owo conceptions of arising (uppada), ceasiog (vaya, nirodha), change of what
has remained ([hita11a afifialhatta), decay (jar'ii), impermanence (anicattii) have
been Jeft intact. These have no room for a substantial entity (an atman, a
svabh'liva) and arc indeed compatible with the Buddha's famous doctrine of
noo-substantiaJity (anatta). There could be no reason why a philosopher of
Nagarjuna's caJibre could not distinguish the empiricaJ nature of the Buddha's
anaJysis of the "characteristics of the disposicionaUy conditioned" (sal!khatassa
sankhata-lakkha1{iint) from the metaphysical character of the ideas expressed
by the intcrpreters of the Abhidharma.
34.
179
If the analys.is of the conteots of the present chapter is correct, then there
could be no question that the ilusory character as exemplified by "dream" and
"the city of the gandharoas'' is appplicabJe only to the metaphysical ideas of
arising, stasis and ceasing as presented by the interpreters of the Abhidharma,
and nt to any one of the conceprs of arising, ceasing, decay. change, and impetmanence formulated by the Buddha and accepted by Nagarjuna hirnself.
The Buddha utilized the similies of foam (phef!a) , bubble (bubbula) ,
mirage (manc1), trunk of a plantain tree (kadalt) , and illusion (maya) in order
w illustrate the non-substaotiality of the five aggregates (S 3.142). Nagarjuna
is here using comparable simi!ies for the same purpose . A careless applicatoo of
these similies to explain all forms of ideas, whether substantialist or nonsubstantialist, has given rise to enormous misunderstanclings relating to the
Buddhist doctrine.
CHAPTER
EIGHT
(Karma-karaka--partk.[a)
1.
This really existent agent does not perform a realy existent action.
Neither is it intended that a really non-existent agent performs a really
'
,
non-existent action.
MKV(PJ p. 180; MKV(V) p.75.
181
according to early Buddhism, neither the person nor die aggregate~ (one of
whicb is disposition, sankh'iira) have any substaotial reality. Io the fitst place,
the dispositions chemselves arc impermancnt (11ayadhamm4 sank~iira, D
2.156) and, secondly, all phenomena, includig all persons or aggregates, arc
non-substantial (sabbe dhammii anrJttii, M 2.228; S 3.133; 4.401; A 1.286;
Tsa 10.7 [Tairho 2.668)).
Yet, when the canonical Abhidharma tex:ts rejected a real self or soul (atta)
and listed the various physical and psychological factors that go to constitute
the human personali ty, the intcrpreters of these physical and psychological factors ttansgressed the limits of speculatioo and admitted the real existcnce of
these various factors . Thus carne to be the theory of the substantialiiy of
elemenrs propounded by the Sarvastivadins.
Thcreforc, in his attempt to establish the non-substantiaity of all elements
(dharma-nairatmya) , Nagarjuna was compelled to examine the concepts of action (karma) as well as the agent of such action (karaka) in the prescnt section
of his treatise (leaving the question regarding mora responsiblity for a. detailed
discussion at a later and more appropriate time). As explained previously,
Nagarjuna tealized chat the concepts of substantial existence (sat, astitva) as
well as a.bsolute noo-existcnce (asat, na1tit11a) werc two cxuemcs to be avoided
in any discussioo of action and agent.
2.
A rcally existent cntity bas no' activity. Therefore, acton would be without
an agent. A really existent entity has no acriviry. Thcreforc, cvcn an agent
would be without action.
MKV(P) p.181 ; MKV(V) p. 75.
This is an cxtremely interesring analysis of the implicatioru as welJ as the conscqueoces of admfrring a rcally existing entity (sadbhuJa). a soul or a self (atman,
pudgala) or evcn a substance (!vabha11a). The concept of a self (atman) as envisaged in the substantialist traditions, like the Upanifads, is one of pure cnti
ty, permancot and eternal, unaffcctcd by the changes taking place in the
phenomenal world . lt is beyond all forms of duality and multiplicity. The con
cept of substance, even though rarely dcfined as a " pure enci ty," yet pactakes of
all othcr characteristics , namely , permanence, eternalicy, noo-duility, and
182
non-multiplicity. This means tha.t any activity, any change in quality, in quancity, in character, or in frm would b merely supe.rficial. The real or the essential is eternal. Such implications of the Sarvastivada theory of substance
(svabhliva) wece noted ear1ier (sec Chapter I). If the cause and effect were to be
idc:ncical in essence, then their diffe.reoce becomes superficial. A cause becomes
un-productive and wouJd be like a tree stump that .temains moti'onless (vanjha
ku{a!fha, D 1.14, 56; S 3.211 ; M 1.517; 11vicalit11-nity11tv11, sec Ka1upahana,
Causality , p. 28).
Hence Nagarjuna's statement: "A really existing encity is withoutactivity."
This assercion leads to two rather disastrous conseql.lences, especially for the
doctrine of karma; either an action (lu;muz) will be rendered agent-less
(a-kartru) or an agent (kartr) would be action-less (t1-karmakiz).
'
If one wece to accept the view which is contrary t o the one mentioned at VIU. 2,
that is, a non-existeot entity performing a non-existent action, then both agent
(kartr) and action (ka"na) would be rendered cause-less (a-hetuka).
VIII.2-3 thus turo out to be a elear warning against the universal and indiscriminate application of the examples of "illusion'' (maya) , "dream'' (sv(Zpna) and the "city of the gandbarvas" (gndharva-nagara) , espedally in the mattet of explaining "emptiness" (funyatli) at VIi. 34 and elsewhere.
When a cause does not xis(, both the effect and the sufficient condition
18}
arc not evident. When thcse are ooo-existent, activity, agent and
performance of accion are also not cvideot.
MKV(P) p. 182; MKV(V) p. 76.
Furtbcr impications of the denia of a cause at Vlll.3 are highlighted herc. Not
only would it negate an effecr (karya) or a sufficient condition (k7ira1Ja), it
wouJd also lead to the abandoning of activity, agent as well as action, nooe of
which is accepcable to Nagarjuna.
5.
With the non-occurrence of activity, etc., good and bad arc also not evident. Wben both good and bad do not exist, a fruit arising from these
would also not be evidcnt.
MKV(P) p . 183; MKV( V) pp.76-77 .
Inada's rendering of this verse clcarly indicates his faitbful adhereoce to the
transcendentalist interpretation of Nagarjuna offered by previous interpreters
like Stcherbatsky, Murti, Conze, and most of theJapancse scholars. In spite of
KumarajTva's very elear rendering into Chinese, lnada ttanslates dharma and
adharma as factors and non-facrors respecrively (p. 73). While ie is crue that the
term dharma is used in the Buddhist texts, both in an ontoogica sense (referring to "pheoomcna") and in amore ethical sense (meaning "good") , cbere is no
evideoce at aU that the negacive term ,a.dharma was ever used in the former
sense. A careful examinatioo of the contexts in which it occurs provides sufficient evidence that the term meant "bad" and, hence synonymous wich
akusala. Furthermore, of all che terms used co refer to an effecc, the term phala
occurring in this verse is invariably used in the sense of "fruit ," baviog a mora
connotatton.
The preseot verse. therefore, provides unmiscakable evidcnce that Nagarjuna was upholding che mora philosophy advocated by the Buddha in his first
discourse-the Dhammacappa111111an1rs11tla-wbich lays down a middle pach
184
bctwccn the two cxtremcs , which in ics rurn is based upon the philosophica
middle position prcsented in the "DiscoMrse Io Kiityayana."
The belief in substancial cxistence or eternalisrn (a11hita, sassata) leads to
self-denial (at111-kilamathanuyoga) and the idea of nihilistic non-existence or
annihilationism (n'atthita, uccheda) coQtributes to self-indulgencc (kiimasukhallikiinuyoga) (sec Iotroduction). Verses VIIl .3-4 refer to che substantialist
and annihilationist views of karma, both of which lead to the abandoning of a
mora life (iocluding mora responsibility) as understood by the Buddha. Having spokcn of artha (effect, fruit , consequencc) in relacion to pratyaya (cause,
condition) in Chapter I, Nagarjuna is herc addressingrumself to the question
regarding the :fruit of action" (karma-phala), a detailcd treatment of this problem being reserved for a lacer occasion (Chap ter XVII). In the prescnt chapcer,
Nagarjuna's iotcncion is to cxplaio the non-substanciaity of the "agent'' and
the ''action," rather chan settlc the qucstion of mora] responsiblity. However,
he could not help rcferring to the "fruics of action," primarily bccause the
mctaphysical nocions of "agent" and "action" contributed to thcir vcry denial.
When the fruit docs not cxist, the path of rcleasc or of hcavcn is not ap-propatc. This would imply the futility of all activity.
MKV(P) pp.183-184; MKV(V) p . 77 .
7.
185
An agent who is both existent and qn-exiscent does not perform an action that is both existent and non-existcnt, for they arc self-contndictory.
Wherc can cxistence and oon-cxistencc co-exist?
MKV(P) p. 185; MKV(V) p. 77 .
8.
Existence (sat) and non-ex.istence (asat} applied to the agent and action will
producc some other alternacive rheories than those mentioned earlier, e.g. :
i.
u.
186
W AY
For rcasoos stated above, an agent who has come co be existent does not
pcrform an action thac is non-existent or botb existcnt and non-existent.
10.
For reasons -stated above, an agent who has come tobe non-existcnt does
not pcrform an action chat is exisrcnt or both cxistent and non-existent.
11.
An agent that has come to be botb existcnt and non-existent does not
pctform an action that exists and docs not exisc. This coo should be
undcmood in terms of the rcasons adduced above.
MKV(P) pp. 186-1.8 7; MKV(V) p.78-79.
W hHe VIII.8 utiized the p resent paniciple to refer to the agen t, the p reseoc
verses ernploy the past participle: (i) an agent who has come ro be existent(1adbhuta); (ii) an agent who has com e co be non-existenc (a.radbhula), and (iii) an
agent who has come to be bo~h existent and non-existen t (sadtUadbhuta) .
VIII.10 is not found in the Ch inese version.
12.
An agent proceeds d epending upon action and action proceeds depcncJing upon the agent. We do not pccceive any other way of establishing
(them] .
MKV(P) p.189; MKV(TI) p.79
THf
187
13.
Following this method of the rejection of agent and action, one should
understand grasping. The remaining existentS should be c.ritically examined in terms of the concepts of action and agent.
MKV(P) pp.189-190: MKV(V) p.BO.
CHAPTER
NINE
Examination of the Pri.o r Entity
(Piirva-pank1a)
l.
atha,
'sflly elee 11adanly utll.
"For whomsoever there eicists seeing, heacing, etc., and feeling, etc., he
exists prior to these." So do some declare. -
2.
While the previous chapter is devoted to the refutation of the Canesian enterprise adopted lacer on by some of the Buddhist metaphysicians, the present
chapcer seems to be ca.king up specifically the Kantian project, namely, the
assumption of a primordial condition for all forms of koowledge , induding the
cogito. Heoce the questioo regardiog prior existcnce (purva) .
He could not have beeo unaware of the Buddha's attitude toward the problem of the past (pubbanta). For a r~dicaJ cmpiricist like the Buddha,
knowJedgc of the past (afilllf!J.IC n'iif!a) is as important as any other knowledgc
(D 3.275) . Indeed, knowledge of ''dependent arising" (pa;kcaiamuppada) is
invariably based upon such knowledge. Yet, when the pursuit of that
knowledge is attemptcd beyond its limi~. that is, w hen one tries to achieve absolute certainty w.ith regard to such knowledge, one ends up in specuations
regarding the past (pubbanfiinudittht) rathcr than knowledge (n'ii'!a). The
Brahmajiila-suttllnta refers to a whole hoot of mctaphysicaJ views presented by
188
189
purriiinta-kalpikii).
Nagarjuna was thus convinced that the concepts of the cogito, the atman oc
s1111bh?i11a wcte fotmulated by the metaphysicians who wece actempc~ng to know
the past with ccrtainty. No ocher expl~ation would satisfy their yearning for
certainty regarding the past. Pec.tnancnt self, cternal substance, pcc-existing
cogito, a transcendental unity of appercepcion-tbese could account for
breaks or intcrruptions in. human experience as well as their continuity. The ~m
bolism of the chariotecr (Katha Upani1ad 3.3-6) as wcU as the example .o f the
two birds, one enjoying .the fruit, the other watching (Mu11fhka Upanifad
3.1.1), adoptcd SO cnthusiasticaly by the Brahmanical thinkers, were g1adually
making inroads into Buddhist philosphicaJ thinking. The SammitTyas (if not
identical with, at least relatcd to the Sau~antika school) we.re accused of permitting such a bclief into the Buddhist fod. So says Cand~rkTrci. Yet, Sarvastivada, witb its svabhava-metaphysics is no less culpable of this deviation
tban the Sammitfyas with their pudgala-mctaphysics or even the later
Theravadins with the bhavangametaphysics. "Nagarjuna begins the present.
chapter with a statement, not only of this theory, but also of the rationalizations of thosc who formulatcd such a theory.
wy
3.
As usual, Nagarjuna's first objectioo against positing such an entity that exists
pdor to the experiences such as seeing. hearing, etc. as wdl as feeling, etc., is
epistemologicaJ. This objection should serve as warning against those who
believe chat Nagarjuna recognizes a special intuitive non-sensuous experience
through which_the so-called " ulcirarc reality" (paramiirtha?) is known. In fact,
this question on the pait of Nagarjuna is a elear incJiation of che fact that he
was quite aware of the sort of empiricism advocated by the Buddha , especialy
in his "DiscoUISe on Evetything (Sabba-sutta, S 4.15 ; sec also Kalupahana, "A
Buddhist tract on empiricism," in PEJP' 19 (1969):65-67).
190
6.
191
Sorneone is not evident prior to all of seeing, etc. Again, on different occasions, one could be made k.nown by things different from _seeing, etc.
'
MKV(P)
p. 194; MKV(V)
p .82.
While rejecting the view that there is an entity prior to all fortns of experiences
such as seeing, Nigarjun.a is, at the same time, uying avoid the other extrt!me of assuming two different encities when the experiences are di.fferent.
Avoidig .a metaphysical nocion of ideocity does not mean that one is invaciably
coinmitted to an equally metaphysica notion of difference. Just as much as
identity can be explained on the basis of an empirica notion of dependence,
Nagarjuaa seems to assen that differttnce can and need to be accounted for oo
/
an empirica basis.
to
7.
lf someone existing prior to all of seeing, etc. is not evident, how can
someone existing prior to cach of seeing, etc. be evident.
MKV(P) p.195; MKV(V) p.82.
It seems that hece Nigarjuna is referring to an interestiog-assumption underlying an identity theory. The not1on of self (atman) or substance (s11abhii11a)
would geoerally be presented in order to account for the continuity in a large
number of dissimilar experiences. Taking that premise, Nagarjuna is arguing
that if it is not possible to discover someo.e or entity chat pre-exists all forms of
different experienc.es, then such a person or eotity would not be available even
in the case of individual experiential situations. A momentary cogito would be
as impossible as a permanent and eternal self (atman).
8.
192
If a seer is, at the same time, a hearcr and fecler, then so1neone would ex-
ist prior to cach one [of the functions]. But this is not proper.
MK.V(P) p . 195 ; MKV(V) pp.8283.
Only if the seer, hearer, and experiencer ace absolutely identical. chen he will
prc-exist cach individual experiential situation . Nigarjuna righty denics any
ruch absolutc identity . He was probably assuming that even in the act of sceing
the same object at differcnt times, there cannot be absolute identity, lee alone
in the acts of secing di.ffLrcnr objccts . The reason is not chat human experiences
or even the objccts of expcricnce change every moment, but that the circumstances under which such cxperiences take place could vary. (For a discussion of the perccprual flux , sce William James, Some Prohlems ofPhilosophy,
Cambridge , Massachusetts : Harvard University Press , 1979, pp.31-32.)
10.
lt [i.e., the scH] is not evident in the elements from wtich seeing, hearing, etc., and feeling, etc. come to be.
MKV(P) p .179; MKV(V) p.83.
ENnrr
193
lf he, co whom bclongs sceing, hcaring, etc. and feeling, etc., is not evidcnt, thcn even thcse would not be cvidcnt.
MKV(P) p . 198; MKV(V) p.84.
Nagarjuna starts with the negatioo of an opponent's view chat there is a prior
cntit:y to which the expcrienccs such as sedng and hearing belongs. The implication of the opponent's view is that the experiences of seeing, etc. arc independent elemenrs appropriaced by an equally independent prior entity. As
such, for Nigarjuoa, it is not merely the prior enricy that is unacceptabJe, but
also the experieoccs themselves as concdved of by the opponent. This,
tbcreforc, is not a simple denial of any and all forms of description of experience. Rather, it is a parcicular type of disccimination resortcd to by the
metaphysician chat is rejectcd .
12 .
Whcrcin someonc prior to, simultaneous with or posterior to, seeing, etc.
i.s not cvidcnt, thcrcin thoughts of existencc and non-existeoce are a1so renounccd,
MKV(P) p .199; MKV(V) p.84,
194
CHAPTER
TEN
Examination of Fire and Fuel
1.
If fire wcrc to be fucl , thcn thcrc would be idcntity of agent and action. If
firc wcre to be d.iffcrcnt from fucl, thcn 1t would cxist evcn without the
fucl.
MKV(P) p .202; MKV(V) p .86..
Jl(,
195
196
questioos as to whether the person is real or nominal. the Yatslputriyas fell back
upon the metaphor of "fire and fuel" (agnindhana) in order to illustrate their
point of aview (Akb p.461). This metaphor is then discussed at length and
seems to have been the most important means by whic:h the Yatslpuuiyas attempted to justify their concepcion of a "person."
Therefore, it is understandable why Nagarjuna. after dealing with the quescion regarding a substantia agent (karaka, Cbapter VTII) and aso the motiva
tion for such a theory (namey , the desire to rrac:e one's identity to the past,
purva, Chapter IX), would sette down to an examinacion of a singularly imponant metaphor used by the substantiaists to justify their conception of an
agent.
l t may be necessary to keep in mind that Vasubandhu, who wrote the
Abhidharmakofa, was a Saucrantika who believed that a "person" (pudgala) is
a merc designation (prajapt1) without any realiry. Hence his agreement with
the nominalist position (Akb p .461, a/ha prajaptif?, vayam apy evaf!J
brumaf?). The substancialist position (dravya-vada) was therefore identified
with the Sarvastivada view. Even though the Sarvascivadins did not actualy
propound a substantialist theory of a person. their conception of substance
(wabhavfl) could not escape such implications (sec Sakv p .362 , svabhavala iy
almalal/).
1
However, even if by implication, the Sarvasrivada theory were to be identified with che substantialist view of a person (pudgala), what sort of conception were the Yatslpucriyas upholding? They wece looking for a middle position between substantialism (dravya) and nominalism (prajfJaptt). The discussion in terms of the metaphor of "fue and fuc" was, therefore, intended to
overcome soch dualiry.
The argument follows thus: "Without fuel . there would be no designation of
fire. Yet, fire cannot be designated a.S sometbing different from fuel, nor as
something identical," (Akb p.462, Na hi vinendhanenagnif? prajapyale, na
canya indhanad agnif? iakyale prajflapayifuf?J niipy ananyal/). Similarly, a person is neirher identical nor different from the aggregates. (lf we a.re to accept
the oegacive interpretation of the Nigarjunian dialectic, as is ofren presented
by most modern scholars, tbe Madhyamika position would be no different
from that of the Yatslputriyas as described above.)
Whc.n the question was raiscd as co which of the six sense organs provide
knowledge of the "person," the Yatsputriyas answered: "By means of all six,"
(1abhir api, Akb p.463). They argued: "A 'person' is rccognized depending
upon visualy cognized materia form (ca./qur- vijeyani filPil'!t.). As sucha person should be declared as being visualy cognizable and visually not cognizable;
it is ,neither matecial form nor not materia form ."
Tbese and ocher arguments seem to indicate thac the YatsTputriyas were
following a dialectical method at arriving at a higher synthesis by avoiding the
Full
197
2.
The idcntity of fue and fuel recognized by the VitsTputriyas (as cxplaincd in
terms of the eight elements, alta-dharmaka, sec abovc) would lead to the view
that both firc: and fucl arc buroing all the time (nilya-pradipta), for the caloric
element (uma) is found in both, the difference being quantitativc rather chan
qualicativc . This fucthec lcads to the dcnial of the e.mpirical fact of starcing a
fire . lf fire and fuel arc always burning, thcn fire would be deprivcd of any
spcdfic function. Indeed, the Buddha's ust" of the metaphor of the fi.re at M
l.487 is non-substantiaJist in implication He wantcd to show rhat just as fire ~
not stoccd up anywhece when it is extinguished, even so a "frced one"
(talhiigata) does noc e.ist in ercrnal bliss afrer dcach (param maraf!"ii). Nagarjuna's criticism of the mctaphor of "firc and fuel" secms to follow doscly the
Buddha's own cxplanation of the phcnomenon of fuc .
198
The substancialist point of view cxpressed at X.2 is further analysed herc. If fuel
already has the caloric element (umt1) and, thcrefore, is alrcady burning
(idhyam'lint1), one could not only raise the question as to when it started buroing but also joquite as to whac it is that brings about that burning.
[Fuel] that is <liffertnt is not reached; the urueached is not ignited. Furthermore, that wh.ich is n6t ignited does not cease. That which does not
cease remains, li.kc one that has its owo mark.
MKV(P) p .205; MKV(V) p.87.
199
lf it is assumed that firc and fuel arc different, a futther serics of questions
arise. Difference in the prescnt case implies absolutc distinction or in
dependcnce. As such, one entity cannot reach up to another. Fice canoot rcach
che fuel. Whcn firc cannot reach the fucl , it cannot burn. lhat which does not
burn reroains for ever and does not cease. This expla.ins the vicious circle the
metaphysical speculacions can lead to.
fue,
just as a woman
lf fire and fuel wece considered to be different yet complemcowy, theo Nagar
juna is willing to allow somc son of mutual relationship. He perceives such a
relationship bewteen a man and a woman.
Unfortunately, herc again 'we have a negacive interpretation from Can
dra.krrti. Without ta.king much trouble to cxamine the import of the metaphor
of "man and woman" uscd by Nagarjuna, Candraklrti assumcs that the rela
t iooship exemplified by it is mcaninglcss (dr1(iinta-t1aiy11rthyattz). On the con
uary, Nagarjuna is throwing the gauntlcc at his opponent asking him to show
that the sort of relationship chat cxists bctweeo a man and a woman can a..lso be
obtaincd between firc and fuel as the opponenl has conceit1ed of them .
Indccd, there could not be much difficulty in understanding the empirical
rclationship betweeo a man and a woman. Because of their complcmcntarity,
they arc attracted to cach other. Such a relationship is dearly expresscd by the
Buddha in the first two discourscs in thc Aguttara-.nikaya (1.1-2). Yct the
Buddha ncver attemptcd to go beyond chat cmpirical relacionship-to inquire as
to how it all happened. Such an inquiry was undoubtedly the foundatioo of the
speculations recorded in the Upanz'!ads. Describing the origin of the uaiverse
from a single unitary "self' (atman), the Brhadiira1}yaka Upanifad (I.4.3-4)
says:
He, verily, had no delight. Therefore he who is alonc has no
dclight. He desir~d a second. He became as large as a woman and a
man in dose cmbracc. He caused that self to fali into two parts.
'
200
Here agaio, Nagarjuna is qualifying the sort of relatiooship chat may obtaio
between fire and fuel if they arc atuacced to one another. One of the first conditioos would be that they arc separate. Without such separation it would be
meaningless to speak of one reachiog for the ocher. It is an attempt to destroy
the belief in a myscerious underying unity , any substantial connection. Nagarjuna is wiUing to allow for the empirical differences and the relationship of
dependence among such cvents. However, he is not prepared to leave any room
for any speculation about underlying substances (.r11abhava).
8.
201
If fire is contingent upon fuel and fuel upon fire, which of them is p~
accomplished so that fire could be contingent upon fuel?
MKV(P) p.207; MKV(V) p .88.
The motivation of the substantfalists who were ucilizing the metapbors of "fue
and fuel" (agnlnrlhana) as well as "woman and man" (stff-puru1a), as exlained
at X.6, arc brought to the forcfront hece. Let fire and fuel be related by way of
cootingence (apek,"ii) . Nagarjuna has no objection to it and this is clearly indicatcd by the manner in which Candrilirti himself ucilizcs this particularcon;
ceptioo of cootingence on numerous oa:asionions (sec MKV(P) pp.67, 189,
200, 202.. 345, 492, 527). Io the presenc case, Nagarjuna is oot rejcccing the
mutual contiogence (paraspar?ipek,'ii) of pheoomena, but ooly the inquiry
relating to the prc-accomplishmcnt or prior existence (purva--ni,panna) of any
one of them. Chaptcr IX made it abundantly elear that speculations regarding
the prior entity led to most metaphysical speculations. Having raised the ques-tion as to which one of thcse two thiogs -fue and fuel-is prior, a questioo
that a substantialist cannot resist asking, Nagacjuna procceds to analyse the
poss.ible answers and cxplain thei.r unsatisfactory implication.~ .
9.
If ftre were to be contingcnt upon fuel, there would be proof of fire th.at
is already proved [to e:xist] . When that is the case, evcn fucl would exist
without ftr:e .
MKV(P) p.207; MKV(V) pp.88-89.
Frustrating any attcmpt on the part of the substantialist, Nagarjuna insists that
if fuel wece to be the prior entity (purva-nifpanna), and that firc is contingent
upon it, then what is to be established is alrcady cstablishcd. In other words,
202
10.
(pudgala).
1l .
FuEt
203
X.10 refers to the fire that is already established (.riddha), chat is, something
that is really existent (sad-bhuta). lf one were to move to the other extreme and
speak about events that are not established (a.ui:/dha), that is, those that are
really oon-existent (asad-bhuta), how can such events be contingcnt (apekfya
sidhyate)?
Thus, neithcr the already established (siddha) nor the unestablished (asiddha) can be relatcd by way of mutual contingeoce. Contingence (apek{a) is not
established in thls substantialist way.
12.
.Fire is .not conti.ngent upon fuel; fire is not non-contingent upon fuel.
Fuel is not contingent upon 6re; fue is not non-contingent upon fire.
MKV(P) p.209; MKV(V) pp.8890.
13.
204
WAY
Fi.te does not come out of something different nor is fire secn to be in the
fuel. Herein, with regatd to fuel, the rest is m.tcd .as i.n the case of present
moving, the moved and the not movcd.
MVK(P) pp.210-211 ; MKV(V,l p.90,
(g_atz).
The refutation of all metaphysical formulations of the nocion of identity as applied to fire and fuel is presented here. This is done in terms of the analyticaJ
methods followed in Chapter I.
15 .
Through the examples of fire and fuel, together with the examples of
pot, cloth, etc. evcry method of analysis of the self and grasping have
bcen cxplaincd without exccption.
MKV(P} pp.212-213; MKV(V,l pp.91-92.
20~
Here then is a elear and unequivocal assercion oo che pan of Nagarjuna. Those
who assert the substantial exi.Jtence (satat111am) , whether that be of a monistic
"self' (atman) or of distinct enticies (prthak PrJhak bha11ant1'f!') are not conversant with the teachings of the Buddha. When Nagaijuna makes that assertion
with the statement: "[I) do not consider" ([aha'!'] na manye), what sorr of self
was he recognizing? It certainly could not be anything like what he was
refutiog. The answer to this question will be provided ater.
CHAPTER
ELEVEN
(PUrvriparakoti-pank.ra)
1.
The Great Sage has stated that the prior end is not known. The lifeprocess is without beginning and end. There is neither a beginning nor
an end.
MKV(P) p .219; MKV{V) p.95 .
The criticism of the "self" (atman) as a substantial entity continued in the last
few chapters brings up more related issues for discussion. If there is no such entity, how can the life process consisting of tepeated births and deaths be explained?
Rebitth or rebecoming (ptfn(lbbhava) was an important element in the Buddhist doctrine,, even though the Buddha was concetned more with the problems of the present life than of the past. As mentioned earlier (see commentary on IX.1-2), for the Buddha, the knowledge of the past (afitat?Jse fJaf!a) was
an important means of understanding the present. Yet he did not encourage
speculation regarding the past as he feared that this would eventually lead to all
sorts of mecaphysical views. For this reason, he remained aloof from specuacing
on the absoute origin of things. That aloofness is cleary implied in his statement: "lnconceivable is the beginning of this life-process . The prior end is not
evident," (Anamataggo 1yat?J ... 1af{lJiiro pubbakofi na pannayati, S 2.178,
193; 3.144.151). There is here no denial of the prior end or the first beginning
of things, but ooly of its cooceivability or perceptibility. However, with the
problems that emerged duting the scholastic period In the matter of expaining
any form of origin (utpada), not merely of the first beginning (puN1a kop),
some Buddhists wece compelled to deny outrigbt any form of beginning.
Whilc the Sarvastivada conception of substance left no room for origin and
cessation, the Sautrantikas had difficulties explaining the origin and cessation
of momentary events. The difficulcies invoved in providing an explanatioo
206
207
seems co have led the metaphysicians to assume the absence of a prior end,
rather thao of its iocooceivability. Henc;e the term ana'l!J4tagga ("inconceivable
is the begioning'') came to be replaced by anavqragra ("without end and beginning"). As such, Nagarjuna proceeds with the exa.mination of the view current
during his day, only to revert back to the Buddha's own approach to this problem in the cod. Cancraklr6. confining himself to .t he literary tradition of his
day and influenced by a transcendentalist approach in his interpretation of
Nagarjuna, does not seem to recognize the above mentioned change taking
place in the Buddhist conception of the life-process (.raf!liiira).
2.
How could there be the middle of that which has neither a beginning nor
a_n end? Therefore, the methock of (distinguishing) the prior, the
posterior or both together (i.e., the middle) are not appropriate.
MKV(P) pp.220-221; MKV(V) p.96.
Startiog with the cunent assumption that there is neither a prior nor a posterior
end, Nigarjuna raises the quescioo as to how , in the absence of these two extremities, one can speak of a "middle'' (madhya). He then proceeds to apply
this cciticism to the conception of the life-process (.raf!J-.riira) as- understood and
interpreted by the metaphysicians.
The difficuties cre~ted by the Sa.cvastivadios and the Sautrantikas in the mat-
208
WAY
ter of explaining causa) continuity have beeo discussed at length. The linelU'
view of the causal process broken up into discrete events, one folowing the
ocher, left these evencs without any possible relations . lf the same model were
to be used in explaining evencs such as birth (jalt) decay-death (jafii-maraa),
then the implication woud be that birth has nothing to do with decay-death.
There is no necessary connection between them. If this argument were co be
carried to its condusio, then it could be maintained thac there is immoctaicy
(amrta), for there coll.d be sornething chat continues without decay.death.
Here, Nagarjuna is not insiscing that decay-death should be inherent in birth.
Rather, he is exposing the difficulties confrooted by the metaphysicians who
upheld a linear view of the causa) process.
acter
Pla:cing birth after decay-death in this lineat view of the lite-process, the logical
conclusion is inevitabe that birth cannot relace itself to anythiag prior and,
therefore, is uncaused. lf birth cannot be explained, .just as much as decaydeath could not be accounted foJ (as stated at X.1.3) , then we -are left with the
peak of decay-aeath of
tJOborn (ajiita). Nagarjuna considers it inappropriate to s_
>,'
something/ someone who is not born.
5.
209
6.
The speculation that is questioned herc is specifically related to the sort of succession discussed previously. lt is not every form of reflection that is rejected .
Even if the verb prapacayanti wece to mean "conceptualizing", as
understood by a majority of m odern uanslators of Buddhist texts, in chis context, it does not mean the emptying of the miod of all concepts of birth and
decay-death. lt is the particular form of conceptualization mentioned in the
previous statements as well as the earier verses that is co be avoided.
7.
8.
210
the prior end of thcsc is not evidcnt. Of the cntire life-process as well as of
all existcnts, the prior end is not cvidcnt.
MKV(P) p.224; MKV(V) p .98.
CHAPTER
TWELVE
Examination of Suffering
(Du~kha-pan-k~a)
2.
bi:
2 11
212
3.
Yr1dy amt bhya ime 'nye syur ebhyo vam'i pare yadi,
bhavet para-krtan;. duf?khaf!I- parair ebhir ami krtal;.
lf from these those that arc differeot were to come to be, or if from those
these different [things] wece to come to be, then suffering would be caused by another, for these are caused by those that are different.
MKV(P) p. 229; MKV(V) p .100.
EX/.MINATION OF SUFFERJNG
213
lf suffering is oused by ones owo person, thcn that own person can exist
without suffcring. Who is he by whom suffering is self-ouscd?
MKV(P) p .230; MKV( V) p. 101 .
214.
If one were to accept theseparation of sUfferiog from the person who produces
ie (i.e. , the theory cticicized at XII.4), then it will lead to d.ifficulties not only
for one who adopts self-causation of sufferiog (svayaf!t Artaf!t du//khaf!t), but
aso for one who upholds the opposire view , namely, suffering is caused by
another (para-krtaf!t t:/uf?khaf!t). The latter will have to maintain that suffe.t ing
is caused by one person and passed on to another. But that other wouJd himself
be independen~ of suffering, in the same way as the person who caused it. The
question stili remains as to how that person can be identified .
This is similar to the arguments presented before. The sharp dichotomy between the agent of suffering and su:ffecing itsef proinpts ~agarjuna to question the nature of that othet person (para-pudga/4) who is supposed to be the
author of suffering and who passes it oo to an.other.
7.
With the non-establishment of self-causation, how can there be suffering cased 'by another? For, indeed, if another wcre to cause that suffer
iog, 'in rclaclon to bim it would be self-ca~.
ExAM1NATION OF SUPr'ER1NG
8.
21S
The i.mplications ofXII.3 discusscd carlicr arc stated oncc moce ccarly and explicitly in thcsc two vcrses. If some othcr pctson wece co causc suffcring, theo
that suffering, in relation to that particular person, would be sclf-caused. Tuus,
if one pcrspcctvic is not valid then the other too would be invalidaccd . This, as
pointcd ou t earlicr, is the method adopted at 1.3 to reject both self-nature
(svabh'iiva) and othcr-narure (parabh'iiva) .
9.
If suffeng wece to be caused by both, it would be caused by cach individually. Whcnce can thece be suffering that is causcd neither by
another nor by oneself aild is without a cause?
MKV(P) p.233; MKV(V) p. 102,
216
lO.
lt is not that the foutfold theory applied exdusively to suffering is not cvident. Tbe fouold theo.ry pertaining to other existents too is not evident.
MKV(P) p .233; M.KV(V) p. 102.
Iha-<a's explanation
(p ,88) seems to leave no toom for. a fifth view which both the Buddha (in his
discourse to Kassapa) and Nagarjuoa (at XII.2) wece very clearly and unequivocaUy upholding, namely. "dependent arising of suffering." Hence his
condusion that these four possible views can. equally be applied to demonstrate
the impossibility ofas.serting ele1nents of the external world. On the concrary,
Nagarjuna (as well as the Buddha) were mercly criticizing the futility of
adoptlog these f91J! .particular views io explaining suffering as weU as other
elements in the woi'td of experience. Indeed , Nagarjuna was dearly aware of
the facr that these four are not the ooJy views explicating the causation of suffering. Hence his statement in the very fust verse in this chapter, "Some assert"
(eke icchanti), wruch meaos that it is not evecyone that assects such theories.
CHAPTER
THIRTEEN
Examination of Action and the Agent
(Sa1'!Jskara-pctrtk!a)
l.
The Ble$ed One has said that whatever is of deccptive naturc, that is
delusion . All things that arc of deccptive nature involve dispositions.
Therefore, they are delusions.
MKV(P) p.237; MKV(V) p.104 .
218
ln the first place, the elear distinction made by the Buddha becween
"dispositions" (sar.mkiira) and "phenomena" (dharma) and, secondly, the fact
tbat he specifically referred to the former being subject to suffering, could not
have escaped the penetracing and careful eye of Nagarjuna, a philosopher
whose wcitings have .influenced some of the best brains in the East throughout
the cenrur.ies. If all disposit.ions were coosideced by the Buddha to be subject to
suffecing, then there is no reason to doubt as to w4y Nagarjuoa sbouJd not concencrate bis attention on these "dispositions" aftcr his examination of the prob
Iem of suffering. Hence che reason for the present chapter.
Why the Tibet.an translators should considet this to be an examination of
truth (tat111a) is also nor a myscery. They were simply loolcing at the conclusion
of the chapter. Is there any connection between "disposit:ions" and "truth"?
As pointed out easlier (V.8), the "appeasement of dispositions"
(Ia'f!lskiiropafama) .is the ultimatc goal of Buddhism. Excessive lust (raga) is
supposed to lead to the strengthening or solidificacion of one's dispositions,
which in ruro conuibutes to grasping, no~ only for the objects of sense pleasure,
but also for ideas . The result would be the dogmacie grasping on to absolute
truth or truths. The elimination of lust wouJd then mean the elimination of the
dispositions too (Ia?!J.rkiira-R,aya) which would imply virtual death and oo
motivatioo for any action or even to continue with one's preseot life. Thus, the
Buddha hlmsclf was willing to characterize the death of a "freed one"
(tathagata) as the "cessation of dispositions" (sakharakkaya) (Dhp 383)
leading to the cessation of the stream of bccoming (bha11a-sota) .
Howcver, while recognizing the waning of lust (rag4k.khaya) as the way to
freedom , the Buddha did noc encomage the complcte elimination of dispositions which would mean su icide. Ie seems that che Buddha. did not recognize a
one-to-one relationship betweeo the waning of' lust and the cessation of
dispositions. Hence his emphasis on the appeasement of dispositioos while living and the cessacion of dispositions at the .time of death.
The sucngtheoing of dispositions, as meotiooed earlier, leads to dogmacie
bclicfs. These would pert:Un to personal immort.ality, conceived io the form of
a belief in an eternal soul or self (atman) or of a universal reality (loka,
brahf!14n). Any form of eternalism (fiivata) would be che consequence of such
strong dispositional tendendes. The opposice of ie would be annihilacionism
219
(uccheda), and it is not difficult to understand why the critics of the Buddha
would refer to him as an annihilationist ( ucchedatiiidi) upholding the annihila
tion of re.lly ttisdng sentient being (M 1.140). They were p.robably referring to
the Buddha's advocacy of the "cessation of dispositions" (sankhtirakkhaya) at
death.
Yet, for th~ living human being the Buddha was nor prescribing the elimination of dispositions. Rather he adyocated their appeasement. This view has
significant epistemoidgkal implications. A living human beiog needs to act.
Action involves understanding. Conduct (caraf!a) is preceded by knowledge
(vidya). 'One needsJcnowJedge of oneself as well of the external world. "Omniscience" or knowledge of ever:ything :was not available to the Buddha. Hence,
neither the absolute oripn of things nor the absolute end of things were
discussed in Buddhism (see C)apter XI). Any theoty that attempts to explain
su<ih origins and ends, whether it._pertains to an eternal self oi: soul (atman) or a
substance (sva!Jliiiva) , was unacceptable to the Buddha.
Dispositions are invariably assodated with the knowledge derived from the
senses. The innumerable data provided by the senses cannot easily be handled
by the human being. As William James characterized sense experience, it is a
"big, b!ooming, buzzing confusion" (Some Problems ofPhilosophy p .32). Being unable to deal with such con.fusion, human beings are compelled to be
selective. They pick out the things that interest them, leaving out others. In
tbat process, they deveop dispositions and these disposfrions in turn conttibutes their share in gainiog knowledge of the world . As such, the world of
ordered experience is one that is construted, made, put together (sam
+ vkr. "to do, to make"), by the human being. This is the ptagmatic conception of truth (latt11a) that is prominent in the Buddha's teaching. The appeasement of dispositions thus contributcs to the e!imination of dogmatism, of
grasping after absolute truth or tru~hs. when all the time human beings are
creating truths. If a person is not aware of the process by which he construcrs
the truths about the world, be wiU not only be confused but also disappointed.
Dispositioos can thus rum out to be a great source of confounding and delusion
(mr!a), unless one understands their function in the formiJlation of uuths (lattva). The tram,ators of Nagarjuna's text into Tibetan probably pcrceived the
direction of the argument in this chaptet and na.med it accordingy.
Note that the dduslon (mrrii) is produced, not by all the phenomena (saf'tla-
dharma) but ooly by the way in which these phenomena are put togecher
(sa'J'!Mkarott) for purposes of understanding (see Websters' Seventh Collegiate
Dictionary, 1965, p. 219 where delusion is defined as "self-deception concerning facts or situations"). That putting together is the function of dispositions
~S<l'f?tskara) . Hence, for Nilgarjuna, as it was fr the Buddha, if anything is to
contribute toward delusion that would noc be all phenomena (H1rve dhr1mi1iJ,),
ratbei: it would be all dispositions (sarve sa'J'!Mliii.ra'1).
220
2.
If dispositions cause delusjons, what is 1t about which there arc delusions? The
answer would be: ''The world of e.xperience. " The Buddha bas spoken of thac
world coo. lt is the world that is non-substantial, is empty of any permanent
and eternal entity. All delusioos arise rega.rding that world which is
dependently arisen and non-substantial, but which is being uoderstood as being either eternal or absolutely unreal.
Because of the perception of change, the absence of self-nature of existents is [recognized] . Because of the emptiness of existencs, there is no
existent without self-nature.
MKV(P) p . 240; hfKV(V} p .105
Tbis is a elear statement that truth or reaJ.ity (lattva) (there being no provisional
truth and ultim<tte reality) is neither substantial exisrence nor nihjlistic nonexistence . The perception of change or variacion (anya1habha11a) confirms the.
non-substantiaJity of phenomena (nzl1svabha11a). This is anothcr way of expressing the idea embodied in the discourse to Kaccayana that "ro hi.in who
percdvcs through right wisdom che cessation of the world as it has come co be,
the notion of existence (atthit'ii) in the world does not occur," (S 2. 17).
Cessacion (nirodha ) or change (anyathabhava) does not imply complete anruhilation. Hence Nagarjuna's view that there is no existent that is without
substance (a-svabhava), thac is, soroething that goes into complete oblivion
after Cl(tsting for a white (bhiitva prativigacchatt) leaving no trace at aJI. The
22!
discourse to Kaccayana says that he who perceives arising (iamudaya) does not
hold on to the non-existence of the world . In other words, arising (Iamudaya or
.ramutpiida) contradicts nihjlistic non-existence (na.rtifii, a-.r11abha11a). Nagarjuna perccives this to be emptiness (!unyatfi) .
This, then, is the way in which "dependent arisiag" of phcnomena
(pra fitya.ramutpada) becomes a syoooym for "empciness'' (unyata) or "nonsubstantialicy" (nairatmya) whkh will be further elaborated in Chapter X.XIV.
Whose change would rhere be, if self-nature were not evident? Aga&n,
whose change would there be, if self-nature wete evident.?
MKV(P) p.24 1; MKV(V) p. 105 .
5.
Neither change of something in irself nor of someth.ing different is proper. The rea.son being that a youth does not age nor does an aged person
age.
MKV(P) . 241 ; 11r1KV(V) p. 106.
Nigarjuna cootioues to emphasize the view thac change (anyathabhava) is inexplicable in the contexr of identity or diffecence. "Of itself" ( ta.rya eva) means
"of somethffig chat has substantial exiscence;" "of anocher'' (anya.rya eva) implies " belonging co something completey differenc.'' As mentioned previously
222
(VII.24), "decay" (jara) was not cejected by Nagarjuna. In the pcesent context,
what he intends to convey is that such decay makes no sense wheo applied to
explain a person who is metaphysically conceived either as possessing an eternal
self or as being dlfferent fcom moment to moment.
7.
'
223
8.
CHAPTER
FOURTEEN
Examination of Assoc1atiQJJ
(Sa1!Jsarga-jJartka)
1.
ihe object ofseeing, the seeing and the seer-these threc do not function
in mutual association either in pairs or all together.
2.
Lust, the Iustful as weU as the object of ust shoud be scen in the same
way. The retrulining defilements as well ~s the remaining spheres of sense
should be seen in the tadic mocie.
MKV(P) pp.250 251; MKV(V) p.110.
The pragmatic theory i;if truth, that is, truth as somethiog put together according to human disp\lsitions (sa1,!tJkiira) depending upon something experienced
(dhamta), is not a very pala table one , especialy for some analytical philosopher
who wants to carry his analysis to the very extreme. In the present treatment of
Nagarjuna's philosophy, it has been repeatedly pointed out thar an extremist
analysis eft the Buddhist metaphysician with absolutely distioct entities. For
hlm (and this was the position accepted even by a philosopher like Hume),
1
'What is distinguishable ~ aso separable." Of coutse, these metaphysiciaos
would theo proceed to expl.in events in terms of"composition," of putting different entities rogether (sa1,!tSkaraf!a) accotc!ing to ooe's dispositions (.ra1,!tSkiira)
or, as Hume iosisted, in teons of one's imaginatioo. However, they will have to
cairy the burderi of explaining how only cettain things can be so puttogether
and not aoytfllog a.od everytbing. For example, one can insist thac it is possible
224
225
to bring togecher events such as the eye, color, and visual consciousness
togecher to produce the impression called "perception of color." Yet , one can
nor, either jo terms of dispositions or accordiog to any imaginarion, put
together the eye, sound, and guscatory consciousne~ and produce either a visual
im pression or an auditory im pression.
The ony way in which suci m etaphysicians can explain any possible association is by assuming a su bstancia re acion, an iohereot nature a.moog chose
events thac are so associated . This is how che anaJysis of events into abso u tely
different entities contributed co the recognition of mysterious subsrances. The
Sarvastivada notion of substance or self-nature (111abliii11a) was, therefore, an
inevitable answer to such extremist analysis, in the same way as Beruand
Russel's theory of relations, defined as neither mental or physical, was the
answer to the Humean analysis.
For such philosopbers, a pragmatic theory ofi truth, where truth is defined as
something "made" (ItJf!likrta), becomes a problem bccause their analysis has
deprived them of any empirical relations in terms of. which ch ings can be
associaced . ft is, therefore, not surpzing to see Nagarjuna raking up the quescion of associadon (saf!lsarga), in order to show chat ie does not work in the
background of the metaphysica assumpcions of certain ana ysts.
Thus 1t becomes necessary co keep in mind chat Nagarjuna's cricicism of
associacion is spcdfically rearcd co che associacion of eveots chat wece so
distinguished chat each was assumed co have its own nature (111obha11a). He
begins this chapter with a reference to the various categories he has alrcad y examined at the very oucset in this secdoo of the book, namely, seeing (darana),
the objcct of seciag (drQfavya) and the seer (drfltr) (Chapter III). XIV.2 refers
to another set of categories examined in Chapter Vl. This appica t ion is then
extended to aJJ occurreoces such as the defiements and facu lcics.
3.
226
the pri ncipe of "dependent arising," insisrs chat such distinccions arc not
avai labe among objcccs of seeing, etc. lf these are discinguished or djffe1enciarcd in the way m etaphysicians do, then they cannot enjoy mutual harmony
or associaaon.
6.
EXAMINA110N OF A SSOCIATION
227
other thing does not exist without the other, and therefore, it does not
exist.
These verses seem to higblight the face that one cannot speak of dependence so
long as one .recognizes absolute difference among events. They arc a reminder
of the detaied treatment of the relacion of contingence (apek.fii) undenaken
previously in relation to the metaphor of "fire and fuel" (Chapter A.1.
8.
CHAPTER
FlFTEEN
Examination of Self-narure
(Svabhava-parzk.ra)
l.
The occurrence of self-oatnre through auscs and conditions is not proper. Sclf-narure that has occurrcd as a rcsut of causcs and conditions
would be something that is made.
MKV(P) p.259; MKV(V) p.1 14 .
EXAMINATION OP SEl.l'-NAlURE
229
In the very first verse, Nigarjuna statcs his owo pragmatic view of truth as
something made (krtaka) depcncling upon causes and conditions (he111pra1yaya-sarpbhutaf?). subscance or sclf-nature, if it wece to ocist, couJd not
escape the principle of dependent arising (pralilya.Iamutpada) .
Again,
be a self-natute th2t is made? Indeed, an unmade self. how could there
.
nature is aso non;.contingent upon another.
MKV(P) pp.260-262; MKV(V) pp. 114-11 ~ -
230
This probably could serve as evidence against the belief that Nagatjuna
recognized an ultimate reality beyond bothself-nature and other-nature. In the
case of the Yatslputriyas, the "ultimatdy real" emerges on the basis of an assertion of both idencity and difference, (see commentary on X.1, "Fire cannot be
designated as something differenc from the fuel, nor as something idencical.")
. The Japanese Buddhist scholar Y. Ueda perceives a unique logical principle
adopted in Madhyamika logic detived from the metaphor of "fire and fuel."
According to rum, ''There are inherent conditions in each sucb tbat their
ultimate rdatonship into a whole or unity entails a mutual dcnial of cach
other,'' (see Ioada, p.80, emphasis added). However , Nagarjuna is here raising the question; " Distinct from self-nature and other-nature, whence can
there be an existent?"
Thus, the eight negations are not intended to prove or establish the nature of
reali.ty, as it is oen and loudly asserted . They are primarily and solely intended
to eliminate metaphysical notions, not co characterize either an ultimate reali.ty
or dependent arising. Dependent arising is a totally differnt way of expressing
the truth or reality.
In the second statement above, Nagarjuna maintains that svtJbhav4 and
parabha11a are both dependen.t upon bhava. They represent a further bifurcation of bhava.
EXAMINATION OP SELF-NATURE
231
lt is not merely self-oature and other-nature that arc rejected, but also existence
and oon-existence. The former pair covers a limited range of explanation, compared to the moce comprehensive notioos of ex:istence and non-cxistence.
An empirical definition of existence, as presented by the Buddha, would
mean some thing, some event, some phenomenon available to the sbc senses (see
S 4.15, Sabba-sulla). Such a phenomenoo is assumed to have come to be oo
che basis of cooditioos (pa.f1ccast1muppanna), to remain for a while showing
signs, ac the same time, of decay (!hita.rsa afJflathatta), and then cease to exist
(nirodha, 11yaya)1once agaio depeodiog upon conditioos. So thal even ordioary
unenlighcened people would say: "Change of what is existent is non:exiscence"
(bhiivasya hy anyathabhavam abha11a1(' bruvate janiil/, XV.5).
However, che metaphysicians can take over from this ordinary man's
language, especially with its use of the geoecive or possessive case (bhavasya).
He will assume that change is something possessed by the existenc (bhiiva)
which is always the same. Y et he cannot say the same about non-existence
232
EJV.MlNATION OF SELP-NATIJRE
233
8.
This and the oext three verses seem to constitute a digesr of the detailed and
meticulous analysis of the two extreme views presented by Nagarjuna so far .
lf existence isunderstood in the sense of primal narure (pr11kr11) , in the way
the Sakhya school clid, for. in fut, the Sakhya used the term 111abhii11a to refer
ro che primal oarure, then there cannot be its ooo-cxistcnce. The rea.son is that
change and primal nature or substance arc incompacible.
9.
Not only the existence of primal nature , but also its non-existence is iocompatible with change. Herc primal nature is understood as the substance and change
as the attribute. If the substance is nor available, the attributes cannot be applied to it. If the substance is present, the attributes become superficial . In
brief, the substantialist enterprise coosists of reconciling subscance and attribute aftcr creating a sharp and irreconciliable discinction between them (see
Chapter V).
234
The above explanatioi1 would eliminace the need for assuming that the first
line of the verse represents a question raised by an opponent to which Nagarjuna gives his own reply in the second (see Inada p.99, who follows
CandrakTrti's interpreracion of this verse.)
10.
"Exists' implics grasping after eternalism. "Docs not exist" implics the
philosophy of annihilation. Therefore, a discerning person shouJd not rely upon either existence or non-existence.
11.
These theories of existence and non-existence are not simple and harmless ones.
They contribuce to unforrunate consequeaces. The theory of existence kads to
the dogmacie grasping on to the belief in eternalism. The conception-of nonexistence leads to an equally dangerous view of annihilation, both o~which , as
will be pointed out later, are damaging to the moral life. Hence, a wise man
would not associate himself with such extreme views.
This seems to be a most appropriate condusion to an anaJysis chat was intended to establish che non-substantialicy of all phcnomcna (dharmanairatmya). Nagarjuna did not allow any toom for the reificarion of any one
single phenomenon that was refcrred to as being pan of human experience.
CHAPTER
SIXTEEN
1.
Part Thrce, according to our analysis, consists of Chapter XVI-:XXVI; and is different from Part Two io its treatment of the subject matter, even though the
subject matter itself appears to be similar in them. While Part Two was concerned with the analysis of the elements of existence (dharma) showing how
t hey are lacking in any substance (dharma-11airalmya) and how tbey are
dependently arisen (parfitya.ram11tpanna), Part Three is concerned more with
the explanacion of the human personality (pudgala) without falling into
meraphysical uaps. The human persooality, both in bondage and in freedom ,
is analysed here. The problems of "self' (atman) , questioos regarding mora
responsibility and its associated concepts of time and fruitioning, are discussed
fust. Movfr1g therefrom, Nagarjuna takes up the problem of the person who
has anained f reedom, the question of rruths, of freedom itself, rrying to deal
ooce again with the metaphysica iotetpretations, until be reaches Chapter XXVI when he presencs the most positive explanation of that human p ersonality.
The present chapter beings with one of the most popularly held misconceptions about the Buddha's teachlogs pertaioing to rebinh (punabbhava) . Even
duriog the Buddha's day, when he spoke about rebirth being causally conditioned or ' 'depeodenty acisen" (patci;asamuppanna), and enumerated several
conditions that would contribute co ie (M 1.265), one of his disciples picked out
one among these conditions, namely, consciousoess (11ifJffiif!a), maintaining
235
236
that it is "This very same coosciousness that transmigcates, not aoother" (:dam
eva viflfiifla?(I sandhavatt.' Ill1(1Saratt.' anaflfla?(I, M 1.256; Chung 54.2 [Tairho
1. 766c)). There certainly were many others, including some of his disciples,
who cootinued to uphold such views throughout che centuries. The widespread
p.tevalence of this view seems to indicate the adamant way in which people
believed that for survival to ta.kc place there must be a permanent and eternal
subscance:
The Buddha's answer co rhese believers in a permanent and eternal self or entity is that any factor that conrributes to human survival, whether ie is consciousoess (vififiafa) or disposition (sankhara), or action (kamma) or even
graspiog (upadiina), aJl these arc dcpendencly arisen. For the Buddha , contnuity can be explained in a more empiricaJ way by following the principle of
dependence of impermanenc fac cors of cxistence, where on leaves an impression on another, thus eliminating the need for assuming a permaoent entity.
Nigarjuna is herc referdng to rwo extremes, i.e., permanence (nitya) and
impermanence (anitya) , this latter being the momentary destruction (k!af!abhaga) advocated by the Buddhist metaphysicians. The. former cepresents the
Sarvastivada point of view; the lacter, the Sautrantika.
If the dispositions (Ia?(lskiira) arc presenred as being either pcrmanent or impermanent whcn thcy rransmigrate, and if there is no mention of causaJ conditioning of rhese dispositions as well as the ocher factocs, then the theories of
eternalism and annihilatiooism are inevitable. Furthermore, such excreme condusions arc especiaJly unavoidable when one factor or eotity is singled out and
shown to be the factor lnvolved in transmigratjon.
237
gregatcs, faculties, and elements (as Nagatjuoa tried to do in the last fifteen
chapters) one does not discovcr him. The "person" referrcd to bcre is no ordjnary person. This person shouJd possess the same characteristic which, according to the previous verse , made it impossible for the "dispositions" to
tranSmigcate, nam cl y, permanence .
!nada seems to miss the meaning of the term mrgyt1m'ii11a in his translacioo
of this verse.
Moving from one form of grasping to anotber, t~ere would be othcrbecoming. Who is this person who bas ceased to be and is [therefore]
non-grasping? Wherein does he transmigrate?
MKV(P) p .284; M.KV(V)
p. 124.
I
Uoderstanding the causa! process in a lioear way one runs into difficulties in expaining "grasping" (upadiina) as a reason, not only foc transmigration but also
for conceptualizing a person. White grasping was considered a.o impoctant
cause for the unhappiness and suffering (dukkha), as aJso the rebirtb of a
human bcing, "non-grasping" (anupadiina) was. a conditioo for happiness
(sukha) in this life and for not bcing reborn in a future life. In adclition, eveo
the vcry notion o'f a substantial "self' (alta) is supposed to be the result of
grasping on to the five aggregates (upadiinakkhandha).
However, if graspiog is singled out and explained in a lioear way. then moviog from one moment of grasping to another, one will be faced with otherbecoming (11ibha11a) . To explain this broken or inrerrupted series of graspings,
one. needs to assume that there is something to be grasped so that grasping can
continue. The: aggregates do not continuously provide a foundation for grasping. They arise and cease. With such arising and ceasing, grasping itself would
be ioter.rupted. This me.ans chat grasping that has come to be non-existent
(11ibha11a) would also be noo-grasping (anupadiina). If so, where is this socaled permanent cnticy and where does he transmigrate?
238
The Buddha left unanswered the quescion regarding the narure of a "freed person" (tath'iigata) aftec death (param1nara11a). Nagarjuna wi U return to this
question in his fina chapter, "The Examination of Views" (Dr1fi-pank1a). In
the present context, Nagarjuna is concecned mostly with the living person . The
previous verses referred to the mecaphysical views regarding a living person in
boodage. The present verse is, thercfore, devoted to an exarninatioo of the
mecaphysicaJ view percaining to a living person who has attained freedom.
Speakiog of chat fre.e dom, Nagarjuna doc:s not wanc co assume chat it is the
cessacion of dispositions, QI of a "person." He was probably aware that che Buddha spoke of the pacification of disposicions (sakhara-upasama) in relation to
a living person who has attained freedorn. H e was also aware that the Buddha
did not advocate the annihilation of a sentient being (1att11a, see commentary
of Xlll. l ). Heoce his present st~tement.
D ispositions that are of the nature of upsing and ceasing are neither
bound nor rcleased. A sentient being, like the foregoing, is neither
bound nor released .
MKV(P) p.290: MKV(V) p . 127.
239
6.
7,
lf, in answer to the question raised in the previow verse, it is said that bondage
exists prior to someone being bound, such bondage, according to Nagarjuna,
does not exist. The analysis in Chapter II as well as in Chapter X can be utilized
hete to refute the implications of a substantialist view. of bondage.
8.
240
MJDDl..E W AY
One who is bound is not rcleased. nor is one who is o~t bound freed .
When there is rcleasing of one who is bound, then thcrc would be
simultaneous occurrcnce of bond.age and release.
M.KV(P) p.29) ; MKV(V) p.128.
One who is substantially bound (baadha) , i.e .. one who bas the sef-nature
(s11abhiiJ1a) of bondagc, cannot be frced . Similarly, it is meaningless to spcak of
somconc who is absoutely free (a-baddha). i.c . whose sef-naturc is frccdom,
as one beiag frccd . If one wcrc to speak of someoae who is idready bound and is
beiag freed , thca bondage and freedom would be simutancous.
10.
241
as frcedom?
MKV(P) p.299; MKV(V) p.130.
242
solution that is almost identical with those meotioned above. Niroa,,_a thus
becomes a prapti that fall into the stream (111a-Iaf!'t(ina-patita) and at that
point sa'!'Jara becomes at;i a-prap1i.
As pointed out in the lntroduction, the Buddha's conceptions of bondage
and freedom (and this woud also appJy to Nagarjuoa's views) have nothing to
do with aoy one of the alternacive explanations mentioned above.
CHAP'J'ER
SEVENTEEN
(Karma-phala-partk!ti)
1.
The present chapter, unlike Chapter VIII , deals with the problem of mora
responsibility. It is an attempt to explain the "fruits" (phala) reaped as a result
of one's actions (karma). The docuine of the fruits of action or mora responsibilicy is pivotal to any explanation of human life , whether it is in bondage or
in freedom . However, in the present chapter, the idea of the accumulation of
merit and demerit (pu'!ya-papa) (for future benefit) is examined at length,
primarily because this parcicular idea is mostly associated with the Jife-process
(saf?Jsara) in .bondage. The Buddha insisted that such accumulatioo of merit
and demerit is abandoned (prahlf!a) by a person who is enjoying freedom (nirvaf!a), even though he does not transcend morals or is not unconcerned with
questions relating to mota! responsibility.
Inada assumes that verses 1-19 represent the popular explanation of karma.
This is questionable. Io fact, the popular, and therefore, a mistaken view of
karma is presented only in verses 6-12. Verse 13, as will be pointed out, refers
to a more sophisticated theocy of moral responsibility held by the Buddha and
his disciples.
The present verse deals with two importaot virtues-self-restraint and
benevolence-and these constitute the friendly way (maitraf?1 dharmafl) which
serves as the seed that fruitions herc as well as in the furure . !nada reads three
virtues-self-restraint, kindness towards others and benevolence. On the conuary, m(litrarrt seems co quality dharma, and Kumaraj1va undetstood it in this
latter sense.
243
244
WAY
pp.30~- 306 ;
MKV(V) p.133.
At A 3.415 (Chung 27.5 (Tairho l.600a]), the Buddha idcntified karma witb
"volition" arid maintaincd I.bat kar-ia, whcther it b_c bodily, vcrbal, or mentaJ,
is to be ra:ognizcd as karma if it is volitional (Cetana 'haf?l bhikkhave kammaf?Z
11adiimi. Cetayil11'ii kllmmaf{l karoti kayena t1acaya manasii ca). ihe emphasis
oo volitjon was intendcd to eiminate the wrong belief that a person is responsible for any and every action be pcrforms, a view that was advocated by the Jain.a
thinkers of pte-Buddhist India (sec Kalupahana, Causality, pp.125- 126). The
distinct varieties of karma referred to herc arc the one's preseoted in the
canonical Adhidharma, and these arc based upon the discussions availabe in
the early discowses.
4.
5.
245
Whatever words and deeds that arc wociated with dclight and
dcsignated as nonintimation, and also tbosc others rctniniscod as nonintimation, but arc associated with non-delight; si milady, merit as well as
demerit consequent upon enjoymcnt, and finally , voliti?n - these arc
reminisced as the scvcn things that arc productive of action.
Some of the ter~ used here to define the various forms of karma appcar for the
first time in the Abhidharma (sec Akb iv.1-2; Akb pp.162 164; Adv
pp .118-119). They arc absent in the eady discourses. However, takcn in
themseves, they do not seem to crcate any philopsophical problems. The
philosophical problcms arose because of the manner in which these actions
wece interpreter/. These interpretations are then taken up for ex:aminacion by
Nigarjuna in the following verses.
6.
This is actually the point at which Nagarjuna begins his analysis of the
metaphysital assumptioos. Hece he immediately turns on to the theories of
idencity and difference. The assumption taken up for criticism in the :first line
needs to be examined carefully. UodoubtedJy, it is the problem ofpotentilJI ex-
246
7.
Wbatcvcr serics that begins with a sprout p rocccds from a sccd, and thcn
produccs a fruit. Howcver, without a sccd, such [a sccics] would not pro-
cced.
MKV(P) p.312; MKV(V,J p . 13) .
8.
247
Since a series arises Crom a sd and a fruit ariscs from a series, a fruit t.hat is
prcceded by a seed is, thereforc, neither inteuupted nor etcrnal.
MKV(P) p.3 13; M.k'V(V) p. 135.
9.
10,
Since a continuous series arises from thought and from the continuous
.series the uprising of \l fruit, the fruit that is preccded by action is neithcr
intcrrupted nor etemal.
MKV(P) p .313-314; MKV(V) p . 135.
248
11.
w/.Y
The ten pure paths of action are the means of achieving good. The five
smnds of setlSC pleasutc represent the fruit of good, here as well as in the
next life.
MKV(P) p.314; MKV(V) p.136.
Following the causal pattern aid down above, namely, antecedence, the
Sautrantika would explain the tenfold path of action (karma-patha) as beiog
initiated by volition (cetan'il) which puts it together (tatliiibhisa7?1skilraal, A.kb
p.248). Volition WU$ becomes the karma, and the series of accions, bodily and
verbal (k'iiya-1iik), dctermined by that volition, becomes the vchicle of action"
(karma,,af ca pantliiinaf?, ibid.). The pure bodily and vernl actioos would
then be the mcans by which good is achieved (dharmasy11 fiidhanop'iiyiif?). The
five strands of pleasurc to be cnjoyed in a "heavenly" life (svarg11), cithcr herc or
in the next world, wouJd be the fruit of the god voJition. This is the manncr in
which the Sauttantlkas otplained the Buddha1s notloo of karma and its effect.
249
13.
14.
Herc, a .debt and karma are compared to an imperishable promissory note. The
metaphor is significant and needs to be carefully cicamined. It is used by
Nagarjuna to ilustratc the doctrine of karma as described in one of the most
250
251
and cooditions, have to face the consequcnc;cs. The imperishability of the promissory note may aJso mean that even if th'c promissory note is descroyed there
is an obligation on onc's part to honor such an agreement.
If', in order to account for such an obligation, one wcre to assumc a substanda1 oature (prakrti = wabhava) in that act, Nagarjuna's reponse is chac sucb a
nacure is i.not determinate" or is "inexplicablc" (avyakr1a), an :11.nswer that the
Buddha himself gave when qucstioncd about metaphysical issues (sec Chapter
XXVII).
Finally, in terms of the realms in which the consequences may be reaped.
such actions can be foutfold. Candarkini rcfers to the fourfold realms as (i) the
sphere of sensuality (kiimiivacara), (ii) the sphere of materiaity (rupivacara),
(iii) the sphere of the formless-{ariipavacara) , and (iv) the state of freedom or
absence of influxes (aniifrtWa) .
15.
2)2
17.
ExAMJNATION OP 'fHE
FRuJT OF AcnoN
253
18.
Karma~111?
That [imperishable] arises in the present life, corresponcing to all the actlons having dual natures [similat and dissimilar, good and bad, etc.] and
stays so even when matured.
MKV(P) p . 321.; MKV(V) p.138.
19.
Phalll~11jalikrafft4d 11a
sa marrJ'!ad va nirudhyate,
anafravatrt I tilra11aftt ca vibhagaf!' tatra lakrayet.
254
'iY/ AY
of the individual. ln the case of the latter, it is necessary to remtmber what was
said at XVII.17 , i.e., that all accioos performed during a lifetime are not continued . Only one of the myriads of actions performed can domioate the last
thought: moment of a person. This wouJd mean that many other karmas, even
though all of them have not matured, may become nulified at the time of
deat~.
20.
dha.
MKV(P) p ,322; MKV(V} 138.
21.
255
Havjng <:oncluded the- explanatioo of the more appropriate view .of karma as
advocated by the Buddha, Nigarjuna does not leave the discussioo without
taldng a look at the possible metaphysical interptetacions or any m.i.sunderstanding of th.is doctrine. He has already spoken of the arising (utpaa'a)ofkar.nia at
the moment of rebirth (pratisaf!U/hi). That arising is understood iii rlacion to
the principle of dependent arising (prafityasamutpada). The i.mperishability
(avipra'fifa) is introduced in order to explain the continuity in the fruitioning
of action. It is not intended as a justification for the belief in a permanent and
eternal substance (svabhava). However, some of the Buddhists did utilize a notion of substance to account for the functioning of karma. It is this particular
notioa of substaace that is taken up for analysis.
If karma is "non-substantial" (nil/svabhava) in the way the Sautrantikas
understood it, i.e ., without any perceivable cootinuity, but ooly as something
that is continually inter.rupted, then the arising of such karma cannot be explained. If arising cannot be accounted for in such a metaphysical way , neither
can cessation be admitted. Imperishability (avi'prar;afa), as explained by
Nigarjuna, becomes the only othet alternative.
Unfortunatly, Candrakrni, who favored a rather absolutistic interpretation
of Nigarjuna (sec comments on the Dedicatory Verses), utilizes the conception
of inlpecishability in order to deny any form of arising. It is because he had such
.. an interpretation in mi'n d that he quotes the famous ve.rse elucidaciog karma at
this .point rather thao utilizing itwhen the i.mpecishabiliry was first meotioaed
by Nigatjuna at XVII.14. As has been shown alieady, Nagarjuna was n~t
critical ofany and every form of arising or ceasing. He was only rejecting the>
metaphysical ideas.
22.
lf itis aSSwned that actio.o comes to be from self-nature, i-t certainly will
256
be etccnal, and action would a1so be uncaused, for that which is crernal
23.
24.
Uadbubtedly, all conventions would tben be contradictcd. The distinction benveen the_performance of merit and evil will aJso not be proper.
MKV(P) p .325 ; MKV(V) p .140.
257
With the cejection of a life of mora purity resulting from the deoial of human
responsibility for act~ons, all mota conventions like merit and demedt (puyapapa) would be reodered 1Peaningkss. lt is interescing to not e thac Nagarjuna
is not referring to the good-bad (dharmt1-adhamz.a or kusala-akusala) distinc
tion , for this atter distincc~n is differctnt from the former in regard co ics value
as a convencion (11ya11ahar~). This is compacible with the Buddba's own explanation of 'karma. On 'pragmatic grounds, the Buddha recognized the
merit/ deme.cit distinction. lt was helpful in leading theordinary people coward
accepting a mora life. However, the notions of merit and demerit coud be
harmful in che long run. especialy because it involves the idea of accumuation
of merit for the sake of future enjoyment and pleasure. Funhermore 1 it is easily
assoc.iated with che notions of reward and punishment, a notion that the Buddha was not willing to relate to the doctrine of karma (see M 1.373; Chung 32. l
[Tairho l.628b]). As such, the Buddha insisted that a morally perfected person.
would eiminatc: the desire to accumuJate merit or demerit (punna-papapaht11a, Dhp 39; samiliitii paliiiya punnapiipaf!I, Sn 540). Yet, it does not mean
that suc~ a person also abandons the good/ bad (kusala-ak_usala) distinction
which is the very basis of merit and demerit. lod~ed , a morally perfect person is
expected to promote good, while eliminating evil or uomed.torious actioits (see
above XVU.l , 17). lt may be for this reason that even a ater Mahayana
philosophir like Dogen deemed it approprate to compile a whole treatise on
this subject.
258
MrooL.E WAY
This is the same sort of criticism that Nigarjuna made of self-causation (st1atautpa1Jt) in Chapter I.
27 .
ExAMINATION OF 1HE
FRurr OF ACTION
2~9
such, karma and defilments become attributes of the personaJity (de/.a) . In the
ptevious verse , Nigarjuna questioned the substantial reality of both karma and
defilmcots. lf they arc cmpty of such reality, what could be said about the per
sooaJity itself?
28.
29.
NQ pratyaya-samutpannaf(J niipratyaya-samullhitaf!J,
aJti ymf!iiitl idaf!J k.armll tasm41 kartipi niisty aJa.
260
Since this action does not exist as asen from a condition nor as issuing
forth from a non-condition, evco an agent does not exist.
MKV(P) p.328; MKV(V) p.141.
The causa! cxplanations of karma offcred by the metaphysidans, oamcly, selfcausation, cxternal causation, etc., or the ooo-causal cxplanations arc not accep~blc . If karma itscf cannot be expained in thls way. it would be futile to
attcmpt any such explanations of an agent of karma. Note the use of the term
i"'1fl.J (this) to ccfer to wma, similar to the use of the term efii at XVII.6, thus
spccifying the typc of explanation that is rcjected by hirn. Por this rcasoo, we
prefer to confine his cdticism only to the mctaphysical views mcntioned in the
verses immediatey preceding (XVII.21-28), lcaving the moce appropriate view
he mentioocd untouched. Tbis secms to be the only way in which one can
rccognize consistency in Nagarjuna's statements throughout this chapter.
30. Kllf1'/'la cen niisti karfii Cli llukll/ syi1 hlrmaja'f!' phalat?J,
maty 111ha phale bhokti kuta eva 'bh1111i1y11ti.
lf both action and agent are non-existent, whett could therc be the fruit
boro of action? When there is no fruit, where can therc be an ex
pericncu?
MKV(P) p.329; MKV(v,) p .141.
31.
261
32 .
In the same way, an agent is like a crcated form and his action is ike' his
creation. lt is like the created form created by another who is cr~ted.
MKV(P) p.330; MKV(Vj p . 142.
.
0
262
This represenu the Buddha's expeence and cooceptioo of his owo personality.
Having stated this, he i.mmediately proceeds to examine whether there is
aoytliing beyood this experience and cooceptioo. What he describes is no mote
than the funciton of man(IS, the faculcy which is responsible for the formulacion
of the metaphysical ideas of self (atman) and substance (s11abha1111). The statement reads:
With his mind thu serene, . .. firm and impercurbable, he applies and beods down his mind to the calling up of a men tal image.
He calls up from this body aoother body, having form, made of
mind (mano-maya), having all (his own body's) limbs and pans,
not deprived of any organ.
This is how manas becomes a sensus communis surveying the sensory fields of
other faculties (M 1. 295) and maiotaining a feeling of identity, which then gets
converte< to a permanent and eternal iitman. Could it not be pssible that
Nigarjuna was aware of the above statement of the Buddba? What could be
the 'differe.oce between the cteation of a non-existeilt form thtough the power
of psychok.inesis and th generation of a belief in a permanent and eternal self
tbough the activities of manas? It seems that human beings, with fa:culties
through which they arc able to perceive and conceive, a.re not the objects of
Nigatjuna's critidsm. lt is only the manner in which perceptions and.conceptions arc formulated that is under criticism.
The metaphors usec at the end of Chapter VIl to illustrate the natutc of
m~tapiysical theories pe~taining to arising, stasis, and ceasing, arc employed
here to elucidate the character of similarly conceived theories relating to
defilements, actions, personalities, agents, and conscquences . .
CHAPTER
EIGHIEEN
Examination of Self
(Atma-par"ik.fa)
1.
If the self wcrc to be idcntical with the aggreptcs, it will .pattakc of upr:ising and ccasing. If it wcrc to be diffcrent from the aggrcptcs, it would
havc the charactcristics of the non-aggreptcs.
MKV(P) p.341 ; MKV(fl? p . 145.
The conception of an individual self (atman) was ' previously cxamincd in a
varicty of contc:xts. The prcscnt anaysis was occasioned by a occd to cxplain the
lifc-process as cooditioned by human actions (karma), the subjcct mattcr of the
preccding cfuptcr.
The Buddha's analysis of the human personaity into five aggrcgates (paflcllkkhandha) was intended to show that underlyiog the empirie.al factors constituting the human pcrsooality there is oo pcrrnaneot and eteroal self. The
Buddha's view was that chcsc five factors servcd .as the basis for any conceptuaization of a self or soul. Hence thcy arc aways referrcd to as aggregatcs of
grasping (upiidiinakkhandha) .
Nagarjuna bcgios his investigatioo into the conception of self by raising two
questions pertaining to the nature of the self, espccially in .its rcatiooship to
the fivc aggrcgates. If the self andthc aggrcgatcs werc identical, thcn the self
would havc to paru.kc of the characteristics of the aggregatcs. Thcsc latter bcing subjecc to arising and ccasing, the self cannot remain pcrmanent and etcrnal . On the contrary, if the self and the aggregates wece to be diffcrent, theo
the former could not have the $arrIC characteristics as the latter. Leaving the
argument at that, Nagarjuna is allowing the rcadcrs to come to thcir OWll conclusions.
So far Nagarjuna has not givcn any indication that he tecognizcs a spccia intuicivc faculty througb which one can sec beyond the world of change and impcrmancnce. Indecd, all that be has admiucd points to his i:ccognition of sense
263
264
c:xpcrienccs as the foundation of human knowledge. The impcrmanent aggregates constitute not only the human personality, but also its experiences. If
the self is considered to be different from the aggregates, Nagarjuna is herc implying that it is unknowable, not merely inconceivable, for it will not have any
of the characceristics of the aggregates chat are all that we know through sense
cxpcnencc.
2.
Jn the abscnce of a self, how can there be something tbat beJongs to the
self? From the appeasement of the modes of self and self-hood, one abstains from acating the notions of "minc'' and "I."
MKV(P) p . 34~ -347; MJ(V(V) pp.147 148.
If a permancnt entity does not exist, one cannot assumc the existence of
anything that bdongs to ie. The deniaJ of a permancnt entity does not mean
that Nigarjuna is committed to a rejcction of self-awareocss or selfconsiousncss . The rejcction of the lattec would undcrmine the very foundation
of his cpistemology. As mcntioned carlier (sec lll.17), Nagarjuna, following
the Buddha, recognized consciousness (and this includes sclf-awareness), not as
a preexistent cogiJo, buc as part of the human personaity condicioncd by facrors such as the sense organs and the objects of perception. Sclf-awarcncss or
self.instinct can be pursued to its extremc limit. The result is che "construction
of a self' (ahaf!l + kara) , which eventualy leads to the belicf in permanence.
The other cxueme is the complete rejetton of any form ofselfawareness, which
is tantarnount-to annihilation.
Without falling into these two exttemcs, Nigarjuna is herc prcsenting the
Buddha's owo "middle way" philosophy when he speaks of the appeasement
(f11ma), not the complere cradication , of the "self' (at.man) and ''whatever that
pertains to a self" (itmant) .. This is pecfectly in accord with the "appeasement
of dispositions" (1~kiiropaiama), the "appea5ement of the object"
(drf11(t111yopaama), ~nd the "appeasement of obsessions" (prapaficopafama),
discussed eatliec(see commentary on V.8).
Through the appeasement of the self-instinct one eliminates the
met2physical nod ons of a self (atman ), and through the appeasement of the
o bject (drtlf'WJopaam11) one is ablc to realize the non-substantiality of
26~
E:JW.lNATlON OF SELF
phenomcna and would not eling to them~ "ooe's own" ('iitmani). These
culminate in the absence of self1Shness (ni"'1'1ma) and the absence of egoism
(niraha'f(lkara).
The dual meaning of the term 11h11'f(l/dira isworth noting. Ah11f?Jkir11 (literaJly. "1-making") mcans both ego-centcredness and pride. )Vhile the term
aha'l.'kira has come to be so popula,r in ordinary languagc, it is interestingto
note that oo such term is construcied with the pluraJ of ahaf!I, namely, maya'f(I,
as ""'Jllf!IUra ("we-making1') would have expressed an idea which is eq'ually
unacceptable to the Buddha and Nigarjuna, for they were not willing to
e~te th~ notion of oneself (aha'f!I) altgether in favor of an equ~lly
mc~physical notion of a "social self" ,
266
THE
WAY
with the interna!._ or the exterml, have wancd, ' chen grasping comes to
cease. With the waning of that [grasping], there is wani.ag of birth.
The usc of the iii formula as mama-iii and 11ham-ili in the prcscoc scatcment
makcs it sigoific:antly differcnt &om the founcr statcrncnt at XVlll.2. In the
former statement, Nigarjuna spoke of 111m11n (self) and 'iilm"iy11 (that which
bclongs to the self) and cmphasizcd the nccd ro appcasc such awar~ncss or f~el
ing. I the prescnt verse, he refers-to t1h11m ("I") and mt1ma ("mine") using the
iii-formula and insists upon thcir complete elimination. (.,r11jt1) . Thus, it is not
che fact of self~awarencss that causes problems for the human beings but the
theorizing bascd upon such sclf-awarencss. The cogito may thus ruro out to be
harmless, so long as it is considered to be a product of the sensory process (sec
m. 7), but ergo sum is what is dangerous, episcemoJogically as wcU as ethically.
When such thcorizing has waned (kf.i11e), t}?cn there is cessarion of gtasping
(upadin11-nirodh11), which is frecdom whilc living. The cessation of grasping
cvcntually lcads to the waning of rebirth (j1111man11f? k,rayaf?).
The face that this statement of Nigatjuna immediately foUows his criticism of
theorizing relating to "mine" and "I," that is, speculation relatlng to subject
and object, becomes very valuable in deterroioing the meaning of the cerm
flWp11, a term that has caused much confusion and misunderst:anding.
Vikalpa can mean two differenc types of discriminatioo. One is the type of
discrimination made at the pheoomenaJ. levcl. lt is the discrimioation referred
to at XVIII.2, a discrimination that 'is empiricaJ y grounded , but which should
be kcpt under control (fama). The second ~ the type of discrimi02tion made at
a mecaphysical Jevcl. lt is the discrimination referrcd to at XVIII .4, which has
ExAMJNATION OF Sm.F
267
gone far beyond the cmpirica levcl and thus become theorecica or speculative.
For Nigarjuna, che defilements f action foJow from the atter, not from the
former. It scems that this is the primary reasoo for his rcfcrence ro and criticism
of 11ikalpa at XVIIl.5 rathcr than at XVIIl.3.
Wrong actions (mithya-karman111). i.e actions chat are defilcd, emanate
from wrong beliefs (milhy1i-dr1/I), which arc the results of wrong thoughts or
discriminations (mithya-sa~kalpa, mithjii 11ikalp11). Obsessions arc- the inevitable tesults of such wrong discr.iminations. When- such obsesioos arc appcased , then a person does not get involved either in a ootioo of a permanent
self or in a theory of complete annihilacioo. The reaizacion that self-awareness
is dcpeodently arisen (IlL7) is a realization that it is empcy of a permanenc
subsrance (svabhava-iunya). This latter is the middle path that avoids eter
naism and annihilationism.
6.
The Buddha's havc malce known the conception of self and taught the
doctrine of no-self. At the same time, they have not spoken of somethiiig
as the self or as the non-self.
AfKV(P) p.355; MKV(V/ p.152
If the distinctions made in XVIII.2 and 4 are not recognized, it is nacuraJ for the
interprecers of Nigarjuna to run into diffiucies in explaining the contents of
tl:iis verse. Hece agin we have che use of the iti-formula, this time used with the
terms alman and anatman, as atma-iti and anatma-iti. However, the differeocc bctween the Buddha's specu ations and those of the metapbysicians in
this regard is thac the Buddha does not speculate on any ena ty (kaicid) as
alman OC as anatman. In other words, he does not reify either atman or
anatman. Reifying atman one eods up in eternaJism; reifying anatman one is
led to annihiJationism. Withouc resorcing to such reificacion, the Buddha has
indicaced the meaning of atman. (atmetz'prajnapitaf!I) and has spoken of the
implications of anatman (aniitmeti deiita~) . Both atman and an1ilman are explained by the Buddha in terms of dependent arising (.prafityasamutpada) .
This doctrine of dependent arising eliminates the need for posrulating either
permaoence or annihilation.
268
269
EXAM1NATION OP Sm..F
8.
Evcrythi.ng is such, not such, both such and not such, and oeither such
.and not such: this is the Buddha's admonition.
MKV(P) p.369:
MKV(~
p . 157.
270
W.AY
On the basis of this statement, Inada, following his predecessors in the interpretation of Nigarjuna, rcachcd the conclusion that "truth is non-relationaJ,
non-descripti:ve, non-diffcrential. ... it is thatness or thusness," (p.113).
Refercing specifically to XVIlI.8, he says 'that herc "Nigarjunaintroduces the
famed Four-corncred Logic, , , . i.e the pssible conditions of is, is not, both
is and is not, and ncither is nor is not, in order to exhibit the fact that fina!
truth uanscends all these possibilities; it is fUnyllt'ii per se" (ibid.)
o far, our analysis ofNagarjuna's statcmcntS has failed to reveaJ any form of
four-cornered logic that he uscd to establish an ultimate truth. Whenever he
ucilized it, he did s i.o order to rejcct metaphysicaJ assumpcions, rather than to
establish something or some theory.
Mter srating the fact that metaphysical views, especially those relating to a
tr1thagata after death, take us beyond the sphere. of thought
(citta-gocara)(XVUI. 7), Nagarjuna is here expanding the discussion to include
one of the most persistent problems of metaphysics, namcly, "everything" (sarVa'f!Z). lt is the problem that led the Sarvastivadins to uphold the view that
"everything exists" (sarvam astt) in .the form of substance (svabhava). Nagarjuna is simply allowing that metaphysica qucstion to be setded by the usc of
ihe fourfod proposicions tbat negate cach other.
Indeed, this is not presented as the "teaching" or "message'' (iisana) of the
Buddba, as Inada seems to understand. Quite on the contraty, it is an "admonition' ' or "advice" (anufiina) in regard to the manner in which spccuation
about "everything'' can be resolved, namey, by detnoristrating the inevitable
self-contcadictions. In other words, he is stadng that the question regarding
"everything" cannot be setted by aoy form of 4iscussion, a view clearly expressed by the Budcha in his famous "Discoutse on Everything;, (Sabba-sutt11, sec
commentary on IX.3), which Nagarjuna was probaby, conversant with.
0
truth.
MKV(P) p.372; MKV(V( p. 158.
This is oneof the most iJllportant statcments ofNagarjuna, quoted often by his
dassical as wel as modern interpreters. The most receot translatioo and inter-
ExAMINATION OF SELF
271
pretttion comes from !nada and, as such, it could be consider~d a digcst of the
existing vicws. Hence, it is appropriate to quote Inada's rendering of this verse
in full. lt reads as follows :
Non-conditionally rclated to any cntity, q uiscent, nonconceptuafucd by conceptual play, non-discriminative and nondiffercntiated. Thcsc arc the charactcristics of reality (i .c. , dcscriptive of one who has gained the Buddhist truth) (p.115).
The term apara-pratyaya is herc taken to mean a special kind of rclation that
trarucends any form of empirical conditionality. iinta signifies "quicscence," a
quicscence resulting from the avoidance of any cooceptuality, probably the sort
of pcace and quiet experienced by one who has temporarily stoppcd the func- .
cioning of the six sense facultics by reaching the state of cessation (nirodhasamapatti, or sana-11edayita- nirodha). lt is where the dicbotomy of subject
and object is compJetcly dissolved (nir-11ikalpa) and where the variegated expedences of the world, the variety of m eanings or fruits (n'iinartha), is
climinated. Truth, in such a context, cannot be very different from that of
either the Upanifads or the Vedanta. l t is the flushing out of all conceprual
thinking (citta-vrtti-nirodha) , thereby transforming the empirical expecience
into one of absolute, utimate truth or reality.
However, a glance at the "Discourse to Katyayana," the primary source for
Nigarjuna's formulation of the "middle way," will reveal the untenability of
such an explanation.
Even though the verse seems to desccibe the characteristics of truth or reality
(tattvasya lalt1af!t1f!J) , every preceding scatement points to the means by which a
conccprioo of cruth is arrived at. Hence, it is one of the most important
scarements on epistemology. The most salient fearures of this epistemolgoy acc
already clearly embodied in the Buddha's discourse to K.atyayana, presented in
the form of an answer to t he question 'as to what "right view" (samma-dittht) is.
The concencs of the verse can be analysed in the light of this discourse in the
following manner.
The term apara-pratyaya does not refer ro a uuth chat is non-condicionally
rclated to any entity. Rather, it explaios the manner in which koowledge
(n'ii11a) is attained by one who has right view'' (samma-diftht). After rejectiog
the metaphysical views penaiolng to permanent existence (atlhifii) as well as
the belief in a permanent and substantial personal entity (alla .. . rne). a
belicf that will require the testimony of some ocher person who caims to know
the absolute bcginning of things, the empiricist Buddha daimed that
knowledge (of one who has right view) ~curs withouc having to dcpend upon
anorher person (aparf!-Pa&cay'ii flaf!am evassa ettha holi, S 2. 17). Ir is
272
knowledge for which one does not have to depend upon another, primarily
because it pertains to arising and ceasing of empi.deal phenomena. It involves
personal vcrification. a verlfication that can be accomplished by someooe
before one l:iegins to formulate any right view.
Man's search for a permanent entity, white he is equipped with limited
epistemological resources, leaves him with unresolved questions. He continues
co doubt. He is constantly perplexed and croubled. Looking for permanence,
he misses the empirically given. The ,search for the unseen "beauty queen"
(janapada-kaljiinT, D 1.193; M 2.40) makes him forget the immediatley relevaot questions (M 2 .40). As such, he has peace of mind. How.ever I if he were
to direct his attention to what is immediately given, .and understand the
human predicament in its context without being ioquisitive abouc
metaphysical entities (dukkham eva uppa1/amana'f!t uppa1jati dukkha??i niru/
jhamana?!J nirujjhatiti na kakhati 114 vicikicchatt; ibid.), his mind would be
peaceful (Siinta_
'f!l). The Buddha, in one of his very famous scatements, insisted
reflecting person understands the arising and ceasing of
that when
phenomena, all his doubts disappear (Ud 1). Such peace of mind is achieved,
not by ignoring what is relevaot in the human cootext, bur by igooring the irrelevant and irresolvable metaphysical issues.
Such a state of peace (flintt) cannot be achieved so long as one is bound by
one's prejudices (11piiyup'iidiinabhinivesa-vinibandho, ibid.,) This is the
"obsession'' (prapaca) chat Nagarjuna is referring to in the present cootext.
The discourse to Kat.yayana has no reference to any conceptua proliferation.
How such obsession~ have further stre.ngthened and encouraged the search
for utimate truths, contriburing to indiscriminate discrimioations,- soch as
those of existence and non-existence (bh'iiva-ab.h.ava)
or self--narure and other.
'narure (s11abhava-p11rabha11a), has akeady been explained by Nagarjuna. These
are the disctiminations that are to be avoided in the search for truth. Nirvikalpa .refers to the absence of such discrimioations.
A pluralistic view of the world is not incompatible with dependent arising
(pralityasamulpada). Pluralism in the context of dependent arising does pot
imply the existence of self-contradictory truths. It oeed not necessarily lead' to a
oorion of an Absolute that transcends such self-contradictory truths. The
critedon for deciding what is true io the cotllext of dependent arisiog is consequence or fruit (artha). When the Buddha maintained that "truth is one; chere
is no second" (eka'f!t hi sacca'f!t na dulijam aflhi, Sn 88'1), he was certaioy
referring to this pragmatic criterion of truth based upon the notion of dependent arising, not an absolute truth that uaoscends all forms of duality and
plurality. Nagarjuna's characterization of truth as "not having a v.ariety of
meanings" (aiinariha'l(Z) reflects more the Buddha's owo concepcion of truth.
To summarize, the conception of truth and the epistemoogical means on
the basis of which it is formulated all point to the face that the truth under con-
no
EXAMINATION OF SEl..F
273
10.
Whatever that arises depencling upon whatever, that is not identical nor
clifferent from it. Therefore, it is neither annihilated nor eternal.
MKV(P) p. 375 ; MKV(V) p. 150.
Whatever is arisen dependent upon (pratftya) another, that is, the dependencly
arisen (prafityasamutpanna). is not appropriately expJained in terms of identity
or difference. As empahsi.zed so often by Niigarjuna, absoJute identity involves
permane.nce and absolute difference implies annihilation. Dependent arising is
the middle way adopted by the Buddha in eluc'idating change and causation.
11.
That is without a variety of mean.ings or one single rneaning, it is not annih.ihlcion nor i~ it eternal. Such, it is reminisced, is the immottal message
of the Buddhas, the patrons of the world.
274
12.
CHAP'fER
NINETEEN
Examination of Time
(Kala-parTk!a)
1. Pratyutpanno
'niigata
If the present and the future exist contingent upon the past, ,then the pre~
sent and the future would be in the past time.
2.
Pratyutpanno
pratyutpanno
'niigala ca
Again, if the present and the future were not to exist therein [i.e. , in.the
past], how could the present an,d the future be contingent upon that?
MKV(P) pp. 382-383; MKV(V) p . 163 .
276
Moreover, non-contingent upon the past, their [i.e. of the present and
future] establishment is not evident. Therefore, neither a present nor a
future time is evident.
MKV(P) p. 383; M.KV(V) p.163.
The present verse embodies Nagarjuna's criticism of the ootion of cime referred
to in XIX.12. Taken away from tharcootext, this will appear co be a compJete
rejection of the very notion of rimc. However, Nagarjuna's cdticism pertains
only to the cootingencc (apek{a) uoderstood in the light of a theoty of inherence. On a previous occasion (X .-8-12), Nagarjuna has convincingly
demonstratcd the difficulties involved in explainiog conti~gence or reJativity in
the context of theories of ideotity (which is also implied in inherence) and dif.
ference.
Nagarjuna's argument seems to .rcad as follows :
1.
Major premiss:
The present and the future arc not scen to be cstablished non
contingent upon the past.
2.
Middle term:
Contingeoce of the present and the future on the past impLies
the substan tial existeoce of the present and the future in the
past, which is not evident.
EXAMINATION OP TTME
3.
277
Conclu1ion:
Therefore, the present and the future, as substantiaJ entities,
do not exist.
Ignoring the middle term, so cleary _defined at XIX.1-2, Nigarjuna's condusion will appear to be an absolute rejection of time. lt wouJd then read as
follows:
I.
Pint premisJ:
The present and the future are not contingeot upon the past.
2.
Second premiu:
The present and the future arc not non-contingent upon the
past.
3. Minor premi.u:
The present and the future cannot be both contingent and
non-cootingent upon the past.
4.
Conclusion:
The present and the future do not exist.
Nigujuna is insistiog that the same argument be applied to the concept of the
present in relation to the past and future, and to the future in relatioo to the
past and present. In addition, he maintains that this analysis can be extended
to similar concepts like the highest, the owest, the middle, etc. In all chese
cases, the metaphysicaJ issues emerge as a result of the abso/ute distinctions that
are being made. Such absolutc distinccions arc being ofren made in logical
analyses, and are oot supporced by empirical evidence . Time, aJ experienced ,
cannot be analysed into three water-tight 'Compartmeots as past, present, and
278
'
5.
A non-static time is ,iot observed. A static time is not evident. Even ifthe
unobserved time were to be obse.rved, how can it be made knwn?
MKV(Pj p.385; MKV(V) p. 165 .
pp.165-16~ ,I
ExAMINATION OP 'nM1!
279
CHAPTER
TWEN1Y
Examination of Harmony
(Samagn-parz k! a)
lf the cffect were to arise Crom a harmony of cause and conditions, and if
it wcre to exist in the ruumony, how can it atisc from the hacmony?
2.
If the effect were to arise fcom a harmony of cause and conditions and if ir
wcre not to exist in the harmony, how can it arisc from the harmony?
MKV(P) p .391 ; MKV(v,J p. 168.
EXAMINATION OF H A.RMONY
281
For this reason, in the very first verse, Nagarjuna takes up three ideas: (i) harmony, (ii) distinction betweeo cause and condicions, and (iii) the arising of an
eff.ectfrom a harmony of cause and cooditions. (Note Nagarjuna's use of helu
in the singu lar and pralyaya in the pl ural.)
Nagarjuna's critidsm is mainly directed at the idea of self-causation. If the
fruit arises from the harmony (siimagrya, abJacive case) of a cause and a set of
cooditions (helo!/ pratyayanaf!Z ca), then it is already existent in che ham1ony
(samagry'iif!Z, locacive case). H ow then can it arise from the harmony
(1amagrya)? The causal process presenced in this manner implies che idencicy
between "harmooy of cause and conditions" and the fruit or eff.ect that arises
from it. The ideotity theory of causatioo was already criticized in Chapter I.
Similarly, as stated atXX.2, if the fruit or effect atising ftom such a harmony
were not to be in the harmony, chat is, if the cffect is different from the harmony, it can never arise from that harmony. This is a criticism of the nonidentity theory of causacion discussed in Chapter I. These two vecses, therefore,
state the difficulties involved in accepting theories of identicy and difference.
3.
Heto ca pratyayanaf!Z
If it is assumed chat the effect exists in the harmony of cause and conditions, should it not be observed i.n the hatmony? Howcver, it is not
observcd in the haunony.
4.
Helol ca pralyay'iin'iif!Z ca Iamagry'iif'(Z n'ii1ti cet phala1!1hetavaf? pratyaya ca Jyur ahetu-pratyayaif? ItJ'fn'iil/.
If the cffect were not to exist in the harmony of cause and conditions,
thcn the cause and conditions would be comparable co non-cause and
non-conditions. '
MKV(P) pp.392393; MKV(V) p.169.
lf the identity theory is valid, rhen the fruit could be observed (grhyela) in the
harmony itself, eveo before it is produced through such harmony. However,
Nagarjuna assumes chat ie is not observed or grasped .in this manner. Once
284
become the transformation of the cause, then it follows that tbere is a rebirth of a cuase that was already bom.
MKV(P) p.396; MKV(V) p .17L
Among the variety of causes that were formulated to account for a continuous effect (nif:;anda-pha/a) are complementary (sabhaga) and universal
(sarvatraga) causes (Akb p .94). Explaincd in the light of the theory of
moments, a universal cause would mean the contiouous acising of the same
cause in order to account for the cootinuous effect. The continuous effect
(ni.fyan4a-phala) thus turns out to be a cransformacioo (sarp,krama11a) of che
cause (helu). Nagarjuna refuse:i to recognize the rebirch of the same cause that
has ceased.
EXAMlNTION OF HARMONY
11 .
285
What causc, even if it wcre not separated from the effect, will give rise to
the effect? A cause does not produce an effect eitber impercepcibly or
pccccpribly.
M.KV(P) pp.398-399; MKV(V) p.1 72.
When the analytical process was carried to its extreme, many evenrs, whicb
under norma! cootexts would not have been quescioned , c:une to be doubced .
For example, inscead of a reJaced event, analysis produced two: a relarion and
an event. Wheo the norma! empiricist criceria wece adopted in the Jatter case,
one was compelled to assume chat the relation is not perccived in che same way
as the evenr is perceived . The metaphysician was thus compeUed to insist upon
the subscantial existence of the relatioo. "Birth is the arising of whac is to ~e
born and this does not take place wichout causes and conditioos," so says the
Abhidharmakofa (janyaJya Janik.ii 1atir na hetu-pratyayair vina, ii.49). The
bhii1ya on this passage concinues to argue about che narure of this "birth"
(jatt), insisring that the genetive case (!a/{ht) (as io che sracement, "arising of
what is to be boro") makes no sense if birtb (jiitz) is not perceived in the same
way as "that which is to be boro'' (Janiki.i) is perceptible. The Sautrantika
Vasubandhu argues against this position saying chat "umbers, Hmits, distinction, union, analysis, ochcrness, sameoess" are recognized as reals (salwa) in
the speculatioos of the herctics (llrthakara), and chat these arc oecded only to
establish the knowedge (but/dht) of the reality of "the one , the dual, the great.
the individuated , the uniced, the separated, the other, the same, etc. " To illustrate his point of view. he refers to the example of "the union of f o1m "
(iiipaJya sa<f!Jyoga) and maincains that the generive ca~e indicates the ownnature (svabhava) of "form ." However, in his owo Sautrantika view ie is a merc
designacion (pr(ljflaph~matram, Akb p . 79).
Ie is this conttoversy 'rega.rding the reality or urueality of numbers, conjunctions, disjuoctioos, etc. (a concroversy thac has contioucd to plague
philosophers in the modern world) that Nigarjuna is referring to in the present
verse when he uses the terms rlr!fva (seen) and adr11va (unseeo).
12.
286
THE
13.
15.
287
When an assemblage does not exist, how can a cause produce an effect?
When an assemblage exists, how can a cause produce an effect?
MKV(P) pp.401-402 ; MKV(V)p . 173
16.
Turning atound, Nagarjuna now takes up che concepcion of the effecc or fruit
(phala). If che cause is empty (Junya) of che effecc, it can never produce an effect. Neither is it appropriate co assume that the effect is produced by the cause
if it is already in the caus, hence nor empty (afunyar?t) of the effecr.
17.
A non-empry effen will not arise; a non-empcy effect will not ce-.tSe. For,
the non-ceased and non-ariseh will also be the non-en1pty.
MKV(P) p.402: 1HKV(V) p. 17-i.
This verse should clarify the meaning of the famous terms atnruddharri ("nonceased") and anutpanna1?1 ("non-ariscn") morc rhan any ocher scatement of
288
wAy
18.
How will the empty atise and bow will the empty cease? lf something is
empty, it follows that it is non-ceased and non-atisen.
MKV(P) p.403; MKV(V) p .174.
Taken by itself, this verse can be used to justify the view that accotding to
Nagarjuna "emptiness" (sunyaf(i) is the utimate truth beyond all forms of
description. Hence the negative d~scription: "non-ceased'' (ant'rttddha'f!Z) and
"non-arisen" (anutpanna'f!Z).
However , considered along with XX.17, whkh rcjects the notioo of identity
presented by the Sarvastivadins as self-nature (.rvabhava). which according to
Nagarjuna is "oon-empty'' (afunya), what is referred co as "empry" (Unya) in
the pi:eseot verse is mo,re apptopriately understood as a reference to the nonidentity theory of the Saucrantikas. It may be remembered that the first Buddbist school to deny the Sarvastivada theo.ty of self-nature was the Sautrantika
school. How che Sautrantika theory of "emptiness'' or ''absence of substaoce"
(nil/-svabhava) and their theoty of "momeotary destruction" (kfaf!a-bhanga)
Jcd to a denial of both arising and ceasing has already been pointed out (VIl.17
ff.).
As such, the present stacement of Nagarjuna, following upon his refutation
of ideotity, must involve a rejection of difference. the rwo extremes that he has
pe(Sistencly criticized. In other words, che Sarvastivada and Sautrantika
theories both rendcc acising and ceasing mcaningless.
19.
EXAMINATION OP HARMONY
289
The identity of causc and effcct is indecd not appropriatc. The difference
becwcen causc and cffect is indeed not appropriatc.
20.
21.
How is it chat a causc will producc an cffect which comes to be on its own
naturc? H ow is it that a cause will produce an effect which docs not come
to be on its own nature?
MKV(P) pp.403-404; MKV(J1 p.174.
22.
Identiry and difference are thus shown co mii tate against noc merely arising,
290
23 .
24.
The effect is not made by the harmony, nor is it not made by a harmony.
Where iodeed can there be a harmony of condirions wichout an effect.
MKV(P) pp.406-407; MKV(V) p. 176.
291
qucstion is: Where can chere be a harmony without a fruic or effect? This fioal
conclusioo need not be understood as a deniaJ of fruit or effect. On the contrary, ie can be the assertion of a pragmatist who insists that chete canoot be a
harmony of causes and conditions without a fruir or effecr.
CHAPTER
TWENTYONE
Examination of Occurrence and Dissolution
1.
2.
The terms Sllf!lbhava and vibhava need to be cransJated keeping in mind the
purpose of this secrion. lt is an attempt on the part of Nagarjuna co cxplain the
life-proccss (saf!Mara) or the human pcrsonality without resorting to a theory of
self or soul (iitman1 pudgala) cooside1ed to be eternal. As mentioncd earlier,
this whole section is devoted to the cstablishing of the idea of nonsubsrantiality of the human person (pudgala-nairatmya) ..This has to be achiev,
cd not onJy by showing the untenabilicy of the theory of permancnce or eternalism , but also of a conccption of annibilationism.
Thus, in this particular chapcer satr1bhava, in the sense of ocCUirence, pcrtains to the "birth" (janma) of a human being conditioned by various factors,
without any underlying permanent entity passing from one life to another.
Vibhava, in the sense of dissoution . mcaos "death'' (mara11a), and herc the re'is
no implication of competc annihilation. In the life-proccss, binb is thus not
the absolute beginning , nor is death the absoute end.
292
293
The first two verscs deny the occurrence of death wichout (t1inii) binh or at
the same time (saha).Just as much as death docs not occur without birth, there
is no up-rising (udbhava) witbout dissolution (vibhtJva). This is an empirical,
rather than a logical, analysis of birth and death. A rationalist can argue that
"all human beings arc not monal,'' for everyone who has becn born has not
died. Such a rational argument did not prcvent the Buddha from acccpting
mortality as a fact of life. For him, the evidencc lies in the fact that so fu all
human being who have died had been born. However, this does not lead the
Buddha to assert the metaphysical view that death is inherent ~ bitth.
4.
294
WAY
lndeed, the discourse to Katyayana utilized the cmpirical argument that the
belicf in a permaoent entity is abandoned wben one perceives the cessation of
the world (loka-nirodhaf!J ... yathabhufaf?1- sammappanfl aya passato yii loke
atthita sii na hotz). Nigarjuna's argument herc is not that "there is another
realm or aspect of beingwhich peope havc always overloo~ed. Thisis the realm
or aspect of bhiiva, [which] refers to the truy dynamie worldly existcnce" (as !nada seems to assumc, sec p .12 5). Rather, it is a rejection of bhava, piimarily
because impermanence (anityatfi) is incompatible with bhava, which impies
permanence. In fact, Nigarjuna was probably aware that the Buddha bad
always employed the term bhava to expain the process of "bccoming," instead
of the absuact term bhiva. Indeed bhiva, or its more resuicted form svabhava,
is equivaent to astitva (attht'tii) and more often Nagarjuna understood the
term in that sense.
29)
7.
Occurrence of that which is waning does not exist, nor is there occurrence
of that whicb is not waning. Dissolution of that which is waning does not
exist, nor is there dissoution of the not waning.
MKV(P) p.415 ; MKV(V) p.180.
The term k!aya was used in the Buddhjsr texrs in the cootext where warung or
compJete extinction is implied. Whereas the term nirodha could mean ce.asing
that coud be followed by arising (utpada) and, as such, t hey could be used as
comp lementaries to explain change and impennanence as well as dependent
arising, the term k!aya had no such complementary term except irs negation ,
a-k!aya, wh ich impJies permanence. For t:his reason, Nigarjuna was able to
maintain chat there is neither absolute cessation (k!aya) nor perrnanence
(a-k!aya) of both occurrence (sa?'(lbhava) and djssolution (vibhava),
8.
296
9.
"
TuE PHllOSOPHY OF THE MIDDLE W Ay
l O.
lt is not appropriate to assume tha.t occurrencc and d.issolution are identical. lt is not appropriate to assume that occucrence and d.issolution arc
diffcrcnt.
MKV(P) pp.416-4 18; MKV(l1 pp. 180-181.
lt is probab1y the use of the term bhava at XXl.8 that Jed !nada to assume chat
it represents a unique realm of existence recognized by Nigarjuna. However, if
we arc to keep in mind the two metaphysical schoos- Sarvastivada and
Sautrlintika-and their metaphysical doctrines of identity and difference, it is
possible to interpret the statement in verse 8 as wcll as the two verses chat follow
as straightforward criticisms of these two schools.
For example, a Sautriincika who denies a bhiva or .wabhava can maintain
that occurrence and dissolution can take plac:e without a permanent entity
(bhava, s11abha11a). Occurrence and dissolution woud then mean the absence
of continuity. Nagarjuna denjes this.
On the conuary, a 52.rvascivadin can maintain thar a bha11a oc wabhava can
exist without occurrcnce and dissolution, and this would account for continuity
but negate difference. Tbis too is rejected by Nagarjuna.
Similarly, occucrence and dissolution arc incompatible with the "empty''
(fUnya), as understood by a Sauuancika, or the "non-empty" (afUnya) as ex.plained by the Sarvastivadin (see XX.16-18).
Furthermore, occurrence and dissolution arc neither identica (naika) nor dif
ferent {niini) in a metaphysical sense.
11.
297
Dryate
lt may occur to yon chat both occurrcnce and dissolution are seen. How
cvcr, both occurrence and dissolution arc scen only through confusion.
MKV(P) p.419;,MKV(v,) p .181.
12.
An existe.n t does not arise from an existent; neither does an existent arisc
from a non-existent. A non-cxistent does not acise from a non-existcnt;
neither does a non-existent arise from an existen't.
13.
An existent does not arise from iuelf, or from another or from both itself
and anothcr. Whcnce can it then arise?
298
Bhiiva and abhava referred to herc may be compared with the sat and 11.fat in
the pre-Buddhist Indian philosophy. The unresolvable metaphysical questioos
that plagued Indian philosophy for centuries, uestions such as "Did existence
(sat) arise from non-existence (t11at)?" 01 vice versa, have once again been in~
ttoduced into Buddhist thought by the Sarvastivadins and the Sautrantikas.
The idencity and oon-idencity th.eories of causation, theories of self-causacion
and exteroaJ causation, and many other metaphysical views thatemerged in theBuddhist uadicion are repeatedly mentioned and rejected by Nagacjuoa.
14.
[On the contrary,] for him who is engrossed in existence. there would be
neither annihilationism nor eternalism, for, indeed , becoming is the
senes of uprising and ceasing of cause and effert.
16.
299
The Saucrantika position was no moce differeot. They assumed chat bhava is
oone other than bhava, the process of becorning represented by the series
(sarpt'iina) of arising and ceasiog of effect and cause (phala-hetvol?) As such ,
they believed chat cheir coocepcion of ex.istence docs not come under either
eternalism or annihilationism.
Howeve.r, Nagarjuna has a different perception. He 3:-SSum es that if the process of 'becoming (bhava) is analysed in to a series of arisi'ng and ceasing of effect
and cause, as the Saurrantikas did, one is compelled to recognize che nonrebirch (a-puJ'lllT-utpattt) of chat whicb bas ceased, and there would be compete annibiacion of the c.ause. This is simiar to the argument used at XXI. 7.
17.
300
However, the Sautrantika will say that as a result of the appeasement of the
sedes of becoming (bha11a-saf!Jfat1), there is annihilation at the tltne of nirvaa.
Having stated this position, Nigjrjuna proceeds to analyse its implications.
18.
It is not propec to assume that thcre is first becoming whcn the last has
ceased . Nor is it proper to assume that thete is first becoming when the
last has not ceased.
MKV(P) p.425; MKV(V) p.184.
The Sautrantika tbeory of a series of momentary existences is under investigation here. As meotioned before, the Sauuancikas were often faced with the
problem of explaining arising (utpida) . Thus, Nagarjuna argues that the first
(moment of) becoming (prathamo bhava4) cannot occur when the last (carama)
has ceased, for there will be nothing to give rise to the former . Th is is what was
referred to as the cessation of the cause (hetuccheda) at XXI .16. The other
alternative is to assume tbat the enticy of the last moment has not ceased
(aniruddha) , and this, of course, makes it difficult for the first becoming to occur at all .
19.
If the fust were to be born when the kst is ceasing, then that which is
ceasing would be one and that which is being boin would be another.
Assum'.e that the first becoming occurs at the time wheo the last is ceasing
(nirudhyamana). NQ:garjuna insists that, in that case, whac is ceasing is one
301
thing and what is arising is somcthlng com plctcJy diffcrent (aparo). Nagarjuna
is herc referring to the implications of the theory of mo.menrs, namely, the
recognition of absolute d iscinccions.
20.
Ii it is assetted th.at the ceasing is also the being boro, this would not be
proper. For, in th.at.case 1 whatever that is born in reation to the aggrcgates, would also be dying at the same time.
21.
Thus, the stream of becoming is not proper in the context of the three
pcods of time. How can there be a s.tream ofbecoming th.at does not aist during the three periods of time?
CHAPTER
TWENTYTWO
(Tathagata-pafik.ra)
l.
The tathiigata is neither che ag.gregates noc different from them. The aggcegates are not in him; nor is be in the~ggregates . H e is not possessed of
the aggregates. In such a context, who is a tathagata ?
2.
ln addicion co some of the terms used by the Buddha to refer to his owo
achievements, his disdpJes used a vast array of epithets in extolling his virtues.
It is significant to noce that none of these epithets caused so much
m isunderscanding as the one under discussion in the preseot chapter. narriely,
tathagata. lt seems chat the very cooceptioo of tathagata iovited
misundetstanding.
l"he term can be rendeced inro English as "thus-gone" (tathii-gata) . The
conception of o ne who has "rhu>-gone" immed iatey brings to mind the idea of
an ''agent'' (sec Chaptcr 11). lt was. thefefore, ioevitable tliat when questions
relaring to rhe "destiny'' of r.he enlightened one were raisttd. they were always
ralsed in relation to a tath1ig11ta.
30~
EXAMlNATION OF TATHAGllTA
303
Nagarjuna was aware that questions pertaining not only to the final desciny,
but also to the nature of the living sa.int were raiscd during rhe Buddha's day . A
discussion between Sariputta and a monk named Yamaka, who had enten:a.ined rhe belief rhat a lathagala is annihilated after death (param maraf!a) is
repocced in rhe Saf!'yutla-niliiiya (S 3.109-115; Tsa 5.2 (Tairho 2.30c-3lcl).
Reading the first part of this discussion, one gcts the impression that Sariputta
was 'ieluctant to identify the tatliiigala with the five aggregates or to distinguish
the tath'iigata from the aggregatcs. On rhe basis of this, it is possible to come to
the condusions, rhat rhe tathagala is linguiscically cranscendeot.
However, if the discussioo is followed to the very end, one can clearly sec rhat
such a conclusion is not warranted. For Sariputta is not willing to admit a
talhagala in an absolute sense (saccato thetato), comparable to the
metaphysical "self'' (a/man) that was considered to be pcrmaoent and eteroal.
Indeed , toward the end of rhe discussion, Sariputta movcs from the conceprion
of talh'iigata to the notion of "self' (atta) and refuscs to admit a self rhat is identical with or different from the aggregates.
Nagarjuna, as if he had read this discoursc:, begins the present chapter in an
idencical way, first ma.inta.ining that tle tath'iigata is neither identical nor different from the aggregates, and then proceeding to questioo the existeocc or
non-existence of the talhagata after death. As in che Sa'1pyulta passage, Nagarjuna immediately qu,alifies his rcfereoq:: to ,the living tathagata, insisting that
the tath'iigata or the buddha under invscigation is one possessed of self-nature
(s11abha11a) and beoce similar to the nodon of "self' (a~ta) rejectcd by Saripuna.
Nagarjuna thereupQn uses his f'amous argumcnc that if the tathagata is not
found in cerms of self-nature, he cannot either be found in terms of ochernature (para-bh'ii11a).
304
'THE
5.
lf there were to be a tathligata because of non-graspiog on to the aggrcptes, he should still depend upon them in the present. As such he
will be dependent.
MKV(P} p .438; MKV(V) p. 190.
EXAMINATION OF TA11iAGJ\TA
30S
be freed from the agg~egates, not jo the latter sense. Yet, with the development of substantialism, that is, when a freed person carne to be looked upon as
being totally different from the one in bondage, cach having his own nature
(.wabhi11a)(see Chapter XXV), the freed one was pcrceived not only as one not
gr25ping (anupidiiya) on to the aggreg:ites, but also as one who is independent
of the aggregates. lt is this subsrantialist interpretation chat Nagatjuna is
criticizing when he points out chat if a tathagata were to exist without grasping
on to the aggregatcs (skandhan anupadiiya), he will still be dependent upon
(11padadyad) tbem ac the prcsent time (idiinl'?I), that is, as long as he is aJive.
Nigatjuna was thus going back to the Buddha's owo definicion of a freed one.
tathiigata?
MKV(P) p.439; MKV(P) p.190.
306
8.
He who, sought for in the fivefold manner, docs not exist in the form of a
different idcntity, how can tbar tathagata be made known throogh
grasping?
MKV(P) p.439' MKV(V) p.190.
The substancialiast explanation of a tath'iigata would imply that he has completely uaosformed himself in to a d ifferent entity, chat is, a tathagata having
his own-nature (wabh'iiva) with no relatiooship to the person in bondage .
However , examining the fivefold aggregates, no such encity can be dis<:overed.
Such a tath'iigata cannot be explained in terms of dependeoce (upadiinena) .
Thus, the conceptioo of depeodence (up'iidiina) is incompatible witi both
idcoticy a nd difference. What is denied herc is neither dependence nor a
tath'iigata, but merely the m ctaphysical approaches co both dependence and
tath'iigala.
lnstead of rranslating tatt11a and anyatva and as idencity and diliereoce, we
bave rendered che phrase as "different idenity" since it occurs in the singular.
9.
ExAM1NATI0NoF
TAmAcATA
307
10.
Thus, grasping and gra.spec arc empty in every way. How can an cmpty
tathagata be made known by somcthing that is empty?
MKV(P) pp.440-441 ; MKV(V) p.191 .
Thus, grasping as well as the one who grasps are empcy in every possible way.
They are devoid of aoy substance.
For the substantialist, the lalhagala as well as the aggregates have substance
or owo-.nature, even though they arc clifferent fromone another. The substantialist can cxplain the tathigata, whose self-narure (svabhiva) is freedom, contrasting him with the one who is in bondage as a result of his being a "graspcr"
(upadiitr) and whose nature is discina (para) from that of the tathagata.
However, witb Nagarjuna's deniaJ of self-narure, thar sharp dichotomy aJso is
dissolved. Hence Nagarjuna's insiscence chat an empty tathagata cannot be
made koown in relation to an equally empty ''grasper" (upidiitr) or "grasping"
(upadiina) referred to in the previous verse.
11 .
Note again the use of the tli-formula. Nagarjuna is rejecting any theonzing
308
12.
Siifvafiifiivatiidy
Siinta is .an appeased one. It is the tathagata who has appeased the dispositions,
'obsessions as we11 as the object (sec comments oo V.8). For him, the fourfold
metaphysical alternacives eicher cegarding the duration of phenomena such as
erernality (a11ata) and oon-eteroality (aiivata) or regarding the extent of
phenomena such as the finite (anta) and the infinite (ananta) do not exist. H e
has stopped brooding over the past and ruoning after the future.
13.
EJw.JNATION OF TA m AGATA
309
sisting that a tathilgata "exists" or "does not exist," a person would think
similarty even of one who has ceased.
MKf/(P) p.447; MKV(V) p. 194 .
The Buddha's reasons for the rejection of the notion of tath'iigata in the
Sa11Jyutta passage refcrred to above (see comments on XXII.1-2) are clearly emphasized by Nagarjuna. The Buddha rejected a tath"(igata bccause his existence
was asserted in a real and absouce sense (saccato thetato): When Nagarjuna
spcaks of a dogmacie grasping (gt'1ih11) on to something as the real or substantial
(ghana) existence or non-existence (asfiti . . . niisfitt) of the tathagata, he was
expressing the sentiments similar to those of the Buddha. Fu!thennore, arguing in a.sim.ilar way as the Buddha did, Nagarjuna maintais that the same sort
of substantiaist specuations lead to the views regarding the existence and non'existence of the tath'iigata even after his death.
Hece chere is no denial of a talhag4ta, but only of a substantial entity. The
verse tbat follows is unequivocal in this regard.
14.
naivopapadyate,
para'f{l nirodhad bhavati buddho na bhavatiti .Va.
Hete the term asmin, in the locative absoute construction (asmin s11abbii11ataf
ca f unye), refers to the t11tliiigatt1. If the tpthiigata who is alivejs, empty of selfnature, then it ~not appropriate to assume that he exists or does not exist after
death. lt is only the substantialist thinking (cintii) that leads to the
metaphysical quescions which wece left undedared (avyakrta) by the Buddha.
15.
310
Those who geo.erate obsessions with greac regacd to the Bpddha who has
gone beyond obsessions and is constant, all of them, impaired by obsessions, do not perceive the tathiigata.
Here we radically differ from the prevailing cxplanations that prapaca means
thought distinct from reality (see !nada, p . 135). Having rejected the moce
widespread view that Buddhisrn recognizes an "unspeakable" (a11acya) and "indefinabJe" (anirvacanlya) truth or reality (tattva) , which Jeads co the above iq.
terpretatioo of prapaf!_ca, we have reodered the term as "obsessioo. ''
The Buddha remains aoof from obsessions (prapacali'ta"!t) . As such, he is
not understooc or grasped by those who are obsessed. A person who is obsessed
with the idea of identity will understand the Buddha in a way .different from
one who is obsessed with the idea of difference. One wilJ say that he "exists"
(astt) and the othec will insist that he "does nor exist'' (niistt) .
The Buddha who has overcome such ''obsessions" is "not so variable"
(a11yaya?fl) . His perceptions are not variable in the same way as those of the
unenightened ones who are dominated by obsessions. Nagarjuna could not
have been unaware of the defin:ition of the Buddha as "one who has become
stable and ste;JY' ( f hita1'{1- ane1jappatlaf!l, A 3. 37 7; f hita7?1 ciltaf!Z, S 5. 74).
T he term a11yaya in the present coutext expreses the same idea of stability and
steadfasroess achieved by a Buddha. This is not to assume his permanent ex
1Steoce.
16.
of self-nature.
MKV(P) pp.448-449; MKV{V) p .195.
T he first statement of Nagarjuna may be takeo to mean thac there is a self. nature of the tathigata which is identical with ~hat of the universe. This wduld
be justification for the belief in a permanent entity wh.ich is identical witb the
reality of the universe, comparable to the atman and brahman of the Hindu
EXAMlNATION OP TAmAGATA
311
CHAPTER
TwENTY THREE
Examination of Perversions
(Viparyasa-pan k! a)
1.
Sa~alpa-prabht1110
Lust, hatred, and confusion are said have thoug}tas their source. Perversions regatding the plea.sant and the unpleasant arise depending upon
these.
MKV(P) p.451; MKV(V) p .197.
Followiog upon a discussion of the tathagata in reJation to the world, a discussion thac avoided absolute identicy and ab$olute difference, Nagarjuoa rakes
up the questioo regarding perversions (11iparyasa) which makes a difference between a person in bondagc and one: who is freed .
The four perversions are discussed by the Buddha at Anguttara 2.52. Tbey
pertain to percepcions (saflflti), thoughts (citta), and views (diftht). Perversion
(vipalliisa) of perceptioo or thought or view occurs with the identification of
the impermaoeot with the permaoent (anicce niccan tt) ,
11. the not unsatisfactory with the unsatisfactory (aduk.khe dukkhan h),
UL the nonsubstantial with the substantial (anattani alta ti) ,
and
1v. the unpleasant with the pleasant (tliubhe ubhan lt).
t.
313
amanapa) sensations occur even in the enlightened ones (Iti11uttaka 38). Perversion is the wrong identification of these exp~riences . However, the same cannot
be said of the cognitive peNersioos, for the Buddba would be reluctant to
assume that there is an experience corresponding to something that is either
permanent or substaotiaL
For Nagarjuna, perversions ii and lv arc not due to purely inteUectual or
cognitive incapacity on the part of the indlvidual. Tbey are due more to the
subjective elements dominating thoughts sur.h as lust and hatred, wbicb acise
along witb thoughts (sa1{Zkalpa-prabhavo). even though these lattcr are not
part of the wodd of experience. Th.is explanation of Nagarjuna is based u pon a
passage in the St11(1yulla wherein the Buddha identifies desire (kQ,ma) with
thoughts of lust (sa1{Zkappa-rag4) without confusing it with whatever is
beautiful (citrint) in the world (sec S 2.22; Tsa 48.20 [Taisho 2.345b]}.
As such, it is not surprfai.ng to see Nagarjuna beginnibg his analysis with the
last of the perversions, namely, the identification of the pleasant with the
unplcasant (a.ubhe ubhan Jt), a subjective perversion that is based upon the
cognitive. confusion (i.e., anattani atfii tz). Nagarjuna was probably interested
in beginning his analysis with the subjective perversion because the metaphysicians, who carried che analytical process beyond its limit, bad difficulty in accounting for the emergence of sensations such as the pleasant and the unpleasant.
The perversions of the pleasant and the unpleasant are dependcntly arisen. As
mentioned before, t hey are tht products of 1ust and hatred; they arise within
the individual . For this tea,son, they are not found in themselves (na
s11abhavataf?). Whatever defilments (.klea) occur as a result of such perversions
annot be pa.et of the expetiemced world. Rather they related to the way in
which the world isperceived by .the individual. lt is ooly in this sense that they
are looked upon as being unrcal (na.tattvata'f?).
314
The perversin regarding what is pleasant and unpleasant has been traced back
to the pecversion whcre the non-substantial (anatman) is .identificd with che
substancial (atman). The substantial and the non-substantial, in the eyes of the
mctaphysiciari, pertain to existence (flJtitva) and non-cxistence (n'1isti111a)
respectively (see V.8; XV. 71 11). The discourse to Katyayana .rejects both thesc
views as being metaphysi1=al.
Nagarjuna is herc insisting that neithc.r the 6cistence not the oon-existence
of a metaphysical self can be proved. lf there were to be no such self, then the
defilcments associated with such a self also cannot exist. In the absence of a
substantial self, if only the defilernents wece to exist, then they should have selfexistence, which was an idea denied at XXIII.2. Tuus, neither the substantial
existence of a self noc the substantial existence of defilrnents can be established.
Not onJy are the defilments not established as substantia elements, they can
not be proved to exist even as attributes. If defilements are considcred as
belonging to someone(.kacia) who issubstantially existing. the abscoc~of such
a substantial entity would mean the absence of de(llemcnrs as attr.ibutes.
Ex.AMlNATION OF PERVERSIONS
315
The defilments arc like the view of one's own personality. Within the
defied, they arc not found in the fivefold way . The defiled is like the
view of one's own personality, for even within the defilements it is not
found in the fivefold way.
Just as much as botb the deft.lements (k.leia) and the defiled (k.li;Fa) arc not evident in substantial form, so are the perversions that give rise co dcfiements .
Tbey too arc not fouod in aoy substantial way. The question theo is: What is
the nature of the perverson relating to the pleasant and the unpleasant depending upon wbich defilements are said co arise?
Here there is no denial of perversions nor the deftlements. What has been
quescioneq is only the way in which theso are cooceptualized.
7.
THE
316
WAY
Material form, sound, taste, touch, smeU and concepts- these are
discriminatcd as the sixfold foundations of lust, hatred, and confusion.
MKV(P) p .456; MKV(V) p.199.
Analysing !ust, hatred, and coofusion in terms of the four perversions, it may
be maintained that Just and hatred arc subjective attitudes, while confusion
refers to the cogni tive aspect of understanding (sec com.men ts on XX1lI. I),
even though the cognitive and artirudinal aspects are dependent upon one
another. The present statement of Nagarjuoa implies the dependence of the
attirudinal as well as the cognitive aspects of experience upon the sixfold objects
of sense experiencc.
gandharvanagarak"iir7i
maficz~svapna-sa?rt,nibhaf?.
Material form, sound, taste, touch smell as well as concepts-all these are
comparable to the city of the gandharvas and resemble mir.ages and
dreams.
MKV(P) p.457; MKV(V} pp.199200.
The similes of the "dreamH (svapna) and the "city of the gandharvas"
(gandharva-nagttra) have already been employed, a.long with :ilJusion"
(maya), to refute the substantialist cxplanation of the dispositionally conci
tioned phenorncna (sa??ZskrtaXsee VII. 34). The six objects of experience referred to at XXIII. 7 arc indeed dispasitionally conditioned. They arc not objects
that arc found in themselves (s11abh411ataf?). Nor arc they absolutey noneXJstent.
ExAMINATION OF PERVERSIO"NS
317
How can the pleasant and the unpleasant come to be in people who are
fabrications of illusion or who are comparable to mirror images?
MKV(P) p .458; MKV(V) p.200.
What Nagarjuna has bee n criticizing so far is a substantiaist theoi:y of the pleasant and the unpleasaot (svabhtii/alo , .. fubhaJubha11iparyayan XXIII.6).
His argument in the prescnt verse is directed against the belief that such
substantial expeticnces can occur in thoughts of hwnan beings who are
themselves non-substa11tial, and who a.ce comparable to mirror images or reflections (see commentary on :XVII.31-32).
10.
We make known that the unpleasant does not exist without being conti,ngent upon the pleasant, and that the pleasant, in its turo, is dependent upon that [i.e. the pleasant] . The.refote, the pleasant [in itself] is
not appropriate.
1I'.
We make known that the pleasant does not exi$t without being contingent upon the unpleasant, and that the unpleasant, in its turo. is
dependent upon that [i.e. , the peasant] . Therefore, the unpleasant [in
itself] is not evident.
MKV(P) pp.458-459; MKV(V? p ,200.
This is a elear refutation of the substancialist views of both the pleasant and the
318
MIDDLE WAY
unplcasant. Nagarjuna insists that thcy ace dependent upon one another. Thcy
arc not independent experiences wherc one is repaced by another, as in the
case of the theory of "attainmcnt" (praptz) and "oon-auainment" (apraptt)(see
comments on .XVI.10, XXIV.32).
12.
When the pleasant is not evident, whence can there be lust? Wben the
unpleasant is not cvident, whence can there be hatred?
MKV(P) p.459; MKV(V) p.201.
Io addition to being mutuaHy dependent, the plcasant and the unpleasant provide a foundation for the subjective tcndencies such as lust and hatred. Thus,
lust would be non-ex.isrent if the pleasanc were not cvident. Similarly, hacred
would be non-ex.istent, if the unpeasant wece not evideot. This, indeed, is the
conclusion of the Sa'f!'yutta passage referred to at XXIII.1. In that context, the
Buddha was not denying the pleasant and the unpleasant expericnces in the
world. He was simply insisting chat w hen such experiences occur a wise man
resuainrs his ycarning (chanda) for it.
13.
If tbere were to be grasping on to the view, "Wbat is impermanent is permanent," then there is perversion. The impcrmancnt is not evident in the
contcxt of the empty. How can there be grasping or pecversion?
MKV(P) p.460; MKV(V) p .201.
So far Nagarjuna has endeavored to show thac the perversion regarding the
pleasant and the unpleasant is che result of a cognicive confusion which led to
che belicf in a substance ot self (atman) . Wich the present statement, Nagar-
Exl.MINATION OF PERVERSIONS
319
juna begins co analyse the conception of impermanence (11nity11) in order to explain che lathagata's cognitive uoderstanding of the world of experieoce. This
understanding enables the tathagata co eliminate the perversion relating to
happiness and sufferlng .
Herc, the perversion pertains to grasping of the impermanent a:s the perma
nent. lf so, the perspectivc in wbich the lalhagata looks at the world should be
one of impermanence. Unforcunatcly, the notion of impermanence chat
dominated the Buddhist tradition during Nagarjuna's day was more a
metaphysical one (see commentaries on Chapter Vll) than an einpirical one.
For the metaphysician, the absence of permanence implied the reality of the
momeocary. Nagacjuna rightly believes that as much as grasping after permanence is a perversion. so is grasping aft er the reality of the momentary ( =
k1an.1'lla). The deoial of permanence does not commit oneself to the ocher ex
cceme of momentary.destruction (k/an.a- bhaa). Emptiness (unyafii) does not
imply any such momentariness .
14.
It is possible for someone to raise the quescion as to whether grasping after the
empry would irself be a perversion, just as much as grasping after che permanenr or the impermanent would consritute perversioos. Nagarjuna is herc raising this question and chen proceeds to answer it in the following verse.
15.
320
W/\. Y
The middle path enunciated in the discoutse to Kacyayana avoided the two extremes relating to philosophical understanding and explanation. This was
achieved thro1Jgh che appeasement of dispositions and the elimination of
grasping. Because of non-grasping, all che metaphysical qucstions relating to
the faculcies (yena grh11iit1), the proces.s of understanding (griiha), the person
involved in such understanding (grahtfii) as well as the object of uderstanding
(yac ca grhyate), come to be appeased. The appeased one (fanta) does not continuc to taise questions or doubts beyor.d a certain limit, not because he knows
evetything nor bccause he does not care to know, but because he is aware of the
conflicts generated by any pursuit of koowledge that gocs beyond experience.
The facr chat grasping for emptiness can conscitute a sort of petversion
(f'iinyatii dr1tz) has alrea.dy been e.xplained by Nagarjuna (XIU.8). This does
not mean that t he very conception of emptiness is invalidated in the same way
as the conceptS of permaoence and momentariness would be invalidated, The
reason ff!r this is thar the notions of permanence and substance as wel as of
niomentarioess arc not empirically grounded compared with dependent aiising, non-substantiality, or emptiness. Both the Buddha and Nagarjuna would
categorize the formcr under wrong thoughts (mithya sa1?Jka/pa), while tbey
would consider the latter as right or appropriate thoughts (saf!Jyak saf!Jka/pa,.
ka/pana yatra yojyate, XVll. 13) , The verse thar follows should be understood
in such a conteXC. This indeed is the fina conclusion of Nagarjuna in the
Kiirika (sec XXVII.30).
16.
When grasping; wrongly or righty, is not evident, for whom woud the.r e
be perversion and for whom woud chere be non-perversion?
MKV(P) p.466; MKV(V) p.204.
EXAMINATION OP PERVERSLONS
32l
With grasping gone, whether it be for the right thing or the wrong thing, the
enlightened one does not involved himself in any substancialist thinking
rdating to perversion or non-perversion. This is the state of the saint who has
anained freedom from grasping (anupiidaya vimuktt).
17.
18.
Upon reaching sucha evel of mora and intellectual development (as referred
to in the previous verse), one does not get involved in mecaphyska spcculations such as whether pcrversions arise in one who is a1ready afflicted by pcrversions, or not afflktcd , or is being afflicated. The speculation thac is avoided
pertains not only to the past and the future buc also the present. As such he
avoids the metaphysics discussed in Chapter Il . When perveisioos themselves
are not per~eived as being substantial, how can one consider a perverse person
as a substantial entity.
f9.
322
Picking up the argument from the previous verse, Nigarjuna is bere specifically
rejeccing the su bstantiaist ootions of perversions as well as persons who arc
pervcrse. lf perversions are substancial or having self-narure (s11abha11a), they
cannot be considered as arisen (utpanna) . When they are non-arisen or unborn
(ajata), there cannot be a person in whom these would arise, for they cannot
serve as attribuces.
20.
An existent does not arise from itsef, nor does it arise from another, nor
both itsef and other. If so, whence can tbere be a person who is subject to
pcrversions?
MKVP) p.468; MKV(V) p.205.
This verse, which is not available in KumlirajTva's translation, represents U application of the analysis of substancial existence (bhava) in Chapter I to the problems of a substantial petsoo or eotity. It is aJmost identical with XXl.13.
21 .
If either the self, the pleasant, the permanent, or the happy is evident,
then neither the self, the pleasant, the pcrmanent, nr the happy constitutes a pcrversion.
MKV(P) p.468; MKV(V) p.205.
EXAMJNATION OF PF.RVERSIONS
323
terms used br the Buddha at A 2.52. In the preseot verse, he adopts a slightly
different terminology in referring to the perversions. Instead of fubha and
aubha, he uses the p~ of terms uci and .auci. and instead of adukkha be has
sukha. This latter terminology was indeed utilized by che interpreters of
Abrudharma when discussiog the perversions (see Akb p.286). As such, it is a
elear indication that N:igarjuna was conversan t withg the early discourses as
much as he was familiar with the Abhidharma commenrarial Hterature.
Nagarjuna's argument in the present verse coud lead tp misunderstanding
unless it is seen in the context of his previous sta.cements abouc the perversions,
expecially at XXIII.20. lf the self, the pleasant, the petmanenc, and the happy
arc evidenc as selfexistent entitzes, chen, indeed, they do oot constitute perversions. Unfortunately, Inada's uanslation does not seem to bring out this strong
sense of "exist" that Nagarjuna is implyicig here.
22.
If neither the self, the p~easant, the permanent1 nor the happy is not evident, chen neitbec the non-self, the unpleasant, the impermanent, nor .
the $nffering would also be evident.
23 .
324
Thus, with the cessation of pcrversions, ignorance ceases. When ignorance has ceased, the disposition.s, etc. come to cease.
ltfKV(P) p.469; M.KV( V) p.206.
24.
lf, indeed, certain dcfile!bents of someonc have come to bt: un the basis
of sclf-naturc, how could they be rclinquished? Who cver cou1d relinquish self-nature?.
25 .
Nagarjuna's conclusion in this chapter is that the dcfilemeots (klea) , whicb arc
the rcsults of the pcrvetsions discussed abovc, cannot be elim.inated , and ,
therefoce, there could be no lalh'iigata, if the.se defilements are ooked upon as
being either substanciaJ; i.e,, something that has come to be (bhuta) having
EXAMINATION OF PERVERSIONS
32~
CHAPTER
TwEN1YFOUR
'
1.
If all tbis is empty, the n the.re exists no uprising and ceasing. These imply
the non-existence of the four noble truths.
MA'V(P) p.475 ; MKV(V) p .209.
326
Thurus
327
When [the Buddha] declared: 'Ooe should perceive happy feelings as suffering,' [i.e. , che perception of one who has eiminated
the perversions,] both [hap~incss and suffering] arc available
thercin. Happiness is inherently so, because there is pleasantness ..
However, eventually there is suffering, because of its chaoging and
impeananent nature. When that [feeling] is perceived as hap
piness, it contributes to enlightenment, through its enjoyment.
Wheo it is perceived as suffering. it leads to release, by being non
attached to it. (Akb p.331, Yad uktaf(t "sukh'ii 11edanii dul;khe ti
dra/(a11ye li ubhayaf(t tasyam asti. Sukhat11a?tt ca svabhavato
1
'
328
W/\ Y
2.
Understanding (parijn'ii) pertains to the first of the four noble truths, namely,
chat suffering exists. Rclinquishiog (prah'ii1'!a) refers to the second, narody, the
cause of suffering, which is explained as craving (tr!t{ii). Realization (i?ik#karma) applies to the third, namely, the state of freedom from suffeting, which is
nirvana. Cultivation or practice (bha11ana) involves the fourth, namely, the path
leadiog to the cessation of suffering.
329
doctrine of the four fru.its (arya-phtlla) . Even though freedom without grasping
(anupadii vimuktz) is sometimes referred to as the one goal (ek4y11na), yet a
deliberate attempt to assert degrees of attainments where some arc considered
to be inferior to others is conspicuously absent, Like the relay of chariots
(rathavinlta) , one segment of the path is as imporcaat as the other,
''dispassion" (vairagya) being one dominant attitude permeating all segments.
This has an imporcant bearing on the concepcion of ttuth to be discussed soon.
4.
If the eight types of individuals do not exist, tbere will be 110 congregation. From the non-existence of the noble trnchs, the true doctcine would
aso not be evident.
MKV(P) p.478; MKV(V) p.210.
Inada was probably assuming that cet refers to thought (citta) when he
translaced pan of the first line as "the eight aspiracions of men do not exist,"
whereas it could be more ~ppropriatdy read as a cooditional particie.
The assoc.iation of the ttue doct.tine (sad-dharma) with the fout noble truths
(tiry11-1a1y11) to a point whe:te the abse.oce of th,e atter implies the non-existenc~
of the former should nacurally raise questions regarding the more popular
assigoment of doctrines to the var.ious sehools where the four noble truths are
assign~d to the . so-called H~nayana with the superior Mahayana having
somethiog more to offer, Such an assignroent. becomes really questiooable
when a greac Mahayana thinker like Nagarjuna himself admits of such a cor
relation (XXIV.30).
This equation is also signlficant for another very important reason: Dharma,
as ''teaching" also means a "statement" of doctrine. Some modern linguistic
philosophers would prefer to use the term "truth" primarily. in referring to
statements rather than to facts . Sad-dharma, .identified with truth, seems to accommodate such a perspective.
S.
330
6.
Whcn the doctrinc and the coogregarion arc non-existent, how can there
be an cnlightcncd one? Spcaking in this .m anner about cmptiness, you
contradict the thrce jewels, as wcll as the reality of the fruits, both good
and bad, and all such worldly convenrions.
MKV(P) pp.478-489; MKV(V) 210-213.
At this point the metaphysidan brings up the notion of "emp tiness" (1unydta).
For him, emptiness is a problem, not because of any othcr reason, but because
it implies "the emp ty" (finya), and this latter lcaves no room for substantial existence (sad-bh'iiva) of the fru its (artha) of both good and bad as well as alJ the
worldly conventions-.
Inada's transation of dharma and adharma as prope and improper acts is a
couective to his earlier rendering of these rwo cerms as factor and non-factor at
Vlll.5 . However, his rranslation of saf!J11ya11ahiira as somcthing additional to
dharma and adharma can be quc:stioned in the light of the use of vyavahara at
XVII.24, wherc a similar, but not idential, set of categories (pu11y11-p'lipa,
"merit and demerit") is referred to as vyavah'iira. Jndeed, this particular use of
the term 11y1111ah'iira ( = Illf!lV[lt) will throw much light on an undc:rstandiog of
the distinction becween the ewo truths discussed at XXIV.8.
331
This has turned out to be one of two most discussed verses in Nagacjuna's
Kiin'/ca. Modern disquisitions on the conception of two truths could perhaps fili
severa! substantiaJ volumes. Instead of plodding over trodden ground, the preseot discussion will be confined to a comparison of the conception of two tnlths
in early Budchism and the metaphysical vetsion presented by the interpreters
of the Abhidharma, with a view to clacifying Nagarjuna's position.
Nagarjuna's version will be ex:amined in the light of the problems posed at the
beginning of the pi:esent chapter, as wel as his refcrence to woddly conventions
in the previous chapters.
In the Su1ta-nipat41 the Buddha condemned any arcempt to uphold a view
(di!!ht) as the u!timate (paramaT?J)(Sn 796ff.). Refusing to recognize any
knowledge of "things as they really .a.re," and ma.king a more sober claim to
knowJedge of "things as they have come to be'; (yathabhuta), the Buddha was
reluctant to accept any notion of paramattha as "ultimate reality ." Instead, he
claimed to know "the dependently ariseo" (pa(iccasamuppanna) and, on that
basis . formulaced the cooceptioo of ''dependent arising" (pa{iccasamt1ppada).
In such a context, it was more n1eaningfu for him to speak of attha (Sk. artha)
332
sa?phita).
The Buddha also recognized that views about good and bad, puricy and impurity, are in most cases relative convencions (Sn 878-894). According to the
same text, 'good (kusala) and bad (akusala) are conventions that vary depending
upon contexts (sammutiyo puthujja, Sn 897). These are che ways of the world
(loka) , often charactecized as sam1nut1~ 11ohara (D 3.232) or panfJatti (S
4.39-40). However, there is no indication that, sioce these are relative conventions, the Buddha advocaced the transcendence of both good and bad.
Having defined the good as the ftuitfu, the Buddha characterized the
ultimate good :as the ultimately fru i tfu!. The term paramattha was thus used to
refer to the "ultimate fruit'' rathet than ''u.ltimace realicy." Sammuti and
paramattha are therefore oot two contrasting truths. Theformer is a mixed bag ,
while the latter represents the ultim.ate ideal. As a result of anaining nibbiina.
which is the complete eradication of lust (raga), hatred (dosa), and confusion
(moha), the Buddha found himself enjoying an ultlmate fruit, withour hurting
hirnself or others (na attantapo na parantapo, D 3.232). Parama.ttha thus
becomes the mora.I ideal as reflected in the Buddha's own att.ainment df
freedom and happiness.
The theory of dependent arising (pra!f.ccasamuppada) expla.ining the
phenomena that arc dependently arisen (paficcasamuppanna) thus accommodates the four truths as well as the two truths. All ttuths being pragmatic,
there is herc no place for an "absolte or ultimate reality." The Buddha's
epistemological scandpoint does not allow for such speculations.
This, howevec, was not the case with the metaphysicians. l t is significant to
noce tbat when the Buddhist metaphysidans were faced with the problem of
reconciling the four truths with their conception ,o f substance (s11abha11a), they
were compelled to fall back on the conception of two truths (Akb p.33).
Howcver, their interpretation of the, two truths is totaHy different from the
Buddha's and , in fact, seems to be contrary to it. Here again, Vasubandhu is
our source.
As a Sauttantika metaphysician, Vasubandhu refers to the two truths (satya)
and surreptitiously moves on to a discussion of existents (sat): sa?fZvrtt~sat and
paramiirthasat (A,b p.334). He tbeo provides two examples to illustrate the
. nature of saf!lvrti-sat. The fust is a 'pot' (ghat) . There canoot be knowedge of
a pot when it is broken ioto pieces. The second is water (ambu). Water is not
knowa independent of the knowledge of "form" (riJpa). Contrasted with these
two is knowedge of the paramartha-sat. 'Materia! form' (ritpa) is an example of
such existeoce. Io this case, wheo an object is broken down inro its ucimacey
irreducible elemenrs, namely, ;uoms (paramii1'Ju) , there is knowcdge of the
"unique narure" (s11abhava = s11a/ak!a1Ja?) of such acoms. For the metaphysi-
333
cian, that unique nature, whether it is called svabha11a qt s11alakfa'la, has aways
remained an epistemological enigma .
This interpretation of the two truths is totaly abseot either in the eary
discourses or in the canonical Abhidharma. In the so-called Theravada ttadition, it appears for the first time in the ooo-canonicaJ tcxts (Mi/n 160), coouibutiog, as it did in the case of the Sarviiscivada and Sautraocika schools, to
insoluble problems such as the duality of mind and matter. Vasubandhu's
statement of the two uuths- .raf(lvrti and paramiirtha-in the above contcxt,
where he was r~cordiog the interpretation of the Sauuiintika view, remains in
sharp contrast to the spirit of the Buddha's teachlng on "noo-substantialism ."
This shouJd certainJy provide an interestiog background to the analysis of
Nigarjuna's owo version of the two cruths.
Those who do not un'derstand the distinction becween these two truths do
not understand the profound troth embodied in the Buddha's mcssagc.
MKV(P) p.494 : MKV(V) p.215 .
Niigarjuna is, of course, criticizing his opponents for not understandiog the
Buddha's rnessage. If so, Niigarjuna's owo explanacion of tbese two trud~
should not come anywhere close to the one discussed by Vasubandhu, according to which the .raf(l11(ti reprcsents a merc designac:ion, not an ultimate reality
or paramiirtha. It is an ootologkal speculatioo whkh is not supported by the
Buddha's own conception of dependent arising.
10.
THE
WAY
335
11.
Vinaayati
.!KV(V)
p .21 6.
12.
336
Thus, the Sage's (the Buddha's) thought recoiled from teachlng the doctne having reflected upon the difficulty of undemanding the doctrine
by peope of meager intelligence.
MKV(P) p.498: MKV(V) p.217.
This passage should dispel any doubts regarding the naru:re ofthe Buddha's
reasons for his ini~ial reluctance co preach. le was noc because of any intellectual
incapacity on the parr of the human beings, but mostly because of the emot ional difficulties chey would have in brcaking away frorn the accepted theories
in which they have fouod safety and comfott, a sort of 'mooring' (alaya),
especiaHy in accepting a less absolutistic and fundament?Jly non-substantialist
(anatta) philosophy and a way of life . As iodicated above, the phrase used by
the Buddha to refer to the attitude of the human beings is alaya-ratii
("delighcing in alaya," where alaya is derived from 4 + V li implying some
sort of mooring or obsession). Alaya represents an obsession for not only the
pleasure~ of sense, but aJso ideas, dogmas, theories, etc.
13.
337
Furthermore, if you wece generate any obsession with regard to emptiness, the accompanying error is not ours. Thac [obsession] is not appropriate in the context of the empty.
MKV(P) pA99; MKV(V) p.21 7.
funya.
14.
Everything is pertinent for whom empriness is proper: Everytbing is not pertinent for whorn the empty js not proper.
MKV(P) p.500; MKV(fl/ p.218.
This terse stacement of Nagarjuna, represencing an extremcy valu_?.b~e assessment of the two concepcs of "emp tiness" (unyata) and "the empty" (funyaf!t),
can be comprehended only in t)le background of his previous statement (X:XIV.13). Ie is a cricicism of the absoucistic aod substantiaJist enterprise wherein
abstract concepts Jike "empciness" reccive a divine status thercby becorning
compatibe wich anything and everything in human experience, like the
Platonie "forms". whcrcas any emphasis on the concrete leaves everything .
338
15.
Sa
tva~
You, acuibuting your own errors to us, ace like one who has mounted his horse
and confused about it.
MKV(P) p.502; A1KV(V) p. 218.
16.
339
17.
You will also contradict [the norions of] effccc, cause, agent, pctfoanance
of action, activity, arising, ceasing, as weU as fruit.
MKV(P) p.503: MKV(V} p.21 9,
How the recogrunon of self -narure (svabhava) contra4icts all forms of empiricaJ knowledge, knowledge recognized by the Buddha relating to dependent
arising, mora behavior (karma), and responsi biity (karma-phala), has already
been explained in detai l in the numerous chapters t hat precede. Herc Nagarjuna is simply summarizing all his conclusions.
18.
340
wAV
341
saf!Jvrti
19.
A thing chat is not dependently arisen is not evident. For thac reason, a
thing that is non-empty is indeed not evident.
MKV(P) p .505 ; MKV(V) p.220.
342
884) would insist that only one of these aternacivcs is crue (ekaf{l hi saccaT(J).
and not the second (na dutiya'!J). This means chat neither the Buddha nor
Nagarjuna could be characterized as absolutiscs.
However, if the two alternatives were to be two metaphysical altcrnatives,
then both the Buddha and Nagarjuna would be compelled to ncgacc them.
Takco out of context, wabhiiva and nzf/11111bhii11a could appear as mccaphysicaJ
alternacives. So could a!unya and filnya. Yct , apralitya.samutpanna and
pralitya.samutpanna, as understood by the Buddha and Nigarjuna, could not
be easily coo-.:ened to metaphysiall alceroatives. The reasoo for this is that the
term pralityasamutpanna, beiog a past parcic~ple, does not refer strictly to any one
tempora! experience, whcther it bclo_ngs to the past, present or future, nor does
it traoscend ternporality altogether. Whil_e it has a present connotacion, it is not
divorccd from the pasc. lt i~ . therefore, a term most appropriately used to
describe the events perceived by the Buddha through his "knowiedge of things
as they have come to be" (yathabhuta-fiii'la) . lt refers to the events experiencep
in the so-caled "spedous present" (see comments on XIX.4).
lt is this empiricist prajnapti that servcs as a corrcctive to any propos3.I which
would turn either pralityasaf!Jutpada or unyata into an absolute truth , ineffable and a-tempora!. lt is, indeed, the philosophical middle path referred co at
XXIV. 18 and the Buddha's discourse to Karyayana.
20,
If all this is non-cmpty, there exists no uprising and ceasing. Thcsc imply
the non-cxistencc of the four noble truths.
MKV(P) pp.505-)06; MKV(V) p.220.
By rescuing the philosophical middle pach from aoy absolutistic or substantialist incerpretation , Nagarjuna has sec the foundation for the explanation of
the Buddha's doctrine of che four noble truths. The facts of arising and ceasing
arc central to the fouc noble uuchs. lf tbere ever has been a permanenc enticy ,
an encity that is noc empty of a subsrance. then dependence as wdl as the four
noble truths would have been falsified . No such entity has been discovered so
far. Hence the four truths have remained valid.
21 .
How can there be suffering that is not dependently arisen? Suffedng has,
indeed, bccn described as impermanent. As such, it is not evident in
tcuns of self-nature.
MKV(P) p.506; MKV(V) p.220.
Nigarjuna is herc: returnjng to the interpretation of suffering by the substantialist metaphysicans (sec comments on XXIV . l), who held that suffering exists
in terms of self-nature. He is reminding che metaphysicians that the Buddha's
conception of suffering is founded not ony on the idea of dependent arising
but also the notion of impermanence. Io face, the perversion regarding the notion of impermanence is aJso the cause of che perversion regarding the concepcion of suffering (sec comments on XXIII. l).
22.
Throughout the treatise, Nigarjuna was refusing to recognize that the conception of self-nature or substance leaves any room for the recognition of arising
and ccasing. This was contcary to the attempr on the part of the metaphysicians. Nigarjuna is herc insisring that the conception of arising (samudaya)
makes no sense at all when applied to self-oature.
Self-nature is not something that comes and goes. lt is oot 20 occutreoce. lt
is thece for ever. As such. it contradicts the theory of emptiness which is intendcd to explain the occuuencc of cvents. Empciness, as ment:iooed earlier
(XXIV. 18), is synonymous with "dependent arising."
344
23.
WAY
Just as the notion of self-nature conuadiccs the idea of arising, it also renders
che conception of cessacion meaningless. Note the cmphasis on the present participle , santa (left untranslated by lnada, p. 149), used in relation duf?kha ,
implying "suffering that exists" in terms of self-nacure. The notion of exiscence
defined in this manner has already been criticized by Nagarjuna (1.6) . In effect
Nagarjuna is saying thac the nocioo of exiscence (sat) may be compatible with
che conception of self-oature, but ie is not appropriate io the context of "chat
which has come to be" (bhuta) .
to
24.
The priociple of sclf-nature (svii.bhiivya, noce the use of the absuact noun instead of svabhiiva) explaios the way in which self-nature funcri~ns . !hus, if
somechings are assumed co have self-nature , whac is assumed is that chings happen on cheir own (svo bhavo) without the support of anything else. la tbis
sense, chey arc independent. If rhe pach (marga) Jeading to che ccssacion of suffcring (duf?kha) were to be explained in cerms of self-narure, ie means chac che
way will work out on its own , wichouc any effort on the part of one who is expecced to cultivate it. If one is expected ro c utivate the pach, it means chat one
has to make an effort . Ie does not happen auromatically .
25.
345
When suffering as well as its arising and ceasing are not evident, through
the cessation of suffering where will the path lead to?
MKV(P) p.508i MKV(V) p.221.
Insisting upon the recognition of self-nature, the metaphysicians were compeled to deny the fact of suffering as well as its arising and ceasing. lt would,
therefore, be meaningless to speak of a path leading to the cessation of suffering. Substancialist speculation leaves only two aternatives: either there is cessatio of suffering or there is no cessation of suffering. If the fact is that there is .
cessacion of suffedng (dul;kha-nirod/;atva). thtre is no room for a path. It happeos in any case. If the fact is that there is no cessation of suffering, then it is
meaningless to think of a path. FaraJism being the consequence of both standpoints, the notion of a path Jeading to any goal is rendered uttetly meaningless.
26.
346
tialists would be defeated. Therefore, he was simply asking the question; "Is
it not the case that self-narure is fixed?" He is, io fact, insiscing that if ie ~~
not fixcd, ie is not a self-nature. A change of subst.aoce was, io the eyes of
Nagarjuna, a self-conuadiction.
Hence he argues: If there is any inabili:cy to understand suffering because
such ioability is inherent, is through self-pacure, then there can never be ics
underscand:ing. Something chat is inherently uoknowable can oever be
subsequently known. Thi is the most telliog criticism of self-nacure
27.
28.
347
nature, to realize a f ruit that bas already becn realized through self-
nature?
MKV(P)
p . ~10;
MKV(VJ p.222 .
which will be taken up for detailed treatment by Nigarjuna later on). This, indeed, is a fatalistic or a deterministic explanation of causality. Either the effect
exists in the cause or it does not (see discussion of artha [ = phala) at 1.6).
In tbe absence of the fnilts, tbere arc neither tbose who have attained the
fruits nor those who have reached the way [to sucb attainmeot]. If the
eight types of indivjduals do not exists, there will be no congregation.
30 .
From the non-existeoce of the noble truths, the truc doctrine would also
not be evident. In tbe absence of tbe doctrine and the congregation, how
can there be an enlightened one?
MKV(P) p .) 10; MKV(V) p.222.
Having shown that the explanation of the attainment of the frui~ (phala) of
life is rendered i mpossible or meaningless by the adhetence to the ootioo of
self-nature, Nagarjuna rurns the table on the metaphysicins, showing them
how the denial of emptiness (iiinyatii), rather thn itS assertion, leads to a
denjaJ of all that they wece trying to explain.
348
31.
W AY
32.
Wh~oevet
p . 511~
MKV(V) p.223.
This is the one and only time Nagarjuna, the so-callcd pau on of Mahayaoa,
rcfcrs to the way (caryQ) of a bodhi.sall11a. Yet, the kind of criticism he is prcsenting herc offers no consolacion to those who accept cercain docrrines of
popular Mahayana. Any substaotiaJist theory, according to Nagarjuna's view,
militates against the ca.(eer of a bodhisattva.
To uphold che view chat a person is by narure u ncnlightencd is taotamount
to saying chat he can never attain the fruit of eolighteruncnt and frecdom by
excrting himself. Sir:Qiarly, to assert che view chat a person is by narure
enlighccncd, is a potential buddha, or possesses a bodht~citta, makes the attainmcot of enightenm.ent meaningess (XXIV.28) or impossible.
This, indeed. is reminiscient of the long drawn controvcrsy between the Sar
vastivadins and the Sautrantikas regarding tbe oarure as wcU as the functioning
of good (kusa/a = dharma) or bad (akusala = adharma) thoughts (citta). The
metaphysical problems generated by an extremist analysis in rclation to
phenomena in genera have been explained in Chapters I and Il . The selfsame
metaphysical problems appeared in the explanatioo of moraJ phenomeoa. The
Sarvastivada-Sautrantika controversy relating to the "seed,s that arc of good
nature" (kusa/a-dharma-bija) reflects their iovolvement in sucb mt"taphysical
4
1SSUCS.
350
THE
33.
No one will, indeed, do good or bad. What could the non-empty do?
foc, self-nature does not perform.
M.KV(P) p.511 ; MKV(v,i p.223.
Inada , once again. renders the terms dharma and adhamta as factoJs and non~
factors of experience, thereby reacling moce ontoogy than axiology inco the
statement of Nagarjuna. substantialist ioterpretation of good and bad a.llows
no room for their cu ltivation or performance. If someone; is good in terms of
self-nature, he does not have to 'perform the good; ir is simply there. SimiJarly
with bad. Self-nature (svabhava) implies absolute existence (sad-bhava), not
occurrcnce (sa'f(tbhava, XXIV.22) .
34.
351
As for you, the fruit would be evident even without good or bad. Tbis
means that for you a fruit occasioned by good and bad would not be evident.
MKV(P) p.512 ; MKV(V) p.223 .
35.
Thus, Nagarjuna insists that rnora discourse and a subsrancialist world-view arc
incompatible. If something is good by nacure, good in terms of self-narure,
good in itself, chen it musc be always good. Ir cannot be otherwise. Such an absolutistic theory will fail to accommodate some individual or panicular siruations tbat arc in conflict with the theory, but which would cectaioly be valid in
certain concexrs. This was a serious defect in the absolutistic cheory. as explain
ed by Nagarjuna in the following verse.
36 .
3~2
You will contradict all the worldly conventions when you contradict the
empciness associated with dependent arising.
MKV(P) p .)13 ; A-fKV(V) p .224.
This, ooce again, bighlights the significant reationship betwcen worldly conventions, that arc siruatiooal or contexrual and the prindple of dependent arising which, as explained earlier, is a univesal. The only way che universal can
accommodate the siruational is when the universal is not looked upon as corresponding co an "ultimace reaLiry." The subsrantialists who assumed that there
is an ultima ce reaJiry, rherefore, we re faced wich all the insoluable mecaphysics.
Thus the actual function of emptiness is the eiminarion of this substancialist
sring (see commcnts on XXIV . 18).
37.
For one who contradicts emptiness thece would be nothing that ought to
be done; accivity would be uninitiated and an agent would be nonacnng.
MKV(P) p.513; MKV(V) p.224.
The unfortunate consequences of upholding a subsrantialist theory and denying empciness arc listed herc. lncerestingly, all of them percain co human
behavior and moral responsibiliry. This says much abouc che concerns of
Nagarjuna, who by popular acclaim is more a logician primarily concerned with
language and truch and therefore with ucimate reality , rather tban a mora!
philosopher iotecesred in axioogy and, for thar reason, emphasizing the conception of "u timate fruit. " He is supposed to have scorned aoy specuation
about human behavior (karma), wbat human behavior oughr ro be (kartavya),
and who a responsibile human agent (kurvarJa) is.
In brief, a substantialist view leads co a denial of ~he human element fu ncrional in this w.ord, an element t hat is generally described as "disposition"
(saT(lskara). Not only does it negate the world condicioned by human disposirions (i.e., the saT(l.!krta), ie also denies any activiry and creativiry in the natura!
world (sec XXIV.38 that follows).
38.
353
In a substantialist view, the universe will be unborn, oon-ceased, remainlng immutable and devoid of variegated states.
MKV(P) p.513; MKV(V) p.224 .
The assumption of a substance (svabhava) would depri.ve the natura! world , the
world of dependent arising, of all che variety (vicitra) and freshness and leave it
sterile and unproduccive . This , indeed, is the Buddha's criticism of erernalism
(sassata-diffht) when he maintained t hat according to rhis view the self and the
world are sterile, immovable, and remaining stable like a pillar," (D J.14; S
3. 202, 21 1, etc yatha sassato atta ca loko ca vanjho ku{tiffho esikauhayz't{hito):
39.
If the non-empty [is evident] , then reaching up to what has not been
reached , the act of t'crminating suffeng as well as the reunquishing ofall
defilemenrs would not be evident.
MKV(P) p .51) ; MKV(V) p.225.
The substantialist view would oot ony negate the world decermined by h uman
dispositions (sa11}skrta) and che naruraJ world of dependent arising
(prafitysamutpanna), but also the idea world , che world of freedom . N iryana
would remain inexplicabe in the context of a substantialisc world-view. This is
che subject maccer of the next chapcer. Before proceeding to explain freedom,
Nagarjuna has a quotation from the Buddha (XXIV.40).
40.
354
The Buddha maintained chat he who pcrceives dependenc arising pcrceivcs the
dhamma (M 1.190191 ; Chung 7.2 [Tairho l.467a}. Perceiving dependent aris
ing is not mcrely perceiving "things as they have come co be" (yath'iibhuta), but
also seeing how a human being placed in such a context of dependent arising
experiences suffering (dul/kha); what causes such suffering; what kind of
freedom can be attained and what the path is that leads to the attainmcnt of
freedom and cmancipacion. Dependent arising and the four noble truths arc,
therefoce, the foundations on which the whole edifice called Buddhism is built.
Any school of Buddhism chat refuses to recognizc the centralicy of these doc
uines would loose its claim to be a legitimate pan of that tradition. These con
stitute the truths chat Nigarjuna was attemptiog to explicatc in che pcesent
chapter.
CHAPTER
TwEN1YFIVE
Examination of Freedom
(Nirvar;,a~partk!ti)
l.
If all tUs is empty, there ests neithec arising nor ceasing. [As such,]
through the relinquishing and ceasing of what does one expect freedom?
MKV(P) p.'.>19; MKV(V) p.227.
Even though someof the problems rdating to freedom (nittlaf'!a) have al.ready
been discussed in the context of a tathagata (Chapter XXII) and the four noble
truths (Chapter XXIV), Naga.rjuna singles out this topie for further analysis,
especially in view of certain grave misconceptions that emerged as a resuJt of a
substantialist world-view. Without making any attempt to determine what
these metaphysical views were, many a scholar has plung.ed himself inro assertions about Nagarjuna's coaception of freedom and produced views that arc no
less metaphysical than those rejected by Nagaijuna.
The present verse 6cplains the di.fficulties the metaphysicians, who acceptcd
substantial phenomena, cxpeticnced when they attempted to elucidate
freedom. While the ptcvious chapter dealt with the problems the substantialists faced when they accepted a notion of self-nature and tried to accountfor
che four noble t.ruths, especially the empirical fact of sliffering (duf?kha). the
present context Nagarjuna is primacily concerned with the question of freedom
from suffering. The substantialist dilemma herc would be : How can freedom
( niniiin.a) be explained , if the conception of empciness is ucilized not only to
explain the empiricaJ fact of~suffering but also to elucidate ninii'!a) which,
even though described as the cessation of sufferiog (du~kha-nirodha), was also
the uJtimace or absoluce reality.
After deoying any substance (111ahava) in the conventiona! or the contextua
(11yav11hara). if Nagarjuna had not proceeded to extend that denial to the idea
(p11ramiirtha), the substantialist could have remained silen.t. Hbwever, when
Nagarjuna univetsaJ.ized "the empty" (i#njll) by saying "aJJ this is empty" (IllT:
3)5
356
2.
'
lf all this is non-empty,
thete exists neithec arising nor ceasing, [As such,]
As in the previous chapter, it is because of his preference for an empiricai explanation of things in terms of arising and ce~ ing (udaya.vyaya) _that Nagarjuna is not willing to accept a mctaphysical substaQce. Hence his argument that
relinquishing (praha11a) a.nd ceasing (nirodha) are meaningless in the contcxt
of the ''non-empty" (afiinya). Thus, for Nagarjuna, the non-cmpiricaJ view is
the one expressed in the form , "All this is non-empty (sarvam idam afUnyatrJ) ,
rather chan .the view presented as "AU this is empty" (sarv(lm ida?(l fUn.:;af!l) . If,
on the i:ontrary , the substanti.ists were to accept the empirical phenomena to
be empty, but noc.ni rvaf!a, srill Nagarjuna could ask the question: lf nif'tl(Zf!a is
a permaoenr and eternal substance, why talk of arising and ceasing, relin
quishing and abandoning. for suffering (duf?kha) or defilements (kiesa) that
need to be relinquished actually do not affect the originally pure existence?
For Nagarjuna and the Buddha, neither the empirical events nor the
utimate fruit wece substantial. Neither samsara
nor nirvana
.
. were' absolute in
any sense. As such, what Nagarjuna is presenting is not different from the cmpiricaJ view of bondage and freedom explained in the Buddha's discourse. ro
Katyayana.
3.
EXAMINA.1.lON OF FREEDOM
357
pannartz.
Thus. the sixfold acriviry- rclinquishing, reaching, interruption, remaining.
constant, ceasing and arising - as explained by the metpphysicians need to be
negated beforc an empiricist theory could cmerge. Such mecaphysical explana-
358
p . 524~
M.k"V(V) p.229.
Inada ~es bhava in the present context as the nature of ordinaty existence. Instead, the term is better explained as a reference to metaphysical existence
(a.rlitt1a), as has been the case with Naprjuna (see especially, XXl .15-16; also
XXV.10). The metaphysicians who admitted bliava or rvabhava as eternal and
perrnanent entities nevcr attempted. an empirkal justification of tbeSe eotities .
They seem to have assumed that these are known through "ominscience" (stlf'tlt1Jf4f11a) . Nigarjuna, realizing the Buddha's attitude toward such knowledgcclaims (sec discussion of Sabba-sutta at IX.3) and, thcrefore, making no
refcrcncc to sucb knowledge at all in the present text, simply noted the implkations of rhls metaphysical sp eculation and iosisted that such existence (bhava,
s11abhi11a) is invariably associated with charactcristics (/a/qaa) , Uke decay and
death (jtll''ii-maraf!a). Thus, freedom will not includc frecdom from decay and
death and this would contradict the Buddha's claim that he is freed from the
recurrent cyde of births and deaths. On the contrary, if the mctaphysicians insis.ted that there is no invariable connection between existence (bhava) and
characterisiics (la/qaf!4), then they <.:ould claim tha t after p11rinirvar1a a freed
peoon can retain the eternal existence and drop the characteristics. N:igarjuna was
qui~e certain that this is an extension of the metaphysical position and is in conflict with the non-substantialist teachings of the Buddha (sec X:XV. 17).
EixAMINATION OF fREBDOM
359
Morcovcr, if frccdom wcre to be cxistencc, thco &cedom would be condicioned. Yct, an existence that is unconditioncd is not evidcnt anywbere.
MKV(P) p.526; MKV(v) p.230.
In rendering the terms Jaf!JSkrta and t1.It1f!llkrta as "condirioned'' and the "uoconditioned" rcspectively, we havc, in the present cootcxt, tried to ret.a.in the
interpretation of the metaphysicians, for it is this panicuJar interpretation that
is being questioncd by Nagarjuna. UndoubtedJy, it is the Sarvastivada theory
which cquatcd Jtlf!IJR[/4 and prafityt1.Iamulpanna that Nagat:juna has in mind
(see commcnts on VTI. 1). The implicacioo of this equation is that "the uocon
ditioncd" (asaf!1Jkr14) is also the "independent" or "uncaused''
(aprafityasamutpanna), an implication not acccptable to both Nagarjuna and
the Buddha.
In fact , XXV .4-6 highlight the sharp distinction the metaphysicians assurned
between frcedom and bondagc (sec Chaptcr XVI , Examinacion ofBoodagc and
Releasc). lt is this sharp distinction, whkh is the foundation of the substan
ciafuc cxplanacion of freedom and bondage, that is being analysed by Nagarjuna. Unlcss this metaphysical cxplanation is kcpt in view. speculatoins about
Nagarjuna's owo conception of frecdom can turo out to be as wcird as those of
the met.aphysicians.
360
7,
8.
If there were to be no p ermanent existence, there could be oo permanent nonexistence . If chere wece to be no absolute existence , there could be no nihilistic
non-existence. Just as much as freedom is not absoluce existen~e, it is also not
nihiisLic noo-existence, Nigarjuna's atternpt in the present chapcet is directly
aimed at getting rid of sucha metaphysical explanation of freedorn . The Buddhists, throughout history, were prone to .make such distinctions, sornetirnes
ignoring the empirical middle position advocared by the Buddha. This is what
Nagar)una intends to explain in the next vr:rse.
361
in
10.
The teacher has spoken of relinquishing both becom.ing and otherbecoming. Therefore, it is proper .to assume r.hat freedom is neither existence nor non-existence.
MKV(I() p.530; MKV(V) p.232 .
362
WAY
As
11.
ExAMINATON OF FlUlBDOM
363
no moce than the release from suffering and there is rtothing transcendental
about it.
12.
As pointed out eadiei:, the substantiaist definition o( free dom implied independence, rather than non-grasping or non-dinging (sec comments on XXIl.5). Thus, if the metaphysicians were to define freedoro as both existence and
non-existence, it could not be independent as they expect it to be. This is
because existepce and non-existence are dependent.
13.
As in the .previous verse, here too Nagiirjuna is takiog the definition proffered
by the opponent and cdticizing his conception of freedom. This is similar to
the argument adduced by Nagarjuna atXXV .6 , except that in the present case
Nigarjuna is insiscing that if something is both existence and non-existeoce, it
could not approptiately be called an "unconditioned." 'The "uncondi tioned,"
by the meraphysician's definition, is the "inde(>endent" (apratftyasamutpanna),
and an element witb rwo eotities as parts of it will always be conditioned by
those rwo parts.
364
15.
Anjanii from (yanj, ''to annoint") can mcan a symbol. Here Nagif.rjuna is not
speaking of logicaJ proof to decide the validity of a symbolism , or a proposicion. Rather, he is interested in the ernpiricaJ justification. Thus, unless both
existence and non-existence, as cxplained by the metaphysician, can be shown
~o have empirical validity, their oegations too would ruean nothing.
16.
EXAMINATION Of FREEDOM
Thls seems to be a rather devastating cr1ticism of the more popular view that
freedom caooot be expressed either as existeoce or as non-existence. That is,
it is linguistically transcendent or is ineffable. If the statement, "Freedom is
neither existence nor nonexistence," is intended to express the ineffability
of nit;iii'!a. Nagarjuna is questioning the meaningfuloess of that very statemenc. This means that absolute negation is as metaphysial as absolute assertioo , ''absoute nothingness" is as meaningless as "absolute chingness," and
these arc che absolutes chat are expressed by terms like bh'iiva and abhava.
17.
lt is not assumed that the Blessed One exists after deat h . Neither is it
assumed that he does not eist, or both, or neither.
18.
These, indeed, are the metaphysica assertions made regarding the tathagata
(XXII) which both Nagarjuna and the Buddha rejecied. The foundations of
these metaphysical views were the theocies of identiry and difference. This very
important problem is next taken up for examination by. Nagarjuna.
19.
366
This statement of Nagarjuna has contributed to a major and wide-spread assertion regarding the uniqueness of Mahayana philosophy, namely. the ultimate
identity of sa1{'Jilira and nirvii11a. This assertion may appear to be correct, if we
arc to ignore all that has been said by Nagarjuna regardiog the metaphysical
doctrines of. identity (ekatva) and difference (n'iinatva) , especially in the
chapters dealing with the tathagata (XXII) and the four truths (XXIV).
Those who upheld the view that this statement is an assenion of the identicy
of Sllf!JSfJf'fJ and nirtiii11a do not seem t have paused for one moment to reflect
on the question regarding the nature of the identity they were implying; nor
have they attempted to place that conception of identity ( if there is one) in the
historical context.
The facr that chere wa's a great urge on the part of the Buddh.ists, especially
after the Buddha's death, to taise him to the level of a supreme being, having
no real connections with the ordinary human world, can easily be seen from the
mote popular Mahayana texts lilce the Lalitavistara and the
Satldh11rmapuf!t/4.fik11 as wel as the Theravada treatises like the}iilaka-nidiinakathii. Through thac popular perspective, substancialist views regarding the
nature of the Buddha began to emerge among philosophers. These
philosophical views were prominent with the early metaphysicians like the Sar
vastivadins and the Sauuantikas .
.Nirv'a11tJ, understood as the "ultimate reality'' (paf'l~martha), came to be
distinguished from sa1{'JS'iira, the unreal, he convention, the impermanent .
The Buddha's owo view chat niniiif?IJ is the "ultimate fruit' ' (paramattha), a
culmination of the fruit (111th11) of everyday life, the highest mora peection
invoJving the eschewing of aJl immoral cooduct (sabba-pap11ssa a.kartT!/111?") and
the promotin of good (kus11/111s11 upp,;11mplll/ii), was gradually being forgotten .
Dharma was gradually being distinguished from the dharma in che dharmaadharma context. The inapprop,riate equation of the pu;,ya-papa distinc:tion
with the dharma-adharma distinction (see commeots on XVJI.24) led to the
belief in a Dharma that transcends che dhamza..adhanna distinction.
However, this was not Nagarjuna's understanding. Vyavah'iira, the contex
tual or the conven,tional , 1s not provisional in a cheap pragmacic sense and,
therefore, unreaJ. lt is the concrete wichout which the ideal (paranzartha)
makes no sense at aU (XXJV.10). lt is the absolute distinction between
vyavahara and pararnartha rhat is denied in che present verse.
The fact that the Buddhist metaphysicians were involved in Jong-drawn
EXAMJNATlON OF FREEOOM
367
20.
Whatever is the extremicy of freedom .and the extremicy of the lifeprocess, between them not even a subtle something is evident.
21.
368
Metaphysical views relating to the finite, etc to the etcrnal, etc after
death arc associated with [the problems of] f.reedom as well as the
posterior -and prior exttetities.
1WKV(P) p.536; MKV(V) p.23).
22.
23.
When all things are empty, why [specuate on] the finite, the infinire,
both the finite and the infinite and neither finite nor theinfinite? \Vhy
[speculare on] the identical, the different, the etetnal, the non-eternal,
both or neither?
MKV(P) p.537; Ml-.'V(V) p.235 .
and
EXAMINATION OF FR.BIDOM
24.
369
The Buddha did not tcach the appeasement of all objccrs, the appeasement of obsession, and the auspicious as some thing to some one at some
pbcc.
MKV(P) p.538; MKV(V) p.236.
Inada has broken up the above inro two distinct statements and thereby lost its significance. The first line contaios qualificarions of dharma occurring in the second.
N:igarjuoa's emphasis is on the phrase: kacil dharmaf, as it was in the case of
the two important statementS made previously in the present chapter
(XXV. 19-20). When the Buddha spoke of freedom (nirva fla), which he
quaJified as the appeasement of aH objects (upaklmbha = al11mbana =
dra1ta11ya, cf. drfJ!(avyopaama at V.8) or the appeasement of obsessions
(prapalcopafama) or auspicious (Jiva, sec Dedicatory Verses). he was nor refeuing to them as "some thing,'' that is, some cotity having a specific distinction
(viiefaf!a) or subdety (1uiulqma111a). He was oot speaking of freedom in the
way the substantialist cooceived of it.
All these twenty-five chapters are, therefore, negative io characrer and tone.
They were devoted to a rcfutation of the two metaphysical but related views of
existence and noo-ex.istence (astitv'ri-ntistitva). Having cleared up the dust that
had gachered around all the doc~rines preached by the Buddha, Nagarjuna is
now ready to go on to the positive description of bondage and free dom as
enunciated by the Buddha in the discourse to Kacyayana. Nagarjuna's ttearment of the metaphysicaJ issues chat ernerged in relation to all these doctrinesdoctrines pertaining to causacion, change, the human personaJity, survival, karma, mora respo.nsibi ity, and freedom-is so cxhaustive and compe te that he
can proceed to explain the Buddha's conception. of bondage and freedom
without any fear of any one raising any question. Por he has already answered
them all. Herein Lies the greatoess of Nagarjuna as a philosopher.
CHAPTER
TwEN1Y SIX
l.
37 1
trine primarily through negations {XXV .3 and Dedicatory Verses), while ignoring al the positive statements of Nigarjuna.
XXVI. l is a furt her cxplanation of the Buddh a's statement : "Depending
upon ignorance arc dispositions" (aviJJapaccaya sakhafii). lts d aborarion is
also the Buddha's and is presented in the Kukkuravatika-rutla (M 1.390).
2.
372
vijiinaf!J
JIJ1(Jpravartatc.
Thus, depeoding upon the eye and mateal form, and attention too, and
depencling upon the psychophysical personality pcoceeds consciousness.
'Whatever is the harmonious coocurrence of the three factors: material
form, consciousness, and eye, is contact. .Feeling proceeds from such
contaet.
MKV(P) p,553554; MKV(V) p.242.
6.
p . 5~6;
MKV(V} p.243.
lt is inceresting ro noce that at this point i"n the explaoarioo of the twelvefold
formula Nagarjuna speaks of freedom or release (mak.fa). It is a point at which
,
374
W AY
the process of bondage can be interrupted. Nagarjuna is problably emphasizing this because he witnessed how his fellow Buddhists , in spite of their enormous intellectual capacities, constantly adhered to metaphysicaJ views and wece
caught in "Brahma's Net" (brahma-jii/11). Some of these intellecrual giants, who
wece able to write commentary after commentary, even though they had abandoned househoJd lives wece cnamoced with their views and invoJved jo ceaseJc~
diatribes. Realiziog the emphasis placed by the Buddha upon "non-grasping"
(anupadiina), Nagarjuna interrupts his exposition of the process of bondage co
explain freedom.
8.
10.
Thus, che ignorant forms disposjtions that constirute the source of the
375
life process. Therefore, it is the ignorant who is the agent, not the wise
one, because of his [the atter's] perception of truth.
MKV(P) p .558; MKV(V) p.244.
11.
12.
376
With the cessation of these, these othere factors [of the twelvefold formula] would not proceed. ln this way, this entire mass of suffering ceases
comt>etely.
CHAPTER
'fwENTY SEVEN
Examination of Views
(Drffi-parz k~a)
1.
Whatcver views asserting an eternal world, etc. based upon [the perceptio.nJ: ''Did I exist or not exist in the past?" are associated with the prioc
The first line of the verse has been reconstructed by Poussin on the basis of the
Tibetan ttanslation.
In che Pari(eyyaka-sutta (S 3.94-99; Tsa 2,.,25 [Tatiho 2.13c-14a]}, the Buddha maintained chat views such as "The self and che world are etetnal" (sassato
afta ca loko ca) are metaphysical because they are dispositional answers
(sankharo so) to querries about the past such as: "D id I exist in the past or
not?" As such, chey are not based entirely upon empirical facts. lndeed, they
are attempts to go back to the prior end of existence (pubbanta). While the
Buddha recognized them as futile attempts, mostly because of the limitarions
of human knowledge and understanding (see Chaptet XI), he was not uowill
ing to accept wbatever evidence available through veridical memories (sadi,
pubbenivasanussati). On the basis of such evidence, he characterized the past
existences as impecmanent (anicca), clispositionaly decermined (sankhata), and
dependently arisen (pa;iccasamuppanna), and not as permaoent (nicca) , immutable (dhuva) , and eternal (sassata) .
Nagarjuna's explanatioo of the metaphysical views of eternalism (a-vata),
etc. is, therefore, a vivid representacion of the Buddha's attitude regatding such
v1ews.
2.
378
wAY
Whatever views asserti.ng the finite, etc. based upon [the perceptioo]:
"Would I not exist U1 the futu.re or would I become soreQne else?" arc
associ.ated with the posterior end [of existence].
MKV(P} p .573; MKV(Vj p.249.
The assumptions that the self and the world arc finite or iefinite ate similarly
based upon one's dispositions (sakhara). Those who arc enamored with life as
it is would insist upon the world being infinite. Those who are averse to life
would advocate finiteness, insisting that there will be no way in which life
could continue. This is tantamount to annihilation (uccheda-ditthi, S 3.99;
Tsa 2.25 [Tairho 2.14bJ) .
This sratemenr may appear, at first sight, to mean a denial of rebirth or survival; that is, it would be inapproptiate to say: "1 existed in the past." Howevet:,
if one "is careful in observing the emphasis in the second line, nan1ely, sa eva
("he himself"), it will become apparent that what is denied is not ally relatiooship between two lives, but the identity of the two persons in different existences. Therefore, the statement, "I existed i11 the past," becomes
metaphysical only if an absolute identity is posited, which indeed was the prod ivity of the metaphysician.
4.
EXAM1NATIC5N OF Vtl!WS
379
5.
self.
MKV(P} p.575; MKV(V) p.251.
380
TifE
Mrooi.E WAY
[Taisho 1. 767aJ) , one of his disciplies, Sari, immediately assumed that "tbls
consciousness icself t.ransmigrates, and ot anotber" (zdam eva vifiiiiif!a'f(l sandhavati sa'f(lHtrati ananfla'f(l, M 1.256; Chung 54.2 [Tairho l .767a]), chereby
atrributing ao identity theory to the Buddha. The Buddha's immediate
response was to. deny such identity by asserting that consciousness is depeodenty arisen (paficcasdmuppanna). Theo the Buddha proceeded ro show how
consciousness, when explained in terms of causa! dependence, leads to a denial
of such identity. This, indeed, is what Nagarju na eodeavors to do in the
present cootext.
6.
Grasping is not identical with the self, for that ~i.e grasping] ceases and
arises. Furthermore, how can grasping be the gta$per?
MKV(P) p.576; MKV( V) p .251.
As was dooe by the Buddha, (see comments above XXVlI.5), Nagarjuna is rejecting the notion of self (iitman) on two grounds . First, it is assumed to be
permanent and eternaJ , whereas grasping that is identified with the self is sub- ject to ac:isiog and ceasiog. Secondly, the self is also assumed to be the ageo t
behind all human action and, rherefore, of grasping. lf so, how can tt be both
action and agent at the same time?
7.
EXAMINATION OF VIEWS
381
For che Buddha as wel as for Nagarjuna, the denial of a substancial encity is
based upoo empirical evidem::e, namdy, the perception of an individualiry consisting of the five aggregates. The five aggregates do not appear individually as
insulated discrete elementS. They appear asa lump (puflja) wh.ich retains its individuality (based upon dispos.hions) and cootinuicy (founded tipoo consciousness). In such a conte.xt he is caUed a person ( hoti satto ti sammuti, S
1.135; Tsa 45.5 [Taisho 2.327a]). In the context of a society, he becomes a
social being with relarionships to others (as son, facher , or daughter , mother.
etc.) In the context of mora behavior, he becomes good or bad (see the explanation of empirical self by William James, The Pnnciples of Psychology ,
vol.1,291-293). H owever, if the self wete to be considered different from che
perceivcd individuaity, it woud turo out to be a rather mysterious en city and
bence unknowable through the availabJe means of knowledge.
CandcakTrti, who pcefers a transcendentalist interpretation of Nagarjuna, .
gives .a negative explanacioo of what is very cleary a positive statement of
Nagarjuna.
8.
Thus, he is neitber clifferent from grasping nor identical with it. A self
does not exist. Yet, it is not the case that a person who does not grasp
does not ex;ist. This much is certain.
M.KV(P) pp.577-578; MKV(V) p.252.
382
9.
W/\ Y
The statement, "I did not exist in che past," is not appropriate, for this
person is not different from whosoever existed in the previous lives.
M.KV(P) p .578: MKV(fl?p.252 .
This . theo is a elear deoial of absolute difference. Just as much as rhe statement, "I existed n the past," is noc appropciate so long as it is interpreted to
meao absolute identity, even so the statement, ''I did not exist in the past," is
not appropriate as long as it is cakcn to mean absolute differeoce.
10.
If this person wece to be different [from that person in the previous existence] , then he wouJd come to be even forsaking tbat person. In that
case he would remain the same and, in such a context, an immortal
wouJd emcrge.
MKV(P) p. 579: MKV(fl? p.252.
11.
(1f that were the case,] there would be annihilation and destruction of ac-
EXAMINAT!ON OP VIEWS
383
tions. This implies that the fruic of action performed by one will be experiencecl by another.
M.KV(P) p.580; M.KV(V) p.253 .
The verse has been reconstructed by Poussin on the basis of the Tibctan uanslauon.
H ow a metaphysicaJ coocepcion of difference would lead not only to a denial
of survival but also a repudiation of moral cespoosibility has bcen aJready
discussed by Nagarjuna (Chapter XII). There it was shown that he depcnded
upon a discourse of the Budclha co explain this problem. The presenc is simply a
rcstatement of chat argument.
12.
Yet, in that context, the error of assuming a n emergent without prior existe nce docs not follow. Eithcr the self would be caused or, if it has occurred, it woud be without a c:ause.
1HKV(P) p.580; MKV(V) p.253 .
The concept of self (atman) was posiced in order to account for the concinuity
in the human personali cy which could also explain mora responsibility .
However, the denial of an eternal self led to the opposite view that there is no
continuity, but annihilation (uccheda). The denial of an eteraal self and the
consequeot assenion of nnihilarion do not imply (na prasajyate) che further
metaphysical view.; chat- stu:ticthing chat did nor exist before comes to be
(abhutva sqmhhotz), which carne co be interpreted as the abhutva bhava utpada in the Sautrantika school (sec Kalupahana, Causality , p .p . 152254). In
other words, rhere is no implication hece chat existence is completely independent, withouc any prior connections. As such, if there wece to be any self
(atman), ir would be "made" (krtaka, see karaka ar XXVT. 10). lf it is not, and
if it were assumed co arise , the self would be causeless.
13.
584
Thus, whatever view there is such as, "I existed in the past; I did not exist;
both or neither," is not really appropriate.
MKV(PJ p.581 ; MJ(V(V) p.253.
The views (dr!ft) referred to here a.re the metaphysical views relating to idencity.
difference , both or neithe.r . lt should be ooced chat the reasons for rejecting
these views are empirical. Empiricism, in the Buddha as well as in Nagarjuoa,
allows for the recognition of concinuity without having to posit absplute identity or absolute difference.
14.
A view such as "Will I exist in the future?" or "Will I not exist in the
futu1e?'1 is comparable to those associated with the past.
MKV(P) p .5.82; MKV(V) p.254.
Here again, the views that rue inappropriate are those i nvolving identity and
difference, not aoy explaoation of what the future could be based upon one's
experience of the process of dependent arising.
15.
16.
385
17.
If a part wece to be divine and the otber part to be human, then there
wouJd be both the eternal and the non-eter.na!, and this tod would not be
p ropcr.
MKV(P) p.584; MKV(V,) p.255
The combination of two metaphysical views do~s not prov1de for a noometaphysical one. The Buddha's rejection of SJJch views is clearly srated in the
Brah11iajala-1uJlanta (D 1.21) . Nagarjuoa is simply reiteratiog that posiLion
herc .
386
18.
THE
PHILOSOPHY OF THE
MIDDLE W'AY
Supposing both the eternal and the non-eteroa arc established, then it is
not possibe to cithcr assert the etcrnal or the non-etetna.
MKV(P) p.585; MKV(V) p .255.
Nigarjuna is hece refusicg to accept a conclusioo which is only a pan of a conjunctive proposition.
19.
cxist.
MKV(P) p.585; MKV(V) p.255 .
The m.ctaphysics rejected in Chaptcr II is refccred to in the first line. The second line cmphasizes che ideas cxprcsscd in Chap ter XI .
20.
If it is thought that thcrc is oothing ctemal, what is it that will be noncrernal, both ctecoal and non-eteroal, and also what is separated from
tbese two?
MKV(P) p .586; MKV(V) p.256.
WMINATION OF VIEWS
387
21.
H rhe world were to have a Jimjt, how could there be another wo.rJd?
Furthermore, if the world were to have no limit, how cou1d thcre be
another wodd?
MKV(P) p.587; MKV(V) p.;?56
22.
The simile of the lamp (patlipa) was popu]ar a.moog the Buddha and his
disciplcs, especialy in their expanation of freedom (nibban11). As the flame of
388
23.
na capy ami,
skandhaf? skandhan prafityeman atha loko 'ntaiiiin bha11e1.
If the prior aggregates were to pe destroyed and rhese aggregates were also
not to arise depending upon these other [aggregates], then the wodd
woud be finice.
If the prior aggregates were not to be destroyed and these aggregates were
aso
not to asc dcpcnding upon these other [aggregates], then the world
would be infinite.
MKV(P) p .588; MKV(V) p.256.
EXAMJNATION OF VJE\'(/S
25.
389
lf the world we.re to be pa~dy finice and also pardy infinite, it would be
both finite and infinite, and this too is also not proper.
'
'
The rejection of both the finite and the infinite, the etetnal as well as the noneternal, as constitucing the reality, was prompted by the Buddha's refusal to
recognize two djfferent levels of reality: a changing and finite world contrasted
with an eternal and infinite ultimate reality or an Absollte. As such, neither it:i
the Buddha's philosophy, nor in Nagarjuna's thinking is thete any room for an
Absolute of any sort.
26.
How can it be possible that one part of a gr:asper is dest!oyed and the
othetpart is not destroyed. This too is not proper.
27.
Uptidiinaikadea
How can it be possible that one part of grasping is destroyed and another
part js not destroyed, This too is not appropri.ate.
MKV{P) pp.589 -~90 ; MKV(V) p.257 .
Nagacjuna leaves no room for the recognitioo of an ecernal and absolute entity
either in the person grasping (up'iidiitr) or in grasping (upadiina).
390
28 .
Supposing both the finite and the infinite are e5tabiished, then it is not
possible to assert either the finite or the infinite.
MKV(P) p .590; MKV(Ji? p.257.
This rejeccion of the finitc and the infinite is comparabJe to the rejection of the
eternal and the non-cternal (XXVIl.18).
29.
The recognition of depeodencly arisen phenomeoa (prafityasamutpanna dharma) meaos the acccpdnce of the non-substantiality or emptioess of all these
things. If things are non-substantial, how can thcrc be views about the eternal
and the non-ete,r nal , the finite and the infinite? The answer to this question
has been provided by the Buddh.a and clearly .rcstated by Nigarjuna. Tt is the
resut of an urge on the part of human beings to find absolute answers to ques.
tioos such as "Where did 1 come from?'' or ''Wherc do I go fcom herc?" These
qucstioos wouJd be raised and attempts to answer them be made so Jong as
human beings arc propeUed by a "craving for becoming" (bhava-tr1'!ti) o~
"craving for other-becoming" (vibhava-tu'!ii) . This was the riddle of human
existence faced by the Buddha. Understanding that riddJe of existence, the
Buddha attained freedotn (nirva11a) by spewing out craving (tr11iii)~ and
abandooing any grasping (upadiina) .
30.
EXAMTNATION OF VtBWS
391
I revcrcntly bow to Gautama who, out of compassion, bas taught the truc
doctne in order to rclinquish all vicws.
MKV(P) p.592; MKV(V) p .258.
NOMlNAL FORMS
ag ni (firc) X. I, 6-9. 12- 1); nirogniAa X .9
ag111 (beginning) Xl.1. 2
11;1kura (sproul) XVIL 7
alj11ni (proposi tion) XXV. l 5
alita (pasc) XlX. 1-3; XX. 12; XXVll. l, 3, 9,
13- 14
XXl.6
a11y11111a (differtncc) XlV. 3-4. 7: X.X, t9;
XXIl.8
a11yathiit11a (change) .XV.9
anyathiibhiiva (change) Xlll.;}- 6; XV.5. 8
apalu1rfant; (climinacion) XVL. 10
XXII. 11
11aryar1hya (meaningless) X.2-3
alarrz (adcquarc) Vll .2
a11agiihalif!1, dur- (difficulty of undcrscanding) XXIV.17. /
a11ara (end) Xl.1. 2
a11as1ha (state) Vll.28; XXIV.38;
avaslho XVJ.6
at1ava11hi, ana11a11hiti (infinite regress)
Vll.3. 19
303
394
XVUl.2, 3
XXlll.22
111mal.r:111 (self..caused) Xll.8
i1ma-111f{Jy111'fl!lka (sclf-n:sttaint) XVll.1
ilmanly11 XXJV. I 5
xvm.
iilm1J11
2
p4iiil1TNI (anothcr self) vn. 25. 32
svilma (iaelf) m .2; Vll.13, 25. 32; :XX.24
$V11-pri1ma VIJ.8, 12
mdriya (faculty)
!Ilf/ (sile) m.1
Urtifuna (fucl) X.I. 4, ~9. U-15
idhm;ina (buming) X.4
I. I; Vll.14; XX. 10
tm- (non-) l.9; Vll. IJ..: 14, 17, 22; XVU.21;
XVlll.7; XX.17- 18; XXlll.9: XXY.3
im-.uj>Qpatti (ab.sense of arising)) V.4;
XX.22
11p11J)iltli1t1 VU..20
uihy11 (uprising) XVJ. 5; XVIll. l: XXL 15-16;
XXN.l, 20; XXV. l, 2
uihyo-~111f!114na XXI. 1~16
udiihrto (cxamplified) Vll.34
utibhuti (occuuencc) Vl.3
1uibht11111 (uprising) XVU. to; XXl .2
upfllllmbha (objcct) XXV.24
uplli4"111 (appeasement)
uplllllmbhopaiama (appcasemcm of
objcct) XXV.24
tl171!{1111yop11ftlma (appeasement of
objcct) V.8
pr11paflcopaJam4 (appeasement of
obse.ssions) Dedicarory Verses; XXV.24
11ptlf11111a (appcased) XXIIJ. 15
.upiidiino (grasping) 111.8; Vlll. 13; X. U ;
XVl.3 , 6; XVllJ.4; XXII.7-10; X.XVl.~7 ;
XXVll.4- 8, 27
""" (non) XVl.3, 6, 9; XXVI. 7
nir-(witho11~) XXII. 7
upadaua (sphcrc of grasping) XXVl.6
:t1'(spherc of non) XXJJ.7
11pidii1r: (graspcr) XXlf.10; X:XVL 7;
XXVll.6, 26
upiyt1 (mcans) XVI!. I I
upiiyisa (dispair) XXVI. 9
upiiltlmbha (ccnsurc) JV .9
up4/abtiha (ccnsurcd), a1'111pilabdh11
(unccnsurcd) IV .~.
urdhva (abovc) IX. 12
11/jxmfltl (arisco)
XV.4;
lNDEX
eka (one)
ek.al11a (idcntiry) VI.4 , 5; Vll.30; X . I ;
XIX.4 ; X:X.20
ek"tirtha (one meaning), an ekanha
XVlll. 11
XXIV. 17
a-kiiryaka (in-effcn-ivc) IV. 3
kr1a (donc, causcd) Xll. 1-4. 7-9:
XVll.24, 32; XXVIl.5, Il
a- (not) XVIJ ,22, 23
krta.k.a (made) XV 1-2; XVIL23;
XXVll.12
J.ririma, 11- (unmade) XV,2
kriyfi (activity) 1.4; Vlll.2, 4-6;
XXIV . 17, 37
kalpa (fabricarion) XXll.9
kalpan?i (thoughr) IX,12, XVU.12, 13
11i-k.alpa (discrimination) IV.5
395
XVlll.5
XVI. I; XIX.4
puniaparasaha-krama XI.2. 6
klei (defilemcor, impurity) XVIl.26-27, 33;
XVU.5: XVlll.5; XXJll.2-6, 24-25
k/11fii1maka (defiling natwe) XVll.26, 27
396
1~12;
XIV.l
(not-) 111.5
darana (view,
mctaphysical view)
3-4
dra(avyopt11ama (sec
upalam.a)
x:xv. 24
dea (body) XVI!. 27. H
do1a (error, faulr) VJil.8; XVU. 12. 16.
23; XXJV.1.5; XXVll.12
do!a-prasai1ga XXlV, U
daurmanasya (dejccilon ) XXVI. 9
dviialJ (pairs) XIV. L
d11c1a (hacred) XXOI. l, 7. 12
397
INDEX
XXJV.21
nityalii (pcrmancncc) XVll.6
a- (impcrmancncc) )QQ.4
19-21
a- (that wbich docs noi ccase) X.5
nmtrkl ( cc:asc:d) XX1 I. n
pa)a
pa~
(cloth) X .15
398
THE
a XVII.5
putra (son) lU. 7
pudgala (pct!lon) XII.4-6; XVl. 2
puru1a XXTV .4, 29
purufa (man) X6
-pudgala XXJV.4. 29
purra (p rior) Jl.13; V. 1; Vl. t ; l'X.6-8; X.8;
XJ.1-3, 6, 8; XV. Il ; XVl.7; .XX.8-9;
XXVU .2)-24
PrthaJ: (discrctc. scparacc:) Vl.8; X . l6
lllfJ (discrcrcnC3s) Vl.4-7; XX.20
, -bhiiva (discretcness) VJ.6-7, 9
prakaia (illuminacion) Vll.9
prakrti (pramal narure) XV.8- 9; XVll.14
pr.1j1JajJl i (eommunicatio fl, &on 11en1ion)
XXJ/.l/
1.4
&alfliiml? (four) I. 2
pratyikhyiiya (fot!lak.ing) XXVll.10
pralyulua (ccfuted) lll. 3
pratyulpanna (prcscnt) XlX. 1- 3
prPtyudiivrtta ( cccoilcd) XXJV.12
pradipa (lighr) Vll.8-12
pradipta (aflamc) X.2- 3
propaflca (obscssion) XVIU.) , 9
-alila (gone beyond-) XXIl.15
-hata (impaired by-) XXll. 15
-opaama
XXlV,9
a- (unenllghtcncd) XXJV 32
pmtyeliP (self-enlighic.-ned ) XVll. 13;
XVlll.12
sarn
(pcoctly
cnligh1enc.-d), Dc:dica1ory
Vcrscs-; XVIII. 12
399
INDEX
XXJV .5
xxv.4
a (without) V.1-3
11Jkandha- (-of non-aggrcgatc) XVlll.2
sarpskrta (of the conditioocd) Vll. 1, 3
-karrnanl (function as-) VII. 2
/11kf11'!1, tri- (having duce charactcristirs)
VII. I
.
lakfya (ch:uutcriz.cd) V. 5, 7; XI. 7
liriga, SI/O (owo matk) X. 5
loka (world) X:XVll. 21, 23-2)
para (other-) XXVU .21
-ni1tha (pattoo of the-) xvm . 11
-sarrivrti (worldJy coovcntion) XXIV.8
/auAika (worldly) XXIV.6, 36
400
XXVI.2, 4-)
vitijflrni11111 ( cvidcnt) XXIV. 22
fi (not) 1.3; V.6; IX.2; XI\1.7;
XXIIL 12, 16
11itlyii (knowledgc) XXIV.11
11- (ignonncc) XVU.28; XXIII.23;
XXVI.1 , 11
J1itl11il# (wise ooc:) XXVI.10
a (ignorant one) XXVL.10
11inii (without) Vl.5; IX.4-5 ; Xll.5-6;
XX.24; XXI.1-2, 4, 6, 8; XXlll>-4.;
XXV.4
11initmtd111 (separatcd) ll.1; XXVIL4-5
11ip111114 (sub)ect to perversfon) XXIU.17
a- (not ) XXIIl.17
11i.paryflya (pcrversiOJJ) XXIlI.6, 1}-14.
16-2 1, 23
a- (non-) XXIJL 16
flipary'iisa (pc:rversion) XXIII.1- 2
11ip1Jry4Sjaf!iiina (being subject to
pervcrsion) XXII!. 18
flipiil:a (maturiry) XVII. 25
l'iptmvfl (marurcd) XVII.18, 2~
11ijm1'!iiifl, 11- (impcrlshable) XVll.14- 15 , 20
vibha1111 (sec bh1111a)
11ibl/ilgt1 (distinction) XVIl.19; XXIV.9
prtwi (XVll.24
vibhaviil (adept) X,V. 7
111roli (non-dclight) X:VU.4
11- ( delight) XVII .4
vbuadha, par'1Jp11r11- (sclf-conrradictory)
VIU.7
11iie!"1!" ( distinguishing) XXV . 19
wAy
a(comtant) XXII.15
vya1111Jthi'4 (dctermined) IX. 2-4; XVU. 25
vyflflahiinr(convencion) XVI1.24; XXlV.10
IO'!J XX1V.6, 36
vyasth4 (scparaced) l.11; VII.2
11jiillr1a. a (indcccrmlnate) XVll.14'
11jiillhya111 (explained) Ill.:>, 9; X.15
11jiillhyiin11 (cxplanation) IV.9
'JUtsarga (rejeccion) Vlll. H
i11bda (sound) XXlll. 7
ft1ma (appea.scmcnr) XVIlf.2
Pl'fl XXl.17
i inltl (pcaccful) Vll.16; XVlll.9; XXII. 12
~gr11h11 (grasping
after-) XV. IO
Jiisl11'a (mcssage) X.16; XVlll.11
b11ddh11- (Buddha's-)XV.6; XXIV.9
anu (admonition) XVIll.8
I 'iisJr (teacher) XVll.31~ :XXV.10
Jir11Ja~ (head) Vll.31
fiw (auspicfous), Dcd.icatory Vc:rscs; V.8;
XXV.24
ftll/11 (pure) XVIJ.11
i11r;i (pleasant) XXlll.21- 22
11- (unpleasant) XXIII.22
finy11 (cmpty) XIII. 7; XVU.27; XX.16, 18;
XXl.9; XXll.10, 14; XXlll. 13-14;
XXIV. l, 13-14; XXV. 11 22
il (non) XIII. 7; XX. 16'-17; XXl.9;
XXIV.19-20, 33. 35, 39; X:XV.1
fiiny11m iri ("empty") XXIL 11
fil (cmptincss) IV.8-9; Xlll.2-3, 8;
XVIl.20; XVlll.5; XXIV.6-7, u,
B-14, 18, 22, 36-37
-14rtha (mcaning of>-) XXJV ,7
401
INDEX
XVll.6
11 (non) 1.6-7, 12: Vll.20 , 31;
Vlll.7-8, Il
-111111~11'!1 (substantiality) X.16
.Ja (existcoce) 1.10
-111'1 (scmiem bcing) XVI. I , 4-~
-bho11a (existcncc) XXJ.17; XXlV.6, 16
4bliii11a (nonexistencc) XXJ.17:
XXJll.n
-bhu111 (come to be , real) Jl . 24-2~;
Vlll. 1-2, 7. 9-1 I
1P-bhu111 Il.24-2) : VUJ. I, 3, 7, 9- ll
XXJV. ~
20, 30
samutpatia (arising)
pr11fity'1 (dcpc:ndcot-)(sec prRl1/ya)
samutiaya (arising) XXJV.22. 25, 40
402
Jlll'Pll
XVll.17-18,
~4;
XVlll.8; XXll.15;
XXVl-2, 24
Ariji ( acrivlcy) Vlll.6
-Rufi (view$) Xlll.8; XXVlI.30
-dh11fl'J'UI (things) Vll.29; XXV.22
-bhi1111 (-cxisrcncc) VU. 24; Xl.8,
XXVU.29
-Iw (-in the wodds) VII'. 11
s~111hi (everyway) ll. 14
111ha (with, togcthcr, simutancous,
coocomitant) Vl.3, JO; XI.5; XXI.I, 3,
5-6
(without) VI.10
J11habl:la1111 (co-existence) VI.4-9
iiiltrirb/t111111 (rcalizatioo) XXJV.'27
. iiill[ilt11rm11 XXIV.2
rjitlhaflll (proof, achicving) X .9; XVll.11
iiitlhyll (10 be provcd) IV.8
a- (iocorrigiblc) Xlll.8
iii11J11gfi (harmo.ny) XX. l-4, 7-8, 23-:Z4
proty11ya- (-of conditions) XX. 24
ltrttJ (made by-) XX. 24
sif!tpru'~ (slmultancous) IX. 12
iiirdhaf?J, (togct:hcr, jointly) X. lS; XIV.4;
11
XXl.20
pra- Vl.8
1u@T~(head)
Xlll.3
svay~ (self, oncself, own) X:Xlll.18
-ltiira ( -causing) Xll.9
krt11 (Ca\ISed) Xll,1-2, 4, 7-8
-maya (made of.) I. 13
11111rg11 (hcavcn) Vlll.6
VIJ.31
of
t1
VII.27; XIX.5
-bhiva vn.22
VERBAL FOR.MS
ajyate (mll,dc knowa) IX.5-6; XXV.16
ade1ayal ( taught) XXVII. 30
adhigamifjyaJi (will anaia) XXIV.32
lldhigamyale (is act:aincd) XXJV.10
anupaiy111i (perccive) XXIV. 16
apekfya (bcing eontingcnt} X.8- 12; XIX.1-2
llfl X.12; XIX.3; XXIIl.10-11
11bhiifala (has said) XID .1
abhipravarlale (procced) 1.12;
7' 9;
xvn,
XXVl,12
INDEX
abhi~11m,
9. 13
1111aiJi (comprchcnd) V.6
aga&&hati (comes) x.n
ag11rnj11 (dcpcncling upon) XXVl.3
iipnuyill (shoud reach) X. 7
arabhyate, ar11bhye111 (begun, initiated)
11.12- B
lfn'ty11, 1111 (not rcying) XXJV. IO
afffyeta (should 1cly) XV.10
403
ll11rute XXIV . 13
ulpay11 (woud thiaJc) XXIJ. 13
llramate (proc~ds) VJI. l}
g11&&ha1i (gOC$, movcs) 11.8-11. 22-25;
XXVl.1
pra 11.23
g11&&he1 X:XVll.19
gamyate li. 1, 4
grhyalt' (is observcd, is graspcd) XIX.5;
XXJll.15
grh~ati XXlll .15
urifyate XXIV.33
.uryat XJ I.7
dha/qyati (bums)
X .)
404
nirudhyllllii XVllJ.4
11iro11111 XX. 17-18
n1r.:lir11nti (posit) X .16
11itW1r111111 (produces) 1. 7
nirvll!Jllli (cease) X. 5
ni,-,#{y11111i (J will be free) XVI.9
"i!i&yote (is infuscd) XXVl.2
lllhof'!i!Joti (will destroy) vn. 11
pori.lllp11y11Se (umcclvc) Vl.8
prt1fa11P11Jemahi XXlll.10-ll
pra}noydle (is known) Xl. l
pra1i/J11dh11re (conmdicc) XXJV. 5- 6 , 17, 23,
36
x:xv
XXN.f.
Vll. IJ
prop!J11le X.5
prety11 (having gooc bcyond, in the nat life)
XVll.1.
m1"yan111xvr.5
m1Jcye111XXVl. 7
mn'yale (dies) XXl.20
mriy4l11 Xl.5
405
INDEX
V.2
llirlyPntll lX. ll
11itly11nte XXlll.2, 6: XXJV. 3
11itlya1 Vlll.13
vinasay1m1i (ruin) )Q{IV, 11
11ip11~y11ti (matures) XVU.25
111pr11f!ll!Jl1ti (pcrishes) XVll.21
vihavayet (should be critically cxamincd)
VJil. 13
11~/PSlltl
Jll'f?1b"411i!Jllli XXVll.29
s1111UU1hig11nl11f!J (to rcalizc) XXIV.28
J11m11<kti (uiscs) XXVU.6
s11m11tle!Jllle XXlV.22
111m11p111rity11 (bascd upon) XXJV.8
I11f!111irlyate (is cvidcot) 1.14; VIl.17
1ao/-111r111i (t1'11nsmigratc.s) XVI.2
St1f!Ullrt1trli XVI. l
JITf?11t1rify111i XVI. 2
saf?Uuroti (forms) XXVl. 10
sitlhy111i (is csrablishcd) Vl.B-9; XV.4-~ ;
XXJll.4; XXV.15
stilhyate X. l 0--11
sitlhy111ah XXIJl.3
1itftihyaum X .lO
406
Mroou;
wAy
GENERAL INDEX
INDEX
407
Dhammac11kkappa11alta1111-1111111 l-2.
Dham11iap4d.rJ 20, 54, 91.
dharma (dham._1714), Abh[dhanna concepcioo
of. 20-21, dharnt4.(ihatu 8; docuioe,
discourse 25, 329. 331. 392; foUI different
uscs 15-16; ethical 43 , 68, 88, U3, 183,
243. 257. 330, 335, 336, 340, 349, 366;
metaphysical 18, 19, 22-24, 32, 39. 77.
84. 141. 172 , 176. 177, 369; life
( ~ janman) 2)3, 275 ; nacurc ( = dh11rrnali)
55, 58 , 268, 269; ontological 4', 8, 12, 19.
21, 22, 24, ~4. '!>7. 40, 51. 55, 56, 67, 70,
71, 83-85, 90~ llO, 11, 132, 140-142. Ul,
153. 181, 217-220, 224, 234, 235. 273,
286, 288, .Hl, 336, 354, 390, (See also
unde( demcnrs.)
diffcrence (absolute, real, etc.) 12, 16, 23,
33, 40, 50, H. 29, 64, 76, 81, 92, 101 ,
106, 108, 111 , 116, 128, 129. 136. 137.
149. 160, 168, 182, 191, 192, 197. 199.
202, 211, 221. 225-228, 230, 231, 23~ ,
244. 2ts . _259. 262, 261, 273. 274, 276,
281, 284. 288, 289, 296, 304, 306-308,
310, 312, 360, 362. 365, 366, 381-385 ,
387.
disdples (rii11aka, ecc.) 2-4, 17, 19, n , 26,
31, 32. 79, 80, 90, 133. 23~. 236, 240,
243. 249. 250, 274, 292, 380, 387.
discrimination H, 56, 59, 88, 92, 126, U9,
143. 193. 266.
dispositions (sarrz.skiira, sllkhar11) io-12, 14,
18, 40, 46, 49. 65. 66, 72, 73, 82, 84, 138 ,
408
409
INDEX
no.
no.
410
objcct (cin!(1111y11,
11!f1J4.
V/! AV
Rath1111inlla-1111111 240.
reality 9 . U. 27, 44 , 49. 57- 59, 76. 82, 84,
85. 144, 152. 156. 163. 180, 181, 196.
213. 218, 220, 23()-232. 249, 2.59, 271,
n9. 310, 319, 330-334, 340, 352,
355. 37.5, 389; ultimatc: or absolutc
rcaJicy (p11TrJmii.r1ha) 16, 17. 19, 20, 66.
87. 189. 203, 268, 331. 3.H . 356. 361 ,
364. 366.
411
INDEX.
3, 4, 6, 24, 25 ,
174, 366.
Sarvasrivada i . 6, :H -25, 32, 36, 39, 41. 50.
52, 58, 62, 64. 67, 76, 77, 84, 85,
107. 109. 119, 127, 135. 141, 143. 156.
159-162 , 169, 170, 173, 182, 189. 196.
206, 225. 236, 256. 280, 288, 290, 296,
299. H 3, 349, 359. 367; Sarvinivadins
22, 25-28, 32, 34, 35, 38-40,
44, 50, H, 60, 62, 69, 77, 81, 84, 105,
106, n;, 119, 125, 120, 129. 134. 137.
U6, 160, 1n-116. 181, 196, 201. 213,
270, 276, 288, 298. 327, 338, 349. 366.
Sauuaocika 6, 22-28, 34-36, 41 , 44, 52, 54,
57. Go, 62, 67, 16,
81. 84, 05 , 106,
IB, 119, 125, 128, 129, 134, 141, 143.
U6, 159. 161 , 163-166, 168-170. 172176, 189, 194-196, 206, 207, 213, 236,
246-248 , 255, 256. 286, 286, 288, 290,
293 , 296. 299. 300. 301 , 332, 333. 338.
349, 355, 367, 383.
'self (almaf) 9. 14, 19. 20, 27, JO, 32, 39.
40. 44. 48, 51, 55, 56, 63-65. 67, 68, 74.
78,, 105, 180, 181, 191, 218, 262-264,
269, 303. 318, 380, 383 .
sclf-indulgencc l, 4, 90, 184.
sclf-mortification i, 18, 90. 91.
self-l)atOIC (J1JiJbliiifJa) 1,
23, 28, 32- 36,
38-40, 48-52, 55-57, 64, 67, 69. 71, 74,
76. 77, 80, 81-83, 88, 102, 107-110,
113, 114, 140,, 141 , 154, 160, 169. 212,
215, 220, 221, 225, 228-282. 191 , 240,
255 . i57. 258, 272. 280, 288, 298. 299.
302~304, 306-311, 313, Jl), 322, 324.
325, 339, 343- 351, 355. 357. 382.
sclf-tcsuainc 53, 90, 91 , 243.
sense expcricncc 12. 82, 83. 159, 219, 264,
316, (sec also undcr expcricnce)
space (ii.iiia) 36, 39. 68, 89, 131, 147-149,
Ul, 161.
Spnmg, Maivin 96, 154.
Stchcrcabsky, T.l. 23. 70,' ?5, 154. 183. 19~.
n.
n,
412
MrDOLE WAY
24, 240.
VitsTpuuiya 197, 195-197, 200, 202, 222,
230. 299.
Vigr11/J111ifiiw1r111irl 92.
Vinaya-pi/f1ll 4.
Ueda, Y 230.
ullimtlte retJllty (see umler re4'/1y).
undet/11reti questtons (1111yiilr1a-1111Jlu) 31.
Warder, A. K. 7, 95.
Wittgenstein, Lud'l(ig 93, 217.
wrong view 12, 13, 78.
Yogacira 7, 9, 37.
BANARSIDASS
PUBLISHERS PVT. LTD.
- - - Dellu (INDIA) - - E-mail: mlbdCvml.com
Wcbsite: www.mlbd.com
Rs.425
Code:0774x