0% found this document useful (0 votes)
62 views16 pages

Toon - Fictionalism and The Folk

This document discusses a theory of mental fictionalism proposed by Adam Toon. Mental fictionalism holds that while mental states like beliefs and desires may not exist, talking about them as if they do exist can be useful. The summary develops a version of this view drawing on Kendall Walton's theory of make-believe. According to this account, talk of mental states is a kind of pretense used to describe people and their behavior, rather than claims about actual internal states. The view aims to clarify how ordinary talk about the mind can be legitimate even if future science finds no real mental states exist.

Uploaded by

Krisztián Pete
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
62 views16 pages

Toon - Fictionalism and The Folk

This document discusses a theory of mental fictionalism proposed by Adam Toon. Mental fictionalism holds that while mental states like beliefs and desires may not exist, talking about them as if they do exist can be useful. The summary develops a version of this view drawing on Kendall Walton's theory of make-believe. According to this account, talk of mental states is a kind of pretense used to describe people and their behavior, rather than claims about actual internal states. The view aims to clarify how ordinary talk about the mind can be legitimate even if future science finds no real mental states exist.

Uploaded by

Krisztián Pete
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 16

The Monist, 2016, 99, 280–295

doi: 10.1093/monist/onw005
Article

Fictionalism and the Folk


Adam Toon*
ABSTRACT
Mental fictionalism is the view that, even if mental states do not exist, it is useful to
talk as if they do. Mental states are useful fictions. Recent philosophy of mind has seen
a growing interest in mental fictionalism. To date, much of the discussion has con-

Downloaded from http://monist.oxfordjournals.org/ by guest on October 10, 2016


cerned the general features of the approach. In this paper, I develop a specific form of
mental fictionalism by drawing on Kendall Walton’s work on make-believe. According
to the approach I propose, talk of mental states is a useful pretence for describing peo-
ple and their behaviour. I try to clarify and motivate this approach by comparing it to
well-known alternatives, including behaviourism, instrumentalism, and eliminativism. I
also consider some of the challenges that it faces.

1 . I N TR OD UC T IO N
How should we make sense of ordinary talk about the mind? When we say that
someone has a particular belief or desire, are we claiming that they have a certain
sort of causal state inside their heads? If we are, might future cognitive science show
that we are wrong? Might it turn out that mental states, like beliefs and desires, do
not exist? In this paper, I explore one way to approach these longstanding questions
concerning the status of folk psychology: mental fictionalism. Put simply, mental fic-
tionalism is the view that, even if mental states do not exist, it is useful to talk as if
they do. Mental states are useful fictions.
Recent philosophy of mind has seen a growing interest in mental fictionalism
(e.g., Wallace 2007; Demeter 2013a). To date, much of the discussion has concerned
the general features of this approach and the difficulties it faces.1 In this paper, I de-
velop a specific form of mental fictionalism by drawing on Kendall Walton’s work on
make-believe (Walton 1990, 1993). According to the account I will put forward,
when we say someone has a particular belief or desire, we are not making a claim
about their inner machinery. Instead, talk about mental states is a useful pretence for
describing people and their behaviour. As a result, the legitimacy of ordinary talk
about the mind does not depend upon whether future cognitive science will discover
beliefs or desires inside our heads.
The structure of the paper is as follows. First, in Section 2, I give a brief outline of
Walton’s theory, focusing on his discussion of metaphor and prop-oriented make-

* University of Exeter

C The Author 2016. Published by Oxford University Press on behalf of The Hegeler Institute.
V
All rights reserved. For permissions, please e-mail: [email protected]

 280
Fictionalism and the Folk  281

believe. In Section 3, I show how we may draw on Walton’s analysis to develop a fic-
tionalist analysis of folk psychology. In Section 4, I further clarify and motivate this
account by comparing it to a number of well-known alternative positions, including
behaviourism, instrumentalism, and eliminativism, as well as alternative forms of fic-
tionalism. Finally, in Section 5, I consider some important challenges facing mental
fictionalism.

2. PRO P-O RI EN TE D M AKE- BE LI E VE


Imagine some children playing with a doll. They pick the doll up and hold it in their
arms, push it down the hallway in a pushchair, cover it with a blanket, and so on. As
they do so, the children imagine themselves picking up a baby and cradling it, taking
it to the shops and lying it down in its cot to go to sleep. In Walton’s theory, dolls

Downloaded from http://monist.oxfordjournals.org/ by guest on October 10, 2016


and other objects used in make-believe are called props and the rules that govern
their use in the game are called principles of generation (Walton 1990). Within a game
of make-believe, the properties of the props, together with the relevant principles of
generation, make propositions fictional. To say that a proposition is fictional, in
Walton’s sense, is simply to say that participants in the game are prescribed to imag-
ine it. For example, if the doll’s “eyes” are closed, the children are to imagine that the
baby is asleep. It is fictional that the baby is asleep. Notice that, since the content of
a game of make-believe depends only on the props and principles of generation, it
possesses a certain kind of “objectivity”: if the doll’s eyes are closed then it is fictional
that the baby is asleep, even if none of the children happen to notice this.
One important feature of games of make-believe is participation. Children playing
with a doll do not simply sit and look at it. Instead, they carry out various actions
with the doll (e.g., putting a bottle to its “mouth”) and these actions generate imagin-
ings within the game (e.g., that the children are feeding the baby). Like the doll, the
children themselves become props in the game. The children also participate ver-
bally. For example, David might sing a lullaby as he rocks the doll in his arms,
thereby making it fictional that he is singing a lullaby to get the baby to sleep.
Importantly, acts of pretence can be used to make genuine assertions. Suppose that
Anna looks at the doll and says “She’s sleeping now!” When she says this, Anna pre-
tends to assert that the baby is asleep. But she also indicates that pretending in this
way is appropriate and, in doing so, makes a genuine assertion: she claims that the
state of the props is such that to pretend in the way that she does is, fictionally, to
speak the truth. In other words, Anna claims that the doll’s “eyes” are closed. Once
again, notice the objectivity of games: if, in fact, the doll’s “eyes” are open, then
Anna’s pretence is inappropriate and her assertion is false.2
The reason that children play with dolls, it seems, is not because they are inter-
ested in the properties of the doll as such. Dolls are interesting only in so far as they
allow the children to immerse themselves in a make-believe world in which they can
cradle a baby, take it out in its pushchair, feed it or rock it to sleep. Walton (1993)
calls this kind of make-believe content oriented. He distinguishes it from a rather
282  Fictionalism and the Folk

different use of make-believe, which he calls prop oriented. Walton’s central examples
of prop oriented make-believe are cases of metaphor or figurative language:

Where in Italy is the town of Crotone?, I ask. You explain that it is on the arch
of the Italian boot. ‘See the thundercloud over there—the big angry face near
the horizon,’ you say; ‘it is headed this way’. Plumbers and electricians distin-
guish between ‘male’ and ‘female’ plumbing and electrical connections. We
speak of the saddle of a mountain and the shoulder of a highway.
All of these cases are linked to make-believe. We think of Italy and the thun-
dercloud as something like pictures. Italy (or a map of Italy) depicts a boot.
The cloud is a prop which makes it fictional that there is an angry face. Male

Downloaded from http://monist.oxfordjournals.org/ by guest on October 10, 2016


and female plumbing or electrical connections are understood to be, fictionally,
male and female sexual organs. The saddle of a mountain is, fictionally, a
horse’s saddle. But our interest, in these instances, is not in the make-believe it-
self, and it is not for the sake of games of make-believe that we regard these
things as props. [. . .]
Make-believe [. . .] is useful in these cases [. . .] for articulating, remembering,
and communicating facts about the props—about the geography of Italy, or
the identity of the storm cloud, or functional properties of plumbing or electri-
cal fixtures, or mountain topography. It is by thinking of Italy or the thunder-
cloud or plumbing connections as potential if not actual props that I under-
stand where Crotone is, which cloud is the one being talked about, or whether
one pipe can be connected to another. (Walton 1993, 40–41)
In content oriented make-believe, our interest lies in the content of a make-believe
world. By contrast, in prop oriented make-believe, our interest lies in the props
themselves; the role of make-believe is to help us to understand the props. Despite
the difference between these forms of make-believe, Walton’s analysis of utterances
involving prop oriented make-believe parallels his analysis of utterances in the chil-
dren’s game. If Mark says “Crotone is on the arch of the Italian boot,” he is involved
in pretence, much like Anna when she looks at the doll’s eyes and exclaims “She’s
sleeping now!” And yet, just like Anna, Mark also makes a genuine assertion: he
claims that the state of the props is such that to pretend in the way that he does is,
fictionally, to speak the truth. In other words, Mark asserts that Crotone is in such-
and-such a position on the Italian coastline. Invoking a familiar game of make-believe
in which Italy is imagined to be a boot provides him with a more colourful and mem-
orable way of communicating this fact.
Walton’s theory has been influential amongst fictionalists in many domains (e.g.,
Crimmins 1998; Joyce 2005; Kroon 2001; Yablo 2001). In the next section, I show
how it can be used to develop a form of mental fictionalism.

3. FOLK PSYCHOLOGY AS FICTION


I now want to suggest that we should understand ordinary talk about mental states
in terms of pretence. One way to introduce this idea involves a twist on Wilfrid
Fictionalism and the Folk  283

Sellars’s famous myth about the origin of talk about mental states (Sellars 1956; cf.
Yablo 2005). Sellars asks us to imagine a society who at first use only what he calls a
“Rylean language” that is restricted to terms referring to overt behaviour. At some
point, along comes a visionary theorist, called Jones, who develops a theory of inter-
nal, psychological episodes, which he dubs thoughts. Jones bases his theory of
thoughts on the model of overt verbal behaviour. However, like all models, Jones’s
model is accompanied by a commentary specifying which of the features of its source
domain (overt verbal behaviour) are to be carried over to its target domain (internal
psychological states). For example, Jones is clear that his theory doesn’t claim that
there is any hidden tongue that produces inner speech or that inner speech can be
heard. Using his theory, Jones is then able to predict and explain the complexity of
people’s behaviour in a way that the Rylean language could not.

Downloaded from http://monist.oxfordjournals.org/ by guest on October 10, 2016


With Sellars’s story in mind, I want to propose an alternative, fictionalist, myth.
According to this myth, what Jones introduces to our Rylean ancestors is not a theory,
but a useful game of prop oriented make-believe. Jones invents a game in which we
are supposed to imagine that people undergo inner episodes, called thoughts, which
are analogous to overt verbal behaviour. These inner episodes respond to experience,
interact in certain ways and cause certain behaviours. According to this alternative
myth, Jones still takes overt verbal behaviour as his model for thoughts. But the com-
mentary he offers on this model is very different from that envisaged by Sellars. In the
fictionalist telling of the tale, Jones no more claims that he is committed to the exis-
tence of these episodes of inner speech than he claims that they are uttered by a hid-
den tongue. Instead, the entire model is proposed merely as a useful metaphor for
describing people and their behaviour. Thoughts are not theoretical entities of a new
theory of the mind, but useful fictions.
We can now fill out our fictionalist myth using Walton’s analysis. Folk psychology of-
fers a fruitful and productive game through which we can make sense of people and their
behaviour, in much the same way that the Italian boot is a useful game for understanding
the geography of Italy. Ordinary talk about mental states should be understood along
the same lines as an utterance like “Crotone is on the arch of the Italian boot.” As we
saw in Section 2, on Walton’s analysis, when Mark says this he is not making a straight-
forward assertion; his utterance is an act of pretence. And yet, by pretending in this way,
he does make a genuine assertion, namely that the location of Crotone is such that, fic-
tionally, he speaks the truth. I suggest that we understand ordinary talk about mental
states in a similar manner. Suppose that Ruth says “John believes that planes can fly.”
When she says this, I suggest, Ruth is not making a straightforward assertion; her utter-
ance is an act of pretence. And yet, by pretending in this way, Ruth does make a genuine
assertion, namely that John is in some state S such that, fictionally, she speaks the truth.
Invoking the game in which Italy is imagined to be a boot provides Mark with a useful
means for describing the location of Crotone. Similarly, invoking the game of folk psy-
chology provides Ruth with a useful means for describing John and his behaviour.
On this view, then, ordinary talk about the mind involves acts of pretence within
a folk psychological game of make-believe. Within this game, we are to imagine that
people have certain inner states inside their heads, such as beliefs and desires. We are
also to imagine that these states arise in certain circumstances, interact in certain
284  Fictionalism and the Folk

sorts of ways, and produce certain sorts of behaviour. We can capture some of the
rules of the folk psychological game in various truisms. If someone is looking at an
object in good light, then normally we are to imagine that they have a particular in-
ner state (a belief) which says that there is an object in front of them. If someone
hasn’t eaten anything all day, then normally we are to imagine that they have a differ-
ent sort of inner state (a desire) which says they should eat something. In general,
however, the rules of the folk psychological game are notoriously difficult to specify.
This need not pose a particular problem for the fictionalist, however. After all, the
rules governing children’s games are rarely explicitly formulated.
Why might someone be attracted to mental fictionalism? The most familiar moti-
vation for fictionalism is a worry about ontological commitment (Wallace 2007).
Thus, the fictionalist might be persuaded by various arguments for eliminativism

Downloaded from http://monist.oxfordjournals.org/ by guest on October 10, 2016


about mental states (e.g., Churchland 1981; Ramsey, Stich, and Garon 1990). And
yet she might also worry that we cannot do without folk psychological talk. The fic-
tionalist therefore aims to show how we can keep such talk around without being
committed to the existence of mental states. There is also a rather different motiva-
tion for turning to mental fictionalism, however. Rather than being persuaded by ar-
guments for eliminativism, the fictionalist might primarily be interested in making
sense of our ordinary talk about the mind. When we examine such talk closely, she
might argue, we find that it is best understood in fictionalist terms: despite appear-
ances to the contrary, in fact the folk are not committed to the existence of beliefs
and desires as discrete inner causes of behaviour; instead, folk discourse treats these
entities as useful fictions. A fictionalist who takes this approach endorses a hermeneu-
tic, rather than revolutionary, fictionalism (Stanley 2001): she presents fictionalism as
a descriptive claim about folk discourse, rather than a prescription for how that dis-
course should be reinterpreted.
Tentatively, I wish to propose mental fictionalism as a hermeneutic fictionalism.
Of course, folk discourse is complex and nuanced, and it might be difficult to capture
this complexity in any single account (Dennett 1987; Godfrey-Smith 2005).
Nevertheless, I want to suggest that a fictionalist analysis captures the spirit of much
of our ordinary talk about mental states. The guiding motivation behind this ap-
proach is familiar from behaviourist or instrumentalist approaches in general: the le-
gitimacy of ordinary talk about the mind does not depend upon speculation about
the machinery inside people’s heads. The fictionalist analysis of ordinary folk dis-
course requires further defence, however. After all, it might be argued, when we at-
tribute beliefs and desires to people, we don’t normally feel as if we are pretending
or engaging in a game of make-believe. I return to this objection in Section 5. First,
however, I hope to clarify and motivate the fictionalist view in more detail by com-
paring it to a number of well-known alternative approaches to folk psychology.

4. CONTRASTS
4.1 Behaviourism
First, let us compare fictionalism to behaviourism.3 Like fictionalism, behaviourism
also claims that ordinary talk about the mind is not committed to the existence of
Fictionalism and the Folk  285

beliefs and desires as inner causal states. However, the behaviourist tries to avoid
commitment to such internal states by giving a reductive analysis of mental talk in
terms of behaviour. Thus, to say that John wants to go to Madrid is not to describe
any state inside his head; it is to describe his tendencies in various circumstances: if
he were browsing through travel guides, he would reach for the guide to Madrid; if
he were in the airport, he would catch the plane for Madrid, and so on. The key
problem for behaviourism, of course, is that filling out such analyses proves to be ex-
tremely difficult. The main reason for the failure of this project, it seems, is that there
is no straightforward, one-to-one correspondence between individual mental states
and behavioural dispositions. Instead, the behaviour that results from any individual
mental state typically depends on many other mental states. John’s desire to go to
Madrid will only lead him to catch a plane for Madrid if he also believes that planes

Downloaded from http://monist.oxfordjournals.org/ by guest on October 10, 2016


fly, that the plane at the gate will take him to Madrid, and so on.
Along with the behaviourist, the hermeneutic fictionalist also argues that folk psy-
chology is not committed to the existence of beliefs and desires as inner causal states.
The key difference between fictionalism and behaviourism, however, is that the fic-
tionalist does not try to avoid ontological commitment by giving a reductive analysis
of mental state attributions in terms of behaviour. Instead, at least on the version of
mental fictionalism I have proposed, Ruth’s utterance “John believes that planes can
fly” means exactly what the realist about mental states takes it to mean: it means that
there is a particular internal state inside John’s head with certain characteristic causes
and effects. The reason that Ruth is not committed to the existence of such entities,
according to the fictionalist, is simply because her utterance is not a straightforward
assertion; instead, it is an act of pretence. Similarly, if we say, “Crotone is on the arch
of the Italian boot” our utterance means the same as if we were (oddly enough) to
claim that there really was an enormous boot floating in the Mediterranean. Within
the context of the game, however, our utterance is recognised as pretence (Walton
1990, 1993; Yablo 1998).
Our pretence involving the Italian boot allows us to make a genuine assertion re-
garding the location of Crotone. Similarly, Ruth’s pretence regarding John’s inner
states allows her to make a genuine assertion regarding John and his behaviour.
There is an important difference between the two cases, however. In the case of the
Italian boot, the use of make-believe is dispensable. We can offer an alternative, literal
paraphrase that captures the assertion we make about Crotone: we are claiming that
Crotone lies on the southern coast of Italy, somewhere roughly between Capo
Colonna and Taranto. Not all metaphors can be given a literal paraphrase, however.
Thus, Stephen Yablo notes the possibility that

the language might have no more to offer in the way of a unifying principle for
the worlds in a given content than that they are the ones making the relevant
sentence fictional. It seems at least an open question, for example, whether
clouds we call angry are the ones that are literally F, for any F other than ‘such
that it would be natural and proper to regard them as angry if one were going
to attribute emotions to clouds’. (1998, 250)
286  Fictionalism and the Folk

Yablo calls metaphors that resist literal paraphrase representationally essential (1998,
250; see also Walton 1993). For the fictionalist, the failure of the behaviourist project
suggests that the metaphors of folk psychology are representationally essential. If we
say John wants to go to Madrid, we are saying that he is in some state S such that it
is appropriate to pretend in this way. There are indefinitely many different forms of
behaviour that might make this pretence appropriate: running eagerly to board a
plane (because he believes it will take him to Madrid); taking the ferry to Santander
and then the train (because he is scared of flying); wistfully thumbing through travel
brochures (because he believes he can’t afford to go to Madrid); and so on. Each of
these counts as a situation in which the rules of folk psychology make it fictional that
John desires to go to Madrid. And yet, just as there might be no way of capturing
what is common to all clouds we call “angry” (apart from that they each make it fic-

Downloaded from http://monist.oxfordjournals.org/ by guest on October 10, 2016


tional that they are angry), so there might be no way of capturing what is common
to each of these forms of behaviour (apart from that they each make it fictional that
John desires to go to Madrid). The problems faced by behaviourism thus turn out to
be an instance of a more general phenomenon, namely the difficulty of giving a literal
paraphrase for metaphors and figurative language.

4.2 Instrumentalism
It is also helpful to compare fictionalism to instrumentalism. Instrumentalism can be
characterised in a number of different ways. Intentional systems theory aims to capture
the principles underlying our ordinary belief and desire attributions (Dennett 1987).
According to David Braddon-Mitchell and Frank Jackson, instrumentalism is the
view that “[t]here is nothing more to being a believer and a desirer, a thing with be-
liefs and desires, than being a being whose behaviour is well predicted by [intentional
systems theory].” Thus, the instrumentalist claims that

‘S believes P and desires Q’ is true iff (a) the behaviour of S is well predicted
by intentional systems theory, and (b) the best belief and desire hypotheses ac-
cording to the principles of intentional systems theory for predicting S’s behav-
iour are that S believes P and desires Q. (2007, 159)
An important challenge for instrumentalism is provided by the Blockhead thought
experiment (Block 1981). Suppose Blockhead’s behaviour matches our own, but its
inner machinery involves a giant ‘look-up’ table determining its response to each pos-
sible input. Intuitively, it seems, we would not count Blockhead as a genuine thinker.
And yet, if all we mean when we say that someone has beliefs or desires is that their
behaviour can be predicted by intentional systems theory, then instrumentalism can-
not account for this intuition. As Braddon-Mitchell and Jackson (2007, 163) observe,
fictionalism can avoid this worry by rejecting the instrumentalist’s semantic thesis.
We have seen already that the fictionalist takes an utterance like “John believes that
planes can fly” to mean what the realist does: taken literally, it claims that there is
a particular sort of internal state inside John’s head. As a result, fictionalism can
account for our intuitions regarding Blockhead: if Blockhead does not possess the
right sort of internal machinery, then he doesn’t count as a true believer. To be a
Fictionalism and the Folk  287

true believer one would have to have a certain internal organisation, which
Blockhead lacks. As Braddon-Mitchell and Jackson see it, by developing along fic-
tionalist lines,

instrumentalism is no longer the comfortably uncommitted doctrine it pre-


sented itself as: a cautious refusal to traffic in speculation about what goes on
inside us. The only viable option turns out to be a version of the radical thesis
that all ascriptions of belief and desire are false. (2007, 164).
But, as I understand her, the fictionalist can remain agnostic regarding whether we
humans have the required internal organisation to count as genuine believers. She
simply insists that, regardless of whether we have this internal organisation or not, it

Downloaded from http://monist.oxfordjournals.org/ by guest on October 10, 2016


is useful to talk as if we do.
Daniel Dennett is often taken to be the leading proponent of instrumentalism. Of
course, Dennett himself has rejected the label “instrumentalism” for his position, as
well as “fictionalism” (Dennett 1987, 1991). Despite this, I think that the version of
mental fictionalism that I have proposed shares interesting similarities to Dennett’s
view, and that it offers a way to interpret aspects of Dennett’s position that critics
have found problematic. For example, Dennett (1987, 72) distances himself from fic-
tionalism, which he takes to be the claim that theoretical statements are useful false-
hoods. And he also denies that talk about mental states is neither true nor false.
Instead, Dennett argues, talk about beliefs and desires can be true, although this is a
truth which “one must understand with a grain of salt” (1981, 72–73, emphasis in
original). To explain this idea, Dennett draws a parallel with centres of gravity:

I should have forsworn the term [instrumentalism] and just said something
like this: My ism is whatever ism serious realists adopt with regard to centres of
gravity and the like, since I think beliefs [. . .] are like that—in being abstracta
rather than part of the “furniture of the physical world” and in being attributed
in statements that are true only if we exempt them from a certain familiar stan-
dard of literality. (1981, 72)
Thus, Dennett suggests, claims about beliefs and claims about centres of gravity can
both count as true, even if neither beliefs nor centres of gravity exist. The analysis I
introduced in Section 3 offers a way to make sense of this idea (cf. Hutto 2013).
When we say that a system has certain centre of gravity, we pretend that its mass is
located at a certain point. Taken literally, this is false. And yet, when we attribute a
centre of gravity to a system, we also make a genuine assertion: we claim that the sys-
tem’s mass is distributed such that it is appropriate to pretend that all the mass is lo-
cated at a particular point. And this claim can be straightforwardly true. Similarly,
when we claim that someone has a certain belief, we pretend that they have a particu-
lar inner state. Taken literally, this is (or might be) false. And yet, when we attribute
a belief, we also make a genuine assertion: we claim that they are in a particular state
such that is appropriate to pretend in this way. And this claim can be straightfor-
wardly true.
288  Fictionalism and the Folk

Notably, Dennett also insists that, although beliefs and desires might not exist,
the patterns picked out by the intentional stance are nevertheless entirely real, objec-
tive features of the world (Dennett 1987, 1991). Moreover, Dennett argues, these
patterns would be overlooked by Martians who knew all there was to know about
the physical world, but failed to adopt the intentional stance. Once again, I think that
a fictionalist analysis can help us to understand how this might be the case. Suppose
that we say “the clouds over Exeter were angry all day.” There are no (literally) angry
clouds. And yet when we say this we might capture an entirely real, objective feature
of the world: the fact that the clouds over Exeter on a particular day were such that
our pretence is appropriate. And if describing clouds as angry is a metaphor that re-
sists literal paraphrase—that is, if we are unable to give a description in the language
of the physical world that specifies what it is that all clouds that we would fictionally

Downloaded from http://monist.oxfordjournals.org/ by guest on October 10, 2016


count as angry have in common—then the pattern exhibited by clouds over Exeter
today might be inaccessible to someone who doesn’t recognise this particular game.
Similarly, even if beliefs and desires do not exist, pretending that they do might allow
us to pick out perfectly real and objective features of the world. And if talk of beliefs
and desires is a metaphor that resists literal paraphrase—that is, if we are unable to
give a description in the language of the physical world that specifies what it is that
all people who count as possessing a particular belief or desire have in common—
then these patterns might be overlooked by beings that did not take part in the game
of folk psychology.

4.3 Prefix-fictionalism
Many discussions of mental fictionalism focus mainly on a version of the approach
that we might call prefix-fictionalism (Armour-Garb and Woodbridge 2015). On this
view, utterances such as “John believes that planes can fly” are taken to be elliptical
for prefixed claims like “In the folk psychological fiction, John believes that planes
can fly” (Wallace 2007; Parent 2013). By contrast, I have proposed a form of pre-
tence-fictionalism (Armour-Garb and Woodbridge 2015): talk about mental states
should be understood as an act of pretence, rather than involving an implicit prefix.
While both prefix and pretence versions of mental fictionalism try to avoid commit-
ment to mental states, they offer different analyses of folk psychological talk. In this
section, I argue that we ought to prefer the pretence form of mental fictionalism.
The prefix form of mental fictionalism is a version of what Yablo (2001) calls
meta-fictionalism: according to the prefix-fictionalist, utterances that appear to be
about people’s mental states turn out to be claims about the contents of a particular
theory, namely folk psychology (see also Eklund 2007). Yablo (2001, 75–76) pre-
sents a number of challenges for meta-fictionalism, focusing primarily on mathemati-
cal fictionalism. First, Yablo argues, meta-fictionalism has problems dealing with
modal claims. We regard claims like “2 þ 2¼4” as necessarily true. According to the
prefix-fictionalist, however, when we say “2 þ 2¼4” we are claiming that “In standard
mathematics, 2 þ 2¼4.” And yet, arguably, this claim is not necessarily true, since
standard mathematics might perhaps have turned out differently. Second, Yablo ar-
gues that meta-fictionalism faces “problems of concern.” Suppose that we say “the
number of starving people is large and rising.” When we say this, what we care about
Fictionalism and the Folk  289

is people and their desperate situation. And yet, according to the prefix-fictionalist,
what we are really talking about is the content of standard mathematics. Third, Yablo
raises a related, phenomenological worry. When we say “the number of starving peo-
ple is large and rising,” we do not feel remotely as if we are talking about the content
of standard mathematics; instead, we feel that we are talking about people.
Each of these difficulties confronts prefix versions of mental fictionalism. First,
consider modality (cf. Wallace 2007, 20–21). Of course, unlike a claim like
“2 þ 2¼4,” we don’t take attributions such as “John believes that planes can fly” to
be necessarily true. And yet prefix-fictionalism still seems to run into difficulties here.
Consider a possible world in which folk psychology turned out differently (perhaps
our visionary Jones never lived, or took a different model as the inspiration for his
revolutionary account of people’s behaviour). According to prefix-fictionalism, in

Downloaded from http://monist.oxfordjournals.org/ by guest on October 10, 2016


such a scenario, a claim such as “John believes that planes can fly” would be false,
even if all of the facts about John and his aeroplane-related behaviour were exactly
the same. This seems wrong: intuitively, I think, we should still count this as a world
in which John believes that planes can fly. Or, to take another example, suppose that
we grant that, since Freud’s work, the notion of unconscious desires has become part
of folk psychology. Again, it seems wrong to say that, had Freud never written, then
all of our attributions of unconscious desires would be false. Second, consider the
problem of concern. When we talk about people’s mental lives (rather than, say, dis-
cuss philosophy of mind), what we care about are the people we are talking about,
not the contents of folk psychological theory. Finally, when we say “John wants to
go to Madrid” or “John wants a new job,” it certainly feels as if we are talking about
John, not about the way the folk talk about John.
The pretence version of mental fictionalism avoids these worries. On the analysis
I have proposed, attributions of mental states are not claims about the contents of
folk psychological theory; instead, they are acts of pretence that serve to make claims
about people and their behaviour. This allows the pretence fictionalist to respond to
each of the difficulties facing prefix fictionalism. If we say (correctly) that “John be-
lieves that planes can fly,” the claim we make is true in virtue of facts concerning
John and his behaviour. If the contents of folk psychology were to change while the
facts about John remained the same, then our claim would still be true. Similarly, our
attributions of unconscious desires would retain their present truth values, even if
Freud had never written. And the pretence-fictionalist has no problem explaining
why it is that, when we attribute mental states to John, it is John himself that we care
about and whom we feel we are talking about: according to the pretence analysis,
that is precisely what we are doing, although we do so via the use of pretence.
The pretence version of mental fictionalism also avoids a further difficulty con-
fronting prefix-fictionalism. As we have seen, the prefix-fictionalist claims that talk
about mental states is talk about a folk psychological fiction. The guiding analogy
here, of course, is with an utterance such as “Holmes smokes a pipe” which, accord-
ing to prefix-fictionalism, is short for “In the Sherlock Holmes stories, Holmes
smokes a pipe.”4 And yet there seems to be an important difference between the two
cases. After all, it is clear which fiction underpins our talk about Sherlock Holmes:
we can point to our copy of Conan Doyle’s stories. But there is no text that sets out
290  Fictionalism and the Folk

the principles of folk psychology. Indeed, as we saw earlier, such principles are noto-
riously difficult to formulate explicitly. In this respect, mental fictionalism might
seem to be in a worse position than fictionalism in other domains. For example,
Gideon Rosen’s (1990) modal fictionalism is able to draw on David Lewis’s On the
Plurality of Worlds (1986) to set out its guiding fiction. Of course, there are ways
that the prefix fictionalist might try to respond to this worry (see Wallace 2007,
9–11). For our purposes, the important point is that the problem does not arise for
pretence fictionalism. All the pretence fictionalist requires is that we have a reason-
ably coherent set of rule-governed practices for attributing mental states to people
based on their behaviour. It does not require that we are able to distil any folk psy-
chological principles or laws by reflecting on those practices. Indeed, as we noted
above, the rules of most make-believe games—even children’s games with dolls—are

Downloaded from http://monist.oxfordjournals.org/ by guest on October 10, 2016


complex and difficult to formulate explicitly.

4.4 Eliminativism
Finally, let us compare fictionalism to eliminativism. Eliminativists claim that mental
states, like beliefs and desires, do not exist. The eliminativist might offer various argu-
ments for this claim: she might argue that folk psychology is a bad theory
(Churchland 1981), for example, or that it stands fundamentally at odds with partic-
ular developments in cognitive science (Ramsey, Stich and Garon 1990). As we have
seen, the fictionalist need not follow the eliminativist in denying the existence of
mental states; instead, she might remain agnostic on the matter. The distinctive fea-
ture of fictionalism is that it allows us to grant that, even if mental states do not exist,
we can nevertheless continue talking as if they do. This represents a clear advantage
of fictionalism over eliminativism. Abandoning talk about beliefs, desires, and other
mental states would require an enormously dramatic and far-reaching transformation
in our language. The fictionalist aims to show that the legitimacy of ordinary talk
about the mind does not depend upon beliefs and desires finding a place in the theo-
ries of future cognitive science.
Why talk about mental states if they don’t exist? According to the fictionalist,
such talk shares the advantages of metaphorical and figurative language more gener-
ally. We have seen already that metaphors can allow us to make claims that we are
unable to express in a straightforward literal description. But metaphorical and figura-
tive language also brings further advantages. Metaphors introduce a “framing effect”
(Moran 1989; see also Demeter 2013b): we are asked to “see” our primary subject
(e.g., Italy, clouds) in terms of a secondary subject (e.g., a boot, emotions)
(Beardsley 1962; see also Hills 2011). This yields a host of different cognitive bene-
fits. Metaphorical claims are often especially vivid and memorable, for example, and
prompt a range of further inferences about their primary subject. Consider the meta-
phor of theories as buildings (Lakoff and Johnson 1980). If we are told that someone
is hard at work constructing a new theory, we are immediately led to wonder what
the theory’s foundations are, whether it requires further support, whether it will ulti-
mately stand or fall, and so on. By asking us to see people’s behaviour as the product
of inner states interacting in various ways, folk psychology introduces an enormously
powerful framing effect. It provides us with a way of describing people and their
Fictionalism and the Folk  291

behaviour that is vivid and memorable (e.g., “John had an overwhelming desire to go
to Madrid”), prompts us to make a range of further inferences (e.g., “if John thinks
there’s any way he can get to Madrid, he’ll take it”), allows us to contrast different
people’s behaviour in new ways (“Ruth’s desire to go to Madrid is nowhere near as
strong as John’s”), and so on. The key point, according to the fictionalist, is that folk
psychology can possess these virtues even if there are no beliefs or desires.

5 . C H A LL EN G E S
I now turn to consider some objections to mental fictionalism. Each of these repre-
sents an important challenge facing the position, and I cannot hope to do justice to
them properly here. But I hope at least to show that these objections need not be fa-
tal and to indicate some possible lines of response.

Downloaded from http://monist.oxfordjournals.org/ by guest on October 10, 2016


The first, and most obvious, challenge concerns the phenomenology of talk about
the mental (Wallace 2007; see also Eklund 2007). As we noted earlier, we don’t nor-
mally feel as if we are engaging in pretence when we attribute mental states. When
we say “John believes planes can fly” or “John wants to go to Madrid,” we don’t feel
as if we are engaging in make-believe; we feel as if we are making a straightforward
assertion about John. Of course, one response to this worry is to endorse a revolu-
tionary fictionalism. But there are also ways that we might look to defend hermeneu-
tic fictionalism against this objection. The first point to stress is one made a number
of times already: on the pretence version of mental fictionalism, mental state attribu-
tions are used to make genuine assertions about people and their behaviour, albeit
via pretence. Moreover, we need not insist that the folk pretend in the same manner
as children participate in their games; for example, perhaps they merely indicate the
relevant pretence, without engaging in it (Walton 1990, 1993).
More positively, the fictionalist might point out that we often don’t notice when
we are speaking metaphorically, especially when metaphors are familiar to us (Yablo
2000; see also Eklund 2007). Once we reflect more closely on our talk about mental
states, she might argue, we see that it bears striking similarities to metaphorical lan-
guage. To support this claim, the fictionalist can draw on some well-known argu-
ments for instrumentalism. For example, Yablo (2000) notes that objects invoked in
make-believe have problematic identity conditions (e.g., “is the fuse you blew last
week the same as the one you blew today?”). In a similar vein, Dennett notes that
“common intuition does not give us a stable answer to such puzzles as whether the
belief that 3 is greater than 2 is none other than the belief that 2 is less than 3”
(1987, 55). Another characteristic feature of metaphors is that they invite “silly ques-
tions” (e.g., “What species is the monkey on your back?”). Many realist questions
about mental states, I suggest, also strike us as silly questions (e.g., “Where exactly is
John’s belief about planes? Is it to the right or left of his desire to go to Madrid?”).
The mental fictionalist might also support her interpretation of folk discourse by ap-
pealing to an “Oracle argument” (Eklund 2007). Yablo (2000) offers the following argu-
ment in support of fictionalism about abstract objects. Suppose an omniscient Oracle
told you that there are no abstract objects. Would you stop saying things like “2 þ 3¼5”?
Arguably not. Instead, you would go on talking exactly as before. If that’s right, then it
seems that such talk did not commit you to the existence of abstract objects in the first
292  Fictionalism and the Folk

place. Again, the fictionalist might draw on familiar instrumentalist themes to mount a
similar argument in defence of mental fictionalism. Thus, Dennett (1987) writes:

[s]uppose, for the sake of drama, that it turns out that the sub-personal cogni-
tive psychology of some people turns out to be dramatically different from that
of others. One can imagine the newspaper headlines: “Scientists Prove Most
Left-handers Incapable of Belief” or “Startling Discovery—Diabetics Have No
Desires.” But this is not what we would say, no matter how the science turns
out.
And our reluctance would not be just conceptual conservativism, but the rec-
ognition of an obvious empirical fact. For let left- and right-handers (or men

Downloaded from http://monist.oxfordjournals.org/ by guest on October 10, 2016


and women or any other subsets of people) be as internally different as you
like, we already know that there are reliable, robust patterns in which all behav-
iourally normal people participate—the patterns we traditionally describe in
terms of belief and desire and the other terms of folk psychology. (1987, 235)
Like the eliminativist, the fictionalist can agree that the scenario that Dennett de-
scribes is possible: it might turn out that people do not literally have beliefs or desires
inside their heads. And yet, even if scientists were to make such a startling discovery,
the fictionalist argues, folk psychological talk would continue unabated. What this
shows is that talk about mental states serves a different purpose, which doesn’t de-
pend on the existence of mental states as inner causes, namely providing a valuable
metaphor for identifying patterns in behaviour.
A second important objection to mental fictionalism is that it cannot account for
the fact that mental states appear in causal explanation (cf. Sprevak 2013). If we say
“John’s desire to go to Madrid caused him to spend all his savings,” we appear to cite
a mental state as the cause of John’s behaviour. And yet, if mental states are fictions,
it seems that they cannot be causes. Is this a serious difficulty for the fictionalist?
Consider other uses of metaphor in causal explanations. Suppose we say “the angry
clouds caused Ruth to fetch her umbrella.” Following Walton’s analysis it seems that,
when we say this, we are saying that the clouds were in a certain state S—whatever it
is—such that, fictionally, we speak the truth, and this state S caused Ruth to fetch
her umbrella. Even if there are no angry clouds, it is arguable that this is still a genu-
ine causal explanation. Similarly, if we say “John’s desire to go to Madrid caused him
to spend all his savings,” we are claiming that John is in a certain state S—whatever
it is—such that, fictionally, we speak the truth, and this state S caused him to spend
all his savings. Once again, even if there are no desires, it is arguable that this is still
a genuine causal explanation. But, of course, it falls far short of the idea that folk
psychological explanations pick out discrete inner causes of behaviour, and there is
certainly much more to be said here (for a related discussion, see Dennett [1987,
56–57]).
Finally, and perhaps most worryingly, a critic might argue that mental fictionalism
is incoherent (e.g., Wallace 2007, 2014; Daly 2013; Joyce 2013; Parent 2013). The
charge of incoherence mirrors a well-known objection to eliminativism. The
Fictionalism and the Folk  293

eliminativist claims that mental states do not exist. And yet, the critic claims, assert-
ing something involves believing it. So eliminativism is incoherent: the very act of
asserting the position shows it to be false. Fictionalism faces a related worry. The fic-
tionalist claims that talk about beliefs and desires is pretence within a game of
make-believe. And yet pretence and make-believe are themselves folk psychological
notions. So mental fictionalism is incoherent: the very act of stating the position re-
quires commitment to the existence of mental states. This is perhaps the most seri-
ous objection facing mental fictionalism, and I cannot hope to deal with it properly
here (for fuller discussions, see Wallace [2014]; Joyce [2013]; Parent [2013]). The
most promising response for the fictionalist, I believe, echoes Churchland’s (1981)
well-known response on behalf of eliminativism (see also Wallace [2007], Joyce
[2013]).

Downloaded from http://monist.oxfordjournals.org/ by guest on October 10, 2016


Churchland (1981) argues that the charge of self-refutation begs the question
against eliminativism: it assumes that we must explain what happens when some-
one makes an assertion (puts forward an argument, defends a position, etc.) in
folk psychological terms. And yet this is exactly what the eliminativist denies.
Eventually, according to eliminativism, we will come to possess a proper neuro-
scientific theory of such activities which is radically different from that offered
by folk psychology. At present, however, we have no alternative but to describe
activities such as assertion using folk psychological notions. The mental fictional-
ist might take a similar line. The fictionalist’s central claim is that the practice
of folk psychology should be understood in a similar way to activities such as
playing games or engaging with fiction. Eventually, we might come to possess a
proper neuroscientific account of such activities which is radically different from
that offered by folk psychology. At present, however, we have no choice but to
describe these activities using folk psychological notions such as pretence and
make-believe.5

N O T ES
1. An exception is Demeter (2013b), who proposes a particular form of mental fictionalism that treats folk
psychology as a device for expressing an interpreter’s affective reactions.
2. Note that here I adopt a pragmatic, rather than semantic, interpretation of Walton’s account (for more on
this distinction, see Friend [2007]).
3. Throughout this discussion, I will use the term “behaviourism” to refer to analytic, rather than methodo-
logical, behaviourism. While the analytical behaviourist offers an analysis of ordinary talk about mental
states, the methodological behaviourist instead proposes a restriction on the proper object of psychologi-
cal inquiry. For a classic defence of analytic behaviourism, see Ryle (1949). For methodological behaviour-
ism, see Skinner (1974).
4. For a discussion of the problems facing this approach to fiction, see Friend (2007).
5. Versions of this paper were presented at the conference on Mental Fictionalism at the University of
Edinburgh, July 14–15, 2014, “Shaping the Trading Zone: Bringing Aesthetics and Philosophy of Science
Together” at the University of Leeds, September 5–6, 2014, and the workshop on Scientific Fictionalism
at the Institute of Philosophy in London, June 12–13, 2015. Thanks to the participants at each of these
events for helpful comments and criticism. And a special thank you to Fiora Salis for all her encourage-
ment and hard work in editing this volume. This project has received funding from the European Union’s
Seventh Framework Programme for research, technological development, and demonstration under
Grant agreement No. 331432.
294  Fictionalism and the Folk

R EF E RE NC E S
Armour-Garb, B., and J.A. Woodbridge 2015. Pretense and Pathology, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Beardsley, M. 1962. “The Metaphorical Twist,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 22(3),
293–307.
Block, N. 1981. “Psychologism and Behaviorism,” The Philosophical Review, 90(1), 5–43.
Braddon-Mitchell, D., and F. Jackson 2007. Philosophy of Mind and Cognition: An Introduction, 2nd
ed., Oxford: Blackwell.
Burgess, J. and G. Rosen 1997. A Subject with No Object, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Churchland, P M. 1981. “Eliminative Materialism and the Propositional Attitudes,” The Journal of
Philosophy 78(2), 67–90.
Crimmins, M. 1998. “Hesperus and Phosphorus: Sense, Pretense, and Reference,” Philosophical
Review 107, 1–47.

Downloaded from http://monist.oxfordjournals.org/ by guest on October 10, 2016


Daly, C. 2013. “Psychology and Indispensability,” The Monist 96(4), 561–81.
Demeter, T. ed. 2013a. “Mental Fictionalism,” The Monist, 96(4).
2013b. “Mental Fictionalism: The Very Idea,” The Monist, 96(4), 483–504.
Dennett, D.C. 1987. The Intentional Stance, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Eklund, M. 2015. “Fictionalism,” in E.N. Zalta, ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter
2015 edition), plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2015/entries/fictionalism
Friend, S. 2007. “Fictional Characters,” Philosophy Compass 2(2), 141–56.
Godfrey-Smith, P. 2005. “Folk Psychology As a Model,” Philosopher’s Imprint 5(6), 1–16.
Hills, D. 2012. “Metaphor,” in E.N. Zalta, ed., The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2012
Edition), plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/metaphor.
Hutto, D. 2013. “Fictionalism about Folk Psychology,” The Monist 96(4), 582–604.
Joyce, R. 2005. “Moral Fictionalism,” in M.E. Kalderon, ed., Fictionalism in Metaphysics, Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 287–313.
2013. “Psychological Fictionalism, and the Threat of Fictionalist Suicide,” The Monist 96(4),
517–38.
Kroon, F. 2001. “Fictionalism and the Informativeness of Identity,” Philosophical Studies 106,
197–225.
Lakoff, G. and M. Johnson 1980. Metaphors We Live By, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Lewis, D. 1986. On the Plurality of Worlds, Oxford: Blackwell.
Moran, R. 1989. “Seeing and Believing: Metaphor, Image, and Force,” Critical Inquiry 16(1),
87–112.
Parent, T. 2013. “In the Mental Fiction, Mental Fictionalism Is Fictitious,” The Monist 96(4),
605–21.
Ramsey, W., S.P. Stich, and J. Garon 1990. “Connectionism, Eliminativism and The Future of Folk
Psychology,” Philosophical Perspectives 4, 499–533.
Rosen, G. 1990. “Modal Fictionalism,” Mind 99: 327–54.
Ryle, G. 1949. The Concept of Mind, London: Hutchinson.
Sellars, W. 1956. “Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind,” in H. Feigl and M. Scriven, eds., The
Foundations of Science and the Concepts of Psychology and Psychoanalysis, Minnesota Studies in the
Philosophy of Science, Vol. 1. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Skinner, B.F. 1974. About Behaviourism, London: Jonathan Cape.
Sprevak, M. 2013. “Fictionalism About Neural Representations,” The Monist 96(4), 539–60.
Stanley, J. 2001. “Hermeneutic Fictionalism,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 25(1), 36–71.
Wallace, M. 2007. “Mental Fictionalism”, unpublished manuscript.
2014. “Saving Mental Fictionalism from Cognitive Collapse,” unpublished manuscript.
Walton, K.L. 1990. Mimesis As Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational Arts,
Harvard: Harvard University Press.
Fictionalism and the Folk  295

1993. “Metaphor and Prop Oriented Make-Believe,” European Journal of Philosophy 1(1),
39–56.
Yablo, S. 1998. “Does Ontology Rest on a Mistake?” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society,
Supplementary Volume 72, 229–61.
2001. “Go figure: A Path Through Fictionalism,” Midwest Studies in Philosophy 25(1), 72–102.
2005. “The Myth of the Seven,” in M.E. Kalderon, ed., Fictionalism in Metaphysics, Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 88–115.

Downloaded from http://monist.oxfordjournals.org/ by guest on October 10, 2016

You might also like