(Library of Philosophy and Religion) R. W. K. Paterson - Philosophy and The Belief in A Life After Death-Palgrave Macmillan (1995)
(Library of Philosophy and Religion) R. W. K. Paterson - Philosophy and The Belief in A Life After Death-Palgrave Macmillan (1995)
General Editor: John Hick, Fellow of the Institute for Advanced Study in
the Humanities, University of Birmingham
Selected titles
R. W. K. Paterson
Formerly Senior Lecturer in Philosophy
University of Hull
w First published in Great Britain 1995 by
MACMILLAN PRESS LTD
Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire RG21 6XS
and London
Companies and representatives
throughout the world
A catalogue record tor this book is available
from the British Library.
ISBN 0 333 61633-2
© R . W . K . Paterson 1995
All rights reserved. No reproduction, copy or transmission of
this publication may be made without written permission.
No paragraph of this publication may be reproduced, copied or
transmitted save with written permission or in accordance with
the provisions of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988,
or under the terms of any licence permitting limited copying
issued by the Copyright Licensing Agency, 90 Tottenham Court
Road, London W I P 9HE.
v
1
Philosophy, Belief and
Disbelief
1
2 Philosophy and the Belief in a Life after Death
21
22 Philosophy and the Belief in a Life after Death
Now, I do not believe that any (or all) of the above points
suffice to refute decisively the claim that my identity as a
person is inseparable from the identity of my body. There are,
for example, plenty of philosophers who would dispute the
Problems of Post-Mortem Identity 31
III. Transcendental
(a) Soul. We may conceive of the soul as a simple non-
material entity or 'substance', existing independently, in
itself unchanging, but underlying and 'owning' the
individual's diverse and changing mental states and
attributes. Because each individual's soul is unique, it is
Problems of Post-Mortem Identity 39
make only a few brief comments on the scale and quality of such
evidence as is in fact available, since for our present purposes it
will be enough to show what evidence, if available, would tend
to establish the identity of a disembodied person with some
individual known to be deceased.
In the nature of the case, the evidence for someone's post-
mortem identity cannot be specific to his identity in the sense of a
continuing 'soul' or unanalysable T, since these concepts, we
have seen, are explicitly transempirical. Of course if we were
constrained on philosophical grounds to accept some such
transcendental account of the meaning of personal identity, then
any general evidence for someone's post-mortem identity would
necessarily point to the survival of this transcendental reality -
but the bearing of this evidence would then be necessarily
indirect. In its intrinsic character as evidential material (that is, as a
set of publicly available empirical facts), the relevant evidence
would need to be of either a physical or a psychological kind, or
of both kinds, whatever the person's 'identity7 might consist in.
59
60 Philosophy and the Belief in a Life after Death
between physical and mental facts are, or are not, as they seem,
and to consider the implications of each of these alternatives for
the available logical models of the mind-brain relationship.
Some of the available models strongly disfavour, or altogether
exclude, the possibility of a life after death (for example,
epiphenomenalism, or identity theories), while others (notably
interactionist dualism) are much more hospitable to the idea of
survival, leaving this as at least an open possibility.
First of all, then, why do many philosophers argue that we are
bound to distinguish logically between physical and mental
facts, and why do some of them go on to claim that this basic
conceptual distinction gives us coercive grounds for differentiat-
ing mental events and processes numerically from physical
events and processes, that is, for inferring an ontological or
existential duality from the premise of a conceptual duality? The
answer to the first question is fairly clear. In talking and thinking
about physical facts we necessarily use concepts which have no
place in our talking and thinking about mental facts, and vice
versa. Thus we can meaningfully describe one stone as heavier
than another, and we know how to set about proving this, but
such an assertion makes no literal sense when we try to compare
one thought or feeling with another thought or feeling. We can
describe someone's mind as alert or envious, but such statements
would be devoid of meaning if made about an apple or a
rainstorm. And so dualistic philosophers have often concluded
that what seem to be two sets of phenomena, physical and
mental, which we necessarily conceptualize in such irreducibly
different ways, must indeed be wholly different in kind: however
exactly physical brain processes may be correlated with some-
one's mental processes, they have claimed, the correlations must
hold in every case between literally two numerically different
processes, either of which is conceivable as going on in the
absence of the other.
Before we consider the claim that two qualitatively different
processes are therefore two numerically different processes, let us
briefly review the characteristics which we necessarily ascribe to
mental processes only, and which therefore do seem to differ-
entiate these qualitatively from any and all physical processes.
The central characteristic of every mental event, process, or
state is that it is actually or potentially conscious. Since Descartes,
The Mental and the Physical 61
The image of the candle and its flame is intended to express one
of the oldest and most popular versions of the relation between
brain and mind. This is epiphenomenalism, or mind-brain
dependence. According to epiphenomenalists, mental states and
processes are no more than a by-product of the workings of the
physical brain. The brain in its workings produces many bodily
changes, directly and indirectly, for example altering heartbeat
and raising or lowering blood pressure, which in turn can react
on the brain, as when high blood pressure causes a cerebral
haemorrhage. It also generates sensations, emotions, thoughts,
memories, choices and all the phenomena of consciousness, but
the difference is that these mental phenomena do not react
causally on the physical system which produces them. Hence
mental states are nothing but the completely passive reflections
of what is happening in the brain, or the causally inert shadows
of physical brain states. All the true action in our lives is initiated
in the brain. Our minds are throughout merely impotent
spectators. A man cannot be punched by his reflection in a
mirror, or trip over his own shadow.
The epiphenomenalist accepts that mental processes are
conceptually and phenomenologically different from brain
processes, and he also accepts that they are numerically and
existentially distinct. When I have thoughts about going to the
theatre, there are in addition various electrochemical events
occurring in my brain, and the epiphenomenalist acknowledges
that these constitute two existentially distinct trains of events
taking place, the brain events and my thoughts. Thus epipheno-
menalism must be considered a species of dualism. But it rules
out the characteristic element of interactionist dualism, for it
does not admit that mental states can in any way influence brain
states or indeed future mental states. My present thoughts, qua
thoughts, do not make any difference to what I will do, or even to
what I will think. The causal traffic moves in one direction only,
from the physical to the mental, because without the occurrence
of brain events there would not even be any mental events. Hence
The Mental and the Physical 71
which we can then identify with the original brain which died
long ago and is now 'resurrected'. No doubt the Reverend James
Fordyce, minister of Cauldshaw in Buchan's Witch Wood, who
kept 'ilka tooth I have ever casf to go into his coffin with him so
that all his bodily parts might be together on Judgment Day,
acknowledged that this was 'just my fancy to keep all my dust in
one place' and that God could of course gather his 'remnants
from the uttermost parts of the earth'. Let us accept that the
Reverend Fordyce had, and only ever will have, the one self-
identical brain. Its existence overrides the time-gap in exactly the
same sense that a collector might buy a genuine Ming vase,
although it had been smashed into hundreds of bits many years
ago, provided that these bits had all been preserved and were
then put together with expert skill in exactly the same order they
formerly occupied.
Thus if the God of monotheism exists, belief in a general
physical resurrection seems to be coherent, according to
philosophers like Nielsen. However, Nielsen points out, there
is a huge difference between mere logical coherence and causal
possibility. This gap could be bridged only if we had good
grounds for believing in the God of monotheism. And since
Nielsen and many other philosophers consider that there are no
good grounds for believing in such a God, and that the very
concept of an infinite omnipotent individual is probably
incoherent, their conclusion is that the belief in a physical
resurrection is, even if coherent, emphatically not a belief anyone
can reasonably hold.
We have been looking at resurrection theories against the
background of epiphenomenalism, which is one of the physic-
alist theories available if we wholly reject the possibility of a
disembodied self, which Nielsen does. So does Penelhum, who
rejects the idea of resurrection unless its adherents smuggle in
'an impossible doctrine of intermediate bodiless existence'5.
Otherwise the idea breaks up on the reef of identity, for the
'resurrected' body could at most be a replica of the original body,
now defunct. We have seen, I think, that this is not the case. And
so far we have not found compelling reasons to dismiss the
possibility of a completely disembodied personal existence. This
concept would obviously negate our present epiphenomenalist
premise. It is perhaps worth noticing at this point that traditional
74 Philosophy and the Belief in a Life after Death
No one who was conversant with the scope and quality of the
evidence for extra-sensory perception could reasonably hope to
identify thoughts and experiences with brain changes, or to show
that they are merely the mental products or reflections of brain
changes. I cannot possibly begin to discuss this evidence here,
but shall merely state that it seems to most serious students to
justify us in accepting that telepathy, clairvoyance, and pre-
cognition are among the marginal capacities of men and other
animals. If telepathy consisted in some kind of physical radiation
between brains, telepathy tests should show a consistent decline
in scoring levels as the distance between the participants is
increased. Yet all investigates agree that there is no covariance
between distance and scoring level. (If the physicalist replied that
perhaps the brain possesses an automatic 'volume control' which
amplifies weaker signals, we can ask for his evidence for this
hypothesis, and of course we shall get no answer, for this reply
would simply be another unsupported theoretical artifice,
adopted ad hoc.) Furthermore, physical barriers do not affect
ESP, as the Russian physiologist Leonid Vasiliev discovered to
his dismay more than a generation ago when he conducted
experiments during which the participants were completely
enclosed in metal containers blocking out all electromagnetic
waves between one millimetre and one kilometre, Vasiliev
having admitted it to be highly improbable that ESP might be
due to electromagnetic waves outside this range. Yet the ESP
results, he found, were not thereby impaired.
Anyway, the only 'brain waves' identified or suggested by
neuroscientists are far too weak to carry telepathic messages.
According to W. Grey Walter, if we considered brain rhythms as
radio signals, 'they would fall below noise level within a few
millimetres from the surface of the head'. 15 Hans Berger, father
of electroencephalography, once suggested that in telepathy the
electrical energy in the sender's brain gets transformed into a
completely different kind of energy,16 which can be radiated to
any distance and pass through all barriers without the slightest
diminution and which, on reaching the receiver's brain, gets
The Mental and the Physical 83
consider these here, because neither of these theories can get off
the ground unless we first postulate a God to fill notorious gaps
within the theories themselves. The parallelism of Leibniz
requires a God who has pre-established the perfect harmony
between the physical and the mental (which are deemed to be
intrinsically incapable of interacting, on the ground of their
ontological diversity); and the idealism of Berkeley famously
requires a God to account for the continued existence of material
objects which are temporarily or permanently unperceived by
human or other percipients (since 'material objects' are supposed
to consist of nothing but groups of sense-data or 'ideas'). Perhaps
there is a God who forever operates in the ways conceived of by
Leibniz or Berkeley. But I do not think we should use the concept
of such a God as the necessary postulate for some special theory
of the relation between mind and body.
Hence by far the most plausible mentalist theory hospitable to
the belief in a life after death is some form of interactionist
dualism. At the end of the first section of this chapter (on p. 69),
having distinguished the mind conceptually and phenomenolo-
gically from the body, I said that this was not enough to establish
that mind and body were numerically and existentially distinct.
But now, after having examined the best attempts to identify the
two and noted the conspicuous inadequacy of these attempts, we
can I think reasonably conclude that the mental and the physical
form an existential as well as a conceptual duality. In short we are
minds, which have bodies. A person and his body work in close
partnership while his body lives, but the nature of the two
partners is radically different, and their ultimate destinies may
be radically different.
Naturally I accept that the world contains many a thing which
we can conceive of in different ways and describe in different
terms drawn from quite different vocabularies but which turns
out to be nevertheless just one thing, albeit differently conceived
and described. If in swallowing an aspirin I am swallowing
acetylsalicylic acid, I am not swallowing two things (as I would
be if I swallowed the aspirin with water) because aspirin is just
acetylsalicylic acid. There are not two heavenly bodies, the
evening star and the morning star, but rather the one heavenly
body, Venus, manifesting itself at different times. Temperature is
not a result of mean molecular kinetic energy, but just is mean
The Mental and the Physical 93
103
104 Philosophy and the Belief in a Life after Death
This last point does not apply in the same way to a variant of
the argument from tradition which we might call 'the argument
from consensus'. Thus in an extremely thorough poll of United
States adults in 1980-81, the Gallup organization discovered that
about two-thirds (67 per cent) of those questioned believed in a
life after death while just over a quarter (27 per cent) did not. 12
Yet if we ask whether Gallup found anything that might tend to
erode any significance we were inclined to attach to this very
considerable majority of contemporary believers, the answer
must be that assuredly they did. For two parallel surveys
conducted with representative samples of prominent scientists
and physicians showed that the proportions of believers in these
two highly educated groups were merely 16 per cent and 32 per
cent respectively.
However, sets of figures like these surely offer scant guidance
to anyone concerned to hold a rational belief one way or the
other. As I claimed in Chapter l, 13 the mere circumstance that
someone believes something has perhaps a slight degree of
evidential value, but surely its value is very slight indeed. A
superstition is still a superstition, however widely held. We need
to know, not only how many heads nod in agreement to some
proposition, but above all why the owners of these heads
consider themselves justified in accepting this proposition and
rejecting alternative propositions.
Although indeed we can usually have a rather higher degree
of confidence in beliefs distinctively held by the more knowl-
edgeable, we obviously need to be satisfied here that their
admittedly greater level of knowledge in fact extends to the
particular subject in which we are interested. When we
investigate, we may find, for instance, that Mill based his
rejection of the argument from tradition on his uncharacteristi-
cally dogmatic supposition that people's former widespread
experience of apparitions of the dead must have been no more
than the work of their fancy, in dreams, waking hallucinations,
and misinterpretation of their visual and auditory sensations,
because they had little or none of the knowledge we now
possess of the actual course of nature'.14 This last phrase eerily
reminds one of Hume's notorious declaration of the sceptical
attitude he would still adopt even if every historical record
affirmed that Queen Elizabeth had been reliably pronounced
108 Philosophy and the Belief in a Life after Death
dead on the first of January 1600, had been buried, and her
successor proclaimed, but that after a month she had reappeared,
resumed the throne, and reigned for another three years. No
quality or quantity of historical evidence could ever persuade
him to 'admit of so signal a violation of the laws of nature'.15 Mill
at least professed himself agnostic, not downright sceptical,
about the possibility of a life after death. But his agnosticism
seems to have been based on a total scepticism about the
evidence on both sides of the question. One inevitably wonders
whether so honest and clear an intelligence would have persisted
in this total scepticism about the evidence if Mill had been able to
study and weigh the detailed accounts of crisis-apparitions and
apparitions of the dead which were published a generation after
his death in the SPR's Report of the Census of Hallucinations (1894)
and in F. W. H. Myers' Human Personality and its Survival of Bodily
Death (1903). To pursue this speculation further, however, would
switch our attention towards particular varieties of concrete
factual claims of an empirical kind, and away from the purely
general arguments with which we are at present concerned.
Our passional nature not only lawfully may, but must, decide
an option between propositions, whenever it is a genuine
option that cannot by its nature be decided on intellectual
grounds; for to say, under such circumstances, 'Do not decide,
but leave the question open', is itself a passional decision - just
like deciding yes or no - and is attended with the same risk of
losing the truth.25
cannot imagine any one of them (how small soever it may be),
which I cannot easily sunder in thought, and which, therefore,
I do not know to be divisible.32
This does not mean that the soul 'is absolutely incapable of
annihilation, even by the infinite power of the Creator, who first
gave it being. But only that it is not liable to be broken, or
dissolved, by the ordinary laws of nature or motion'.38
This famous argument from the indivisibility of the soul is
open to a number of seemingly fatal objections. First of all we
may question the premise. Indeed, if we grant that the soul is an
immaterial substance, it obviously cannot have material parts.
But why should it not be composed of spiritual or mental parts?
Plato himself often spoke of 'the three parts' of the soul, by which
he meant the lowest or sensory capacity of the soul, governed by
feelings and appetites, the intermediate or 'spirited' element of
the soul, governed by courage and a sense of honour, and the
highest or rational part, governed by wisdom and the love of
truth. Plato may have thought of these as levels of functioning,
rather than as strict 'parts' or 'ingredients'; and no doubt he
thought of immortality as a prize to be won and enjoyed only by
the rational part of the soul, when freed from its lower accretions;
however he would thereby appear to be acknowledging that
immortality is not in fact within the eventual reach of our full,
118 Philosophy and the Belief in a Life after Death
the second group, are fitted to enter into an intimate and trustful
relationship with the God who created each one of them.
Next we need to ask why the deity should vouchsafe
immortality to any of his creatures, whether human or nonhu-
man, who are able, in some relevant degree, to enjoy communion
with him. Since God has all life, glory, goodness and blessedness
in and of himself, he is necessarily all-sufficient in and unto
himself and therefore stands in no need of communion with any
of the creatures he has made. He might have created each of us to
occupy a limited and transitory role in the overall scenario of the
cosmos he has built, in which alone he takes full delight. Perhaps
' 'tis all a chequer-board of Nights and Days where Destiny with
Men for Pieces plays, hither and thither moves, and mates, and
slays, and one by one back in the Closet lays'. No - if God will
not allow persons to lapse into nothingness, this can only be from
his love and mercy towards them. Every self-conscious creature,
and even those who are far removed from anything we can
appropriately call self-consciousness, like the spider which
scuttles away from imminent danger, seems to fear and avoid
extinction. If our hope of immortality rests on a belief in God's
mercy, we must surely conclude that his mercy will not be
restricted to those who are able to enjoy communion with him
but will also extend to every sentient being, however humble,
that stands in need of divine mercy. This classic theistic
argument, then, would logically result in an endless future life
not only awaiting 'persons', even when this concept is stretched
to embrace the higher animals like horses or dolphins, but also
awaiting every sentient creature, even still-born human infants
and even mice and flies. Perhaps this outcome ought to be
willingly accepted by theists. But it is fairly safe to say that it is
not one which they tend to anticipate, or traditionally welcome.
Another attribute commonly adduced by theists is divine
justice. God is the supreme Lawgiver and Judge, who will in the
end ensure that all wrongdoing is justly punished and that all
virtue receives its proper reward. During our present lives we
can see only too plainly that here on earth there is frequently an
enormous disproportion between happiness and desert. In this
world honest and generous people often lead lives marred by
suffering and deprivation, while greedy and cruel men may
derive great advantage apparently from their very hard-heart-
General Arguments for Immortality of the Soul 125
would be to forget that after all God has already seen fit to
incorporate these lowly beings in his actual plan of terrestrial
creation, that in so doing he has endowed them with some real if
primitive measure of mentality, and that we need to show good
reason why there cannot be a future for individuals with a very
low order of mentality in his overall plan of Creation as it is
going to develop. Hindus, Buddhists and other adherents of
nontheistic religions seem to find no intellectual difficulty in
accepting this possibility. Moreover, from a purely secular
standpoint we have to recognize that the continued existence
of elephants or mice after their physical deaths would merely
involve a continuance of their consciousness, perhaps including
a crude reminiscence of their former bodies and the perspectives,
expectations and attitudes to which they had become habituated
during their earthly lives; and we have to remember that anyway
the entirely natural processes of evolution have undeniably, as a
matter of hard fact, resulted in the existence of these creatures, on
the same planet as human beings, with our normally much
greater minds. There is nothing inherently absurd about the fact
that we at present live surrounded by small-minded creatures, of
whom we customarily take little notice. And if human minds can
survive into a wider universe, there is nothing absurd about the
thought that the minds of owls or wolves might also survive in
their different spheres in that wider universe. Whether a creature
is worthy to exist - whether it is admirable, beautiful or useful - is
one question. Whether a creature in fact exists, or is likely to
continue to exist in different circumstances, is an altogether
separate question. However trivial we may consider the
existence of a rabbit or a shark, we have to accept that the
universe in fact does contain many things which we regard as
trivial, quite worthless, and even very harmful. We need not
welcome this fact. Nevertheless we have no option but to put up
with it.
Many Christians have believed that the uniqueness of human
beings is shown by the fact that it was in a human being, Jesus of
Nazareth, that God became incarnate. And many have affirmed
that the resurrection of Jesus provides us with the sole
dependable ground for believing in a life after death. John Hick
has pointed out that it is only in relatively recent times that Jesus'
resurrection has come to be viewed as a primary ground for
General Arguments for Immortality of the Soul 127
belief in a life to come, but Hick does accept that the resurrection
confirms and support this belief,44 although 'it is impossible for
us today to be sure in precisely what the resurrection event
consisted'.45
Although we cannot now know exactly what happened in
Palestine 2,000 years ago, let us accept that at least Jesus
demonstrated that he had in some way survived his crucifixion
and death. Any inferences we base on this must partly depend
on how we perceive the nature of the risen Jesus, who is
traditionally perceived as distinctively human as well as truly
divine. Distinctively human, we can ask, but why not distinc-
tively a Jew? Distinctively human, we can equally ask, but why
not distinctively a sentient being? If the former perception might
exclude inferences to the survival of death by non-Jews, that is by
the great majority of human beings who have ever lived, the
latter perception would permit inferences to the survival of death
by all nonhuman sentient creatures, past, present, and to come.
The difference between Jesus and a sparrow or lizard does not
need to be spelled out. But neither does his difference from an
American gangster or a dying brain-damaged infant. The
difference between Jesus and all creatures, whether human or
nonhuman, is that Jesus is regarded as inherently divine. This
Christian argument, then, begins from the premise that someone
who was absolutely unique in history, who was indeed God
incarnate, survived his death on the cross; and proceeds to the
conclusion that all non-divine creatures who resemble him in a
particular respect - that is, as human (but why not as Jewish? or
as sentient?) - will for that reason also survive their deaths. It
seems to me that any argument of this kind, based on the earthly
destiny of a figure postulated as absolutely unique because
divine, must be judged seriously defective if intended to show
that everyone who shares the humanity of Jesus (but who of
course has no share whatsoever in his divine status) will
necessarily join with him in a life beyond this one.
I have not mentioned the promises made by Jesus. Perhaps all I
need to say is that, if Jesus was veritably God, then obviously we
may rely unreservedly on these promises once we are sure that
we have correctly grasped what they mean.
Nor have I mentioned the contribution made to some religious
believers' conviction of a life after death by the very numerous
128 Philosophy and the Belief in a Life after Death
reports of saints and other holy figures who are known to have
died but who appear to and sometimes communicate with,
inspire, and comfort people here on earth many years, and often
many centuries, after their physical deaths. These reports - along
with reported visions of Jesus - need to be added to the reports
of secular apparitions which we shall consider in the next
chapter. Whatever may be their special religious interest, if they
are to be claimed as evidence for a general human survival of
death these claims obviously have to be assessed in the light of
the rational criteria for evaluating apparitional evidence in
general, which we shall duly be examining.
131
132 Philosophy and the Belief in a Life after Death
decisive comment: 'No one has ever come back to tell us whether
there is a life after death, or what it is like!' They regard this
comment as unambiguous and incontestable. It is in fact
eminently contestable, as the evidence we shall be reviewing
will amply demonstrate. Apparitions of the dead, for instance,
may well not be at all what they seem to be, but there is no
denying that at any rate they constitute prima facie evidence that
some individuals known to be deceased have briefly 'come back',
and to deny that it is even possible that apparitional experiences
may bear this interpretation is obviously to beg the contested
question at the very outset. And the comment is equally far from
being unambiguous. Are those who have been successfully
resuscitated when on the brink of physical death, and subse-
quently give a first-hand account of their ostensible experiences
at 'the borderland', to be counted as having 'returned from the
dead'? Is someone who is held to be the reincarnation of a
recently deceased human being to be regarded as one and the
same person who has now ostensibly come back as a new
individual? If the spirits of the dead ever communicate to us via
mediums, is this what their 'return' to us properly consists in?
Someone who had emigrated from Britain to Australia for good
would indeed not be considered to have literally 'come back' to
Britain merely because we could speak to him by telephone or
wireless, or see him on a British television screen. However, if
what we wanted was proof that he had survived the voyage and
descriptions of his present life in Australia, and these were
thereby supplied to us, it would be captious to complain that
they were forthcoming from someone who was no longer
domiciled in Britain. In any sense which is relevant to the belief
in a life after death, there is a body of evidence which suggests
that some individuals have apparently returned from the dead to
acquaint us with their new life in their new situation, and
evaluation of this evidence is therefore an appropriate task which
must not be shirked.
quite a long way. In 1926 the physicist Sir William Barrett, one of
the original founders of the SPR, published a collection of cases
entitled Death-bed Visions. One might well expect that many
dying people would have purely subjective hallucinations, that
these would probably include hallucinations of various absent
relatives and friends who were meaningful to them, and that a
fair proportion of these would be of people who were already
dead. However, one might also expect that the dying would
naturally hallucinate the figures of many absent relatives and
friends who were in fact still alive but whose presence would
have met their emotional needs, especially if those who were
dying belonged to different age-groups and were not entirely
confined to the aged, whose emotional needs might of course
predominantly centre on individuals whom they knew to have
predeceased them. In fact Barrett found that all deathbed visions
involved only those relatives and friends who were already
dead. Of particular interest were those cases where the dying
person 'saw7 the figure of someone whom he or she believed to
be still alive but who at the time was actually dead. Thus there
was the famous case reported by Lady Barrett, an obstetrician, of
a young woman dying after her delivery who appeared to see,
not only her dead father, but also the figure of her sister, Vida,
whose death three weeks previously had been deliberately kept
from her because of her own serious ill health.2
However, later and more systematic studies have shown that
Barrett was wrong in his belief that all deathbed visions involve
only the figures of human beings who are dead. In 1959-60,
Karlis Osis, a professional parapsychologist, circulated a ques-
tionnaire to 10,000 US physicians and nurses and carefully
analysed the 640 responses he received from them, providing
details of their observations of 35,000 dying patients, including
1,300 examples of apparitional experiences? 190 of the respon-
dents were then interviewed in depth. He discovered that 18 per
cent of the apparitions seen were of living persons, 54 per cent of
deceased relations, and 28 per cent of religious figures (e.g. Jesus,
saints, angels). Lest these and other findings might have been
influenced by cultural factors such as the Judaeo-Christian
background of most US patients, Osis and a fellow-parapsychol-
ogist, Erlendur Haraldsson, later conducted a cross-cultural
survey both in America and in India.4 In the USA they sent
136 Philosophy and the Belief in a Life after Death
It may be asked: since these people did not in fact die, in what
sense were they 'at the point of death'? And since they were all in
fact alive at the times when they had the experiences they
narrate, how can their narratives possibly supply useful evidence
of what, if anything, happens to human beings after they do
actually come to die?
The simple and obvious answers to these questions are, I
suggest, the correct ones. The patients concerned were in a state
where their vital functions were giving clear signs of being on a
rapid course of collapse which, in the judgment of their medical
attendants, would almost certainly have ended, within a period
of minutes, in their final and irreversible cessation as living
individuals. Without medical intervention, they would have
been physically dead. It is in this sense that they were 'at the
point of death'. And we are, I think, entitled to presume that if
people have in fact reached any kind of limit, in this case the
limit of physical life, the experiences which they can recall
having when at or near this limit, and which purport to be
glimpses of what lies beyond the limit, at least deserve to be
taken seriously and to be subjected to rational evaluation.
What, then, are the characteristics of these experiences? Let me
divide them into (a) general characteristics, which are recalled as
having pervaded the entire sequence, and (b) serial characteristics,
which relate to different elements of the sequence in the order in
which they unfold.
(a) The general characteristics of NDEs are as follows. First,
they are 'ineffable', that is, the experiences are not fully or exactly
describable in language which does adequate justice to then-
depth and tonality. Secondly, they have a perceived quality of
'timelessness', as if all intuitive sense of the duration of the
experience had been lost or was irrelevant. Thirdly, they are
recollected as having been pervaded by a profound sense of
'reality7, leading the subjects to assert vehemently that then-
experiences were utterly unlike those of a dream or drug-
induced fantasy. Fourthly, the experience is almost invariably
interpreted as a 'death experience', that is, throughout the
experience the subjects believe that they have now died or are in
process of dying. Fifthly, the predominant feeling is one of peace,
calm, tranquillity. And sixthly, nearly all subjects describe the
NDE as if it took place outside their physical bodies, as
The Evidence from Psychical Research 141
had obliterated the scratch with powder, etc.; and had never
told anyone about the incident.
5. A woman is lying in bed waiting to feed her baby, with her
husband asleep beside her. Suddenly she sees a tall man, in
the uniform of a naval officer, leaning on the foot rail of the
bed. She rouses her husband, who also sees the figure. The
apparition addresses a few words to the husband in a
reproachful tone before turning away and disappearing into
the wall. He then informs his wife that the figure was that of
his father, dead for fifteen years. Later she learns that seeing
the apparition had deterred her husband from taking
financial advice which would have proved ruinous. 27
6. Passing a colleague on the landing of a factory office stairs, a
worker is surprised when his 'Good morning7 elicits only a
strained stare. On returning home he learns that the man had
fallen on a dwarf-fence post the previous evening and had
died in hospital that morning of peritonitis.28
7. On a winter's afternoon a young airman is sitting in his
quarters reading and smoking, when the door opens and a
close friend of his looks in and greets him cheerfully. Later
that day he discovers that his friend had been killed,
approximately at the time his apparitional figure was seen,
when his aircraft had crashed in dense fog. 29
of human beings who are alive and well when their apparitions
are perceived.
Nevertheless recognized apparitions of the dead and dying
form a substantial sub-class of apparitions in general. In Green
and McCreery's survey, where 72 per cent of all apparitions were
unrecognized, 'about two-thirds of all the recognized apparitions
reported to us were of people or animals whom the subject knew
to be dead 7 . 30 The incidence of apparitions of the dying is even
more strikinely significant. In the SPR's great Census of
Hallucinations an apparition of the dying was defined as one
which occurred within 24 hours of the death of the person whose
apparition was perceived. Taking the annual death rate for
England and Wales as given in the Registrar-General's Report for
1890, namely 19.5 per thousand, the authors calculated on this
basis that an apparition of an identifiable individual within 24
hours of his death might be perceived by chance-coincidence in 1
case out of 19,000. In fact out of the 1,300 cases they collected, 30
were cases of apparitions of the dying, that is, a proportion of
about 1 in 43. This is equivalent to about 440 in 19,000, or 440
times what might have occurred by chance alone. As Tyrrell
points out, this very high proportion is still more impressive
when a number of other relevant factors are taken into full
account (e.g. collective percipience, demonstrable effects on the
percipients, and the number of times which were actually very
much within the 24 hours limit).32
The criteria we ought to adopt for assessing the overall
importance of apparitions of the dead and dying for the belief in
a life after death are, I suggest, as follows.
(a) The frequency with which they occur. Let us recall that most
surveys show that roughly one in ten of the population
reports having perceived an apparitional figure, whether
recognized or unrecognized, at some period of their lives. 33
Now it is not unreasonable to conjecture that if two-thirds of
recognized apparitions represent individuals who are dead,
a similar proportion may hold among those apparitions, the
majority, which go unrecognized. After all, however
extensive our acquaintance, there are always vastly more
people whom we do not personally know, and never will
know, than those whom we do know and can recognize. But
154 Philosophy and the Belief in a Life after Death
so, they are more often than not invisible and inaudible to
others who are present, they often seem to walk or glide
through walls and closed doors, and so on. This combina-
tion of apparently physical and manifestly non-physical
characteristics makes the apparitions studied by psychical
research markedly imlike the 'ghosts' created by writers of
fiction or depicted on the cinema screen. Where a huge
number of independent witnesses testify to the occurrence
of a type of phenomenon, and we find that their separate
descriptions conspicuously tally in respect of a large
number of central features which they would have been
highly unlikely to anticipate, this clearly tends to be very
strong evidence that the type of phenomenon which they
are describing has in fact occurred pretty much as they have
described it.
The reports of apparitional experiences frequently teem
with circumstantial detail. For example, in Example 1 above
the apparitional figure is described as having an aquiline
nose, grey hair, and pale grey or blue eyes, and as wearing a
big waterproof apron. She looked with surprise at the
kitchen unit and gas stove. In Example 2 the apparition of
the mother was in her nightdress with the little shawl
around her shoulders that she always wore in bed. In
Example 3 the grandfather appeared wearing a medium
grey suit, white shirt, black tie, socks, and shoes, and the
percipient could see the smoke coming from his pipe as he
smiled at her with a contented expression. She noticed that
the time on the clock was nearly 10.10 a.m. In Example 4 the
salesman saw a little breast-pin and a comb in the hair of his
sister's figure, the lower half of which was hidden by the
table on which he had been writing. In Example 5 the report
is accompanied by a map of the layout of the bedroom, and
the deceased father is described as wearing a cap with a
projecting peak. As the apparition passed the lamp, the
room was thrown into shadow. In Example 7 the percipient,
Lieutenant Larkin, saw his friend, Lieutenant McConnel,
half in and half out of the room, holding the door knob in
his hand. He was in full flying clothes and was wearing his
customary naval cap, which he had retained from his earlier
days in the RNAS and which only two other men (of
The Evidence from Psychical Research 157
extra partner: 1 am glad to get that off my chest at lasf. All this
Findlay knew of his own knowledge to be true.41
The London medium, Mrs Leonard, gave a sitting to an
anonymous sitter, Mrs Hugh Talbot. Her control passed on a
message from the late Mr Talbot, requesting his wife to look for a
relevant passage in a book which was 'not printed' but lias
writing on'. Mrs Talbot thought a red log book might be meant,
but the control said 'No, it was darker and would she please look
on page 12 or 13'. 'It has a diagram of languages in the front. . .
Indo-European, Aryan, Semitic languages. . .a table of Arabian,
Semitic languages'. On returning home, Mrs. Talbot could hardly
be persuaded to look for such a book. But right at the back of the
top book-shelf she found with astonishment a shabby black
leather notebook of her husband's. Pasted into this was a table of
all the languages mentioned, and on page 13 was an extract
copied out from an old book entitled Post-Mortem, describing the
blissful situation of the author after death.42
When Mrs Winifred Coombe-Tennant died in 1956, she was
remembered as a well-to-do, influential, energetic public woman
who among much else had been the first British woman delegate
to the League of Nations Assembly. Only a very few people
knew that in fact she had also been for many years a medium,
under the pseudonym of 'Mrs Willetf, who had given private
sittings to the former Prime Minister, Arthur Balfour, his
distinguished brother Gerald, Sir Oliver Lodge, and various
other eminent men and women. After her death, and while her
mediumship was still a closely guarded secret, W. H. Salter of the
SPR asked another medium, Geraldine Cummins, to try to get in
touch with the deceased mother of a Major Coombe-Tennant. In
the small cottage in Ireland where she was staying, Miss
Cummins, an automatist, prepared herself in solitude to write
any scripts which might be dictated by this unknown spirit. The
entire story of her scripts, with an analytical foreword by C. D.
Broad, has been published as Swan on a Black Sea.43
These scripts immediately began to pour forth a wealth of
material which Miss Cummins soon felt sure was emanating
from the spirit of the late 'Mrs Willetf. The forty scripts, written
over a period of two-and-a-half years, gave many details of Mrs
Coombe-Tennanfs early married life, of her family and her
husband's family, of her associates and their activities, of the
The Evidence from Psychical Research 165
them. Again the telephone rang. It was Albert Best, who said that
he was being impressed by Ann to let her husband know that 'if
you look in the bottom drawer of the chest of drawers, in the
right hand corner under some shirts, you will find three clean
collars'.45 Mr Kennedy looked and there were the three collars.
Albert Best went on to say that Ann was reminding her husband
to send to the laundry the twenty-three soiled collars which he
had already accumulated in a special box where he kept them.
When he counted the soiled collars, the minister found that there
were twenty-three in all.
Mr Kennedy records many such incidents, as for example
when in the 1970 General Election for the first time he voted
Conservative and was humorously reprimanded by Ann, a
lifelong socialist, via the entranced Albert Best; or when he was
told by Albert Best that Ann was talking about £42, just four
hours after he had drawn exactly £42 from his bank account.46 At
any hour of the day the medium might feel that he was being
contacted by Ann and would quickly let her husband know of
the feelings, experiences, and memories which he believed she
was trying to impress upon him. Many of these concerned odd
events in her early life of which her husband knew nothing until
he made inquiries of her mother and sister, who until then had
themselves almost forgotten about them. One example was when
Ann (via Albert Best) had joked about ballet shoes, which then
recalled to her sister an occasion when Ann had unsuccessfully
tried to 'point her toes' in her young sister's tiny ballet shoes by
holding the ribbons in her hands. Another message referred to a
joke in her family 'about milk in relation to Bill' (Ann's brother,
killed as an air-gunner in 1944). On being questioned, Ann's
mother at last remembered how one summer Bill had naively
applied milk to his hair as an inexpensive substitute for
brilliantine - until it eventually became rancid and he was
acutely embarrassed by its smell. 47
The history of mediumship contains very, very many
examples of communications which are at least equal in
evidential value to those I have cited. Thus the series of sittings
in which communication was apparently established between
the gifted, highly intelligent, and cultured medium, Eileen
Garrett, and Flight Lieutenant Irwin, commander of the ill-fated
airship R101 which had crashed in France shortly before, has
The Evidence from Psychical Research 167
of his friend's name so often that his young sisters used to chant
'Not Reece, but Riss' to tease him, until their father put a stop to
them. Out of 124 items of information given, 51 were classified as
definitely correct, 12 as good, 32 as fair, 2 as poor, 22 as doubtful,
and 5 as definitely wrong.
Secondly, there are 'drop-in communicators', that is, commu-
nicators who are apparently unknown to the medium and to the
sitters, but who seem to arrive uninvited at a sitting which is
trying to make contact with some quite different deceased person
or persons. 'Irwin', for example, first communicated at a seance
at which an investigator was attempting to get in touch with the
spirit of Sir Arthur Conan Doyle. Often these interruptions occur
without the communicators supplying any credible evidence of
their identity. Sometimes, however, they make statements about
themselves which can be subsequently verified and which
appear to be outside the knowledge of anyone present. During
and after World War Two a small circle in Cambridge met
regularly to use a ouija board, and received communications
from more than two hundred deceased persons, mostly friends
and relations of the circle members. Although they had a number
of drop-in communicators, these cases were left unverified until
Dr Alan Gauld investigated them many years later. Between 1950
and 1952 one such communicator, 'Harry Stockbridge', spelled
out several items of information about himself. According to
these Stockbridge had been a 2nd Lieutenant attached to the
Northumberland Fusiliers, although mention was also made of
the Tyneside Scottish; he had died on July 14 1916; he had 'hung
out' in Leicester, where there was a record; he had been tall,
dark, and thin, with large brown eyes; and his mother was also
dead. With great patience, and in the face of considerable
difficulties, Gauld set out to check these various items and at last
found them all to be precisely correct. To discover this he had to
consult obituary notices in two Leicester newspapers of the time
and two obscure works of military history, all of which, however,
he found to contain relevant inaccuracies; to obtain a death
certificate and confirmation from the records of the War Office
Library, which showed that before his death 2nd Lieutenant
Stockbridge had been transferred to a Tyneside Scottish
battalion; to examine a photograph preserved in the archives of
his old school; to consult his surviving brothers; and to find his
The Evidence from Psychical Research 169
former names and those of their relatives and close associates in,
say, early Victorian England, dates and specific place names, and
they make reference to bygone happenings of obscure local
significance, to items of furniture and other utensils in the home
or at work, and to habits of eating, drinking, dress, and conduct
typical of the period to which their ostensible memories relate.
The hypnotized subjecf s voice may change, and he or she may
use little-known locutions expressed with appropriate accents
and in a dialect completely alien to their normal speech habits
but strongly reminiscent of those which prevailed in another
place at an earlier time. The subject seems throughout to identify
completely with the archaic personality which is now expressing
itself to the onlookers.57
When the objective factual statements vouchsafed under
hypnosis are subsequently investigated, many of them turn out
to be unverifiable for a number of obvious reasons, for instance a
total lack of documentary or other historical and biographical
evidence. But when they are capable of being verified, they are
not infrequently discovered to be true in almost every particular.
Does it follow that they emanate from memories of a former life
which have been reawakened by the effects of hypnosis?
In one sense, of course, they are no more than connected
image-sequences. As such, they could be fantasies elicited by the
request of the hypnotist to revert to the experiences of a former
life. This alone, however, would not account for the detailed
knowledge shown of the conditions under which a deceased
personality once lived, which are often far beyond any knowl-
edge possessed by the hypnotist. Yet it is very difficult to
establish that this knowledge could not have been acquired by
the subject by normal means, unconsciously or semi-consciously,
perhaps while listening without specifically attending to a
programme on the car wireless, flicking over the pages of a
magazine at the hairdresser's, overhearing snatches of a
conversation in a restaurant or bar, or in some other way which
has now been forgotten. Although cryptomnesia on this scale is
always a highly improbable explanation, it is antecedently much
less improbable than the recollection of fragments of a past life.
In a few instances, re-hypnotization of the original subject does
seem to have elicited definite recall of the occasion on which the
subliminal reading of a text, say, has furnished him with the
180 Philosophy and the Belief in a Life after Death
brothers and sisters, and her former children (now young grown-
ups) which the deceased personality characteristically had
dining her earlier lifetime, despite being herself actually a young
child at the time of this 'reunion'. Frequently these members of
her previous family accept this as completely appropriate and
accept her as their reincarnated wife, sister, or mother. Some-
times she displays skills, for example of conjoined dances and
songs in Bengali (although now she speaks only Hindi) which
she ostensibly learned during her previous incarnation.
Throughout she behaves, and seems to think and feel, as if her
identity with the deceased personality is virtually complete.
Now if we exclude fraud, misreporting and coincidence as
general explanations, the only naturalistic explanation with
which we are left is cryptomnesia, which can scarcely begin to
account for a young child's detailed knowledge of obscure
episodes which happened years ago in another family in another
town, with whose members he or she is not acquainted and
concerning whom he or she has had no opportunity of acquiring
any information. We therefore have to consider paranormal
explanations. The knowledge and skill displayed might in theory
have been acquired by ESP, either retrocognitively from the past
behaviour and characteristics of the deceased individual or by
recent or current telepathy from the memories retained by that
individual's surviving relatives and friends. But once again I
have to point out that there is no independent evidence for the
occurrence of ESP of this level on such a scale with regard to
propositional knowledge, nor with regard to the acquisition of
skills of any level on any scale. The 'super-ESP' hypothesis must
be judged a non-starter.
We cannot entirely rule out the possibility that the young child
might be functioning as a kind of medium, through whom a
discarnate spirit is communicating over a period of years.
However, a medium (who anyway is nearly always an adult of
mature age) typically serves as a vehicle of communication for a
large variety of discarnate spirits and when in her ordinary state
of mind does not profess to be literally one and the same person
as any of them. There is also the possibility that the young child
is 'possessed' or 'obsessed' by the deceased individual whose
personality purports to be expressing itself through him, and that
after a considerable period of time the child's natural personality
The Evidence from Psychical Research 183
dead, and of the long dead. The cumulative weight of the facts
supporting the survival hypothesis, even when their evidential
value has been appropriately scaled down, is bound progres-
sively to erode the basis on which we may seek to continue
scaling them down. By the time we are ready to weigh up the
numerous impressive phenomena of mental mediumship and
also the suggestive data associated with ostensible reincarnation
cases, we may well judge that there remains only a very limited
balance of antecedent improbability telling against them as
evidence of survival (albeit a sufficiently adverse balance to
induce us to make a much lower estimate of their evidential
value than we would otherwise have made). But after we have
weighed up mental mediumship and ostensible reincarnation
data in this manner, we should, I think, be prepared to find that
the balance of prepossession has tilted decisively. Certainly there
remains enough antecedent improbability attaching to the idea of
survival to justify us in viewing any fresh types of survival
evidence with a considerable degree of reserve. But we are now
in a position to assess the overall probability or improbability of a
life after death, in the light of the principal types of evidence
which we have already examined.
There is in my opinion a probable conclusion which we are
intellectually constrained to draw from all this evidence, after
having ultimately subtracted from its evidential value quite a
substantial element representing the antecedent improbability of
any kind of survival. This conclusion is that on the whole, but
quite clearly, the facts point in the direction of personal survival
of bodily death. If we draw this conclusion, there is still a fan-
possibility that we may be wrong. I cannot claim that the belief in
a life after death has been coercively shown to be true. We are
dealing with relative probabilities. The fairly common view of
physical death as a total and final destruction of the personality
is not 'disproved', in the sense of proof or disproof with which
we are operating. A rational judge, who well understands the
evidence, could nevertheless reject the inferences on which I
have based my conclusion, without in any way forfeiting his
claim to rationality. Yet I am fairly sure that he would in fact be
wrong. Survival of physical death has therefore not been
'proved'. But it has, I think, been shown to be overall distinctly
probable.
6
The Concept of an Afterlife
We have seen that, when all the relevant conceptual issues have
been clarified and all the relevant empirical facts have been
gathered in and appropriately weighed, there exists a clear
balance of probability in favour of the belief that persons can in
some sense survive their physical death. Of course it may be
objected that survival has at most been established in respect of
those individuals whose cases have figured in the evidence.
However, if some individuals have survived death, it is entirely
reasonable to draw the conclusion that all other individuals who
sufficiently resemble them will also have survived death, in the
absence of any evidence to the contrary. And there is no
characteristic which is common to all those people whose
survival is well evidenced, and which distinguishes them from
the great mass of humanity, other than the fact that in these cases
their survival is well evidenced. They differ from one another in
sex, race, religious convictions or the lack of them, in their moral
and intellectual qualities and attainments, in the age at which
they died, and in the manner of their deaths. It is, I suppose,
abstractly possible that some people should continue to exist
after their deaths, while others do not. But there seems to be little
or no evidence to support any belief that this is what happens.
Given that some of us definitely do survive, it looks as if we all
survive.
Now we obviously need to know in what manner we might
survive death. For example, we might survive this trauma of
total body-loss grievously, perhaps irreparably, damaged in
most of our mental capacities, as some people surviving fires or
air crashes find that the injuries with which they have emerged
191
192 Philosophy and the Belief in a Life after Death
and others often claim that it is all around us, that it envelops us
and therefore that our deceased friends and relatives are literally
quite near to us, although normally invisible to us. They may
explain this by claiming that things in the spirit world 'vibrate' at
a much greater frequency than things in our ordinary physical
world. Perhaps this could be so - but it is extraordinary that
physicists have never found any evidence whatsoever of these
rarefied forests, mountains, lakes, and temples, although they
have ransacked the minutest processes of the submicroscopic
universe with the most sensitive instrumentation they can
devise. It certainly looks as if the spirit world and its contents
are not to be found anywhere in space.
If the spirit world has no location, it is idle to speculate about
its spatial extent. How many angels can dance on the point of a
needle? We can usefully ask questions about the area of Australia
or about the surface of the moon. We can think that one day the
huge continent of Australia might get overpopulated (and
perhaps, at some remote date, even the moon). But how can
we think of the next world as perhaps eventually having no more
room for new arrivals? Is this idea absurd because the next world
is capable of indefinite, limitless expansion? Or is it because the
spirit world has no dimensions in the first place, either to get
filled up to to expand?
It would be plainly impossible to construct any kind of map of
the spirit world, by means of which, for example, new arrivals
could be helped to orientate themselves. We are bound to ask
why this is so. Communicators make frequent reference to parks,
galleries, halls of meditation, cities, rivers, or far-off mountain
ranges, but they seldom or never try to describe the relations of
these places to each other or the exact distance between them.
And unlike places in Australia, say, they are never given proper
names. It would be interesting to learn whether my late Uncle
James and a colleague's deceased Aunt Sara, communicating to
us on separate occasions through different mediums and telling
us that they had been present at some great musical concert, had
in fact been present in the same hall at the same time in the same
spirit city, or whether their two experiences were totally
unconnected. As things stand, we have no means of knowing.
Without being given proper place names or precise descriptions,
how could we?
202 Philosophy and the Belief in a Life after Death
The spirits never seem to have much to say about the methods
by which natural processes are sustained in the spirit world, or
about how those things which they find useful for their personal
development get produced and distributed. Even if we assume
that all the spirits of animals as well as men are vegetarian, we
still need to know how it comes about that just the right balance
of soil and climate always produces just the right variety and
quantity of vegetables and fruit which exactly match the tastes of
every member of the population. How are they gathered? What
about the stones to build the halls of learning? Who quarries
them? Are the books in the libraries printed, and if so on what
kind of material and by whom? There is obviously a huge list of
such questions, which seem relevant and understandable given
the kinds of bland general descriptions we are offered by
communicators of the next world and its contents. They stand in
need of an answer. And no clear answer seems to be forthcoming
from the spirits themselves.
Then there is the issue of organization and control. Decisions
will need to be taken about the size and lay-out of the parks, the
siting of orchards and crop-bearing fields, the size to which spirit
communities should grow, about the distribution of resources to
libraries as against concert-halls, and so on. Is spirit opinion
always completely unanimous? Or are there the equivalents of
political parties and pressure groups? How are the rights of
minorities protected? Are there courts of law and agencies to
enforce the justice they declare? Descriptions of the next world
given through mediums tend to suggest that the spirits all have
broadly the same interests, wishes, and preferences. There are no
bad neighbours, no quarrels, no rivalries, no causes of resent-
ment, only love, kindliness, and tolerance.
Such abstract reassurances fail to reassure. Spirit commu-
nicators hardly ever touch on, far less give serious consideration
to, the obvious difficulties to which human relationships can give
rise. Take, for instance, the deep differences in outlook and
values between people dying in 1995 and those who died in 1895
or earlier. Do they live in the same spirit communities, despite
the huge generation gap? We can imagine the problems that
could ensue. Or are they segregated, and if so, by what means?
And consider the artistic activities in which the spirits are said
to spend so much time. Even attaining modest levels of
The Concept of an Afterlife 203
In this book I have been examining grounds for and against the
belief in a life after death. I have limited myself to the
examination of a possible future state which may begin
immediately after physical death and may then continue for
some indefinite period of time, whether long or short. I have not
sought to inquire into what might be the final state of the soul,
after its entire finite destiny is completed. John Hick has drawn a
valuable distinction between eschatology and 'pareschatology7.
'Whereas eschatology is the doctrine of the eschata or last things,
and thus of the ultimate state of man, pareschatology is, by
analogy, the doctrine of the para-eschata, or next-to-last things,
and thus of the human future between the present life and man's
ultimate state'.13 Christians and others have sometimes talked as
if the soul entered into its final state, of perfect bliss or eternal
torment, instantly upon death. Today, for a multitude of reasons,
this scenario seems, to say the least, highly implausible. As Hick
clearly sees, it therefore behoves us to draw upon what
The Concept of an Afterlife 209
213
214 Notes and References
1. It may be argued that there are some mental states which lack this
property, e.g. 'objectless' anxiety or euphoria. However, it is
possible to construe such states as directed to an extremely general
and diffuse object, e.g. one's overall life situation. And it may be
argued that there are physical objects which have the property of
intentionality, e.g. some computers. But in the case of man-made
machines like computers, such 'intentionality' as they may evince is
entirely derivative from the purposes of those minds who have
designed them, and who alone truly have intrinsic intentionality.
We tend to be dazzled by complex and expensive machines like
computers, and can come to view them anthropomorphically. Yet
who would want to attribute intentionality to an old-fashioned Tell
Your Weighf machine on a railway platform?
2. This might seem to create a problem for the concept of 'telepathy7,
usually understood to be the direct, non-inferential knowledge of
another's mental state. The conceptual problem can be easily
overcome, however, if we define telepathy as non-inferential
knowledge of the intentional object of anothef s mental state (what
he is thinking about). This definition might seem to, but does not in
fact, conflate the concepts of 'telepathy7 and 'clairvoyance',
although the intentional object is indeed commonly a physical
object or a construct from features of physical objects. The concept
of clairvoyance is the concept of the non-sensory and non-
inferential knowledge of some physical state of affairs, whether or
not this state of affairs happens to be an object to which another
person's mental state is directed.
3. See J. A. Shaffer, 'Could mental states be brain processes?', in C. V.
Borst (ed.), The Mind-Brain Identity Theory (London: Macmillan,
1970) pp. 113-22.
4. See Kai Nielsen, The Faces of Immortality7, in Stephen T. Davis
(ed.), Death and Afterlife (London: Macmillan, 1989) pp. 2-9.
5. T. Penelhum, Survival and Disembodied Existence (London: Routledge
and Kegan Paul, 1970) p. 99.
6. The Westminster Confession of Faith, Chap. XXXII.
7. See W. Penfield, The Mystery of the Mind (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1975) pp. 21-7.
8. It does not, of course, follow that psychokinesis must be some kind
of obscure physical force. It is supposed to be a purely mental
power, which produces physical changes, e.g. in the distribution of
energy within a brain. See supra, p. 17.
Notes and References 215
16. Critics could perhaps still argue, but with very much diminished
plausibility, that the NDE was being generated by unrecorded
electrical activity in, say, the brain-stem.
17. F. Schoonmaker, Ttenver cardiologist discloses findings after 18
years of near-death research', Anabiosis, May 1979, p. 102.
18. Almeder, op. cit, pp. 195-8.
19. Almeder discusses these in Chapter 4 of his book. Although he is
primarily concerned with the OBE, his analysis is obviously
relevant to NDEs.
20. See, amongst others, H. Hart, 'Six Theories about Apparitions',
Proceedings of the Society for Psychical Research, Vol. 50, part 185 (1956)
and F.W.H. Myers, Human Personality and its Survival of Bodily
Death (London: Longmans, 1903).
21. See supra, pp. 47-50.
22. Green and McCreery, op. cit, p. 123.
23. Op. cit, p. 138.
24. Op. cit, p. 180.
25. Op. cit, pp. 189-90.
26. Proceedings of the SPR, Vol. 6 (1889-90), pp. 17-20.
27. Myers, op. cit, Vol.11, pp. 326-9.
28. Green and McCreery, op. cit, pp. 96-7.
29. E. M. Sidgwick, Thantasms of the Living7, Proceedings of the SPR,
Vol.33 (1923), pp. 152ff.
30. Green and McCreery, op. cit, p. 188.
31. Proceedings of the SPR, Vol. 10 (1894).
32. G.N.M. Tyrrell, Apparitions (London: Duckworth, 1943) pp. 32-3.
33. See supra, p. 47.
34. Proceedings of the SPR, Vol. 36 (1927), pp. 517-24.
35. See supra, p. 153.
36. See supra, pp. 50-5.
37. Proceedings of the SPR, Vol. 16 (1901), pp. 1-649.
38. Ibid., Vol. 13 (1897-8), pp. 284-582.
39. Ibid., Vol.6 (1889-90), pp. 443-557.
40. Ibid., Vol.23 (1909), p. 77.
41. A. Findlay, On the Edge of the Etheric (London: Psychic Press, 1931)
pp. 96^102.
42. Proceedings of the SPR, Vol. 31 (1921), pp. 253-60.
43. G. Cummins, Swan on a Black Sea (London: Routledge and Kegan
Paul, 1965).
44. D. Kennedy, A Venture in Immortality (Gerrards Cross: Colin
Smythe, 1973) pp. 44-5.
45. Kennedy, op. cit, pp. 105-6.
46. Op. cit, pp. 126-7; and p. 115.
47. Op. cit, pp. 49-50; and pp. 47-8.
48. J. G. Fuller, The Airmen Who Would Not Die (London: Souvenir Press,
1979).
49. Proceedings of the SPR, Vol. 45 (1938-9), pp. 257-306.
Notes and References 219
221
222 Index