0% found this document useful (0 votes)
337 views10 pages

Informal Fallacies, Like The Ones Below, Have To Do With What You Are Saying (The "Content" of An

This document provides an overview of 15 common logical fallacies. It defines what logical fallacies are and divides them into formal and informal fallacies. It then explains and provides examples of several specific informal fallacies people are likely to encounter in debates, including ad hominem, straw man, appeal to ignorance, false dilemma, and slippery slope fallacies. The document aims to help readers identify and understand these fallacies so they can avoid using flawed reasoning and spot fallacies in others' arguments.
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as DOCX, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
337 views10 pages

Informal Fallacies, Like The Ones Below, Have To Do With What You Are Saying (The "Content" of An

This document provides an overview of 15 common logical fallacies. It defines what logical fallacies are and divides them into formal and informal fallacies. It then explains and provides examples of several specific informal fallacies people are likely to encounter in debates, including ad hominem, straw man, appeal to ignorance, false dilemma, and slippery slope fallacies. The document aims to help readers identify and understand these fallacies so they can avoid using flawed reasoning and spot fallacies in others' arguments.
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as DOCX, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 10

15 Logical Fallacies You Should Know Before Getting Into a Debate

by David Ferrer

A logical fallacy is an error in reasoning common enough to warrant a fancy name. Knowing how to
spot and identify fallacies is a priceless skill. It can save you time, money, and personal
dignity. Formal fallacies are breakdowns in how you say something, the ideas are ordered wrong
somehow. Their form is wrong.

Informal fallacies, like the ones below, have to do with what you are saying (the “content” of an
argument). The ideas might be arranged right, but something you said isn’t quite right. The content is
wrong. Here’s a list of the 15 informal fallacies you are most likely to encounter in discussion and
debate.

1. Ad Hominem Fallacy
When people think of “arguments,” often their first thought is of shouting matches riddled with personal
attacks. Ironically, personal attacks run contrary to rational arguments. In logic and rhetoric, personal
attacks are called ad hominems. Ad hominem is Latin for “against the man.” Instead of advancing good
sound reasoning, ad hominems replace logical argumentation with attack-language unrelated to the
truth of the matter.

More specifically, ad hominems are a fallacy of relevance where someone rejects or criticizes another
person’s view on the basis of personal characteristics, background, physical appearance, or other
features irrelevant to the argument at issue.

An ad hominem is more than just an insult. It’s an insult used as if it were an argument or evidence in
support of a conclusion. Verbally attacking people proves nothing about the truth or falsity of their
claims. Ad hominems are common known in politics as “mudslinging.” Instead of addressing the
candidate’s stance on the issues, or addressing his or her effectiveness as a statesman or
stateswoman, ad hominems focus on personality issues, speech patterns, wardrobe, style, and other
things that affect popularity but have no bearing on their competence. In this way, ad hominemscan be
unethical, seeking to manipulate voters by appealing to irrelevant foibles and name-calling instead of
addressing core issues. In this last election cycle, personal attacks were volleyed freely from all sides of
the political aisle, with both Clinton and Trump facing their fair share of ad hominems.

Ad hominem is an insult used as if it were an argument or evidence in support of a conclusion.


A thread on Quora lists the following doozies against Hillary Clinton: “Killary Clinton,” “Crooked Hillary,”
“Hilla the Hun,” “Shillary,” “Hitlery,” “Klinton,” “Hildebeest,” “Defender of Child rapists,” “Corporate
Whore,” “Mr. President,” “Heil Hillary,” “Wicked Witch of the West Wing,” “Robberty Hillham Clinton,”
“Mrs. Carpetbagger”, and the decidedly unsubtle, “The Devil.”

The NY Daily News offers an amusing list of insults against Donald Trump: “Short fingered Vulgarian,”
“Angry Creamsicle,” “Fascist Carnival Barker,” “F*ckface von Clownstick,” “Decomposing Jack-O-
Lantern,” “Chairman of the Saddam Hussein Fanclub,” “Racist Clementine,” “Sentient Caps Lock
Button,” “Cheeto Jesus,” “Tangerine Tornado,” and perhaps the most creative/literary reference, “Rome
Burning in Man Form.”

Ad hominems often signal the point at which a civil disagreement has descended into a “fight.” Whether
it’s siblings, friends, or lovers, most everyone has had a verbal disagreement crumble into a disjointed
shouting match of angry insults and accusations aimed at discrediting the other person. When these
insults crowd out a substantial argument, they become ad hominems.

See if you can tell which of these is an ad hominem and which is just an insult.
Example 1: “MacDougal roots for a British football team. Clearly he’s unfit to be a police chief in
Ireland.”
Example 2: “All people from Crete are liars”

2. Straw Man
It’s much easier to defeat your opponent’s argument when it’s made of straw. The Strawman fallacy is
aptly named after a harmless, lifeless, scarecrow. In the straw man fallacy, someone attacks a position
the opponent doesn’t really hold. Instead of contending with the actual argument, he or she instead
attacks the equivalent of a lifeless bundle of straw, an easily defeated effigy, which the opponent never
intended upon defending anyway.

Straw man fallacies are a cheap and easy way to make one’s position look stronger than it is. Using
this fallacy, opposing views are characterized as “non-starters,” lifeless, truthless, and wholly unreliable.
By comparison, one’s own position will look better for it. You can imagine how straw man fallacies
and ad hominems can occur together, demonizing opponents and discrediting their views.

In the straw man fallacy, someone attacks a position the opponent doesn’t really hold.
This fallacy can be unethical if it’s done on purpose, deliberately mischaracterizing the opponent’s
position for the sake of deceiving others. But often the straw man fallacy is accidental, because one
doesn’t realize he or she is oversimplifying a nuanced position, or misrepresenting a narrow, cautious
claim as if it were broad and foolhardy.

See if you can detect how both of the following statements could qualify as a strawman fallacy.

Example 1: “The Senator thinks we can solve all our ecological problems by driving a Prius.”
Example 2: “Quite the contrary, the Senator thinks the environment is such a wreck that no one’s car
choice or driving habits would make the slightest difference.”

3. Appeal to Ignorance (argumentum ad ignorantiam)


Any time ignorance is used as a major premise in support of an argument, it’s liable to be a fallacious
appeal to ignorance. Naturally, we are all ignorant of many things, but it is cheap and manipulative to
allow this unfortunate aspect of the human condition to do most of our heavy lifting in an argument.

Ignorance isn’t proof of anything except that one doesn’t know something.
Interestingly, this fallacy is often used to bolster multiple contradictory conclusions at once. Consider
the following two claims: “No one has ever been able to prove definitively that extra-terrestrials exist, so
they must not be real.” “No one has ever been able to prove definitively that extra-terrestrials do not
exist, so they must be real.” If the same argument strategy can support mutually exclusive claims, then
it’s not a good argument strategy.

Ignorance isn’t proof of anything except that one doesn’t know something. If no one has proven the
non-existence of ghosts or flying saucers, that’s hardly proof that those things exist or don’t exist. If we
don’t know whether they exist, then we don’t know that they exist or that they don’t exist. Ignorance
doesn’t prove any claim to knowledge.

Consider the following examples:

Example 1: “We have no evidence that the Illuminati ever existed. They must have been so clever they
destroyed all the evidence.”
Example 2: “I know nothing about Tank Johnson except that he has a criminal record as long as your
leg, but I’ll bet he’s really just misunderstood.”

4. False Dilemma/False Dichotomy


This fallacy has a few other names: “black-and-white fallacy,” “either-or fallacy,” “false dichotomy,” and
“bifurcation fallacy.” This line of reasoning fails by limiting the options to two when there are in fact more
options to choose from. Sometimes the choices are between one thing, the other thing, or both things
together (they don’t exclude each other). Sometimes there are a whole range of options, three, four,
five, or a hundred and forty-five. However it may happen, the false dichotomy fallacy errs by
oversimplifying the range of options.

Dilemma-based arguments are only fallacious when, in fact, there are more than the stated options. It’s
not a fallacy however if there really are only two options. For example, “either Led Zeppelin is the
greatest band of all time, or they are not.” That’s a true dilemma, since there really are only two options
there: A or non-A. It would be fallacious however to say, “there are only two kinds of people in the
world, people who love Led Zeppelin, and people who hate music.” Some people are indifferent about
that music. Some sort of like it, or sort of dislike it, but don’t have strong feelings either way.

Dilemma-based arguments are only fallacious when, in fact, there are more than the stated options.
The false dilemma fallacy is often a manipulative tool designed to polarize the audience, heroicizing
one side and demonizing the other. It’s common in political discourse as a way of strong-arming the
public into supporting controversial legislation or policies.

See if you can identify a third option these politicians failed to mention.

Example 1: “Either we go to war or we appear weak.”


Example 2: “Either you love me, or you hate me.”

5. Slippery Slope
You may have used this fallacy on your parents as a teenager: “But, you have to let me go to the party!
If I don’t go to the party, I’ll be a loser with no friends. Next thing you know I’ll end up alone and jobless
living in your basement when I’m 30!” The slippery slope fallacy works by moving from a seemingly
benign premise or starting point and working through a number of small steps to an improbable
extreme.

This fallacy is not just a long series of causes. Some causal chains are perfectly reasonable. There
could be a complicated series of causes which are all related, and we have good reason for expecting
the first cause to generate the last outcome. The slippery slope fallacy, however, suggests that unlikely
or ridiculous outcomes are likely when there’s just not enough evidence to think so.

The slippery slope fallacy, however, suggests that unlikely or ridiculous outcomes are likely when
there’s just not enough evidence to think so.
Certain ad campaigns from Dodge, Taco Bell, and notably a recent one for Direct TV, commit this
fallacy to great comic effect.

It’s hard enough to prove one thing is happening or has happened; it’s even harder to prove a whole
series of events will happen. That’s a claim about the future, and we haven’t arrived there yet. We,
generally, don’t know the future with that kind of certainty. The slippery slope fallacy slides right over
that difficulty by assuming that chain of future events without really proving their likelihood.

Which of these examples is a slippery slope fallacy and which is not?

Example 1: “Your coach’s policy is that no one can be a starter on game day if they miss practice. So, if
you miss basketball practice today, you won’t be a starter in Friday’s game. Then you won’t be the first
freshman to start on the Varsity basketball team at our school.”
Example 2: “If America doesn’t send weapons to the Syrian rebels, they won’t be able to defend
themselves against their warring dictator. They’ll lose their civil war, and that dictator will oppress them,
and the Soviets will consequently carve out a sphere of influence that spreads across the entire Middle
East.”
6. Circular Argument (petitio principii)
When a person’s argument is just repeating what they already assumed beforehand, it’s not arriving at
any new conclusion. We call this a circular argument or circular reasoning. If someone says, “the Bible
is true because the Bible says it’s true”—that’s a circular argument. One is assuming that the Bible only
speaks truth, and so they trust it to truthfully report that it speaks the truth. Another example of circular
reasoning is, “According to my brain, my brain is reliable.” Well, yes, of course we would think our
brains are in fact reliable if our brains are the one’s telling us that our brains are reliable.

Circular arguments are also called Petitio principii meaning “Assuming the initial [thing]” (commonly
mistranslated as “begging the question”). This fallacy is a kind of presumptuous argument where it
only appears to be an argument. It’s really just restating one’s assumptions in a way that looks like an
argument. You can recognize a circular argument when the conclusion also appears as one of the
premises in the argument.

Another way to explain circular arguments is that they start where they finish, and finish where they
started. See if you can identify which of these is a circular argument.

Example 1: “Abstract art isn’t even art. Those pictures and sculptures don’t represent anything, and
that’s how you know its not even art.”
Exmaple 2: “We should be tolerant even of people who believe intolerant ideas. Their ideas matter too,
and we can still learn different things from them even if their particular intolerant idea is wrong.”

7. Hasty Generalization
Hasty generalizations are general statements without sufficient evidence to support them. They are
general claims too hastily made, hence they commit some sort of illicit assumption, stereotyping,
unwarranted conclusion, overstatement, or exaggeration.

Normally we generalize without any problem. We make general statements all the time: “I like going to
the park,” “Democrats disagree with Republicans,” “It’s faster to drive to work than to walk,” or
“Everyone mourned the loss of Harambe, the Gorilla.”

Hasty generalization may be the most common logical fallacy because there’s no single agreed-upon
measure for “sufficient” evidence.
Indeed, the above phrase “all the time” is a generalization—we aren’t all the time making these
statements. We take breaks to do other things like eat, sleep, and inhale. These general statements
aren’t addressing every case every time. They are speaking generally, and, generally speaking, they
are true. Sometimes you don’t enjoy going to the park. Sometimes Democrats and Republicans agree.
Sometimes driving to work can be slower than walking if the roads are all shut down for a Harambe
procession.

Hasty generalization may be the most common logical fallacy because there’s no single agreed-upon
measure for “sufficient” evidence. Is one example enough to prove the claim that “Apple computers are
the most expensive computer brand?” What about 12 examples? What about if 37 out of 50 apple
computers were more expensive than comparable models from other brands?

There’s no set rule for what constitutes “enough” evidence. In this case, it might be possible to find
reasonable comparison and prove that claim is true or false. But in other cases, there’s no clear way to
support the claim without resorting to guesswork. The means of measuring evidence can change
according to the kind of claim you are making, whether it’s in philosophy, or in the sciences, or in a
political debate, or in discussing house rules for using the kitchen. A much safer claim is that “Apple
computers are more expensive than many other computer brands.”

Meanwhile, we do well to avoid treating general statements like they are anything more
than generalizations. Even if it were generally true that women are bad drivers—and I’m not saying they
are—there are still plenty of women who are good drivers. And those “cases” just aren’t covered with
that general statement even if it were true. In my case, my wife is a better driver than I am. So I do well
not to generalize too widely.

A simple way to avoid hasty generalizations is to add qualifiers like “sometimes,” “maybe,” “often,” or “it
seems to be the case that . . . “. When we don’t guard against hasty generalization, we risk
stereotyping, sexism, racism, or simple incorrectness. But with the right qualifiers, we can often make a
hasty generalization into a responsible and credible claim.

Which of the following is a hasty generalization

Example 1: “Some people vote without seriously weighing the merits of the candidate.”
Example 2: “People nowadays only vote with their emotions instead of their brains.”

8. Red Herring (ignoratio elenchi)


A “red herring” is a distraction from the argument typically with some sentiment that seems to be
relevant but isn’t really on-topic. Typically, the distraction sounds relevant but isn’t quite on-topic. This
tactic is common when someone doesn’t like the current topic and wants to detour into something else
instead, something easier or safer to address. Red herrings are typically related to the issue in question
but aren’t quite relevant enough to be helpful. Instead of clarifying and focusing they confuse and
distract.

Red herrings can be difficult to identify because it’s not always clear how different topics relate.
The phrase “red herring” refers to a kippered herring (salted herring-fish) which was reddish brown in
color and quite pungent. According to legend, this aroma was so strong and delectable to dogs that it
served as a good training device for testing how well a hunting dog could track a scent without getting
distracted. Dogs aren’t generally used for hunting fish so a red herring is a distraction from what he is
supposed to be hunting.

Red herrings can be difficult to identify because it’s not always clear how different topics relate. A “side”
topic may be used in a relevant way, or in an irrelevant way. In the big meaty disagreements of our day,
there are usually a lot of layers involved, with different subtopics weaving into them. We can guard
against the red herring fallacy by clarifying how our part of the conversation is relevant to the core topic.

Which of the following examples is a red herring fallacy?

Example 1: “My wife wants to talk about cleaning out the garage, so I asked her what she wants to do
with our patio furniture? Now she’s shopping for new patio furniture and not bothering me about the
garage.”
Example 2: “My wife wants to talk about cleaning out the garage, so I asked her what she wants to do
with the patio furniture? It’s just sitting in the garage taking up space.”

9. Tu Quoque Fallacy
The “tu quoque,” Latin for “you too,” is also called the “appeal to hypocrisy” because it distracts from the
argument by pointing out hypocrisy in the opponent. This tactic doesn’t solve the problem, or prove
one’s point, because even hypocrites can tell the truth. Focusing on the other person’s hypocrisy is a
diversionary tactic. In this way, the tu quoque typically deflects criticism away from one’s self by
accusing the other person of the same problem or something comparable.  If Jack says, “Maybe I
committed a little adultery, but so did you Jason!” Jack is trying to diminish his responsibility or defend
his actions by distributing blame to other people. But no one else’s guilt excuses his own guilt. No
matter who else is guilty, Jack is still an adulterer.

The tu quoque fallacy is an attempt to divert blame, but it really only distracts from the initial problem.
To be clear, however, it isn’t a fallacy to simply point out hypocrisy where it occurs. For example, Jack
may say, “yes, I committed adultery. Jill committed adultery. Lots of us did, but I’m still responsible for
my mistakes.” In this example, Jack isn’t defending himself or excusing his behavior. He’s admitting his
part within a larger problem. The hypocrisy claim becomes a fallacy only when the arguer uses some
(apparent) hypocrisy to neutralize criticism and distract from the issue.

Which of the following is a tu quoque fallacy

Example 1: “But, Dad, I know you smoked when you were my age, so how can you tell me not to do it?”
Example 2: “Son, yes, I smoked when I was your age, it was dumb then. And it’s dumb now. That’s why
I forbid you to smoke, chew, or vape, or use nicotine gum, or whatever you kids do with tobacco these
days.”

10. Causal Fallacy


The Causal Fallacy is any logical breakdown when identifying a cause. You can think of the Causal
Fallacy as a parent category for several different fallacies about unproven causes.

One causal fallacy is the False Cause or non causa pro causa (“not the-cause for a cause”) fallacy,
which is when you conclude about a cause without enough evidence to do so. Consider, for example,
“Since your parents named you ‘Harvest,’ they must be farmers.” It’s possible that the parents are
farmers, but that name alone is not enough evidence to draw that conclusion. That name doesn’t tell us
much of anything about the parents. This claim commits the False Cause Fallacy.

Another causal fallacy is the Post Hoc fallacy. Post hoc is short for post hoc ergo propter hoc (“after
this, therefor because of this”). This fallacy happens when you mistake something for the cause just
because it came first. The key words here are “Post” and “propter” meaning “before” and “cause.” Just
because this came before that doesn’t mean this caused that. Post doesn’t prove propter. A lot of
superstitions are susceptible to this fallacy. For example:

“Yesterday, I walked under a ladder with an open umbrella indoors while spilling salt in front of a black
cat. And I forgot to knock on wood with my lucky dice. That must be why I’m having such a bad day
today. It’s bad luck.”

Now, it’s theoretically possible that those things cause bad luck. But since those superstitions have no
known or demonstrated causal power, and “luck” isn’t exactly the most scientifically reliable category,
it’s more reasonable to assume that those events, by themselves, didn’t cause bad luck. Perhaps that
person’s “bad luck” is just his own interpretation because he was expecting to have bad luck. He might
be having a genuinely bad day, but we cannot assume some non-natural relation between those events
caused today to go bad. That’s a Post Hoc fallacy. Now, if you fell off a ladder onto an angry black cat
and got tangled in an umbrella, that will guarantee you one bad day.

Another kind of causal fallacy is the correlational fallacy also known as cum hoc ergo property
hoc (Lat., “with this therefore because of this”). This fallacy happens when you mistakenly interpret two
things found together as being causally related. Two things may correlate without a causal relation, or
they may have some third factor causing both of them to occur. Or perhaps both things just,
coincidentally, happened together. Correlation doesn’t prove causation.

Consider for example, “Every time Joe goes swimming he is wearing his Speedos. Something about
wearing that Speedo must make him want to go swimming.” That statement is a correlational fallacy.
Sure it’s theoretically possible that he spontaneously sports his euro-style swim trunks, with no thought
of where that may lead, and surprisingly he’s now motivated to dive and swim in cold, wet nature.
That’s possible. But it makes more sense that he put on his trunks because he already planned to go
swimming.

Which kind of causal fallacy is at work in these examples?

Example 1: “Jimmy isn’t at school today. He must be on a family trip.”


Example 2: “Jimmy has a fever, sinus congestion, a cough, and can’t come to school, so he probably
has a test later today.”
Example 3: “Someone really should move this ‘Deer Crossing’ sign. This is a dangerous stretch of
highway and the deer really should be crossing somewhere else.”

11. Fallacy of Sunk Costs


Sometimes we invest ourselves so thoroughly in a project that we’re reluctant to ever abandon it, even
when it turns out to be fruitless and futile. It’s natural, and usually not a fallacy to want to carry on with
something we find important, not least because of all the resources we’ve put into it. However, this kind
of thinking becomes a fallacy when we start to think that we should continue with a task or project
because of all that we’ve put into it, without considering the future costs we’re likely to incur by doing
so. There may be a sense of accomplishment when finishing, and the project might have other values,
but it’s not enough to justify the cost invested in it.

We are susceptible to this errant behavior when we crave that sense of completion or a sense of
accomplishment
“Sunk cost” is an economic term for any past expenses that can no longer be recovered. For example,
after watching the first 6 episodes of Battlestar Galactica, you decide the show isn’t for you. Those six
episodes are your “sunk cost.” But, because you’ve already invested roughly 6 hours of your life into it,
you rationalize that you might as well finish it. All apologies to Edward James Olmos, but this isn’t “good
economics” so to speak. It’s more cost than benefit.

Psychologically, we are susceptible to this errant behavior when we crave that sense of completion or a
sense of accomplishment, or we are too comfortable or too familiar with this unwieldy project.
Sometimes, we become too emotionally committed to an ‘investment,’ burning money, wasting time,
and mismanaging resources to do it.

Consider the following examples. Which of these is a sunk cost fallacy and which is not?

Example 1: “I know this relationship isn’t working anymore and that we’re both miserable. No marriage.
No kids. No steady job. But I’ve been with him for 7 years, so I better stay with him.”
Example 2: “I’m halfway done with college. This is so tough, and It’s not nearly as fun as I thought it
would be, but I don’t know. I guess I’ll finish it and get my degree.”

12. Appeal to Authority (argumentum ad verecundiam)


This fallacy happens when we misuse an authority. This misuse of authority can occur in a number of
ways. We can cite only authorities—steering conveniently away from other testable and concrete
evidence as if expert opinion is always correct. Or we can cite irrelevant authorities, poor authorities, or
false authorities.

Like many of the other fallacies in this list, the argumentum ad verecundiam (“argument from respect”)
can be hard to spot. It’s tough to see, sometimes, because its normally a good responsible move to cite
relevant authorities supporting your claim. It can’t hurt. But if all you have are authorities, and everyone
just has to “take their word for it” without any other evidence to show that those authorities are correct,
well then you have a problem.

Often this fallacy refers to irrelevant authorities—like citing a foot doctor when trying to prove something
about Psychiatry; his or her expertise is in an irrelevant field. When citing authorities to make your case,
you need to cite relevant authorities, but you also need to represent them correctly, and make sure their
authority is legitimate.

Suppose someone says, “I buy Fruit of the Loom™ underwear because Michael Jordan says it’s the
best.” But Michael Jordan isn’t a relevant authority when it comes to underwear. This is a fallacy of
irrelevant authority.

Now consider this logical leap: “4 out of 5 dentists agree that brushing your teeth makes your life
meaningful.” Dentists generally have expert knowledge about dental hygiene, but they aren’t qualified
to draw far-reaching conclusions about its meaningfulness. This is a fallacy of misused authority. For all
we know, their beliefs about the “meaning of life” are just opinions, not expert advice.

Or take the assumption that “I’m the most handsome man in the world because my Mommy says so.”
Now, while I might be stunningly handsome, my Mom’s opinion doesn’t prove it. She’s biased. She’s
practically required to tell me I’m handsome because it’s her job as a mother to see the best in me and
to encourage me to be the best I can be. She’s also liable to see me through “rose-colored glasses.”
And, in this case, she’s not an expert in fashion, modeling, or anything dealing in refined judgments of
human beauty. She’s in no position to judge whether I’m the most handsome man in the world. Her
authority there is illusory. (Sorry Mom.)

There’s another problem with relying too heavily on authorities. Even the authorities can be wrong
sometimes. The science experts in the 16th century thought the earth was the center of the solar
system (Geocentrism). Turns out they were wrong. The leading scientists, in the 19th century, thought
the universe as we know it always existed (Steady State theory). They too were wrong. For these
reasons, it’s a good general rule to treat authorities as helpful guides with suggestive evidence. But
even authorities deserve a fair share of skepticism since they can make mistakes, overstep their
expertise, and otherwise mislead you.

Consider the following examples. How do these statements mishandle authorities?

Example 1: “Because Martin Sheen played the president on Television, he’d probably make a great
president in real life.”
Example 2: “One day robots will enslave us all. It’s true. My computer science teacher says so.”
Example 3: “This internet news site said that the candidate punches babies. We know that’s true
because it’s on the internet.”

13. Equivocation (ambiguity)


Equivocation happens when a word, phrase, or sentence is used deliberately to confuse, deceive, or
mislead by sounding like it’s saying one thing but actually saying something else. Equivocation comes
from the roots “equal” and “voice” and refers to two-voices; a single word can “say” two different things.
Another word for this is ambiguity.

When it’s poetic or comical, we call it a “play on words.” But when it’s done in a political speech, an
ethics debate, or in an economics report, for example, and it’s done to make the audience think you’re
saying something you’re not, that’s when it becomes a fallacy. Sometimes, this is not a “fallacy” per se,
but just a miscommunication. The equivocation fallacy, however, has a tone of deception instead of just
a simple misunderstanding. Often this deception shows up in the form of euphemisms, replacing
unpleasant words with “nicer” terminology. For example, a euphemism might be replacing “lying” with
the phrase “creative license,” or replacing my “criminal background” with my “youthful indiscretions,” or
replacing “fired from my job” with “early retirement.” A romantically involved couple might discuss their
relationship to others as “just friends” so they appear like they have no other romantic relations. When
these replacement words are used to mislead people they become an equivocation fallacy.

Which of these examples is an equivocation fallacy?

Example 1: “His political party wants to spend your precious tax dollars on big government. But my
political party is planning strategic federal investment in critical programs.”
Example 2: “I don’t understand why you’re saying I broke a promise. I said I’d never speak again to my
ex-girlfriend. And I didn’t. I just sent her some pictures and text messages.”

14. Appeal to Pity (argumentum ad misericordiam)


Argumentum ad misericordiam is Latin for “argument to compassion”. Like the ad hominem fallacy
above, it is a fallacy of relevance. Personal attacks, and emotional appeals, aren’t strictly relevant to
whether something is true or false. In this case, the fallacy appeals to the compassion and emotional
sensitivity of others when these factors are not strictly relevant to the argument. Appeals to pity often
appear as emotional manipulation. For example,

“How can you eat that innocent little carrot? He was plucked from his home in the ground at a young
age, and violently skinned, chemically treated, and packaged, and shipped to your local grocer and now
you are going to eat him into oblivion when he did nothing to you. You really should reconsider what
you put into your body.”
Obviously, this characterization of carrot-eating is plying the emotions by personifying a baby carrot like
it’s a conscious animal. So, by the time the conclusion appears, it’s not well-supported. If you are to be
logically persuaded to agree that “you should reconsider what you put into your body,” then it would
have been better evidence to hear about unethical farming practices or unfair trading practices such as
slave labor, toxic runoffs from fields, and so on.

Truth and falsity aren’t emotional categories, they are factual categories. They deal in what is and is
not, regardless of how one feels about the matter. Another way to say it is that this fallacy happens
when we mistake feelings for facts. Our feelings aren’t disciplined truth-detectors unless we’ve trained
them that way. So, as a general rule, it’s problematic to treat emotions as if they were (by themselves)
infallible proof that something is true or false. Children may be scared of the dark for fear there are
monsters under their bed, but that’s hardly proof of monsters.

Truth and falsity aren’t emotional categories, they are factual categories.
To be fair, emotions can sometimes be relevant. Often, the emotional aspect is a key insight into
whether something is morally repugnant or praiseworthy, or whether a governmental policy will be
winsome or repulsive. People’s feelings about something can be critically important data when planning
a campaign, advertising a product, or rallying a group together for a charitable cause. But it becomes a
fallacious appeal to pity when the emotions are used in substitution for facts or as a distraction from the
facts of the matter.

It’s not a fallacy for jewelry and car companies to appeal to your emotions to persuade you into
purchasing their product. That’s an action, not a claim, so it’s can’t be true or false. It would however be
a fallacy if they used emotional appeals to prove that you need this car, or that this diamond bracelet
will reclaim your youth, beauty, and social status from the cold clammy clutches of Father Time. The
fact of the matter is, you probably don’t need those things, and they won’t rescue your fleeting youth.

Which of these is a fallacious appeal to emotion, and which one is not?

Example 1: “The government needs to hear our cry because we are scared. We are scared that this
candidate will not respect us or protect us. We are scared about our future. There’s no hope for people
like us with these candidates in office.”
Example 2: “These candidates stated that they would close down the education department and that
has many teachers worried about their jobs in 2017.”

15. Bandwagon Fallacy


The bandwagon fallacy assumes something is true (or right, or good) because other people agree with
it. A couple different fallacies can be included under this label, since they are often indistinguishable in
practice. The ad populum fallacy (Lat., “to the populous/popularity”) is when something is accepted
because it’s popular. The concensus gentium (Lat., “consensus of the people”) is when something is
accepted because the relevant authorities or people all agree on it. And the status appeal fallacy is
when something is considered true, right, or good because it has the reputation of lending status,
making you look “popular,” “important,” or “successful.”

For our purposes, we’ll treat all of these fallacies together as the Bandwagon Fallacy. According to
legend, politicians would parade through the streets of their district trying to draw a crowd and gain
attention so people would vote for them. And whoever supported that candidate was invited to literally
jump on board the bandwagon. Hence the nickname “Bandwagon Fallacy.”
This tactic is common among advertisers. “If you want to be like Mike (Jordan), you’d better eat your
Wheaties.” “Drink Gatorade because that’s what all the professional athletes do to stay hydrated.”
“McDonald’s has served over 99 billion, so you should let them serve you too.” The form of this
argument often looks like this: “Many people do or think X, so you ought to do or think X too.”

One problem with this kind of reasoning is that the broad acceptance of some claim or action is not
always a good indication that the acceptance is justified. People can be mistaken, confused, deceived,
or even willfully irrational. And when people act together, sometimes they become even more foolish—
i.e., “mob mentality.” People can be quite gullible, and this fact doesn’t suddenly change when applied
to large groups. Which of these is a bandwagon fallacy?

Example 1: “Almost everyone at my school will be at the party Friday night. It must be a popular thing to
do.”
Example 2: “Almost everyone at my school will be at the party Friday night. It must be the right thing to
do.”

You might also like