Contextual Factors: Cognitive Operations, Embodiment, and Context
Contextual Factors: Cognitive Operations, Embodiment, and Context
Contextual Factors
The issue of context has been, in the main, neglected in cognitive linguistic
and much other work on how conceptual systems change and vary. In most
recent work on conceptual systems, the issues of embodied cognition and the
universal nature of cognitive operations have been emphasized. By contrast,
my major goal in the chapter and in this book is to characterize some of the
contextual factors that are involved in shaping the conceptual system. My focus
is on metaphorical concepts, as well as on the interaction between metaphori-
cal aspects of the conceptual system and contextual factors. I propose that in
many cases metaphorical concepts do not arise from prestored mappings in the
conventional conceptual system, as is often assumed in the cognitive linguistic
literature on metaphor, but result from the priming effect of contextual factors
in real situations of discourse on the human mind to establish metaphors. I
begin to explore this issue in the present chapter, and continue the discussion
in Chapters 6 and 7, where I in addition focus on the closely related topic of
metaphorical creativity.
The cognitive operations we use are universal in the sense that all (cog-
nitively normal) human beings are capable of performing them. Much of the
embodiment on which conceptual systems are based is universal (but see Casa-
santo, 2009 and Chapter 5). Despite the universality of the operations and that
of embodiment, the conceptual systems vary considerably both cross-culturally
and within cultures, with individual variation as a limiting case. This is possi-
ble because the contexts are variable and in different contexts people often use
differential operations. In addition, the prominence of certain cognitive oper-
ations may be greater or smaller across groups of people. The changeability of
contexts and that of cognitive operations as affected by differential contexts
leads to differential conceptual systems.
Although I fully recognize the importance of universal embodiment in our
conceptual system and that of the universal availability of cognitive operations,
it seems to me that much of the work on (the metaphorical aspects of) concep-
tual systems does not pay sufficient attention to the role of contextual factors
in shaping what we know and how we think about the world. My major goal in
this chapter is to attempt to characterize some of the contextual factors that are
involved in this process and to show one possible way in which it can happen.
My focus will be on metaphorical concepts and on the interaction between met-
aphorical aspects of the conceptual system and contextual factors.
Cognitive linguists have, in general, paid more attention to the role of the body
than that of context in the creation of conceptual metaphors, supporting the
view of embodied cognition. In my own work, I attempted to redress the bal-
ance by focusing on what I take to be the equally important role of the context
(Kövecses, 2005). In particular, I suggested that there are a number of ques-
tions we have to deal with in order to arrive at a reasonable theory of metaphor
variation. The questions are as follows:
What are the dimensions of metaphor variation?
What are the aspects of conceptual metaphors that are involved in
variation?
What are the causes of metaphor variation?
The first question has to do with “where” metaphor variation can be found. My
survey of variation in conceptual metaphors indicated that variation is most
likely to occur cross-culturally, within-culture, or individually, as well as histor-
ically and developmentally. I called these the “dimensions” of metaphor varia-
tion. Conceptual metaphors tend to vary along these dimensions.
The second question assumes that conceptual metaphors have a number of
different aspects, or components, including the following: source domain, target
domain, experiential basis, relationship between the source and target, meta-
phorical linguistic expressions, mappings, entailments (inferences), nonlinguis-
tic realizations, blends, and cultural models. These either produce metaphor
variation (e.g., blends) or are affected by it (e.g., source domain, metaphorical
linguistic expressions, entailments).
The third question is the crucial one as regards the role of context in met-
aphorical conceptualization. It asks what the factors, or “forces,” are that are
responsible for variation in conceptual metaphors. I proposed two distinct,
though interlocking, groups of factors: differential experience and differential
cognitive styles. I found it convenient to distinguish various subcases of differ-
ential experience: awareness of context, differential memory, and differential
concerns and interests.
Awareness of context includes awareness of the physical context, social
context, cultural context, but also awareness of the immediate communicative
situation. Differential memory is the memory of events and objects shared by a
community or of a single individual; we can think of it as the history of a group
or that of an individual. Differential concerns and interests can also characterize
Contextual Factors 53
either groups or individuals. It is the general attitude with which groups or indi-
viduals act or are predisposed to act in the world. Differential experience, thus,
characterizes both groups and individuals, and, as context, it ranges from global
to local. The global context is the general knowledge that the whole group shares
and that, as a result, affects all group members in using metaphors. The local
context is the specific knowledge that pertains to a specific situation involving
particular individuals. More generally, it can be suggested that the global con-
text is essentially a shared system of concepts in long-term memory (reflected in
conventional linguistic usage), whereas the local context is the situation in which
particular individuals conceptualize a specific situation making use of working
memory. (I discuss the global–local distinction further in Chapters 5 and 6.)
By contrast, the cognitive processes, discussed in Chapter 2, such as elabo-
ration, specificity, conventionalization, transparency, (experiential) focus, view-
point preference, prototype categorization, framing, metaphor vs. metonymy
preference, and others, though universally available to all humans, are not em-
ployed in the same way by groups or individuals. Since the cognitive processes
used can vary, there can be variation in the use of metaphors as well.
In sum, the two large groups of causes, differential experience and differen-
tial cognitive styles, account for much of the variation we find in the use of con-
ceptual metaphors. However, it is only differential experience that can prime, or
prompt, the use of particular conceptual and linguistic metaphors. The various
cognitive operations that make up the characteristic cognitive styles of either
individuals or groups can merely constrain them. For this reason, the survey
that follows is limited to the influence of differential experience on metaphor
creation and variation.
Let us now review how the contextual factors that constitute differential expe-
rience mentioned earlier can influence the creation of metaphors in particular
communicative situations.
been sufficient to redeem himself and clean up the sport of cycling. Several
experts who were interviewed thought that additional steps must be taken by
Armstrong to achieve this. One specialist in crisis management said this in an
interview: “To use an analogy from the Tour de France, he’s still in the moun-
tain stage, and will be for some time” (USA TODAY, 6W Sports, Weekly Inter-
national Edition, 2013). What we have here is that the specialist has extensive
knowledge about the topic of the discourse, which is Armstrong’s doping scan-
dal. That knowledge includes that as a cyclist Armstrong participated in several
Tour de France events and that this race has several “mountain stages.” In other
words, the topic of the discourse primed the speaker to choose a metaphor to
express a particular idea, namely, that, to come completely clean, Armstrong
has a long and difficult way to go. This idea was expressed by the mountain
stage metaphor, which is based on the mapping “impediment to motion → dif-
ficulty of action (making full confession and being forgiven)” in the ACTION
IS MOTION conceptual metaphor.
Surrounding Discourse
Sometimes it is the surrounding linguistic context (i.e., what comes before and
after a particular unit of discourse) that influences the choice of metaphors,
as in the sentence “The Americanization of Japanese car industry shifts into
higher gear,” analyzed by Kövecses (2005). The expression shift into higher gear
is used because the immediate linguistic context involves the “car industry.”
Given a particular topic, a range of conceptual metaphors can be set up. Such
metaphors, that is, metaphorical source domains, often lead to new or modified
source domains in the continuation of the debate involving the topic by, for ex-
ample, offering a new or modified source domain relative to one of the former
ones. This commonly occurs in scientific discussion (for examples, see Nerlich,
2007) and can lead to the establishment of a chain of related metaphorical
source domains for a target.
However, often we are not aware of potential further “usurpations” of the
metaphor against our original intentions. This situation has its dangers and can
be the source of other people turning a metaphor against us in a debate over
contentious issues. A particularly apt illustration of this happening is provided
by Elena Semino (2008). Tony Blair used the following metaphor in one of his
speeches:
Get rid of the false choice: principles or no principles. Replace it with the
true choice. Forward or back. I can only go one way. I’ve not got a reverse
gear. The time to trust a politician most is not when they’re taking the easy
Contextual Factors 55
been recycled over the ages. As an example, let us take a bookmark I was given
in Durham cathedral a few years ago with the following text on it (the example
is first discussed in Kövecses, 2010a):
Almighty God
Who called your servant Cuthbert
from keeping sheep to follow your son
and to be shepherd of your people.
Mercifully grant that we, following his
example and caring for those who are lost,
may bring them home to your fold.
Through your son.
Jesus Christ our Lord.
Amen.
In the prayer, the basic conceptual metaphor is the one in which the shepherd
is Jesus, the lost sheep are the people who no longer follow God’s teachings, the
fold of the sheep is people’s home with God, and for the shepherd to bring the
sheep back to the fold is for Jesus to save the people. We can lay out these cor-
respondences, or mappings, more explicitly as follows:
Source: Target:
the shepherd → Jesus
the lost sheep → the people who do not follow God
the fold of the sheep → the state of people following God
the shepherd bringing back the → Jesus saving the people
sheep
This metaphor was reused later on when God called a simple man, called
Cuthbert, to give up his job (which, significantly, was being a shepherd) and
become a “shepherd of people.” Here it is Cuthbert (not Jesus) who saves the
lost people (a set of people different from the ones in Jesus’ times). Finally, in
the most recent recycling of the metaphor in the prayer said on St. Cuthbert’s
day, 20 March, 2007, the particular values of the metaphor change again. It is
the priests who live today who try to bring people back to the fold—again, a
set of people different from either those who lived in Jesus’ or Cuthbert’s times.
This type of intertextuality characterizes not only Christianity (and other
religions) through time but many other domains within the same historical
period. Thus a metaphor can provide coherence across a variety of discourses
both historically and simultaneously.
Ideology underlying a piece of discourse can determine the metaphors that are
used. Goatly’s work (see, especially, 2007) shows that different ideologies can
Contextual Factors 57
lead to the use of different metaphors relating to the same subject matter. I dis-
cuss an example in a later section of the chapter.
Physical Environment
Although in general I agree with this account of the metaphor used, I would
also add that the metaphor arises from the physical(-social) context in which
it is produced. Dr. Kumi Naidoo creates the metaphor whisper against a back-
ground in which there is a very loud concert and a comparatively quiet summit
meeting. We can think of the loudness and the relative quiet of the occasion as
perceptual features of the two events. In other words, I would suggest that the
particular metaphor derives from some of the perceptual features that charac-
terize the physical(-social) setting.
58 Where Metaphors Come From
Social Situation
Social aspects of the setting can involve such distinctions as man vs. woman,
power relations in society, conceptions of work, and many others. They can all
play a role in which metaphors are used in the course of metaphorical concep-
tualization. (For examples, see Kövecses, 2005 and Chapter 6.)
Cultural Situation
History
Individuals and groups may be characterized by some major interests and con-
cerns in the way they conduct their lives. Either individuals or groups may be
dedicated to particular activities, rather than others. The commonly and habit-
ually pursued activities (of either groups or individuals) become metaphorical
source domains more readily than those that are marginal. (For an example for
this kind of influence, see Chapter 6.)
These are some of the contextual factors that do seem to play a role in
shaping metaphorical conceptualization, more specifically, in creating (often
novel) metaphors. Most of the time the factors do not function by themselves;
instead, they exert their influence on the conceptualization process jointly. Sev-
eral of the factors listed above can simultaneously influence the use of meta-
phors (see Chapters 6 and 7).
I now turn to the analysis of the concept of self to see how one of the
contextual factors mentioned previously, ideology, may influence its concep-
tualization. The examination of this example will lead to a need to reconsider
and refine the view presented so far concerning the influence of context on
metaphor creation.
60 Where Metaphors Come From
Happiness (personal)
Achievement (personal)
Self-interest
Selfishness
Suspicion
Pride
Competition
Indifference
However, there are societies where the notion of the self goes together with
a different network of concepts. The network of concepts that follow can be
regarded as the opposite of the network above:
64 Where Metaphors Come From
Interdependence
Other-centered
Saving the other’s face
Self-denial
Social goals and desires
Happiness (social)
Achievement (social)
Interest (social)
Sharing
Trust
Humility
Cooperation
Care, Concern
Where such a network of concepts exists, we can call that society collectivistic.
It can be described in the following way:
The concepts that characterize collectivistic societies can also be found in indi-
vidualistic ones, and the concepts that characterize individualistic societies can
also be found in collectivistic ones. After all, individualistic societies do have
the concepts used to characterize collectivistic societies, and probably we have
a similar situation with regard to the concepts that characterize collectivistic
ones. However, in both cases we have preferential tendencies as regards the
co-occurrence of the preceding concepts.
The two sets of concepts can be brought into correspondence with each
other in the following way:
Since the concepts come from the two ends of the same scale, they appear to
be each other’s opposites. For example, in the intended sense, independence is
the opposite of interdependence, personal happiness is that of social happi-
ness, suspicion is that of trust, and pride is that of humility. Thus, the concept
of the self seems to co-occur with two very different networks of concepts. In
the former, the self is highly emphasized and in the latter it is deemphasized.
This conclusion makes it necessary to propose a more refined view of con-
textual influence on metaphorical conceptualization than I suggested at the
beginning of the chapter. There my initial assumption was that differences in
contextual factors will lead to differences in metaphorical conceptualization.
But what we actually saw in the preceding paragraphs was that differences in
the contextual factor of ideology did not lead to differences in metaphorical
conceptualization—at least in the three languages/cultures we examined. In-
stead, the contextual factor of ideology led to a difference in the salience of
the concept of self. The self appears to be much more salient in individualistic
societies (characterized by the first network of concepts) than in collectivistic
ones (characterized by the second). In other words, contextual influence may
not necessarily affect metaphorical conceptualization but can affect other as-
pects of concepts (such as salience).
66 Where Metaphors Come From
four domains or mental spaces allowing for mappings not just from the source
domain to the target but also mappings from both (or more) of the input spaces
into the blended space and even from the blend into the input spaces. Indeed,
proponents of conceptual integration theory (CIT) think of metaphor as a
relatively superficial cognitive phenomenon in comparison to blending. What
interests me in this connection is the following question: Does the assumed
higher degree of cognitive elaborateness and depth of conceptual integration
make it immune to the “surface” effects of contextual factors that appear to
characterize metaphor, as shown earlier in this chapter?
In this section, I will go over some examples of conceptual blends and ask
if context plays any role in how they work. More specifically, one issue that can
be raised in connection with conceptual integration is why particular networks
(made up of a generic space, several input spaces, and a blended space) are
formed and expressed the way they are; in particular, why do they have the
input spaces and the particular figurative linguistic expressions they do? I think
part of the answer lies in the role of contextual factors I discussed earlier in
connection with metaphor.
Let us begin with an example of blending studied by Coulson and Oakley
(2000: 187). Coulson and Oakley take the newspaper headline “Tennessee
Tramples Kentucky” and analyze it as follows:
Processes of representational contracting and stretching are what Faucon-
nier and Turner (2000) refer to as compression and decompression, phe-
nomena which they see as central to blending theory. One place where
compression is quite frequent is in news headlines, such as Tennessee
Tramples Kentucky, or Overseas Absentee Ballots Boost Bush. In each case,
the representation in the blended space is interpretable because of meto-
nymic relationships between elements in the blended space and elements
in the inputs. For example, the blended space in the network for Tennessee
Tramples Kentucky is interpretable because of conventional metonymic
mappings between states, their universities, and their universities’ football
teams, as well as conventional metaphoric mappings between combat and
sports.
What seems to be missing from this analysis is an explanation of why we have
the particular metaphorical expression trample in the example. It is not suf-
ficient to say that it is present because of the sport is war/fight/combat con-
ceptual metaphor. There are many expressions that could be used based on this
metaphor (such as defeat, beat, overpower), but of all the possibilities trample
is used. I suggest the reason is that the phonological shape of the linguistic
context triggers the choice of trample over the other potential alternatives.
(On the role of phonological shape in the motivation of metaphorical expres-
sions, see Benczes, 2013.) Trample alliterates with Tennessee. This is admittedly
a very simple, almost trivial, effect of the linguistic context on the choice of
68 Where Metaphors Come From
university cowboys
opponent 1
football team 1
university buffaloes
opponent 2
football team 2
opp. 1 cowboys corall
defeats opp.2 buffaloes
university 1/opp.1/
cowboys
university 2/opp.2/
buffaloes
defeating/coralling
Blend
Figure 4.1 The “Cowboys Corral Buffaloes” blend.
Contextual Factors 69
its effect on creating metaphors in discourse is not part of the conceptual tools
of CIT, it cannot account for this kind of variation in the use of metaphorical
expressions. At the same time, however, I do not wish to imply that the linguis-
tic context always produces this effect.
Coulson and Oakley (2003: 54) examine another example that is very simi-
lar to the corral, cook, drown, and so on, examples. It is a headline again: “Coke
Flows Past Forecasts: Soft Drink Company Posts Gains” from USA TODAY.
They describe the example as follows:
Although I agree with much of this analysis, I would add that the metaphor-
ical verb flows is used here, as opposed to several other alternatives, such as
goes, exceeds, surpasses, because both the immediate linguistic context and the
more general topic influences the choice of the verb. Since coke is a liquid, it
can flow, which is a semantic feature of the word. Thus, the word coke provides
the immediate linguistic context that may motivate the selection of a verb from
among the alternatives in the discourse. In addition to the immediate linguistic
context, the general topic, the subject matter of the discourse, may also play a
role. Since the topic is how the corporation makes profit with its best-known
product, Coca Cola, which is a liquid, this may trigger or prime the use of the
verb flow as well. In other words, in this case the linguistic context and the
topic of the discourse may jointly lead to the selection of a metaphorically
used word.
As a final illustration of a contextual effect, let us take one of the most
celebrated examples of CIT: “If Clinton were the Titanic, the iceberg would
sink.” The input spaces have the Titanic and Clinton, respectively. The Titanic
corresponds to Clinton and the iceberg that hits the Titanic corresponds to
the scandal that hurt Clinton’s presidency. In addition, there is a conventional
metaphor at work here. As Turner and Fauconnier (2000: 135) note in connec-
tion with the example: “It is uncontroversial that cases like the Clinton-Titanic
example involve the basic metaphor purposeful activity is traveling along
a path toward a destination – the traveler projects to the agent, reaching the
destination projects to achieving the goal, and so on, . . . .” But, of course, the
sentence conveys more than the metaphors can account for; namely, that Clin-
ton is so strong that he survives the crisis that the scandal involved him in. This
reading does not come from the Titanic input space, where the Titanic sinks
as a result of its collision with the iceberg. It comes from the blended space
70 Where Metaphors Come From
that uses the Titanic scenario with Clinton as the Titanic, plus causal struc-
ture that is projected to the blend from the Clinton input space (i.e., where
Clinton survived the scandal). Thus, in the blend, we have the Clinton/Titanic
sinking the scandal/iceberg, rather than the scandal/iceberg causing the
Clinton/Titanic’s ruin.
The example shows very clearly a major advantage of CIT, as already
shown in Chapter 2; namely, that meaning does not always arise from simple
correspondences between source and target. What this type of analysis does not
show, though, is why we have the particular input spaces that we do in the net-
work of spaces. In other words, we can ask: Why is it that in order to talk about
the Clinton scandal, the speaker of the sentence uses the Titanic scenario, and
not some other potentially available scenario? In other words, it is not clear at
all what motivates the presence of Titanic input space in the network.
I believe that the model of metaphor creation in context can provide an
account for many such cases, though maybe not for all. In the present exam-
ple, the Clinton–Titanic blend came about because the Titanic movie was very
much in public awareness at the time the blend was created. Thus, in the view
I am proposing, it can be suggested that many of the metaphorical blends are
invented as a result of the influence of what I call the “immediate cultural con-
text” (more on this in Chapter 6). As a matter of fact, Turner and Fauconnier
themselves also draw our attention to the fact that the blend could not have
come about in 1992 without the Titanic catastrophe to begin with and without
the wide popularity of the movie inside the Washington Beltway during the
Clinton presidency. Thus Turner and Fauconnier provide the justification and
motivation for the emergence of the blend in this particular case, but I would
like to see this as falling out systematically from the framework that has been
developed in this chapter.
The four cases of blending that have been considered in the section seem to
result partially from the effect of context on the use of metaphors and blends:
the first from the influence of the phonological shape of the immediate linguis-
tic context, the second from the (semantic) effect of the immediate linguistic
context, the third from the combined effect of the linguistic context and the
general topic, and the fourth from the immediate cultural context. I suspect
that in many other cases of blending the other factors discussed in the chapter
can play a similar role.
Conclusions
A number of contextual factors have been identified in this chapter, but possi-
bly there are more. The workings of these factors suggest that conceptualizers
take advantage of the various factors that make up the immediate (local) and
nonimmediate (global) context in which metaphorical conceptualization takes
Contextual Factors 71
PHYSICAL ENVIRONMENT
SOCIAL SETTING
CULTURAL CONTEXT
speaker/conceptualizer
hearer/conceptualizer
topic
f low of discourse