Our Mathematical Universe?: June 2014
Our Mathematical Universe?: June 2014
net/publication/263201015
CITATION READS
1 12,334
1 author:
Jeremy Butterfield
University of Cambridge
155 PUBLICATIONS 3,495 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:
All content following this page was uploaded by Jeremy Butterfield on 28 December 2014.
1
in
a
different
direction
from
all
the
matter
that
makes
the
universe
we
can
now
observe-‐-‐-‐or
even,
will
ever
observe.
Could
that
be
so?
Well,
the
Big
Bang
is
a
tough
topic
to
understand
in
detail!
But
a
framework
for
understanding
it,
called
inflationary
cosmology,
answers:
‘Yes,
it
is
so-‐-‐-‐and
there
are
not
just
a
few
‘lost
twins’
of
bits
of
early
matter,
but
countlessly
many:
each
of
them
zooming
off,
never
to
be
seen
by
us,
and
also
never
to
be
seen
by
almost
all
other
such
bits
of
matter-‐-‐-‐or
rather,
by
whatever
observers
those
bits
of
matter
might
eventually
aggregate
into’.
So
inflationary
cosmology
proposes
‘separating
the
children
from
one
another
at
birth’
on
a
truly
cosmic
scale!
But
how
much
should
we
trust
inflationary
cosmology?
There
is
good
news
and
bad
news.
The
good
news
is
that
in
the
thirty
years
since
the
idea
of
inflation
was
first
invented
(in
about
1980),
it
has
had
several
theoretical
and
even
observational
successes.
(Cf.
for
example
the
Plus
Magazine
article
on
the
Planck
satellite:
http://plus.maths.org/content/what-‐planck-‐saw.)
So
much
so,
that
it
is
now
physicists’
orthodox
view
of
the
very
early
universe.
The
bad
news
is
that-‐
-‐-‐as
always-‐-‐-‐we
should
also
listen
to
the
counsel
of
caution,
the
voice
of
scepticism.
It
says:
we
must
distinguish
between
established
facts
and
speculations.
This
is
the
first
of
several
counsels
of
caution
(‘health
warnings’)
that
I
will
need
to
issue
as
as
we
proceed
through
Uncle
Max’s
Levels.
Tegmark
himself
of
course
writes
in
a
style
of
enthusiastic
advocacy.
But
to
his
credit,
he
also
intermittently
pauses
to
emphasize
that
his
stances
are
controversial,
and
also
to
reply
in
some
detail
to
possible
objections,
or
indeed
to
actual
critics.
See
for
example,
his
reply
to
George
Ellis
on
pp.
360-‐363.
I
should
also
note
that
this
controversy
is
widespread
among
very
distinguished
cosmologists.
For
example,
one
recent
critique
of
inflation
(and
specifically
of
the
recent
BICEP2
experiment)
by
Paul
Steinhardt
concludes
that
‘the
inflationary
paradigm
is
fundamentally
untestable,
and
hence
scientifically
meaningless’
(Nature,
vol
510,
5
June
2014,
p.
9:
cf.
http://www.nature.com/polopoly_fs/1.15346!/menu/main/topColumns/topLeftColumn/pdf/5
10009a.pdf
).
Agreed:
modern
cosmology
has
established
that
all
the
matter
in
the
universe
we
can
now
observe
was
once
in
a
hot,
dense
fireball
about
the
size
of
the
solar
system.
It
has
done
this
by
combining
precision
cosmological
observations,
with
established
physical
theories:
especially
general
relativity,
and
the
standard
model
of
particle
physics,
which
has
for
forty
years
stood
up
very
well
to
countless
tests,
for
example
at
the
LHC
in
CERN,
Geneva.
(Cf.
for
example
Plus
Magazine’s
articles
on
the
Higgs
boson:
http://plus.maths.org/content/hooray-‐higgs-‐edit-‐0,
and
http://plus.maths.org/content/higgs.)
So
‘the
standard
model’
means
our
quantum
field
theoretic
account
of
how
particles
like
electrons
and
quarks
behave
at
energies
we
can
access.
Those
energies
were
attained
in
the
early
universe
when
it
was
about
the
size
of
the
solar
system,
at
about
10
-‐9
seconds
after
the
Big
Bang.
So
this
consilience
of
cosmology
and
quantum
field
theory
at
high
energies
is
undoubtedly
a
stupendous
scientific
achievement.
Besides,
our
theories
describing
that
hot,
dense
fireball
can
be
extrapolated
back
still
further.
But
as
the
radius
becomes
smaller,
and
the
temperatures,
densities
and
energies
become
higher,
we
leave
established
facts
and
enter
the
realms
of
speculation.
And
for
the
epoch
at
which
inflation
is
supposed
to
have
happened,
we
are
most
certainly
far
beyond
the
realm
of
established
physics.
That
is:
we
are
far
beyond
the
energies
at
which
we
know
both
general
relativity,
and
the
standard
model
of
particle
physics,
to
be
accurate.
Indeed,
at
the
end
of
inflationary
epoch
(if
there
was
one!),
the
radius
of
the
entire
present
observable
universe
was
about
1
metre-‐-‐-‐wow!
But
let
us
be
bold!
Let
us
accept
inflationary
cosmology’s
answer
to
our
question
‘Could
that
be
so?’
Let
us
accept
that
there
are
countless
‘lost
twins’,
separated
into
vastly
many
diverse
universes,
and
that
observers
in
those
universes
will
never
observe
each
other
directly.
This
is
the
Level
I
Multiverse.
Before
we
hit
Level
II,
we
should
note
that
Uncle
Max
has
another
mind-‐bending
suggestion.
Some
inflationary
models
suggest
there
are
infinitely
many
such
universes,
now
mutually
un-‐
2
detectable.
If
so,
there
seems
nothing
to
stop
any
specific
scenario
which
you
believe
happened-‐-‐-‐
some
Tyrannosaurus
Rex
running
through
some
Jurassic
landscape,
Napoleon
being
defeated
at
Waterloo,
or
Uncle
Max’s
nearly-‐fatal
bike
accident-‐-‐-‐being
played
out,
in
replica
form,
in
another
of
these
universes.
Indeed,
there
seems
nothing
to
stop
the
scenario
being
played
out,
in
replica
form,
any
number
of
times
across
the
whole
set
of
universes.
Indeed:
even
infinitely
many
times.
And
what
goes
for
a
scenario
which
you
believe
happened,
goes
just
as
well
for
scenarios
which
you
believe
did
not
happen.
Imagine
Napoleon
winning
at
Waterloo.
Or
rather,
imagine
someone
very
like
Napoleon,
in
intrinsic
respects
(the
hat,
the
arm
in
the
waistcoat
…)
and
in
historical
role
(an
artillery
engineer
who
became
a
conquering
general
.
.
.),
winning
at
a
battle
very
like
Waterloo
(a
flat
landscape,
soldiers
in
red
coats
sounding
like
Englishmen
.
.
.).
Imagine
all
this
being
filled
out
in
some
totally
specific
way.
Of
course
all
the
myriad
details
vastly
outstrip
your
powers
of
description:
even
if,
to
tell
your
tale,
you
could
live
much
longer
than
three
score
years
and
ten.
But
nevermind
the
undescribability
of
it.
Just
imagine
any
such
totally
specific
way
in
which
(to
put
it
briefly!)
‘Napoleon
wins
at
Waterloo’.
Then
the
point
is:
there
seems
nothing
to
stop
that
exact
scenario
being
played
out
in
another
of
these
universes.
And
similarly
for
all
the
countless
other
variants
of
(again:
to
put
it
briefly!)
‘Napoleon
winning’;
and
also,
of
course
for
all
the
countless
variants
of
‘his
losing’.
This
is
giddy
stuff,
to
be
sure.
But
so
far,
the
alternative
universes
we
have
envisaged
have
been
modest
in
one
crucial
respect.
Yes,
they
vary
in
myriad
ways:
but
the
variations
concern
particular
matters
of
fact,
localized
in
space
and
time.
A
dinosaur
runs,
or
doesn’t.
A
man
loses
a
battle,
or
wins
it.
There
is,
so
far,
no
variation
in
the
physical
laws
that
govern
processes.
That
is:
assume
for
a
moment
that
general
relativity
gives
the
correct
laws
for
gravity,
and
quantum
mechanics
gives
the
correct
laws
for
chemical
reactions.
Then
the
point
is:
so
far,
we
have
not
envisaged
a
different
law
of
gravity
governing
the
dinosaur’s
run,
or
a
different
chemistry
governing
the
general’s
digestion
of
his
lunch.
But
in
inflationary
cosmology,
many
models
suggest
that
the
physical
laws
do
vary
across
the
set
of
universes.
If
that
is
right,
what
we
call
‘physical
laws’
or
‘laws
of
nature’-‐-‐-‐the
deepest
and
most
general
patterns
displayed
by
the
ways
in
which
physical
events
play
out
in
our
universe-‐-‐-‐
would
be
better-‐called
‘bye-‐laws’.
For
think
of
how
the
laws
enacted
by
a
municipal,
rather
than
national,
government
are
called
‘bye-‐laws’;
(‘bye’,
like
‘burgh’
and
‘borough’,
derives
from
the
old
Anglo-‐Saxon
word
for
a
settlement
or
town).
This
panoply
of
universes,
differing
in
their
laws,
as
well
as
their
particular
matters
of
fact,
Tegmark
calls
the
‘Level
II
Multiverse’
.
.
.
II.
The
Level
II
Multiverse
One
immediately
asks:
exactly
what
kinds
of
variation
(and
how
much
variation
of
each
kind),
are
being
suggested?
Of
course,
it
all
depends
on
the
model
chosen
.
.
.
Here
we
should
bear
in
mind
that
inflationary
cosmology
is
a
framework
of
ideas
and
results,
not
a
theory
that
is
defined
with
all
due
mathematical
rigour.
So
neither
are
its
individual
models-‐-‐-‐
and
there
is
a
lot
of
room
for
debate
about
which
models
are
best.
This
is
regrettable,
of
course.
But
the
point
does
not
apply
only
to
inflationary
cosmology.
The
standard
model-‐-‐-‐indeed
any
of
our
quantum
field
theories
of
interacting
systems-‐-‐-‐is
also
not
defined
with
all
mathematical
rigour.
Accordingly,
many
brilliant
people,
working
in
the
more
mathematical
areas
of
theoretical
physics,
are
working
to
provide
more
rigorous
formulations
of
quantum
field
theories,
and
thus
also
of
inflationary
cosmology.
(In
fact
the
problems
of
rigour
are
deep:
they
originate
in
the
theories’
answers
to
straightforward
questions
involving
troubling
infinities.
I
will
return
to
these
problems
when
discussing
renormalization
at
the
end
of
this
Section.
And
you
can
read
more
about
them
in
Plus
magazine’s
quantum
field
theory
articles,
at:
http://plus.maths.org/content/brief-‐history-‐quantum-‐field-‐theory.
Cf.
especially
http://plus.maths.org/content/problem-‐infinity)
3
So
let
us
bear
this
warning
in
mind,
but
nevertheless
proceed-‐-‐-‐and
ask:
what
kinds
of
variation
are
being
suggested?
At
first
sight,
there
seem
to
be
two
different
ways
in
which
‘the
laws
of
physics
could
be
different’.
I
will
present
them
in
Sections
IIA
and
IIB.
But
as
we
will
see
at
the
end
of
this
Section,
inflationary
cosmology
suggests
that
the
first
way
in
fact
happens
as
a
special
case
of
the
second
way.
IIA.
Varying
constants
The
first
way
is
the
obvious
one:
just
imagine
altering
the
equations!
A
lot
of
attention
has
focused
on
what
seem
the
most
modest
sorts
of
alteration.
Namely,
not
replacing
‘the
whole
shebang’
(like
chucking
the
equations
of
general
relativity
in
the
bin,
in
favour
of
Newton’s
theory
of
gravity
or
other
modern
rivals
of
general
relativity),
but
altering
the
values
of
parameters
occurring
in
the
equations,
while
keeping
the
same
form
for
the
equations,
including
which
quantities
they
mention.
These
parameters
are
often
constants
of
nature.
For
example:
imagine
altering
the
speed
of
light,
or
the
strength
of
gravitational
attraction
as
encoded
in
Newton’s
constant
in
his
universal
law
of
gravitation,
or
the
ratio
of
the
strengths
of
the
gravitational
and
electromagnetic
forces.
In
the
last
several
decades,
there
has
been
a
lot
of
speculation
about
what
the
world
would
be
like
under
such
alterations
(or
combinations
of
them).
And
these
speculations
have
been
very
fruitful,
for
two
reasons.
First:
since
one
is
‘only’
(!)
altering
the
values
of
parameters,
this
means
that
calculating
what
the
world
would
be
like
is
much
more
tractable
than
it
would
be,
if
one
also
altered
the
form
of
the
laws-‐-‐-‐for
who
knows
what
alternative
laws
one
should
focus
on?
Second:
it
has
turned
out,
in
countless
such
calculations,
that
even
rather
small
alterations
of
parameters’
values
from
their
actual
values
would
make
for
a
world
that
is
incompatible
with
life
as
we
know
it.
For
example,
the
altered
physics
would
be
incompatible
with
the
formation
of
stars
and
of
planets,
and
thus
of
the
complex
carbon-‐based
chemistry
on
which
life
depends.
Here,
we
meet
the
idea
of
‘anthropic
reasoning’.
Roughly
speaking,
this
is
the
idea
that
we
might
take
this
result-‐-‐-‐that
only
a
narrow
window
around
the
actual
value
of
a
constant
of
nature
is
compatible
with
life
as
we
know
it-‐-‐-‐to
be
the
best
explanation
of
why
the
value
is
what
it
is.
But
this
is
not
the
place
to
pursue
this
topic.
(For
more
discussion,
cf.
pp.
143
and
302
of
Tegmark’s
book;
or
many
articles
in
Plus
magazine,
such
as
http://plus.maths.org/content/planets-‐
universes-‐part-‐I;
and
http://plus.maths.org/content/why-‐are-‐we-‐here;
Cf.
also
Wilczek
(2008);
the
definitive
book-‐length
treatment
remains
Barrow
and
Tipler
(1986).)
For
my
purpose
here-‐-‐-‐namely,
to
summarize
Tegmark’s
four-‐level
multiverse-‐-‐-‐all
I
need
at
the
moment
is
the
idea
of
varying
the
laws
of
physics
by
making
such
variations
in
the
constants.
This
is
the
first
of
the
two
ways
of
varying
the
laws;
and
as
I
mentioned,
it
is
the
more
obvious
one.
II.B.
Varying
laws
by
breaking
a
symmetry
The
second
way
is
best
introduced
by
an
analogy
with
a
crystal
forming,
and
how
such
a
process
exhibits
‘breaking
a
symmetry’.
When
a
crystal
forms,
its
atoms
line
up
in
a
regular
lattice;
for
example
a
cubical
lattice
like
in
Escher’s
famous
picture.
Such
a
lattice
can
be
tilted
one
way
or
another:
the
rods
do
not
have
to
be
vertical
and
horizontal,
as
they
are
in
Escher’s
picture.
In
fact,
in
a
real
crystal
the
lattice
is
not
tilted
in
the
exact
same
way
throughout
the
crystal.
Instead,
the
crystal
is
made
up
of
tiny
patches,
called
domains.
In
any
one
domain,
comprising
perhaps
millions
of
atoms,
the
lattice
is
tilted
in
the
same
way.
But
the
lattices
in
different
domains
will
have
different
tilts.
Agreed:
all
this
is
hardly
surprising.
Typically
the
crystal
forms
by
cooling
a
sample
of
liquid.
(Remember
the
blue
copper
sulphate
crystals
you
made
in
chemistry
class
at
school,
competing
for
who
had
the
gentle
touch
to
grow
the
biggest
one!).
The
atoms
settling
down
into
a
lattice
is
an
example
of
that
ubiquitous
phenomenon
in
physics
and
chemistry:
a
system
settling
down
into
its
state
of
lowest
energy.
Ideally,
the
lattice
would
have
the
same
tilt
throughout
the
entirety
of
the
sample.
The
entire
sample
would
form
one
vast
domain,
and
the
energy
would
indeed
be
4
lowest
since
there
would
be
no
domain-‐walls,
i.e.
lines
or
surfaces
within
the
crystal
where
the
tilt
changes,
with
an
associated
energy
cost.
But
that
is
of
course
very
much
an
ideal,
i.e.
an
unrealistic,
situation.
In
reality,
there
will
be
a
vast
number
of
tiny
events
scattered
throughout
the
cooling
liquid
(e.g.
the
presence
of
a
speck
of
dust,
or
a
passing
cosmic
ray):
each
of
which
can
result
in
a
shift
in
the
local
orientation
of
the
lattice.
To
sum
up:
we
expect
the
physics
and
chemistry
of
the
crystal’s
atoms
to
determine
the
general
shape
of
the
lattice,
e.g.
is
it
cubical,
as
in
the
picture?
But
we
expect
the
exact
orientation
to
be
a
matter
of
sheer
happenstance,
influenced
by
local
events;
and
so
it
is
very
likely
to
be
different,
in
different
parts
of
the
crystal.
There
is
a
buzz-‐word
for
the
variety
in
the
tilts,
the
different
tilts
in
the
different
domains:
symmetry-‐breaking.
The
idea
is:
the
physics
and
chemistry
of
the
crystal’s
atoms,
and
the
overall
cooling
process,
does
not
prefer
one
tilt
over
any
others.
These
principles
allow
the
lattice
any
orientation
in
space:
they
have
full
rotational
symmetry.
But
a
specific
state
of
the
system,
i.e.
a
specific
domain,
breaks
the
symmetry:
it
picks
an
orientation-‐-‐-‐because
of
microscopic
causes
that
we
may
never
know
(nor
care!)
about.
This
scenario,
of
symmetric
principles
having
a
non-‐symmetric
instance,
generalizes.
Namely:
a
law,
or
collection
of
laws,
of
physics
can
have
a
symmetry,
while
a
solution
to
those
laws
lacks
it-‐-‐
-‐and
again,
not
because
of
some
mystery,
but
simply
as
a
matter
of
sheer
happenstance.
Once
you
grasp
this
idea,
you
realize
that
examples
are
everywhere:
they
are
two
a
penny.
For
example,
Newton’s
laws
of
mechanics
and
his
law
of
gravitation
are
rotationally
symmetric.
They
encode
no
preferred
orientation.
Formally
speaking:
if
you
calculate
how
your
equation
expressing
these
laws
is
transformed
by
rotating
the
coordinate
system
around
any
axis
by
any
chosen
amount
(e.g.
around
the
axis
passing
through
the
Earth’s
North
Pole,
by
a
33
degree
angle),
you
will
find
that
the
equation
remains
exactly
the
same.
On
the
other
hand,
almost
all
the
solutions
of
Newton’s
laws,
i.e.
the
instantaneous
states
of
bodies
(particles,
planets
…)
obeying
Newton’s
laws,
are
not
rotationally
symmetric.
They
are
not
transformed
into
themselves
by
a
rotation
about
any
axis,
by
any
amount.
That
would
require
that
the
solution
is
spherically
symmetric,
like
a
perfectly
symmetric
sphere
of
dust.
In
short:
the
solution
breaks
the
symmetry
enjoyed
by
the
law.
Of
course,
this
is
in
no
way
a
problem:
it
is
exactly
what
one
would
expect-‐-‐-‐the
instantaneous
state
of
a
collection
of
bodies
is
usually
not
symmetric,
and
the
lack
of
symmetry
is
no
doubt
usually
a
matter
of
sheer
happenstance,
of
historical
contingency—of
where
the
bodies
happened
to
be
placed
and
how
they
happened
to
be
moving.
So
much
by
way
of
explaining
the
idea
of
symmetry-‐breaking.
The
idea
is
very
important,
quite
apart
from
Tegmark’s
Level
II
multiverse.
Suitably
developed,
it
is
crucial
in
various
parts
of
modern
physics.
But
for
present
purposes,
its
importance
is
that
it
engenders
a
second
way
in
which
one
can
envisage
‘altering
the
laws
of
physics’.
To
see
this,
imagine
you
are
a
tiny
homunculus
living
in
the
domain
of
a
crystal
with,
say,
a
cubical
lattice;
and
knowing
nothing
of
the
world
beyond
that
domain.
As
it
happens,
common
table
salt
has
a
cubic
lattice.
So
imagine
you
live
in
(a
domain
of)
a
crystal
of
salt.
Confined
as
you
are
to
your
tiny
environment,
you
might
well
be
unaware
that
the
tilt
of
the
lattice
in
your
domain
is
a
matter
of
sheer
happenstance.
You
might
well
imagine
that
the
tilt
of
your
domain
is
as
much
a
matter
of
law,
as
is
the
cubical
structure
of
the
lattice.
Thus
in
the
jargon
of
‘bye-‐laws’
which
I
introduced
at
the
end
of
Section
I:
the
tilt
of
your
domain
is
in
fact
a
bye-‐law-‐-‐-‐merely
a
regularity
of
your
local
environment.
But
since
you
know
nothing
of
the
world
beyond
your
domain,
you
might
well
mistake
it
for
a
universal
law.
The
second
way
of
‘altering
the
laws
of
physics’
is
now
clear.
The
suggestion
from
inflationary
cosmology
is:
we
might
be
like
the
homunculus!
What
we
take
to
be
the
laws
of
physics
might
be
5
merely
bye-‐laws:
with
different
bye-‐laws
being
true
in
some,
indeed
most,
of
the
other
universes
of
the
multiverse,
universes
which
we
will
never
observe.
So
in
the
analogy
with
the
crystal,
the
universes
of
the
multiverse
are
like
the
domains
of
the
crystal.
And
more
specifically:
these
bye-‐laws
might
involve
symmetry-‐breaking.
They
might
break
a
symmetry
of
some
genuine
law-‐-‐-‐a
law
that
holds
good
across
the
multiverse-‐-‐-‐by
incorporating
some
or
other
matter
of
sheer
happenstance-‐-‐-‐a
matter
that
played
out
differently
in
different
universes.
Indeed,
the
analogy
with
the
crystal
can
be
pushed
further:
just
as
the
crystal’s
domains
settle
into
various
different
lower-‐energy
states
during
a
global
process
of
cooling,
the
multiverse’s
universes
settle
into
various
different
lower-‐energy
states
during
a
global
process
of
cooling.
Besides,
it
turns
out
that
in
some
models
of
inflationary
cosmology,
this
second
way
of
‘altering
the
laws
of
physics’
incorporates
the
first:
which
(cf.
Section
IIA)
involved
changing
the
constants
of
nature.
Here,
two
other
great
themes
of
modern
physics
enter
our
story.
One
is
called
‘renormalization’.
But
it
also
has
a
more
vivid
label:
‘running
constants’.
The
other
has
only
one
name,
but
a
very
familiar
one:
string
theory.
Thus
the
first
theme
is
that
a
constant
of
nature
can
be
dependent
on
the
energy
involved
in
the
process
concerned.
The
jargon
is
that
the
constant
‘runs’
with
the
energy
scale;
so
people
talk
about
‘running
constants’.
Agreed,
this
certainly
sounds
like
weasel-‐words,
to
avoid
sounding
self-‐contradictory
by
saying
‘varying
constants’!
(Or
maybe
it
sounds
like
statistics
about
your
training
for
the
marathon,
collated
by
your
athletics
coach!)
But
actually,
it
is
not
self-‐contradictory.
In
fact,
it
reflects
a
profound
physical
idea:
the
idea
of
renormalization.
This
is
a
big
topic
which
returns
us
to
quantum
field
theory’s
troubling
infinities,
which
I
mentioned
at
the
start
of
this
Section.
I
will
not
go
further
into
it.
But,
again,
you
can
read
more
about
it
in
Plus
magazine
quantum
field
theory
articles.
Among
those
articles,
how
renormalization
tames
the
troubling
infinities
is
emphasized
in:
http://plus.maths.org/content/rise-‐qed
http://plus.maths.org/content/quantum-‐pictures
and
http://plus.maths.org/content/going-‐flow-‐0
So
if
we
accept
that
a
constant
of
nature
can
be
dependent
on
energy,
and
that
the
universe-‐-‐-‐
okay,
the
multiverse!-‐-‐-‐is
cooling
down
after
the
Big
Bang
like
an
enormous-‐-‐-‐okay,
ginormous!-‐-‐-‐
fluid
which
is
slowly
crystalizing,
then
it
makes
sense
that
the
constants
might
also
settle
down,
as
the
energy
decreases,
to
rather
different
values
in
different
domains
of
the
multiverse:
i.e.
in
different
universes
of
the
Level
1
multiverse.
It
is
one
thing
to
say
‘it
makes
sense
that
the
constants
might
also
settle
down
to
different
values
in
different
domains’.
It
is
another
thing
to
have
a
specific
theory
saying
that
indeed
they
do!
And
here
enters
the
second
theme:
string
theory.
Again,
we
first
need
a
‘health
warning’.
Like
the
theories
previously
mentioned-‐-‐-‐
quantum
field
theories,
inflationary
cosmology-‐-‐-‐string
theory
is
not
yet
defined
in
a
mathematically
rigorous
way.
(Indeed,
it
is,
broadly
speaking,
more
ill-‐defined
than
quantum
field
theory:
most
string
theorists
agree
that
what
we
call
‘string
theory’
is
really
a
collection
of
insights
into
a
theory
we
do
not
yet
‘have’,
in
the
way
we
do
quantum
field
theory.)
But
let
us
again
proceed,
bearing
in
mind
that
the
voice
of
scepticism
is
again
whispering
in
our
ears.
String
theory
is
of
course
complicated.
(For
some
details,
cf.
the
Plus
article
http://plus.maths.org/content/string-‐theory-‐newton-‐einstein-‐and-‐beyond).
But
for
the
purpose
of
expounding
Tegmark’s
multiverse,
all
we
need
is
the
fact
that
string
theory
indeed
does
propose
that
familiar
constants
of
nature,
such
as
the
ratio
of
the
strengths
of
the
gravitational
and
electromagnetic
forces,
could
settle
down
to
different
values
in
different
domains
of
the
Level
I
multiverse.
Roughly
speaking,
each
domain
is
associated
with
a
different
lowest-‐energy
state
of
string
theory.
6
(Here
we
meet
other
bits
of
jargon.
(1)
These
different
lowest-‐energy
states
are
called
‘vacua’.
This
jargon
is
taken
over
from
quantum
field
theory.
To
be
honest,
it
is
misleading,
since
‘vacuum’
suggests
there
is
nothing,
i.e.
no
system:
while
in
this
usage,
there
is
always
a
system-‐-‐-‐
the
various
fields
and
strings-‐-‐-‐and
‘vacuum’
denotes
a
state
of
lowest
energy.
(2)
The
complicated
set
of
possible
states,
with
the
various
different
minima,
is
called
‘the
landscape’.)
Thus
we
see
how
the
second
way
of
‘altering
the
laws
of
physics’-‐-‐-‐symmetry-‐breaking
and
us
being
like
the
homunculus
in
a
domain
of
a
salt
crystal-‐-‐-‐
incorporates
the
first,
i.e.
altering
the
constants
of
nature.
So
much
by
way
of
convincing
you
that
the
multiverse
involves
varying
laws.
Welcome
to
Level
II!
III.
The
Level
III
Multiverse
I
turn
to
Uncle
Max’s
Level
III.
It
concerns
the
interpretation
of
quantum
theory:
a
controversial
area
which
we
have
not
yet
had
to
tangle
with,
despite
referring
to
quantum
field
theories.
But
I
will
discuss
it
only
briefly.
For
it
concerns
a
topic
which
readers
of
Plus
magazine
will
be
very
familiar
with.
Namely:
the
paradox
of
‘Schroedinger’s
cat’,
and
the
proposal
to
resolve
it
by
adopting
the
Everettian
interpretation
of
quantum
theory,
also
known
as
the
‘many
worlds
interpretation’-‐-‐-‐the
very
phrase
clearly
suggests
a
multiverse!
Recall
that
‘Schroedinger’s
cat’
is
really
a
parable
for
making
vivid
the
measurement
problem
of
quantum
theory.
(For
details,
cf.
the
Plus
magazine
article:
http://plus.maths.org/content/schrodingers-‐equation-‐what-‐does-‐it-‐mean).
The
problem
is:
the
lack
of
values
for
physical
quantities,
such
as
momentum
or
position
or
energy,
that
is
characteristic
of
quantum
theory's
description
of
microscopic
systems,
should
also
infect
the
familiar
macroscopic
realm
of
tables,
chairs
etc.
For
example:
measuring
the
momentum
of
an
electron,
which
is
in
a
state
that
is
not
definite
for
momentum
(called:
‘a
superposition
of
momentum
eigenstates’)
should
lead
to
the
pointer
of
the
apparatus
having
no
definite
position.
Rather,
it
should
be
in
a
superposition
of
states
that
are
definite
for
position
(called
‘position
eigenstates’).
But
this
is
not
what
we
see!
Witness
the
success
of
classical
physics
in
describing
countless
physical
systems
as
having
at
all
times
definite
values
for
all
physical
quantities.
Schroedinger
makes
this
problem
vivid
by
imagining
that
a
cat
is
fatally
poisoned,
or
not,
according
as
a
microscopic
quantum
system
e.g.
an
electron
has,
or
does
not
have,
some
prescribed
value
for
some
prescribed
quantity
(e.g.
value
‘5
units’
for
momentum
in
the
x
direction).
Thus
Schroedinger
describes
what
he
calls
‘an
infernal
device’
in
which
the
opening
of
a
vial
of
poison
registers
a
prescribed
result
‘5
units’
for
a
measurement
of
an
electron
in
a
superposition
of
momentum
eigenstates.
So
the
cat
ends
up
in
a
superposition
of
being
fatally
poisoned,
and
not:
in
a
superposition
of
being
dead
and
alive.
Yikes!
It
is
now
nearly
eighty
years
since
Schroedinger
(in
1935)
wrote
his
‘cat
paper’;
and
nearly
ninety
years
since
he
and
Heisenberg
(in
1925-‐26)
put
quantum
theory
in
its
established
form,
with
its
idea
of
superpositions
of
eigenstates.
Unsurprisingly,
the
measurement
problem
was
immediately
recognized
and
vigorously
debated,
both
by
the
new
theory’s
architects
like
Schroedinger
and
Heisenberg,
and
by
other
luminaries
like
Einstein.
(So
it
was
not
a
matter
of
the
problem
going
unrecognized
until
the
‘cat
paper’
ten
years
later.)
What
is
more
surprising
is
that
to
this
day-‐-‐-‐nearly
ninety
years
later-‐-‐-‐it
remains
controversial.
So
again,
we
need
a
health
warning:
we
are
again
entering
very
contentious
territory.
But
here
it
suffices
to
say
one
of
the
proposed
solutions
yields
Uncle
Max’s
Level
III
multiverse.
Namely,
Everett’s
proposal
(in
1957:
so
more
than
fifty
years
ago)
that,
in
short,
a
quantum
superposition
represents,
not
a
set
of
alternatives
of
which
one
is
real,
but
an
actual
plurality
of
realities.
In
a
bit
more
detail:
the
universe
as
a
whole
has
a
quantum
state,
which
always
evolves
according
7
to
the
Schroedinger
equation:
which
is
continuous
and
indeed
deterministic-‐-‐-‐so
there
is
no
discontinuous
‘collapse
of
the
wave
function’.
Thus
the
universe
contains
a
plethora
of
Everettian
‘worlds’
(also
called
‘branches’),
where
each
such
‘world’
is
something
like
the
familiar
macroscopic
realm,
with
all
tables,
chairs
etc.
in
definite
positions,
with
definite
momenta.
But
the
worlds
differ
among
themselves
about
these
positions
and
momenta.
Of
course,
each
of
us
experiences
only
a
single
definite
macrorealm.
So
the
idea
is:
each
of
us
just
happens
to
be
in
one
world,
rather
than
another
one.
Or
better:
there
are
many
versions
of
each
of
us,
each
version
happening
to
be
in
one
world
rather
than
another.
So
this
is
indeed
a
proposal
for
a
multiverse.
Welcome
to
Level
III!
(To
read
more
about
the
Everettian
worlds,
cf.
the
Plus
article:
http://plus.maths.org/content/parallel-‐universes)
Notice
that
in
some
ways,
the
same
topics
and
questions-‐-‐-‐even
conundrums-‐-‐-‐will
arise
for
it
as
arose
for
the
Level
I
multiverse.
In
that
discussion,
we
envisaged
that
there
are-‐-‐-‐very
far
away,
and
never
observable
by
us-‐-‐-‐all
sorts
of
scenarios
involving
diverse
macroscopic
objects,
some
of
which
might
well
be
uncannily
similar-‐-‐-‐even
utterly
similar-‐-‐-‐to
familiar
scenarios,
like
Napoleon
losing
the
battle
of
Waterloo.
And
we
ended
by
envisaging
that
some
of
the
scenarios
might
be
similar
enough
for
us
to
describe
them
as
containing
a
person
like
Napoleon
and
a
battle
like
Waterloo-‐-‐-‐but
in
which
that
person
(faux
Napoleon,
as
we
might
call
him)
wins
his
battle
(which
we
might
call
faux
Waterloo).
Similarly
here.
Just
as
Schroedinger
envisaged
that
an
electron
having
one
value
of
momentum
rather
than
another
(‘5
units
rather
than
6’)
could
lead
to
a
cat’s
being
dead
or
alive:
so
also,
Everett
and
his
advocates
envisage
that
the
two
or
more
realities
represented
by
some
microscopic
quantum
superposition
might
lead
to
a
macroscopic
course
of
events,
a
history,
‘branching’-‐-‐-‐of
course,
unobservably
for
the
agents
within
it-‐-‐-‐into
two
(or
more)
histories.
For
example,
a
history
could
branch
into
some
in
which
Napoleon
loses
the
battle,
and
some
in
which
he
wins.
And
here
again,
we
have
to
be
careful
about
language.
On
this
view,
‘Napoleon’
really
refers,
not
to
a
single
person
or
human
body,
but
to
each
of
the
many
‘descendants’,
in
the
various
branches,
of
the
original
person
or
body.
Indeed,
the
Everettian
vision
is
that
there
were,
no
doubt,
countless
microscopic
quantum
superpositions
well
before
the
date
of
the
battle,
appropriately
correlated
with
the
values
of
macroscopic
quantities,
so
that
the
years
leading
up
to
the
date
of
the
battle
involved
many
branchings,
and
the
‘one
Napoleon’
whom
we
at
first
envisaged
starting
the
battle
(of
whom
some
descendants
would
win,
and
others
would
lose)
was
himself
one
of
many
descendants
of
earlier
stages
of
a
‘Napoleon-‐like
career’.
So
there
are
some
clear
similarities
between
the
ideas
of
Level
I
and
Level
III.
But
notice
that
the
argument
for
believing
in
Level
III
has
nothing
to
do
with
cosmology.
The
measurement
problem,
and
the
various
proposals
for
solving
it,
and
the
arguments
back
and
forth
between
these
proposals,
are
all
concerned
with
local
physics,
not
with
cosmology.
This
difference
is
clear
in
another
way
also,
when
we
recall
Level
II
with
its
variation
in
the
constants
and
in
the
form
of
the
laws.
The
arguments
for
believing
in
Level
II
concerned
inflationary
cosmology
and
string
theory,
not
the
measurement
problem.
And
similarly
on
the
other
side:
nothing
in
the
various
proposals
for
solving
the
measurement
problem
suggests
variation
in
the
constants,
or
in
the
form
of
the
physical
laws.
IV.
The
Level
IV
Multiverse
And
so
to
Tegmark’s
fourth
and
last
dizzying
vision.
Unlike
the
first
three
Levels,
this
proposal
is
independent
of
the
details
of
physics.
It
is
distinctively
philosophical:
it
is
a
claim
about
how
mathematics
describes
physical
reality.
It
is
also
a
radical
claim:
namely,
that
physical
reality—
not
merely
is
described
by
mathematics-‐-‐-‐but,
instead,
is
mathematics.
About
this
fourth
Level,
I
propose
to
be
more
critical
than
about
the
three
others.
After
all,
philosophical
claims
are,
broadly
speaking,
more
controvertible
than
physical
claims.
This
is
no
doubt
largely
because
the
sorts
of
evidence
counting
for
and
against
them
is
less
sharply
defined
8
than
for
physical
claims.
So
most
philosophers
accept
that
we
make
the
best
progress
in
assessing
philosophical
claims-‐-‐-‐in
so
far
as
we
ever
make
progress!-‐-‐-‐by
subjecting
them
to
rigorous
scrutiny.
So
I
will
first
discuss
the
claim
that
physical
reality
is
mathematics,
in
general
terms:
indeed,
in
partly
historical
terms.
Then
I
will
state
and
assess
Tegmark’s
argument
in
favour
of
it.
But
as
I
just
warned:
I
will
reject
the
claim.
Sorry,
Uncle
Max!
I
will
proceed
in
five
stages,
giving
each
stage
a
Subsection.
First
I
will
state
the
claim,
adding
a
bit
of
history
(Section
IV.A).
Then
I
will
state
my
main
reason
for
rejecting
it:
that
reason
turns
on
introducing
the
distinction
between
pure
and
applied
mathematics
(Section
IV.B).
To
properly
justify
my
rejection,
I
will
then
give
some
details
about
that
distinction
(Section
IV.C).
In
Section
IV.D,
I
will
use
this
distinction
to
rebut
Tegmark’s
own
argument
for
the
claim:
he
argues
that
it
follows
from
something
we
almost
all
accept:
viz.
that
there
is
an
external
reality
completely
independent
of
us
humans.
Finally,
in
Section
IV.E,
I
add
to
my
rebuttal
by
briefly
discussing
a
philosophical
doctrine
about
the
nature
of
physical
properties:
a
doctrine
called
‘quidditism’.
IV.A.
From
Pythagoras
to
Galileo
and
Beyond
Philosophers
have
long
had
a
name
for
the
claim
that
physical
reality
is
mathematics.
They
call
it
‘Pythagoreanism’.
This
refers
to
Pythagoras,
the
ancient
Greek
(ca.
572
–
497
BC).
For
millennia,
he
has
been
regarded
as
a
mystic
mathematician
who,
among
other
accomplishments,
proved
the
theorem
that
bears
his
name,
advocated
the
idea
of
mathematical
proof,
and
believed
that,
in
some
obscure
way,
the
world
was
made
of
numbers,
i.e.
of
mathematics-‐-‐-‐hence
the
‘ism’.
(In
fact,
we
now
know,
thanks
to
modern
scholarship,
that
Pythagoras
did
none
of
these
things.
As
often
happens,
it
is
a
case
of
the
sober
truth
being
duller
than
the
myth.
For
a
glimpse
of
the
details,
cf.
the
review
by
Burnyeat
(2007),
citing
the
scholarly
work
of
Walter
Burkett.)
But
setting
aside
the
details
of
the
historical
Pythagoras,
there
is
no
doubt
that
the
history
of
science,
and
especially
of
physics,
provides
countless
illustrations
of
the
power
of
mathematical
language
to
describe
natural
phenomena.
Famously,
Galileo
himself-‐-‐-‐the
founding
father
of
the
mathematical
description
of
motion-‐-‐-‐envisaged
describing
many,
perhaps
all,
phenomena
in
mathematical
terms.
Thus
in
The
Assayer
(1623),
he
wrote
the
following
(saying
‘philosophy’
in
roughly
the
sense
of
our
words
‘natural
science’
or
‘physics’):
‘Philosophy
is
written
in
this
grand
book
—
I
mean
the
universe
—
which
stands
continually
open
to
our
gaze,
but
it
cannot
be
understood
unless
one
first
learns
to
comprehend
the
language
in
which
it
is
written.
It
is
written
in
the
language
of
mathematics,
and
its
characters
are
triangles,
circles,
and
other
geometric
figures,
without
which
it
is
humanly
impossible
to
understand
a
single
word
of
it;
without
these,
one
is
wandering
about
in
a
dark
labyrinth.’
Of
course,
since
Galileo’s
time
the
language
of
mathematics
has
developed
enormously-‐-‐-‐in
ways
that
even
he,
a
genius,
would
have
found
unimaginable.
After
all,
already
by
the
mid-‐seventeenth
century
the
calculus
was
generalizing
vastly
from
Galileo’s
‘triangles,
circles,
and
other
geometric
figures’,
so
as
to
consider
arbitrary
curves
and
their
slopes
(derivatives)
and
the
areas
under
them
(integrals).
(More
precisely:
the
‘arbitrary’
curves
need
to
satisfy
conditions,
such
as
being
suitably
smooth,
i.e.
differentiable,
so
that
they
indeed
have
a
derivative-‐-‐-‐conditions
that
are
subtle
to
state,
and
were
hard
to
discover,
as
the
long
history
of
rigorizing
the
calculus
attests.)
As
I
have
stated
them
so
far,
these
developments
seem
to
support
Pythagoreanism.
If
mathematics
gives
us
so
powerful
a
language
for
describing
nature,
why
not
conclude
that
nature
is
mathematics?
As
I
said,
Tegmark
endorses
this
claim.
(In
fact,
this
quotation
from
Galileo
is
one
of
the
mottoes
of
his
Chapter
10,
where
he
develops
and
defends
his
Pythagoreanism.)
But
he
also
ties
this
claim
to
his
over-‐arching
theme
of
a
multiverse.
That
is:
we
should
believe
in
the
equal
reality
of
all
the
possible
mathematical
structures.
Welcome
to
Uncle
Max’s
Level
IV!
9
IV.B.
Beware:
‘mathematical
structure’
is
ambiguous
As
I
announced,
my
aim
in
the
rest
of
this
review
is
to
make
sense
of
this
claim
and
criticize
it.
This
will
of
course
involve
clarifying
the
idea
of
‘mathematical
structure’
and
thus
the
idea
of
all
possible
mathematical
structures.
But
I
can
already
state
the
gist
of
what
Tegmark
believes,
and
of
my
critique
of
it.
Tegmark
does
not
claim
only
the
following:
(1)
‘Nature-‐-‐-‐that
is
the
multiverse,
as
described
so
far,
with
its
levels
I
to
III-‐-‐-‐is
a
vastly
complicated
mathematical
structure’.
He
also
claims:
(2)
There
is
a
mathematical
multiverse:
all
possible
mathematical
structures
are
equally
real.
So,
putting
(1)
and
(2)
together,
he
claims:
(3)
The
multiverse,
as
described
so
far,
with
its
levels
I
to
III,
is
just
one
of
countlessly
many,
equally
real,
such
structures.
To
which
I
say:
(i):
I
am
happy
to
concur
with
(1).
Well,
happy
enough
for
present
purposes.
But
I
think
we
should
take
seriously
all
those
health
warnings-‐-‐-‐Beware:
here
be
speculations!-‐-‐-‐in
the
three
previous
Sections.
(ii):
I
am
happy
to
say
(2):
‘There
is
a
mathematical
multiverse:
all
possible
mathematical
structures
are
equally
real.’
But
I
mean
by
this
something
different
from
what
Tegmark
means:
both
different
and
less
controversial
.
.
.
let
me
explain
.
.
.
In
a
word,
my
message
to
Uncle
Max
is:
Distinguish!
That
is:
we
must
distinguish
between
applied
mathematics
(also
called:
theoretical
physics)
and
pure
mathematics.
And
once
we
make
this
distinction,
there
are
three
important
conclusions.
We
see
that:
(a)
It
is
for
applied
mathematics
that
claim
(1)
is
tenable.
That
is:
it
is
tenable
that
the
multiverse,
as
described
so
far,
with
its
levels
I
to
III
is
an
applied
mathematical
structure.
And
as
I
said:
I
concur
with
this.
(b)
It
is
for
pure
mathematics
that
I
am
happy
to
say
(2):
‘There
is
a
mathematical
multiverse:
all
possible
mathematical
structures
are
equally
real.’
Here
I
should
note:
I
say
‘happy’
to
be
vivid,
and
for
rhetorical
simplicity.
I
admit
that
this
belief
in
a
vast
plethora
of
pure
mathematical
structures
is
controversial.
It
is
controversial
because
most
philosophers
maintain
that
all
our
concepts,
beliefs
and
knowledge
come
from
our
experience
of
the
empirical
world:
our
experience
of
nature
in
space
and
time.
That
seems
right
to
me.
But
it
is
hard
to
reconcile
with
our
having
beliefs,
and
even
knowledge,
about
pure
mathematical
structures:
especially
infinite
ones,
since
they
certainly
seem
not
to
be
given
to
us
in
experience.
Incidentally,
this
belief
in
a
plethora
of
pure
mathematical
structures
is
called
‘Platonism’.
Note
that
this
is
not
‘Pythagoreanism’:
because
the
topic
is
pure
mathematics,
not
the
mathematical
description
of
nature.
Thus
I
call
myself
a
‘reluctant
Platonist’:
‘reluctant’
because
Platonism
is
hard
to
reconcile
with
all
our
knowledge
coming
from
our
empirical
experience.
(c)
Platonism
about
pure
mathematics
(whether
reluctant
or
enthusiastic)
has
nothing
to
do
with
a
physical
multiverse.
To
put
the
point
in
terms
of
propositions
(1)
to
(3)
above:
if
(1)
says
nature
is
an
applied
mathematical
structure,
and
(2)
asserts
a
plethora
of
pure
mathematical
structures,
we
cannot
infer
(3),
that
nature
is
one
of
many
equally
real
structures.
Indeed,
some
logic
books
classify
various
tempting
fallacies
of
reasoning.
One
of
them
involves
two
premises
of
an
argument
having
a
word
in
common-‐-‐-‐but
occurring
with
different
meanings.
Assuming
that
in
each
premise
the
word
has
the
meaning
appropriate
there,
the
premises
are
true;
or
at
least,
can
be
allowed
to
be
true,
for
the
sake
of
the
argument.
And
the
argument
looks
valid,
when
you
look
at
the
pattern
of
the
words.
But
the
conclusion
is
false.
This
is
called
‘the
fallacy
of
equivocation’.
An
example,
with
apologies
to
Jane
Austen
and
lovers
of
Pride
and
Prejudice:
‘Elizabeth
Barrett
is
going
to
the
ball.
To
play
cricket,
we
need
the
ball.
Therefore:
Elizabeth
Barrett
is
going
to
what
we
need.”
(Note,
incidentally,
that
the
equivocal
10
word,
the
culprit
for
the
deceiving
pattern
of
words-‐-‐-‐here:
‘the
ball’-‐-‐-‐need
not
occur
in
the
conclusion.)
To
sum
up:
in
Tegmark’s
propositions
(1)
and
(2),
‘mathematical
structure’
is
equivocal
between
applied
and
pure
structures.
That
in
itself
is
no
error.
The
reader
who
is
aware
of
the
distinction
naturally
reads
(1)
and
(2)
with
the
appropriate
meaning:
just
as
in
my
example’s
two
premises,
we
read
‘the
ball’
with
the
appropriate
meaning.
But
it
is
an
error
to
infer
from
(1)
and
(2),
read
with
their
respectively
appropriate
meanings,
to
(3).
For
(3)
needs
to
be
read
with
‘mathematical
structure’
having
one
meaning
or
the
other-‐-‐-‐applied
or
pure.
But
on
either
reading,
it
doesn’t
follow
from
(1)
and
(2).
(Again:
when
they
are
read
with
their
appropriate
meanings-‐-‐-‐meanings
that
make
them
true,
or
at
least,
tenable
for
the
sake
of
the
argument.)
In
short:
beware
the
fallacy
of
equivocation!
The
upshot
of
this
discussion
is
clear.
One
can
believe
in
the
multiverse
including
all
the
Levels
I
to
III.
And
one
can
believe
this
multiverse
is
a
structure
in
the
sense
of
applied
mathematics.
And
one
can
be
a
Platonist
about
pure
mathematics,
i.e.
believe
in
ever
so
many
pure
mathematical
structures.
One
can
believe
all
this
without
believing
that
the
physical
multiverse-‐-‐-‐that
‘supreme’
applied-‐mathematical
structure!-‐-‐-‐is
a
pure
mathematical
structure.
So
much
by
way
of
stating
what
I
called
‘the
gist
of
what
Tegmark
believes,
and
of
my
critique
of
it’.
I
apologize:
for
a
gist,
it
was
inordinately
long.
So
after
a
gist
as
long
as
that,
you
may
not
want
to
hear
further
details!
But
rest
assured:
it
was
the
main
message
of
my
Section
IV.
Thus
what
follows
is
only
for
afficionados
and
enthusiasts.
But
in
the
spirit
of
friendly
philosophical
debate-‐-‐
-‐let
us
proceed!
There
is
more
to
be
said,
in
three
ways.
First,
I
should
give
more
explanation
of
my
distinction
between
applied
and
pure
mathematics:
this
I
do
in
Section
IV.C.
Second,
Tegmark
gives
a
specific
argument
for
the
claim
I
reject:
that
the
physical
multiverse
is
a
(pure)
mathematical
structure.
So
I
need
to
address
this
argument:
I
will
do
so
in
Section
IV.D.
This
leads
to
my
final
task.
For
in
the
course
of
his
argument,
Tegmark
does
briefly
register
that
‘mathematical
structure’
is
ambiguous
in
the
sort
of
way
I
have
expounded.
So
in
in
Section
IV.E,
I
take
this
up:
it
will
lead
us
to
a
philosophical
debate
about
the
nature
of
properties.
IV.C.
Applied
vs.
Pure
Mathematics
To
spell
out
the
distinction
between
applied
and
pure
mathematics,
I
will
describe
each
in
turn.
Applied
mathematics
gives-‐-‐-‐or
at
least:
aims
to
give!-‐-‐-‐true
descriptions
of
empirical,
in
particular
physical,
phenomena
that
are
located
in
space
and
time.
(Here
‘true’
does
not
mean
‘complete’:
our
description
can
be
true
even
though
typically
the
phenomena
have-‐-‐-‐and
we
know
them
to
have-‐-‐-‐myriad
details
that
our
description
omits.)
For
example,
I
spill
my
glass
of
milk
and
it
spreads
across
the
table.
Applied
mathematics
successfully
describes
how
it
flows,
in
terms
of
relevant
physical
quantities,
such
as
the
positions,
velocities
and
densities
of
small
volumes
of
the
milk.
So
in
this
example,
the
neglect
of
myriad
details
is,
in
part,
a
matter
of
neglecting
the
atomic
constitution
of
milk.
Of
course,
this
is
done
by
modeling
the
milk
as
composed
of
volumes
that
are
large
enough
to
contain
many
atoms
(and
so,
we
hope,
to
be
unaffected
by
atomic
phenomena);
but
which
are
also
small
by
our
human
standards,
so
that
the
milk
seems
to
be
continuous
in
its
make-‐up.
For
my
purposes,
the
crucial
feature
of
this
example
is
the
mention
of
relevant
physical
quantities:
in
the
example,
the
mention
of
position,
velocity
and
density.
Of
course,
it
is
one
of
the
great
glories
of
physics
since
Galileo’s
day
that
it
has
introduced
new
quantities-‐-‐-‐sometimes
very
arcane
ones-‐-‐-‐and
refined
old
quantities-‐-‐-‐sometimes
in
very
subtle
ways;
and
has
combined
the
new
and
the
old
in
a
collection
of
laws
and
methods
that-‐-‐-‐though
fallible,
and
indeed
changing
with
the
passing
decades-‐-‐-‐has
gone
from
one
success
to
another,
both
in
theoretical
understanding
and
in
empirical
quantitative
prediction.
As
examples
of
introducing
new
quantities,
we
might
take
(in
roughly
historical
order):
momentum,
kinetic
energy,
potential
energy,
electric
charge,
entropy,
spin.
As
examples
of
11
refining
old
quantities
in
a
subtle
way,
we
might
take
(again,
in
roughly
historical
order):
the
refinement
of
the
concept
of
mass
(and
so
density)
between
the
times
of
Galileo
and
Newton;
Einstein’s
critique
of
absolute
simultaneity
in
the
Newtonian
notion
of
time;
and
his
unification
of
mass
and
energy.
Without
doubt,
these
and
similar
examples
of
the
development
of
physical
concepts
are
among
the
great
glories
of
physics.
And
this
is
so,
wholly
irrespective
of
what
laws
(e.g.
laws
of
motion)
the
concepts
may
enter
into.
Indeed,
this
is
something
that
every
student
of
physics
knows.
Grasping
the
ideas
involved
in
quantities
like
energy,
entropy
or
spin,
is
a
struggle
and
an
achievement-‐-‐-‐and
usually
much
harder
than
remembering
the
general
equations,
i.e.
the
laws,
which
mention
the
quantities!
So
to
round
off
my
sketch
of
physics
(or
applied
mathematics):-‐-‐-‐
We
have
come
along
way
from
Galileo’s
‘triangles,
circles,
and
other
geometric
figures’.
In
his
day,
it
was
indeed
reasonable
to
hope
that
for
its
concepts,
i.e.
its
quantities,
physics
could
manage
with
just
the
concepts
of
geometry
(as
inherited
from
the
Greeks:
triangles,
circles,
areas,
volumes
.
.
.)
and
maybe
a
little
more-‐-‐-‐such
as
notions
of
contact
or
impact,
and
mass
and-‐or
density.
This
was
precisely
the
agenda
of
the
seventeenth
century
corpuscularian
philosophy
(also
called:
mechanical
philosophy)
spearheaded
by
Galileo.
But
it
was
not
to
be.
Nature’s
imagination
outstrips
ours!
So
as
physics
proceeded
to
examine
successive
new
domains
of
phenomena,
it
has
had
to
introduce
a
succession
of
new
quantities
(and
has
also
had
to
refine
old
ones).
It
is
these
distinctive
physical
quantities
(and
of
course,
their
values
for
the
system
described)
that
are
mentioned
by
the
symbols
in
the
equations
of
physics.
So
to
sum
up:
nowadays,
we
should
revise
Galileo’s
saying.
Namely,
instead
of
saying
‘Nature
is
a
book
written
in
the
language
of
mathematics’,
nowadays
we
should
say:
‘Nature
is
a
book
written
in
the
syntax
of
mathematics,
but
with
the
semantics
of
physics’.
(This
aphorism
is
due
to
Ernan
McMullin
in
his
excellent
paper
on
Galilean
idealization
(1985,
p.
252-‐253).)
I
can
now
be
more
precise
about
what
at
the
end
of
Section
IV.B
I
called
an
‘applied-‐mathematical
structure’.
In
short:
it
is
an
assignment
to
each
of
a
collection
of
objects
of
their
values
for
various
relevant
physical
quantities.
Or
to
say
it
with
a
bit
more
physics
jargon,
and
in
a
bit
more
detail:-‐-‐
(i) Physics
tends
to
think
of
an
assignment
as
a
function,
to
call
objects
‘systems’,
and
to
think
of
such
an
assignment
(function)
varying
with
time,
to
represent
values
changing
over
time.
(ii) So
the
short
statement
above
applies
to
a
collection
of
systems
at
a
time:
such
an
assignment
(function)
is
an
‘instantaneous
state’.
But
the
collection
of
such
states
as
time
varies-‐-‐-‐i.e.
a
history
of
the
collection
of
systems-‐-‐-‐
would
of
course
also
count
as
an
applied-‐mathematical
structure.
(iii) Comments
(i)
and
(ii)
apply
to
field
theories,
where
we
think
of
physical
quantities
applying
to
spatial
or
spacetime
points:
e.g.
the
electric
of
magnetic
field
at
points
of
space.
It
is
just
that
here
the
objects
in
question
are
the
points.
(iv) Though
I
will
not
go
into
detail:
these
comments
also
apply
to
quantum
theories,
in
particular
quantum
field
theories.
The
idea
is
that
an
instantaneous
quantum
state
is
specified
by
the
quantities
for
which
it
is
an
eigenstate,
i.e.
definite
in
value.
(To
be
strictly
true,
this
statement
requires
that
we
set
aside
a
subtlety,
called
‘superselection’;
but
let
that
pass.)
So
much
for
applied
mathematics.
What
of
pure
mathematics?
What
did
I
mean
when
above
I
shouted
to
my
Uncle
Max:
‘Distinguish!’
My
point
was
this.
As
every
student
of
mathematics
learns,
in
the
mid-‐nineteenth
century
there
arose,
for
several
reasons,
the
idea
of
mathematics
as
the
investigation
of
arbitrary
structures.
In
other
words:
people
started
to
think
of
mathematics
as
the
investigation
of
the
consequences
of
arbitrary
rules
that
a
mathematician
postulates
as
governing
some
domain
of
elements.
These
rules
are
abstract
in
the
sense
that
only
their
structural
behaviour
counts;
and
the
elements
are
abstract
in
the
sense
that
nothing
is
assumed
about
their
natures,
or
relations
to
one
another,
except
that
they
obey
the
announced
rules.
12
To
clarify
this
development,
it
is
worth
pausing
over
the
history.
I
say
this
happened
‘for
several
reasons’
because
one
can
discern
different
motivations
in
different
branches
of
mathematics.
Three
obvious
ones
are
as
follows.
(1)
In
geometry,
the
rise
of
consistent
axiomatizations
of
non-‐Euclidean
geometries
forced
mathematicians
to
distinguish
between
(a)
the
actual
geometry
of
physical
space-‐-‐-‐an
empirical
matter
that
is
revealed
by
the
behaviour
of
rulers
and
protractors
(‘Do
the
angles
of
this
triangle
add
up
to
180
degrees?’)-‐-‐-‐and
(b)
the
idea
of
a
pure
system
of
geometry-‐-‐-‐which
could
be
consistent,
and
worthy
of
investigation,
even
if
it
does
not
describe
physical
space.
(Again,
you
can
find
out
more
about
non-‐Euclidean
geometry
in
a
Plus
article.
Go
to:
http://plus.maths.org/content/non-‐euclidean-‐geometry-‐and-‐indras-‐pearls)
(2)
In
algebra,
the
investigations
of
Hamilton
and
Grassmann
into
new
kinds
of
magnitude
(e.g.
quaternions),
with
new
rules
governing
their
operations
of
addition,
multiplication
etc.,
liberated
people
in
a
similar
way.
An
algebraic
system
could
be
defined
by
axioms,
and
consistent,
and
worthy
of
investigation,
even
if
it
violated
the
rules
of
addition
etc.
familiar
from
arithmetic.
For
a
Plus
article
on
quaternions,
go
to:
http://plus.maths.org/content/curious-‐quaternions
(3)
Two
other
factors-‐-‐-‐the
rise
of
set
theory
and
logic,
and
the
concomitant
increasing
concern
to
make
deduction
utterly
rigorous,
by
formalizing
mathematical
language-‐-‐-‐also
contributed
to
this
conception
of
pure
mathematics
as
the
investigation
of
structure:
in
principle,
of
any
structure.
(Both
factors
were
themselves
prompted
by
various
paradoxical
arguments
that
could
be
formulated
in
non-‐rigorous
mathematical
language,
e.g.
about
sets.
For
more
details
about
these
paradoxes,
cf.
the
Plus
articles:
http://plus.maths.org/content/mathematical-‐mysteries-‐barbers-‐paradox
http://plus.maths.org/content/cantor-‐and-‐cohen-‐infinite-‐investigators-‐part-‐i)
Indeed,
set
theory
and
the
formal
languages
introduced
by
the
study
of
logic
provided
the
perfect
framework
for
this
modern
conception
of
pure
mathematics.
For
the
idea
of
a
set
is
so
simple,
almost
contentless!
You
just
gather
any
old
things
together
in
a
set
by
a
pair
of
curly
brackets,
and
you
keep
going,
forming
sets
of
sets,
and
sets
of
sets
of
sets,
as
much
as
you
wish.
And
you
are
then
free
to
postulate
any
structure
you
like
on
your
sets
(e.g.
any
new
rule
of
‘addition’
you
like),
and
to
investigate
your
postulates’
consequences-‐-‐-‐by
stating
your
postulates
and
deductions
in
the
formal
languages
supplied
by
logic.
(For
more
details
about
how
this
conception
of
pure
mathematics
arose,
cf.
Kline’s
magisterial
history
of
two
millennia
of
mathematics
(1972,
especially
pp.
1036-‐1038).
Finally:
in
calling
this
the
‘modern
conception’
of
mathematics,
I
chose
my
words
deliberately!
For
Gray
(2008)
makes
a
good
case
that
this
conception
is
‘modernist’
in
a
similar
sense
to
that
in
which
art
became
‘modern’
at
about
the
same
time,
i.e.
the
mid-‐nineteenth
century.)
Thus
we
arrive
at
the
modern
idea
of
a
‘pure
mathematical
structure’.
In
short:
it
consists
of
a
collection
of
objects,
equipped
with
some
postulated
properties
and
relations
e.g.
an
operation
of
multiplication
subject
to
certain
rules.
The
objects,
properties
and
relations
are
all
abstract
in
the
sense
nothing
is
assumed
about
their
natures,
except
the
behaviour
postulated
by
the
rules.
In
a
bit
more
detail:
as
I
mentioned
above,
set
theory
turned
out
to
be
an
ideal
lingua
franca
for
articulating
this
idea.
Thus
the
idea
of
‘a
collection
of
objects,
equipped
with
some
properties
and
relations’
was
made
precise
as
‘a
set
of
objects,
with
each
postulated
property
being
a
subset,
each
postulated
binary
relation
being
a
set
of
ordered
pairs
etc.’.
The
power
of
gathering
things
together
in
curly
brackets-‐-‐-‐and
iterating!
I
need
not
go
into
further
detail
about
this
abstract
and
structural
conception
of
pure
mathematics.
What
matters
for
us
is
the
main
contrast
with
applied
mathematics,
and
its
structures.
Namely:
there
is
no
mention
of
physical
quantities.
13
Agreed:
physical
enquiry,
and
more
generally
empirical
enquiry,
may
well
have
played
a
crucial
heuristic
role
in
leading
a
pure
mathematician
to
articulate
a
structure.
Of
course,
the
history
of
mathematics
contains
many
examples
of
this.
But
the
resulting
pure
mathematical
structure
makes
no
mention
of
the
physical
quantities
that
inspired
it.
Being
heuristically
important
does
not
imply
being
part
of
the
official
content
of
what
results.
I
agree
that
this
‘lack
of
content’
of
a
pure
mathematical
structure
is
perfectly
compatible
with
the
idea
that
something
‘contentful’,
e.g.
something
mentioning
physical
quantities,
is
an
instance
of
a
pure
mathematical
structure.
For
the
relation
of
instantiation
allows
a
great
deal
of
‘loss
of
content’.
For
example:
Here
I
am
with
my
myriad
properties,
of
size,
shape,
mass,
temperature
etc.
Here
is
my
family
with
its
myriad
properties
and
relations,
e.g.
our
total
mass,
one
person
being
more
massive
than
another,
one
person
being
between
two
others
etc.
All
this
is
‘contentful’.
But
I
am
an
instance
of
many
abstract
‘contentless’
properties:
being
less
than
two
in
number,
not
being
a
set
etc.
And
similarly,
my
family
as
a
collection
of
objects
is
an
instance
of
many
abstract
‘contentless’
properties
and
relations:
being
more
than
two
in
number,
being
the
base-‐set
of
a
group
of
order
6
etc.
But
on
the
other
hand:
this
‘lack
of
content’
of
a
pure
mathematical
structure
is
incompatible
with
something
‘contentful’,
e.g.
something
mentioning
physical
quantities,
being
a
pure
mathematical
structure.
For
however
we
choose
to
make
‘content’
precise
(e.g.
in
terms
of
physical
quantities
or
in
some
other
way):
something
contentful
cannot
be
literally
identical
with
something
contentless.
To
sum
up:
The
‘is’
of
identity,
e.g.
in
‘a
=
b’,
is
NOT
the
‘is’
of
instantiation,
e.g.
in
‘Max
is
tall’.
If
indeed
a=
b,
then
a
and
b
have
the
very
same
content,
if
any
(in
whatever
sense
of
‘content’
you
like).
For
there
is
only
one
entity:
a,
which
is
also
called
‘b’.
But
in
the
case
of
‘Max
is
tall’,
Max
can
have
countless
properties,
as
contentful
as
you
like
(in
whatever
sense),
that
are
not
‘picked
up
on’
or
encoded
by,
or
part
of
the
meaning
of,
the
predicate
‘is
tall’.
With
that
discussion
in
hand,
my
critique
of
Tegmark’s
Pythagoreanism-‐-‐-‐his
claim
that
nature
is
mathematics-‐-‐-‐is
very
simply
stated.
It
all
turns
on
the
simple
but
crucial
distinction
between
the
‘is’
of
identity
and
the
‘is’
of
instantiation.
Thus
I
am
willing
to
concede
to
Tegmark:
(A):
The
physical
multiverse
instantiates
a
pure
mathematical
structure.
Indeed,
being
a
Platonist
about
pure
mathematics,
though
not
yet
convinced
of
his
multiverse’s
first
three
Levels
(remember
the
health
warnings!):
I
would
happily
agree
with
Tegmark
to
the
conditional
claim:
(A’):
If
there
is
a
physical
multiverse
(with
whichever
combination
of
Tegmark’s
first
three
Levels),
then
it
instantiates
a
pure
mathematical
structure.
But
still
I
deny:
(B):
The
physical
multiverse
is
a
pure
mathematical
structure.
The
contrast
between
(A)
and
(B),
between
‘instantiates’
and
‘is’,
might
seem
a
philosopher’s
quibble.
But
it
is
not.
For
it
is
claim
(B),
not
(A),
that
is
needed
to
get
from
Platonism
about
pure
mathematics
to
Pythagoreanism:
from
Platonism
about
pure
mathematics
to
Tegmark’s
Level
IV
multiverse!
IV.D.
Tegmark’s
argument
from
external
reality
But
Uncle
Max
has
a
specific
philosophical
argument
for
his
Pythagoreanism,
his
Level
IV
multiverse:
which
I
have
so
far
not
considered.
So
I
owe
you,
and
him,
an
assessment
of
it.
You
will
not
be
surprised
to
hear
that
I
think
the
argument
fails.
It
is
invalid
in
the
sense
that
it
has
a
true
premise
but
a
false
conclusion.
Indeed,
it
is
invalid
because
of
the
points
in
Sections
IVB
and
IVC:
i.e.
the
ambiguity
of
‘mathematical
structure’
that
arises
from
the
distinction
between
applied
and
pure
mathematics.
But
at
the
risk
of
flogging
a
dead
horse,
I
should
state
the
argument
and
say
why
I
think
it
fails.
14
Tegmark’s
premise
is
what
he
calls
the
‘External
Reality
Hypothesis’
(ERH).
(ERH):
There
exists
an
external
reality
completely
independent
of
us
humans.
His
argument
is
that
(ERH)
implies
what
he
calls
the
‘Mathematical
Universe
Hypothesis’
(MUH).
MUH
is
essentially
(B)
above.
In
his
exact
words:
(MUH):
Our
external
physical
reality
is
a
mathematical
structure.
When
you
add
to
(MUH),
Platonism
about
pure
mathematics,
that
all
the
possible
pure
mathematical
structures
exist—which
I
agree
to-‐-‐-‐you
indeed
get
Tegmark’s
Level
IV
multiverse.
That
is,
you
get:
our
external
physical
reality
(the
multiverse
with
Levels
I
to
III
taken
as
accepted)
is
one
of
a
plethora
of
equally
real
mathematical
structures.
So
what
is
the
argument
that
(ERH)
implies
(MUH)?
The
idea
is
that
since
external
reality
is
completely
independent
of
us
humans,
it
must
have
a
description
which
is
utterly
free
of
subjective
ingredients:
that
is,
utterly
free
of
factors
arising
from
biological
facts
about
human
cognition,
or
cultural
facts,
or
facts
about
an
individual
human’s
psychology.
Tegmark
has
a
vivid
metaphorical
name
for
these
subjective
ingredients.
He
calls
them
‘baggage’:
the
word
‘baggage’
connoting
the
burden
or
error
in
our
description
of
nature
due
to
the
biases
from
our
biological,
cultural
or
individual
history.
He
has
an
even
more
vivid
metaphor
for
the
effort
to
strip
out
such
subjective
ingredients
from
our
description
of
nature:
the
effort
which
science,
especially
physics,
has
historically
made,
and
should
continue
to
make,
so
as
to
overcome
the
biases.
Thus
he
calls
getting
rid
of
the
subjective
ingredients
‘reducing
the
baggage
allowance’
(Chapter
10,
especially
pp.
255-‐265:
the
argument
also
occurs
in
his
earlier
paper
(2008,
pp.
102-‐
108).
It
is
a
vivid
metaphor:
and
in
an
age
when
we
are
ruining
the
planet
with
too
much
jet
travel,
it
seems
a
worthy
aim
.
.
.
And
indeed,
I
agree
with
Tegmark
that
science,
especially
physics,
has
historically
made
successive
efforts
to
overcome
various
cognitive
biases
due
to
our
subjective
constitution
(biological,
cultural
or
individual).
I
also
agree
that
to
make
progress
in
the
future,
we
must
expect
physics
to
continue
to
make
that
effort.
Besides,
many
other
scientists,
especially
physicists,
and
philosophers,
would
agree
with
him.
(In
particular,
many
historians
of
philosophy
would
agree
that
modern
physical
science
from
the
seventeenth
century
onwards
has
successively
removed
various
subjective
ingredients
from
the
scientific
world-‐view.
For
example,
cf.
Williams’
discussion
of
what
he
calls
the
‘absolute
conception
of
reality’
(1978,
pp.
65-‐67,
245-‐249).)
More
specifically,
concerning
Tegmark’s
argument:
I
also
believe
(ERH).
This
is
often
called
in
philosophy,
‘realism’.
As
it
is
usually
put:
the
realist
maintains
that
reality
is
utterly
independent
of
the
human
mind.
I
also
am
happy
to
agree
with
Tegmark
that
(ERH)
implies
that
reality
must
have
a
description
which
is
utterly
free
of
subjective
ingredients.
So
Max’s
premise
is
true.
But
obviously,
this
does
not
imply
his
conclusion
(MUH)-‐-‐-‐for
the
reasons
we
saw
in
Sections
IV.B
and
IV.C.
That
is:
because
of
the
distinction
between
instantiates
and
is,
which
I
emphasized
in
terms
of
the
physical
quantities.
Thus,
in
terms
of
my
labels
(A)
and
(B)
at
the
end
of
Section
IV.C,
I
reply
to
Tegmark
as
follows:
(i) (ERH)
and
the
fact
that
reality
must
have
an
utterly
objective
description
implies
(A):
The
physical
multiverse
instantiates
a
pure
mathematical
structure.
Or
remembering
the
previous
Sections’
health
warnings,
they
imply
the
conditional
claim,
(A’):
If
there
is
a
physical
multiverse,
then
it
instantiates
a
pure
mathematical
structure.
But:
(ii) They
do
not
imply
(B):
The
physical
multiverse
is
a
pure
mathematical
structure.
That
is,
they
do
not
imply
(MUH).
15
IV.E
Is
a
property
‘more
than’
its
web
of
relations
to
other
properties?
In
this
final
subsection
(strictly
for
aficionados
and
enthusiasts!),
I
will
raise
some
more
philosophical
controversy
about
the
distinction
between
instantiates
and
is.
To
his
credit,
Tegmark
does
register
the
distinction,
albeit
briefly:
namely
at
p
260,
footnote.
There
is
more
discussion
in
a
paper
that
preceded
his
book,
where
he
writes
(2008,
p.107):
‘Whereas
the
customary
terminology
in
physics
textbooks
is
that
the
external
reality
is
described
by
mathematics,
the
(MUH)
states
that
it
is
mathematics
(more
specfically
a
mathematical
structure).
This
corresponds
to
the
‘ontic’
version
of
universal
structural
realism
in
the
philosophical
terminology
of
Ladyman
(1998)
and
McCabe
(2006)’.
I
reply
as
follows,
with
three
points,
(a)
to
(c).
(a):
I
agree
that
some
speculative
philosophical
positions
may
collapse
the
distinction,
saying
‘is’
where
the
customary
view
says
‘instantiates’.
But:
(b):
I
agree
that
McCabe’s
discussion
seems
to
endorse
collapsing
the
distinction.
But
on
my
understanding
of
Ladyman’s
position—whose
paper
(1998)
named
and
advocated
‘ontic
structural
realism’-‐-‐-‐he
does
not
wish
to
collapse
the
distinction.
More
important:
(c):
Setting
aside
whatever
might
be
the
views
of
these
authors,
we
should
not
collapse
the
distinction.
My
reason
for
saying
(c)
is
that
to
collapse
the
distinction,
undoubtedly
the
best
strategy
is
to
say
that
a
property
or
relation,
or
at
least
the
properties
and
relations
mentioned
by
physics-‐-‐-‐such
as
the
physical
quantities
that
I
used
in
Section
IV.C
to
ram
home
the
distinction
between
instantiates
and
is-‐-‐-‐is
completely
specified
by
its
web
or
pattern
of
relations
to
other
properties
and
relations.
The
paradigm
such
“relation
to
other
properties
and
relations”
is
the
relation
of
being
associated
together
in
a
law.
For
example,
the
quantities
force
and
acceleration
are
related
by
Newton’s
second
law.
And
so
the
strategy
in
question
maintains
that
everything
there
is
to
know
about
any
physical
quantity,
e.g.
the
entire
nature
of
force,
can
be
recovered
from
the
web
or
pattern
of
relations
among
quantities-‐-‐-‐each
of
which
is
thus
specified
only
as
a
node
in
this
web.
In
mathematical
terms,
this
requires
at
least
that
the
web
is
to
have
only
the
identity
map
as
an
automorphism.
The
idea
is:
if
this
is
so,
then
the
apparent
‘contentfulness’
(cf.
the
end
of
Section
IV.C)
of
physical
quantities
can
be
‘analysed
away’
as
a
matter
of
structure.
That
is:
we
seem
to
glimpse
how
the
applied
mathematical
structures,
with
their
‘contentful’
physical
quantities
could
turn
out
to
be,
au
fond,
pure
mathematical-‐-‐-‐‘contentless’,
‘abstract’,
‘structural’.
But
I
say:
this
strategy
is
wrong
(and
so
the
distinction
between
instantiates
and
is
does
not
collapse).
For
there
is
every
reason
to
think
that
at
least
some
physical
quantities
each
have
a
nature
that
is
not
exhausted
by
their
web
or
pattern
of
relations
to
other
properties
and
relations.
As
I
admitted
in
(a),
I
agree
that
some
philosophical
positions
deny
this.
There
is
even
a
jargon.
To
say,
as
I
do,
that
at
least
some
properties
(or
relations)
have
a
nature
that
is
not
exhausted
by
their
web
of
relations
to
others,
is
to
be
a
quidditist.
(This
is
from
‘quid’,
the
Latin
for
‘what’:
for
the
idea
is
that
a
property
has
a
‘content’
or
‘whatness’.)
So
in
effect,
I
am
saying
that
for
Uncle
Max
to
defend
his
argument
that
(ERH)
implies
(MUH),
his
most
promising
strategy
is
to
deny
quidditism.
But
my
objection
to
him
is:
quidditism
looks
right!
As
the
following
example
suggests.
(Agreed:
my
example
of
electric
charge,
and
the
flip
between
positive
and
negative
values
of
charge,
is
subtler
than
my
discussion
will
suggest.
(For
it
leads
in
to
the
question
of
the
proper
treatment
of
time-‐reversal:
for
which
cf.
e.g.
Malament
(2004).)
So
I
do
not
claim
that
the
case
of
electric
charge
gives
conclusive
proof
of
quidditism.
But
I
do
claim
that
it
makes
quidditism
plausible;
and
thus
that
it
shows
Tegmark
should
have
worked
harder
to
justify
anti-‐quidditism-‐-‐
-‐to
replace
instantiates
by
is.)
16
Take
the
two
properties,
having
negative
electric
charge,
and
having
positive
electric
charge.
Or
if
you
prefer
some
precise
amount
of
each,
e.g.
having
plus
or
minus
one
Coulomb
of
charge.
Imagine
them
(or
one
of
them)
occurring
in
an
applied
mathematical
structure,
i.e.
a
physically
possible
state
of
affairs,
according
to
some
theory.
For
example,
let
the
theory
be
electromagnetic
theory,
and
let
the
properties
(quantities
or
exact
values
of
them)
occur
in
a
possible
instantaneous
state
for
a
collection
of
particles.
Thus:
here
is
a
particle
with
charge
+3
Coulombs,
there
is
another
with
charge
-‐2
Coulombs.
(Recall
the
sketch
of
applied
mathematical
structures
in
(i)
t
o
(iv),
in
Section
IV.C.)
Now
imagine
flipping
positive
and
negative
charge.
Here,
I
do
not
mean
changing
our
linguistic
convention
about
what
amounts
of
charge
we
call
‘negative’
and
which
‘positive’.
I
mean
an
active
transformation
which
changes
the
state
of
affairs:
in
the
new
state
of
affairs,
here
is
a
particle
with
charge
-‐3
Coulombs,
there
is
another
with
charge
+2
Coulombs.
(I
am
using
the
same
language
as
before!)
I
agree
that
this
new
state
of
affairs
of
affairs
will
behave,
e.g.
change
over
time,
in
a
manner
that
mirrors
the
behaviour
of
the
original
state
of
affairs.
Here,
the
‘mirroring’
can
be
spelt
out
in
detail
using
the
idea
of
a
symmetry
of
the
laws.
I
discussed
this
in
Section
II.B.
In
terms
of
the
current
idea
of
the
laws
as
a
web
of
relations
between
quantities,
a
symmetry
is
a
transformation
of
the
web,
i.e.
a
function
sending
nodes
to
nodes
etc.,
that
preserves
the
web’s
structure
e.g.
the
connectivity
relations
between
nodes.
But
I
do
not
need
to
go
into
details
about
the
mirroring
of
the
original
state
of
affairs’
behaviour.
For
the
relevant
point-‐-‐-‐the
point
I
want
to
emphasize-‐-‐-‐is
a
different,
and
a
simpler,
one.
It
is
just
that
the
new
state
of
affairs
is
different
from
the
original.
And
just
that
point
is
enough
to
imply
that
there
are
facts-‐-‐-‐‘content’
or
‘nature’-‐-‐-‐about,
say,
negative
charge,
or
having
an
exact
value
of
negative
charge
(e.g.
-‐2
Coulombs)
that
outstrip
its
web
of
relations
to
other
quantities:
that
cannot
be
‘analysed
away’
in
terms
of
the
quantity’s
position
as
a
node
in
the
web.
For
the
‘flip’
being
a
symmetry
of
the
laws
implies
that
this
web
of
relations
is
shared
with
positive
charge
(or
the
corresponding
exact
value:
in
my
example,
+2
Coulombs):
but
the
states
of
affairs
are
different!
Acknowledgments
I
am
very
grateful
to
Marianne
Freiberger,
the
editor
at
Plus,
for
the
invitation
to
review
the
book,
and
for
dividing
and
editing
the
bulk
of
this
discussion
into
three
separate
articles
appropriate
for
Plus.
They
can
be
found
at
these
URLs:
The review: http://plus.maths.org/content/mathematical-universe-0
Discussion of symmetry breaking: http://plus.maths.org/content/breaking-symmetry
Discussion of the world being mathematics: http://plus.maths.org/content/world-made-maths
I
am
also
very
grateful
to
Harvey
Brown,
George
Ellis,
Huw
Price,
Joe
Silk,
David
Sloan
and
David
Wallace
for
comments
on
a
previous
version:
I
wish
I
could
have
incorporated
all
their
wisdom!
References
Barrow,
J.
and
Tipler,
F.
(1986),
The
Anthropic
Cosmological
Principle,
Oxford
University
Press
Burnyeat,
M.
(2007),
‘Other
Lives’
[a
review
of
two
books
about
Pythagoras],
The
London
Review
of
Books,
22
February
2007,
pp.
3-‐6.
Gray,
J
(2008),
Plato’s
Ghost:
The
Modernist
Transformation
of
Mathematics.
Princeton
University
Press.
Kline,
M.
(1972),
Mathematical
Thought
from
Ancient
to
Modern
Times,
Oxford
University
Press
Ladyman
J.
(1998),
‘What
is
Structural
Realism?’,
Studies
in
History
and
Philosophy
of
Science,
volume
29,
pp.
409-‐424.
Malament,
D.
(2004),
‘On
the
time
reversal
invariance
of
classical
electromagnetic
theory’,
Studies
in
the
History
and
Philosophy
of
Modern
Physics,
volume
35B,
pp.
295-‐315.
McCabe,
G
(2006),
‘Possible
physical
universes’,
arxiv:
gr-‐qc/0601073
(2006)
McMullin,
E.
(1985),
‘Galilean
idealization’,
Studies
in
the
History
and
Philosophy
of
Science
volume
16,
pp.
247-‐273.
Tegmark,
M.
(2008),
‘The
mathematical
universe’,
Foundations
of
Physics
volume
38,
pp.
101-‐150.
Wilczek,
F.
(2008),
`Enlightenment,
knowledge,
ignorance,
temptation’,
in
B.
Carr
ed.,
Universe
or
Multiverse?,
Cambridge
University
Press;
pp.
43-‐54.
Williams,
B.
(1978),
Descartes:
the
project
or
pure
enquiry,
Penguin.
17