J. R. Kantor - Psychology and Logic - Vol. II. 2-Principia Press (1950)
J. R. Kantor - Psychology and Logic - Vol. II. 2-Principia Press (1950)
J.R.KANTOR
Pnonsson or PSYCHOLOGY, INDIANA UNIVERSITY
VOLUME II
1950
\
THE PRINCIPIA PRESS
BLOOMINGTON, INDIANA
∙
∙ ≤ °
CHAPTER XV
SYSTEMS As
CONSTRUCTION PRODUCTS ...............∙ 60
Selection and Analysis of System Products, 60. Investigative
Schema for System Products, 60. Four Types of System Prod-
ucts, 61. A. Material or Content Systems, 61. (1) Things, 61.
(2) Event Systems, 71. (3) Relations as System Materials, 72.
(4) Classes as System Materials, 72. (5) Acts as System Ma—
terials, 73. (6) Linguistic Things as System Materials, 7 3.
B. Linguistic Systems, 7 3. (I) General Reference Systems, 74.
(2) Method Systems, 75. (3) Metalogical Systems, 76. (4)
Autological Cosmic Systems, 76. C. Formal Systems, 76. (I)
Implicatory Systems, 77. (2) Truth-function (Matrix) Sys-
tems, 78. (3) Complete Induction, 79. (4) Mathematical
Systems, 79. D. Operational Systems, 84. (1) Chemical Analy-
sis, 84. (2) Solution of a Mathematical Problem, 85. Scien-
tific Structure and Deductive Systems, 86. Interrelation of
Systemizing Operations and Materials, 86. Characteristic Vari-
ations of System Products, 88. Tight and Loose Systems, 88.
Complete and Expanding Systems, 89. Discoveredyand Con-
structed Systems, 89. Witting and Unwitting Systems, 89.
CHAPTER XVI
INSTRUMENTS FOR SYSTEM CONSTRUCTION 91
Models, Schemata, and Formulae as Logical Instruments,
91. Logical and Scientific Instruments, 91. Logical Instruments
as Products, 92.1nterbehavioral Sources of Logical Instruments,
92. Specificity of Logical Instruments, 94. Logical Instruments
in Operation, 94. Logical and Nonlogical Instruments Com—
pared, 95. Logical Instruments as Miniature Systems, 96. Logi—
cal Instruments as System Items, 97. Materials Of Systemological
Instruments, 97. Orientational Function of Logical Instruments,
98. Representational Tools, 98 . Analogically Descriptive Tools,
99. EXplanatory Tools, 99. Speculative Fictional Tools, 99.
Instruments in Various Orientational Situations, 100. Logic, 100.
Mathematics, 101. Physics, 102. Biology, 103. Psychology,
104. Social Sciences, 1 06. Techniques in Instrument Production,
106. Iconography, 106. Abstraction, 106. De Novo Construc-
tion, 107.
CHAPTER XVII
CATEGORIES AND SYSTEM BUILDINC\ 108
Categories and Logic, 108. Nature and Operation of Cater
gories, 108. Evolution of Categorial Systems, 109. Pro-Aris-
totelian Categorization, 109. Aristotelian Categorization, 109.
CONTENTS vii
Post-Aristotelian Categorization, I 10. Kantian Categorization,
1 10. Categorial System of von 'Hartmann, 11 1. Current Atti-
tudes toward Categories, 112. Categorial Sources, 1 12. Cate-
gories and Concepts, 114. Categories, Classes, and Universals,
114. Categories, Language, and Symbols, 115. Categories as
Interbehavioral Products, 1 I 5. Categorial Continuity, 1 1 6. Cate-
gorial Specificity, 1 1 7. Special Categorial Functions, 1 1 7. Difl’er-a
entiating Functions, 1 I7. Classifying Functions, 118. Descrip-
tive Functions, 1 I8, Explanatory Functions, 1 18. Range of
Categorial Systems, 118. Scientific Departments, 118. Specific
Researches, 1 19. Property and Dimension Systems, 1 I9. Illus-
trative Categorial Operations, 1 19. 1. Mechanics, 1 19. 2. Elec-
tricity, 120. 3. Geometry, 120. 4. Everyday Categories, 121. 5.
Religious Categories, 121. 6. Dimensional Analysis, 122. 7.
Axiological Categories, 124. 8. Thermodynamics, I25. 9.
Biology, 126. 10. Ethical Categories, 127. 11. Logical Cate-
gories, 128. 12. Grammatical Categories, 128. 13. Philosophical
Categories, 129. 14. Aesthetic Categories, 129. 15. Mathemati-
cal Analysis, 130.
CHAPTER XVIII
UNIVERSALS: SYSTEMOLOGICAL COMPONENTS AND PRODUCTS 1 3 I
The Logic of Universals, 131. Historical Treatment of Uni-
versals, 131. Universals among the Greeks, I31. Medieval .
CHAPTER XIX
INTERBEHAVIORAL LOGIC AND CAUSATION .............. 145
Causation as Applied Logic, 145. Is Causation a Logical Prob-
lem? 145. Emergence of Causality in Methodistic Logic, I46.'
Cultural Background of Causality, I47. Classical Causal
Theory, 149. (a) Formal Cause Theory,\149. (b) Epistemo-
lOgical Cause Theory, 150. (c) Ontological Cause Theory,
viii PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
CHAPTER XX
THE LAWS OF THOUGHT AND THINGS ................ 175
Logic and Law, 175. Varying Formulabnons of Logical
Laws, 177. Logical Laws as Products of Cultural Development,
179. Universality and Necessity of Logical Laws, 183.(1)
Nature and Number of Logical Principles, 184. (2) Source,
’of Logical Laws, 184. ( 3) Universality and Necessity of
Application, 185. Specificity and Contingency of Logical Laws,
186. Logical Laws in Reasoning and Thinking, I86. Logical
Laws and Existence, 188. Logical Laws and Data, 190. Logi-
cal Laws and Language, 194. Logical Laws and Mathematics,
196. Logical Laws as Factors in System Building, 199; Logical
Laws and Systemological Behavior, 202.
CHAPTER XXI
I
PROBABILITY AND
INTERBEHAVIORAL LOGIC ............ 204
Probability: Guide to Logic, 204. ‘The Domain of Proba-
bility, 205. Philosophical Presuppositions, 206. Calculative
Presuppositions, 207. Probability Events and Situations, 207.
Probability Range and Continuity, 208. Probability: Univocal
or Multivocal? 210. Generality and Specificity of Probability
Systems, 212. Relative Value of Probability Systems, 214. His-
torical Evolution of Probability systems, 215. Pragmatic Be-
ginnings, 216. ReSponse-Centered Systems, 217. Event-Cen-
tered Systems, 218. Propositional Probability, 219. Probability
as Statistical Operations, 221. Basic Orientation of Probability
Systems, 221. Probability, Certainty, and Necessity, 222. Prob-
ability, Truth, and Error, 223. Probability, Possibility, and
Impossibility, 224. Probability, Potentiality, and Actuality, 225.
Probability in Science, 225. Probability and Induction, 228.
Logic and Events, 228, Relation of Induction‘and Deduction,
CONTENTS ix
228. Probability and Inductive Principles, 229. Probability and
Prediction, 230.
CHAPTER XXII
ANALYSIS OF
PROBABILITY SYSTEMS ............... ∙ ∙ 232
Design for Probability System Analysis, 232. (I) The Sys-
tem Builder, 232. (2) Methods and Procedures, 232. (3)
Materials, 233. (4) Working Auspices, 233. (5) Work Prod-
ucts, 233.Types of Probability Systems, 234(1) Probability
as Rational Responses, 234(2) Probability as Knowledge Re-
sponses, 237. (3) Probability as Laws of Things, 241. (4)
Probability as Propositional Relations, 246. (5) The Truth-
Frequency Theory, 248. (6) Probability as Factorial Coordina-
tion, 253. Probability Systems and Logical Multiplexity, 255.
Probability, Epistemology, and Ontology, 256. General Philo-
sophical Problems, 257. Special PhilosophicalProblems, 257.
Interbehavioral Probability versus Epistemology, 2 57.. Interbe-
havioral Probability versus Ontology, 258. Probability Propo-
sitions versus Probability Events, 2 58. Probability Calculation:
Goal or Operation? 261. Statistics and Probability, 261. The
Nature of Calculation, 262.
CHAPTER XXIII
LOGICAL ASPECTS OF MEASUREMENT .................. 26 5
The Place of Measurement in Logic, 265. What is Meas-
urement? 265. Ideological Trends in Measurement Theory,
266. Measurement as Applied Mathematics, 267. The Power
of Mathematical Reasoning, 269. Numbers as Supreme Uni-
versals, 269. Numbers as Philosophical Abstractions, 27o. Num-
bers and External Reality, 270. Numbers and Mental States,
270. Mensurational Operations and Numeral Assignment, 270.
Specificity of Measurement, 271. (1) Specificity of Measured
Objects, 272. (2) Specificity of Operations and Techniques,
273. (3) Specificity of Mensurative Situations, 274. Levels of
Measurement, 275. Practical Measurement, 27 5. Technologi-
cal Measurement, 276. Formal Metrology, 277. Interrelation
of Levels, 278. Quality and Quantity, 278. (1) Quantity as
Property of Things, 280. (2) Quantity as Measure, 281. (3)
Quantity as Constructions, 28 1 . Variety and Specificity of Mag—
nitudes, 281. Measuring Systems, 282. A. Assumptions and
Postulates of Measurement, 283. B. Choosing and Refining
Units, 284. C. Instruments and Operations, 285. D. Record-
ing, 292. E. Statistical Operations,
∙ How Arbitrary are
Units or Standards? 293. The Nature OfQuantity, Number,
and Magnitude, 295. Measuring and Counting, 296.
X PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
CHAPTER XXIV
METROLOGY AND METASCIENCE ...................... 299
Problems of Mensurational Logic, 299. System Type and
Metrological Evolution, 300. (1) Measuring Systems, 300.
(2) Weighing Systems, 301. (3) Counting Systems, 301. (4)
Calculating Systems, 302. ( 5) Ordering Systems, 302. (6)
Estimating Systems, 302. (7) Evaluating Systems, 303. (8)
Equating Systems, 304. (9) Probability Systems, 304. Measure-
ment: Abstract and Concrete, 306. Measurement: Construction
and Observation, 307. Measurement and Cause, 31 1. Measure-
ment and Objectivity, 312. Measurement and Reality, 313.
Metrology and Logic, 318. −
CHAPTER XXV
SYSTEM BUILDING AND METALOGIC .................. 321
The Continuity of Human Behavior, 32‘1. Metalogic and
Logical Practice, 322. A. Logic and Living, 323. B. Logic
and Science, 324. Constructing an External World, 327. C.
Logic and Philosophy, 328. Towers and Systems, 329. Tech-
niques of Unrestricted System Building, 330. (I) Obeisance
to Utterance, 33o. ( 2) Projection and Fixation of Utterance,
330. Abnegation Motive in Philosophy, 330. Problem of the
Inductive System, 331. Statistical Procedures and .Absolute
Systems, 332. Logic and the Plenum, 333.
BIBLIOGRAPHY 334
SUBJECT INDEX ...................................... 353
NAME INDEX ........................................ 3 56
FOREWORD
This volume emphasizes the applied aspects of the relation be-
tween psychology and logic. Whereas in the first volume we were
chiefly occupied with logical theory, we now investigate the ori-
going processes and finished products of system building. Because
theory and practice are continuous, the materials of the two
volumes are, of course, intimately integrated. The topics of
Volume II are treated on the basis of the principles worked out
in Volume I, the results, therefore, in a significant way consti-
tute illustrations and tests of interbehavioral theory.
Applying logical principles means for us in no sense exploit-
ing them. Interbehavioral logic is not a unique logical system
ready for use in annexing truth and reality. Logics of that type
we reject, along with the various historical philosophies serv—
ing as their foundation. Specificity logic,'In both its theoretical and
applied aspects, constitutes a scientific study of systemizing situa-
tions. .Its application,:accordingly, consists in observing how well
descriptiOns of system making fit when they are projected back
into the fields from which they are drawn. Thus exploitation
gives way to verification.
The chapters of the present volume demonstrate the essential
"place in various logical Situations of (I) concrete Specific Opera-
tions and (2) the things, events, and relations which constitute
the raw materials for (3) systemic products. In many instances,
too, we clarify (4) the types of instruments employed in sys—
tem construction. The indispensability of these four factors is
amply exemplified1n the investigation of system products (chap.
I 5), as well as in many other chapters.
∙
In another instance a writer Who does associate postulates with
presuppositions denies that most of the basic interbehavioral
suppbsitions are postulates. The assumption is that only classical—
logical postulates are postulates. This criticism is made _on the ex—
pressed ground that logic is an a priori discipline; and, Since speci-
ficity logic is not such a discipline, it simply is beyond the pale.
Strangely enough, the argument made for a priori logic concerns the
existence of scientific contents—namely, events—which are inde-
pendent'of scientific work. But this is exactly the interbehavioral po-
sition. All authentic scientific work consists of interbehavior with
events described in Jim, manipulated in the laboratory, and counted
and computed when possible. Descriptions and explanations can only
be structured on such events as an indispensable foundation.
Furthermore, all this activity goes on Within the bounds of human
interbehavior. If thereIs anything that one must call a priori, it
belongs inside this system. N0 contact with scientific work or with
scientific subject matter allows for any absolutes and transcendents,
whether empiricistic or rationalistic.
Several writers criticize my proposed cooperatiOn betweenslogic
and psychology on the ground that, if this cooperation is necessary
for logic, it. is likeWise necessary for physics and other sciences.
FOREWORD XV
Ibid.
p.
Grundlagen, vol. I, 27.
ABSTRACTING AND GENERALIZING OPERATIONS 3
like mathematics itself, has steadily become pervaded by the twin
characters of abstractness and generality.° Has not logic itself
been claimed as the science of pure form, and mathematics as re-
ducible to logic becauseIt can be exhibited as a completely logical
structure?“ That logical proof or demonstration'18 independent of
subject matter has become a greatly lauded principle.7
No appreciable clarification of abstracting and generalizing
processes, however, has materialized. And why not? Probably be-
cause the early introduction of mathematical logic coincided with
the resurgence of mystic doctrines and with the notion that logic
is concerned with Platonic essences. But do not forms really con-
stitute systems and organizations? Are not. forms structures, and
therefore products of ( I) investigation, in the case of objects and
events, and (2) constructed relations between things, when the
latter are submerged in their relations?
However, the conventional doctrine of logical forms has its
value for our' present study. For one thing, the most extreme ab—
straction is replete with material suggesting the paradox that
nothing is so full as the emptiness of a construct. The maxim
maker may define mathematics “as the subject in which we never
know what we are talking about, nor whether what we are saying
is true,”3 but obviously he cannot conceal his cap and bells.9 Why
Should an eminent mathematician10 Confound visible and palpable
things with things, or overlook the concreteness and actuality of
relations?
Formalism in logic and mathematics openly flouts the fact that
such creations as “zero,” “number,” and “successor” have been
used to demonstrate the reductiOn of mathematics to arithmetic
and arithmetic to logic. It seems highly anomalous to deal with
structures, especially such Obviously made and remade structures,
only to forget about the eEort and the plan responsible for their
production. To assert that mathematics is structural is entirely dif-
ferent from saying it reaches out toward empty and eternal forms.
a Bell, Development, p. 153.
\
Stebbing, Modern, chap. Io.
Nicod, Foundations, Part I.
aRussell, Mysticism,p. 75.
’This definition appears in an article designed to be “as romantic as possible,”
ibid., Preface.
1°
Eddington, Space, p. 14 n.
4 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
CONSTRUCTIONAL PRINCIPLES IN
. A.
G. OPERATIONS
AND
∙
Accordingly he attempted to derive all constructs (concepts) by a
process of emptying out sensuous Euclidean pointsvand
1’
Cf. Kantor, Principles, vol. II, chap. I8.
ABSTRACTING AND GENERALIZING OPERATIONS ‘
5
lines, he argued,12 were end results of eliminating all other con-
tent from actual things. Thus, geometry as the science of space
must be concerned with bodies, but bodies from which all the
properties and characteristics are removed, until only a point or
a breadthless line is left. Geometry, therefore, is concerned with
ideal objects produced by the schematization of experientnl ob—
jects."
∙
i
sitions few will attempt to dispute, but the various attitudes tO—
ward the checking criterion are another matter. Within recent
years, since the advent of relativity and quantum mechanics, even
physical scientists question the existence of an objective world—
that is, events independent of the scientist’s descriptive and inter.—
pretative constructions (p. 3I2f). In paper after paper, in book
after book, physicists discuss whether the events with which they
deal are anything but sensations.18 Such discussions always skirt the
abyss of meaningless problems.
It is hoped that the interbehavioral position adhered to in this
work may serve to illuminate the character of the criterion by
which we check our constructions. Recall that the physicist, as well
as every other intellectual worker, operates in a definite reference
field. It is very easy, then, to determine whether or not he is in—
fluenced by presuppositions describable as cultural influences or
simply by local school traditions. As pOinted out in Volume I
(chaps. 5, 6), any notion that things and events are reducible to
sensations (psychic constructs), or that scientific propositions are
based upon sensations, can be definitely traced to the dualism
hampering scientific thinking. In this sense we can'identify the
fluences leading such a physicist as Mach to build upon Hume’s in}.
formulations, or the mathematician Poincaré to retain the conven—‘
tional conceptualism derived from Kant.
Cultural Abstracting and Generalizing. The evolution of the
number system provides the most efiective sample of the pyramid-
ing of individual abstracting and generalizing operations. The base
of the pyramid, obviously, is the series of positive integers. Per-
haps the next few levels should include the negative integers,
ratios, fractions, irrational numbers, and zero. Disregarding exact
chronology, we may point out another series of levels comprising
literate numbers, complex numbers, and ideal numbers. At the
apex, as of our time, we might place the numbers belonging to the
transfinite domains (p. 23). Clearly, these levels represent not
only possible temporal successions but also degrees of abstraction.
Only the most elementary levels of numbers are abstracted from
things. For therest, abstractionS‘and generalizations are produced
physics. But these two sciences are not always regarded as end
points in this reductive procedure. Physics is made basic to chem—
istry, this discipline, in turn, is shaken down to mathematical rela—
tions. Nor does this terminate the process, Since mathematics is
often cut down to logic. Current conventions limit the fecundity.
necessary to reduce logic to something else.
Multiplicative Austractions. The operations we call multiplica—
tive abstraction occur when we not merely analyze given material
but‘immediately add interpretative components. The operations,
in other words, are constructive. We are reminded here of those
continuity physicists (Mach, Ostwald) who fifty years ago denied
that physical events could properly be analyzed into atoms. For
them the basic and fundamental data of physics° consisted of energy,
and energy was regarded as continuous. The atomists, of course,
constructed their analyzed factors, and, though physicists could not
have foreseen recent developments in quantum theory, we might
trade an unbroken line between atoms and energy quahta as ab—
stracted units endowed with more elaborate characteristics.
Every scientific field offers numerous illustrations of construc-
tive abstractions. Consider the multiplicative character of the ab—
stracting operations that produced “sensations” in traditional psy—
chology. Sensations were not only the atoms of the mind, but dif—
fered from other kinds of atoms depending upon how many types
there were in the system. For Wundt sensations contrasted only
with feelings. Other psychologists multiplied sensation .proper—
ties to contrast with images and with will elements also. These
imaginary sensations were even endowed with spatial attributes!
The entire process of abstractive behavior is neatly revealed in the
story of how elements of “consciousness”
can be provided with
spatial properties. But even these extravagantly multiplicative
creations count as nothing beside the creativity of physicists who
make sensations into the fons et origo of the material cosmos.
The multiplicative character of abst‘raction products is excellent-
ly shown by observing how they evolve in the first place. Take
the abstraction stimulus as it developed in psychology. Originally,
.ABSTRACTING AND GENERALIZING OPERATIONS I3
the term was taken over from biology to refer to some condition—
for example, light rays—which incited the action of a receptor
(retina), and finally resulted in the appearance of the sensation in
consciousness. Then the property of inciting an organism to act, as
in performing a motor response, was added to the sensation. When
psychologists became interested in the behavior and adjustments of
organisms to‘ their surroundings, the properties of stimuli were
again increased to include Obj ects. Still later, the stimulus abstrac—
tion became modified in order to take on properties of field factors.
Another good example of the multiplication of abstractive'prod—
ucts centers around the changes in such products as matter and
form. Matter, as abstracted from an art object, is sometimes pre—
Sumed to have no properties until impressed with form by the
artist. But it is asked: “Had the block'of marble no form at all
when it came out Of the quarry?”21 Mill has pointed out that the
word form should refer only to bodily figure. Beyond that every
usage became vague and arbitrary.
a
It is commonplace that all complicated intellectual enterprises
necessarily involve linguistic and symbolic techniques. But, as we
have seen,28 the precise manner in which linguistic and‘ symbolic
things and acts operate in logical situations is not so clearly. recog-
nized. This condition undoubtedly may be traced back to a lack of
adequate views concerning the nature of language and symbolism.
2'
Cf. Ginsburg, Finite.
Concept.
:1 Russell, Reply, p. 703.
'3
Vol. I, chap. 8.
ABSTRACTING AND GENERALIZING OPERATIONS 19
These linguistic events are only very Slowly being appreciated as
essentially interbehavioral in character. Even those writers alive
to the behavioral and interoperational nature of language fail to
differentiate between language operations and the products of
those operations. Thus, to work out the place of language and
symbols in abstracting and generalizing we must separate referring
from denoting action, and these in turn from selecting and en—
larging behavior, as well as from any products of the conjoint
operations of all.
2°
3°
Cf. Xantor, Principles, vol. II, chap. 20.
Treatise, Bk. I, sec. 7.
20 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
Principles, p. 7.
ABSTRACTING AND GENERALIZING OPERATIONS 2I
I. DEFINITION
E ssence: and F orms
Traditionally the treatment of definition has resulted in two
sorts of‘absolutism: one, formalistic, the‘other, methodistic. The
2Cf. Dubislav, Definition; Robinson (Definition) lists 18 names for sorts of
definition.
3o PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
In modern times the search for essences gave rise to the problem
whether they could be located in universals or only in particulars.
Hence logicians divided themselves into nominalists, who made
definition consist of the manipulation of words or terms, and
realists, whose terms reached out toward the essence of things.
Nominal Definition. As a typical example of nominalistic defini-
tion consider Locke’s statement that definition is “nothing but
making another understand by words what idea the term defined
stands for)” The ideas, of course, constitute psychic states pre—
sumed to be the essence of known reality. Though no less psychic
than Locke, Reid builds his definition of definition with greater
emphasis on words.
A definition is nothing else but an explication of the meaning of a
word, by words whose meaning is already known.-Hence it is evident,
that every word cannot be defined; for the definition must consist of'
words; and there could be no definition, if there were not words pre-
viously understood without definition.‘5
By the use of such nominalistic procedures many writers have
hoped permanently to grasp fixed entities. Especially the British
sensationists entertainedthe notion that the reality of an Object
or an event‘could be seized by regarding it as a name. Definition,
therefore, becomes the manipulation of Verbal entities.6 According
to this plan, satisfactory definition is nothing more than the organ-
ization of words to the point of satisfying the organizer. It 'is un—
necessary to reiterate the objections both to the fundamental sen-
sationistic philosophy and to the concrete usage which nominalis-
tic definition implies. On the other hand, taken in a relativistic
framework, nominalistic definition is a useful and important pro—
cedure, its basic Virtue being that it is not equated with the events
defined. The definer, that is, remains aware that definitions consti-
tute constructions. On this basis definition can render service in
r
To be discussed in chap. 18.
Essay, Bk. III, chap. 3, sec. 10. \
“Essays, p. 10.
° Compare‘ Mill’s statement with the above. “The simplest and most correct
notion Of a Definition is a proposition declaratory of the meaning of a word” (Sys-
tem, Bk. I,\\chap. 8, sec. 1).
32 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
An example of a definition
\
13:
PDQ.=.~PVQDf. \
the system itself constitutes the basis for treating its elements,
whereas in nonformal situations the criteria are less definite and
circumscribed. Whether definitions are formal, rigid, and con-
stant, or informal, loose, and temporary, depends upon the fol-
lowing criteria: (I) the definer’s purpose, or the character of the
problem at hand, (2) the types of stimulus objects defined
(things, qualities such as color, brilliance, etc., words, symbols,
actions) 5 (3) a criterion compounded from (I) and (2), namely,
whether things are operated upon directly” or through the inter-
mediation of such an action as ai'concept or an idea, and, finally,
criterion (4.), the question whether definition18 designed to stress
form vehicle—i. e. the words or signs, Or the product of the
intrinsic definitional operation. Around the fourth criterion are
centered problems of vagueness and ambiguity which we treat in
a later section. _
Analysis of Definitional Situations. We listafour outstanding
factors of definitional situations:
A. Stimulus objects, things defined.
B. 'Defining acts. \
ever, that all logicians reject description from the rank of genuine
definition, on the ground that in description the name of a class
is defined by accidents—namely, attributes not included in its con—
notation. Lotze,17 on the other hand, though an absolutistic writer,
accepts methodological descriptions as definition, but thinks they
require checking by traditional classificatory procedures and defini-
tion rules in order tO control arbitrariness. Basically, Lotze is, of
course, attempting to safeguard his metaphysical interests.
Empirical writers are more favorablyinclined toward descrip—
tion. For example, Pepper18 has recently offered a vigorous plea for
descriptive definition. Adopting a modern and improved interpre—
tation of description, he assumes a position 'vis a vis the symbolic
logicians who, because of their exclusive interest in linguistic
formulations, wish to separate definition completely from proposi-
tions.- Pepper Obj ects to the idea that definitions, by contrast with
propositions, are entirely dissociated from truth reference. To
limit definition to the nominal form which is not responsible to
facts, he holds, prevents attaining the clarity and tolerance that
logic should foster.
Nominal definition, which 'Pepper contrasts with descriptive
definition, has two species called equational and ostensive forms.
Equational definition is described as a dyadic relation in which
S, the symbol, is equated- with, defined by, or substituted for MN,
a combin'atiOn of other symbols. Here we have a simple organiza-
tion of linguistic things.
Ostensive definition is likewise a dyadic relation, but in this
instance the-symbol S indicates, or is ostensibly defined by, 0,
some empirical obj ect. The ostensive feature is a pointing or other
type of operation.
By contrast with these two species of nominal definition Pepper
calls his descriptive definition a triadic relation. S, the symbol,
tentatively indicates, or is OStensibly defined by, O, the S18 tenta—
tively equated with, or descriptively defined by, D, a description;
and finally, D hypothetically describes, or is verified by, O, which
now becomes a field instead of a single object. Despite the fact
that the triadic relation seems to comprise the other two plus a
1'
Logik, I'I, chap. 1.
Descfiptive; Definition.
42 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
straight lines, the former passing through the center to the cir-
cumference at both ends, while the latter has one end in the
center. _
On the whole, classification definitions do not imply any
thorough penetration into the properties of things defined 5 how—
ever, the defining operations become modified in the face of the
problems the definer sets himself. Genus-species specifications from
ancient Aristotelian logic penetrated to metaphysical ultimates.-
Classificatory definitions also cover any sort of predicative designa—
tion desirable for logical and nonlogical enterprises.
Defining by Postulation. Again, defining procedures may be
differentiated on the basis of whether the objects defined or the
needs and desires of the definer are stressed. When objects are not
stressed the operations and products are naturally somewhat freer
of the objects’ characteristics as ascertained by various contacts
with them. Proceduresemphasizing objects iiivolve, for instance,
the construction of a map or schedule indicating their essential
properties. Postulational definition, on the other hand, implies
that the constructional activity is directed or influenced by assump—
tions brought to bear on the procedure.0 '
∙
‘° Cf. Campbell, Physics, p. I 22.
↕ Logic, part I, p. xiii.
‘2
Principles, p. 69.
DEFINING AND CLASSIFYING OPERATIONS 51
operations include the ascertainment of the elements of things and
the organization in which they are synthesized. This procedure
involves a more intimate contact with things than occurs in naming
definitions, or in Simply delimiting their boundaries.
Either analyzing or synthesizing operations may be stressed in
some defining Situations, or both may be equally represented as
in the following example.
Protoplasm constitutes a colloidal complex of water, inorganic
salts, and four organic substances, proteins, fats, carbohydrates, and
extractives.
How'elaborate or compact, how simple or complex a defining op-
eration should be depends upon the orientative circumstances. As
a rule, however, the products of analogy and synthesizing opera-
tions are more elabOrate than those of naming or delimiting situa—'
tions.
Defining by Relating and A nalo gizin g. Though probably no
defining operations can dispense with relating acts, some definitions
are more decidedly relational than others. Mathematical defini—
tions are, on the whole, fine examples of this type. To define a one-
member class the following structure is set up:
If x is a member of a and if y is also a member of a, then y is
identical with x.
'
”Principia, vol. I, p. 1 I.
“Definition,” p. 287.
‘7
54. PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
definition, but not all writers offer it, probably on the ground that
it is concerned more with division than definition.
The rule of noncircularity of definition in particular marks the
path from words to things. It is frequently noticed that the repeti—
tion of words is either unimportant or unnecessary, when the
words are employed to refer to, or substitute for, things.“3
For authentic system-building procedures a different set of
rules is required. At the peak stands proper regard for specific
problems and particular reference frames. For effective systemiz-
ing, defining behavior must be articulated with the conditions
under which it is performed. In this way one avoids adopting an
alternative but less adequate procedure.‘
Likewise important is the rule that no particular kind of defini-
tion can serve as a model for all other types. For example, though
mathematical definition is exact and effecti19e for mathematical re—
lations, it can not be employed as a general model for material
which can not be SO rigidly defined (vol. I).
From the standpoint of concrete interbehavioral enterprises the
conventional objection to definition by use is not acceptable. The
question is: Are there specific situations in which such definition is
conducive to the organization of a system? The objection to using
description stems from the neglect Of the psychological aspects of
logic, and the prejudice against concrete behavioral, as over against
abstract formal, procedures.
II. CLASSIFICATION
Classes are essentially systems. Classifying operations, there-
fore, constitute logical or systemizing behavior. They are even
more essentially logical in nature than syllogistic construction op—
erations. Traditional logic, however, has only been Concerned with
the most formal and simple types Of classification.
Here is another instance of the ill effects brought about by the
intrusion Of linguistic factorsInto logical situations. For one thing,
although classification lends itself to the effective arrangements
and organization of actual things, it has been confined to terms and
statements. Nothing has had a 1n trivializing logic.
Consider how the processes of classification have been mishandled
Johnson, Logic, part I, p. 104; Eaton, General, chap.\7; Lewis, Mind. p. 82.
M
DEFINING AND CLASSIFYING OPERATIONS 59
by contamination with division, especially dichotOmous division!
Even the classical logician in his practical contacts with actual
things57 has had to take account of the great discrepancy between
division and classification.
AS system building, classifying work consists of the construc-
tion of classes as products. These products, like all logical products,
may be constructed linguistically or developed on the basis of han-
dling or describing actual things. In all cases a product class is
not to be taken as an eternally existing autonomous entity. Platonic
classes are, of course, simply reification of terms; as such they il-
lustrate the substitution of a constructed ’description for things
described. When actual things are organized, the criteria may be
selected from their Similar properties. Differences in identity are
arranged to form a coherent system. Thus a class men is achieved.
On the other hand, purely constructed classes are set up by means
of constructed properties. Pure and preferred races, for instance,
are constructed out of the autistically created properties of manu—
factured peoples.
Tradition has it that definition is preliminary to classification.
As we have seen,
however, classification may precede definition.
This apparent ’circularity of operation is not objectionable unless
one adopts an absolutistic notion. When system building concerns
concrete, interbehavior we can go even further and point out that
instead Of a circle we have here a Spiral of procedures. In other
words, there is a continuous ascent from one level to another. On
one level definition precedes classification; on another the opposite.
takes place. The fundamental question is whether the systemizing
operations are progressing.
Classification procedures fOr system building must be differen-
tiated from similar procedures carried on for nonlogical purposes.
Involved are variations in criteria, refinement of procedure, and
intensity or amount of detail. Truth tables of formal logic illus-
trate small systems which include at the same time definition, divi-
sion, and classification. By prescriptive definition such systems are
limited to truth and false categories or statements. Further, they
are defined as P false, and Q true is impossible or excluded. Then
the systems are divided and organized intofa conventional pattern.
\
4 4 4 4 4 4 4 4
O 3 6 I2
24 48 96 I 92
0
It is interesting to note that the discovery of Uranus, between
the dates of Titius and Bode, fitted into the Scheme. This. is all
the more remarkable because the original figure for Mercury
should have been 1V2, Since 0 is not V2 of 3. But even mOre ex-
ceptional was the incident of the missing planet or empty space.
Here was an astonishing feat of prediction whereby the planetoid
or asteroid Ceres was discovered on the basis of a crude and un—
workable system. Just how baseless the system was-came into full
view when it broke down with the discovery of Neptune and
Pluto, as the continuation of the above scheme indicates. In the
case of Neptune, however, both Adams and Leverrier assigned
distances to the planet on the basis of the erroneous system which
thus played a part in its discovery.
Neptune Pluto ∙
374
4 SJ
768
4
l
388 779-
i
300 396 ‘
\
obtaining:
32 4’2 52 62
.= 3645.6 X
m2
2
m
-4
Balm'er, calculating the following series, assigned difierent
values to m as below:
m Calculated Observed
3 6562.08 6562.1
4 4860.8 4860.74
5 4340 4340-1
6 4101.3 4101.2
7 3969 3968-1
8 3888 3887.5
9 . 3834-3 3834
10 3796-9 3795
3769-6 3767-5
12
3749.1, 3745-5
13 3733-3 3730
14
-_ 3720.9 3717-5
15 37II 3707-5
16 3702-9 3699.
Anna-len.
64 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
hm2
aPerrin, 1901-, Nagaoka, 1904; cf. Tucker, in Taylor, Physics, p. 820; also
Poincare; Foundations, p. 317.
SYSTEMS AS CONSTRUCTION PRODUCTS 65
At this point, further reconstruction of the Rutherford atom
was necessary. The problem was to Show how electrons could
maintain themselves in the outer atom. According to Classic elec—
tromagnetic theory the circulating electron must continuously
radiate energy and describe a spiral path until it collides with the
proton. Since the observed facts of the hydrogen spectrum did
not accord with the collapse of atoms, Bohr had to construct a bold
postulate.
It was no less than the creation of a stationary motion or state.
This consisted of the circulation of an electron in its orbit with a
constant energy. Unless the electron jumps from one orbit to
another there is neither radiation nor loss of energy, nor absorption
increase of energy. But when the electron shifts from one of
the many possible orbits to another, it gains or loses energy and
emits or absorbs radiation. Energy is lost and waves emitted, when
the electron jumps from an outer to an inner orbit. The instantane—
ous change from an inner to an outer orbit marks the absorption of
energy, in which case the atom iS said to be excited and to Show
an absorption line in the spectrum. _
With respect to radiation, the spectral series of hydrogen can
be envisaged as follows: When the electron jumps to the second
orbit from the third, H a is emitted; from the fourth, H B; from
the fifth-\H 7, etc. This is the Balmer series. Shifts from outer to
lowerienergy levels up to n = 3 give the Paschen infrared series,
Up to n = I the Lyman ultraviolet series, and to n = 4 the far
infrared seriesgof Brackett.
Doubtless the most important item of the system is the importa-
tion into it of the quantum theory. Whenever an electron jumps
from one orbit to another it either gains or loses energy in discrete
quanta. For example, in moving into an orbit of higher energy, as
the electron might do by colliding with another electron, by ab-
sorption of radiation or by high temperature collisions, the change
would answer to the formula hv :2 Ez—El. Similarly the loss of.
energy by radiation of light is described by the same equation; It
is Observed that the frequency of the radiation is measured in
terms of Planck’s constant h. .
how the system assimilates the Balmer and Rydberg items. This
assimilation may be regarded as predictable, since the quantum
theory itself is a radiation theory, and because of the close associa-
.tion of the Balmer and Rydberg constants. As early as I900 Haas
had Shown the probability of expressing the Rydberg-Ritz constant
in terms of h and electronic data.3 Certainly, evidence was already
available that the particular structure of an atom or molecule de-
termines its Spectrum. What was needed, then, was to interrelate
the known facts of the hydrogen spectrum with the relations ob-
taining between the hydrogen electron and proton. N ow, the
quantum atom made possible a theoretical basis for the Balmer and
Rydberg work.
We have seen (p. 5) that the Balmer formula for the hydrogen
Series: 0
m2
= 3645.6 X 2 a
m −4
was arbitrary and purely empirical. Yet it was sufficiently descrip—
tiVe of the order and regularity of spectral lines to be predictive.
Rydberg (I 8 54—1 9 I 9), interacting with the same datum—namely,
the hydrogen spectrum—proceeded from the wave length and
the known velocity of light to the calculation of the number of
waves that pass a given point in a second of time. it became ex—
pressed in cms., through the following developments.‘ First, Bal-
mer’s formula was written:
(In21112−− 4)∙
I I
A = 3645 .6
Then, by multiplying the numerator and denominator on the
right side by 4, the following expression was obtained:
)1—3645.6 22
4
(I In2I)
When this formula is eXpressed in cms., it reads:
I I I” I
—= 109,720 −−−− —.
)1
22 m2 1
a Sommerfeld, Atomic, p. 89.
‘The present system illustration is derived in large part from Tucker (Taylor,
.Physics, (p. 82of). \.
5
The factor 109,720 is, of course, the Spectroscopic constant 0r number of Rydberg.
Later determinations of this number gave the more accurate figure of 109,677. 8 cins'1.
SYSTEMS As CONSTRUCTION PRODUCTS 67
Taking into account the Lyman and Paschen hydrogen-spectral
series, as well as those of Balmer, we obtain the two following
↨ −− − —>
formulae. For the Lyman series:
—
I I 1
I2 m2
3, 4 . . . and forRthe(—Paschen series:
—->
where m = 2,
−−
I I
- I
32 m2
withm=.4, 5,6... .
− —>
Generally, for all spectral lines of hydrogen we have:
—-
I I I
n2 m2
which, when written as follows:
i
cha
we have an equation:
12 21r’e‘m I 1
− − eh”
(n12 1122)
which is equivalent to Rydberg’s CXpression for Balmer’s hydrogen
series. The remarkable thing about this is that such an approxima-
tion is obtained with an equation whose constants e, m, c, b have
been obtained independently of the spectrum of hydrogen.°
Widely acclaimed as a superlative product of imaginative
genius, the Bohr quantum system ,was found to be applicable to
more complex atoms than hydrogen, as well as to the light con-
ditions of molecular substances. For‘our study of system products
it is significant that the Bohr atom system was successful insofar
as it-\in‘tegrated and organized the kinds of data With which it was
\
5 Tucker, in‘Taylor, Physics, p. 824.
68 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
B. Linguistic Systems.
Linguistic systems constitute unique system‘ological products.
Essentially, they are organizations of responses which can be de-
74 PSYCHOWY AND ∞
scribed as references or designations. When building such systems,
the system builder works with referential actions intimately and
inseverably interrelated with the things referred to.
That linguistic systems consist of actions and not things can
scarcely be overstressed. Although the products represent an em—
phasis on language factors, they must not be confused with lin-
guistic content systems of which language things are the ingredi-
ents.’
The constituents of language systems are describable as asser-
tions of every sort and for every purpose. Such assertions may be
magnified to refer to things of cosmic import, or constructed to
designate simple and petty details of events. It is not a reflection
on logic to indicate that organizing a complex court plea is building
a logical system. To distinguish such logical acts from others we
might characterize them as mediate, remote, or nonexecutive re-
sponses. The system builder is handling things assertionally.
At this point we must again call attention to the factors of the
system-building field. In referential acts the system builder’s work
takes precedence over what he interacts with. In this sense linguis-
tic systems are first-degree language systems. Such acts, when re-
ferred to, recorded, or fixated in transcription, become descrip-
tively transformed into second-degree or thing—language systems
(p. 73). Second-degree language systems take their place among
the content structures.
( I) General Reference Systems. The primary distinguishing
feature of these systems is the intimacy of the references. Even if
the referents are regarded as important, there is a personal factor
in the system.
(a) Operational References. Instructions to perform operations
with respect to given things form genuine, and sometimes ex-
tremely important, systems. Their range (p. 84) is enormous
when we take into account references to actions, such as preparing
a prescription, following a recipe, and carrying out complex mathe-
matical operations.
(b) Systems of Argument. The organization of a series of asser-
tions to form arguments is a good illustration of a type of linguistic
system. Consider a lawyer’s series of references to alleged events
For a discussion of language behavior and language things see Kantor, Objective,
chap. 2, and Principles, chap. 23.
SYSTEMS AS CONSTRUCTION PRODUCTS 75
in order to establish a particular belief or conviction. Perhaps a
more formal, and hence more tightly knit, aggregation of asser-
tions is exemplified by the classic paradoxes of Zeno.
I. Motion is impossible because a body cannot arrive at another
place without passing through infinitely many and infinitely small
separate parts.
2. Achilles cannot overtake the tortoise, since he must first reach
the point simultaneously left by the latter. The tortoise will thus al-
ways be in advance, if only by an interval which constantly decreases
to a minimum.
3. The flying arrow is really at rest since at every instant it occupies
a discrete point of its path. Of such zero movements no genuine mag-
nitude can be summed.
(2) Metizod Systems. Important examples of linguistic systems
are found in various reference organizations for the conduct of
reason and scientific work. Here we may cite such classic systems
as those of Descartes, Newton, and Mill.10 These systems, as or-
ganizations of references to operations, difier from simpler opera-
tional reference systems in their generality and specialization for
achieving important results in comprehensive situations.
(a) Descartes’ precepts for rightly conducting the reason and
seeking for truth in the sciences.11
The first of these was to accept nothing as true which I did not
clearly recognize to be so; that is to say, carefully to avoid precipi-
tation and prejudice in judgments, and to accept in them nothing
more than what was presented to my mind so clearly and distinctly
that I could have no occasion to doubt it.
The second was to divide up each of the dificulties which I ex-
amined into as many parts as possible, and as seemed requisite in
order that it might be resolved in the best manner possible.
The third was to carry on my reflections in due order, commencing
with objects that were the most simple and easy to understand, in
order to rise little by little, or by degrees, to knowledge of the most
complex, assuming an order, even if a fictitious one, among those
which do not follow a natural sequence relatively to one another.
The last was in all cases to make enumerations so complete and
reviews so general that I should be certain of having omited nothing.
'° Mill’s system is treated in chap. 19.
“ Haldane and Ross, Philosophical, vol. I, p. 92.
76 ' PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
A - E
C ontraries
a)
0 c3
E
8 0o,"e E
8
e ∙a:
N
t(b 0/,
N
.0
I.∙ °
(J “ed,
0
Subcontraries
I O
∙
\
T T T T T T
F T F T
↓ F
∙
T F F T F F
F F F F T
SYSTEMS AS CONSTRUCTION PRODUCTS 79
Systems involving more than two values require more elabOrate
structures. Suggested modifications become necessary when sys-
tems of simple dichotomy are. opposed to those involving some
content material. On the whole, the two-valued systems can‘ be
kept free from content and SO-called meaning.
(3) Complete Induction. Of all formal situations that of
complete induc‘tion provides the best illustration of the .nature
of system products, chiefly because such systems involve an equal
stress of material and form factors.
The materials consist of relations organized into a stable struc-
ture. N o doubt, emphasis on material has given rise to the histori—
cal term induction. The interbehavioral process involved here iS
primarily the selection of type of relation to be organized. Com-
plete induction products, more than ordinary deductive systems,
stress structurization activity.
Turning to form, complete-induction products consist of systems
in all aspects comparable to the circular structure of deductive
systems. This is well illustrated by the-following classic example.‘
For all integral values of n: '
∙ −
Whoever first developed this system observed the relations
involved, and then set up a formula indicating them. The
formalization procedure consists for the most part of constructing
the formula, a procedure which belongs to the symbolic phase of
system making.
(4.) Mathematical Systems. The acme of formal systems is
presumably attained by constructing a pure mathematical system
or aggregation of axioms—that is, assumptions or postulates—as
in the following example.13
I. If A and B are distinct elements of S, there is at least one m-class
containing both A and B.
2. If A and B are distinct elements of S, there is not more than
one m-class containing both A and B.
. Any two m-classes have at least one element of SIn
There exists at least one m-class.
common.
Every m—class contains at least three elements of S.
All the elements of S do not belong to the same m-class.
No melass contains more than three elements of S.
1”Veblen and Young. Projective, p. 2f.
∞
8o PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC '
N ow, although the synonyms axiom, assumption, and postulate
imply that mathematicians and logicians no longer accept absolute
and self-evident propositions, it is still true that the formality Of
postulate systems leads to notions of pure reason and ultimate
systems Of- objective relations. Many individuals concerned with
formal systems overlook’ the fact that systems can only be con—
structed by' operating upon building materials. Frequently it is
asserted that logical processes may be performed without any
knowledge of concrete objects to which the primitive propositions
or postulates refer,“ or that mathematical deduction can be made
without knowing what one is reasoningxabout.15 More careful
writers, however, go only so far as to say that a pure mathematical
system can be constructed without explicit reference to specific
subject matter.1" Such writers acknowledge, then, that a mathe-
matical system merely intensifies the work of any system which
consists Of abbreviating and abstracting specific complex materials.
Whether or not in presenting the final product any explicit refer—
ence is made to specific subject matter, that reference is definitely
indicated1n the operations performed.
Compare the above abstract system with the following more
concrete point--line system. IS it not obvious that the f_or_m_erwas
derived from the latter, which, aside from the last item, is essen—
tially Veblen and Young’s set of assumptions for a plane proj ec—
tive geometry?
I. If A and B are distinct points, there is at least one line on both
A and B.
If A and B are distinct points, there is not more than one line
3°
on both A and B.
Any two lines have at least one point in common.
There exists at least one line.
Every line contains at least three points of the plane.
All points are not on the same line.
No line contains more than three points of the plane.
In the present situation it is impossible to overlook theI ab—
I
stractor’3 work (chap. I 3,.3), and how that work constitutes
system building. Notice his labor1n mOving from geometry to the
sear
l
1‘
Carmichael, Logic, p. 1 IO.
Veblen, Problems.
Cohen and Nagel, Introduction, p. I 35. '
SYSTEMS AS CONSTRUCTION PRODUCTS 81
logical system. That- such work with definite materials is indis—
pensable in all system building is amply enough demonstrated
throughout the evolution of all abstruse geometries, which are
based upon the observed relations of concrete things in practical
Situations.
How can. we fail, then, to emphasize the factors governing the
choice and arrangement of axioms? This, we ask, despite the
tremendous force of opinion that we Should disregard all influences
on the constructor, and focus only on the product.17 Does not the
entire modern theory Of postulation demonstrate the necessity to
take into account the constructor’s work and circumstances? Is not
the whole history of non-Euclidean geometry a sharp reminder
that the belief in Euclid’s infallibility long obstructed the evolu-
tion of geOmetry?13
AS to the particular influences on system makers in setting up
their geometric axioms, Why does Hilbert choose his five basic
items, whereas Pieri and Veblen each makes use of only two dif—
fering ones?19 There is no question that all these mathematicians,
no matter how they vary in their results, are influenced by specific
features of the geometric universe of discourse. True, they have
freedom to choose what aspects to stress, but since they are build-
ers in specific situations they are constrained by the subject matter
with which-they work.
Mathematics as Postulation. As we have indicated (Vol. I), the.
employment of postulational methods in mathematics emphasizes
system making and the role of the system maker. But we must
stress further the Specific interbehavioral details of mathematical
work. The whole point to glorifying Pythagoreans, Eudoxus, and
Euclid20 as the first explicit employers of the postulational method
calls attention to the systemizing operations in arithmetic and
geometry. To a certain extent this postulational method consists
of analyzing and stating the processes necessary for organizing a
system of things Or numbers. Incidentally, the mathematician’s
motivations are indicated here—namely, the felt need for order
1'
It is especially those who Work with abstract or formal systems who stress the
genetic fallacy, which they interpret as an undue interference with the study of
finished products by concerning oneself with irrelevances Of origin.
∙
YoDng,\Lectures, p. 28f ;Bell, Development, p. 302.
'3
p. 231.
2°
Bell, Development, 665.
82 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
↕ ∙ Whewell, History.
I, p. 262.
84. PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
D. Operational Systems
Operational systems emphasize executive action. They consist of
structures or organizations of techniques, methods, and work plans.
Although operational systems are conditioned by the things op—
erated upon, the factor stressed is the interbehavioral feature of
the structured situation.
'Logicians- willing to renounce the exalted character Of abstract
systems need not hesitate to number among operational products
every sort of prescription or recipe, whether the ordering opera—
tions are performed in the kitchen or pharmaceutical laboratory.
To be sure, such structuring of prescriptive operations may be
very .difierendy rated or evaluated from other systems; neverthe-
less, as a system it differs only in detail from the most abstruse
mathematical or logical systemizing. °
(I) Chemical Analysis. The immediate problem here is to dif-
ferentiate five cation groups and then to isolate the three members
of the first group—namely, lead, mercury, and silver.23
Step 1. Adjust acidity of original solution and precipitate with HCl.
The following cations will precipitate as chlorides:
Cations Pb”, Hga”, Ag.
Chlorides PbCla, Hga, AgCl.
Step 2. Acidify solution and precipitate with H28.
The following cations will precipitate as sulfides:
Cations Pb”, Bi+++, C11”, Cd“, Hg“, AS+++, As++++’sb+++, Sn”, SnVH.
Sulfides PbS, BizS:, CuS, CdS, Hg8, A5283, SnS, SnSa, etc.
Step 3. Add the proper amount of ammonia and H28 to the solution.
The following cations will precipitate as sulfides:
Cations Zn”, Ni”, Co”, Mn”, Fe”.
Sulfides ZnS, NiS, COS, MnS, FeS.
The following cations will precipiate as hydroxides:
Cations CH“, AIHI. _
Hydroxides Cr(OH)a, Al(OH):.
Step 4. Adjust alkalinity and add NH4Cl and (NHOaCOa.
The following cations will precipitate as carbonates: l
Cations Ba", Sr”, Ca”.
Carbonates BaCOs, SrCOa, CaCOa. j
The solution will contain the following cations:
Na, K", Mg”.
Step 5. To precipitate of Step I, containing PbCls, ngClz, and AgCl, add boiling"
H20.
Step 6. To confirm Pb++ add KaCr04 to solution and
precipitatePbCrO4. r
\
The materials for this illustration have been drawn primarily from Meldrum and
’3
Daggett, Textbook. ∙
SYSTEMS AS CONSTRUCTION PRODUCTS 85
Step 7. To residue from solution in Step 5, containing ngCl: and AgCl, add NH:
and precipitate black Hg and HgNH2Cl, this confirms Hga“.
Step 8. Acidify solution from Step 7 with HNOa, the presence of white precipitate
AgCl confirms presence of Ag.
Step 1.
Arrange y 3x:I + 5
The operation here is simply preparing the situation for the
necessary future operations.
Step 2.
Y_-+Ay=3(x+Ax)2+s
“—'31:2 + 6X' Ax + 3(Ax)2 + 5
This step involves another preparatory operation, that of replac—
ing x by x Ax and then a calculative determination of the value
of the function y —|— Ay.
Step 3 .
y+Ay=3x +6' Ax+3(AX)’ +5
y=3x +5
y: 6X°Ax+ 3(Ax)2
Here the given value of the function is subtracted from the new
value to determine the value of y, the increment of the function.
Step 4.
AY —-6
— X + 3 Ax.
Ax
This operation divides the increment of the function by the in-
crement of the independent variable.\
Step 5.
. dy
∙ − 6x
dx
36 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
∙−
domain of natural action, instead of allowing them to fall into
the abyss of transcendentalism.
5
Cf. vol. I, pp. 28f., Iozf., I59f., 294.
INSTRUMENTS FOR SYSTEM CONSTRUCTION 95
is referred to or "described, we have some sort of construction,
whether or not regarded as a model. A genuine model is an
elaborate construction for some particular purpose—personal ori-
entation, or communication. But the most abstract construction is
always continuous with the crudest contacts of individuals with
things.
Envisaged‘as orientational tools, logical instruments are re—
moved from any contact with metaphysical problems. On the one
hand, we are free from a logic dealing with verbal abstractions re—
mote from actual things. On the other, we avoid the implications.
of Platonic reals, according to which propositions or mathematical
formulae are presumed to constitute realities. Logic on our basis
does not therefore consist of propositions or forms which consti-
tute an autonomous and unique realm, nor is it concerned with
fundamental tautologies—with language, as the logical positivists
have it. Rather, all models, no matter how elaborate, are specific
interbehavioral procedures fitting a particular logician’s purpose.
Because of this specificity, it is inevitable that certain elements
of the construction are not derived from the crude data. Every-
one, depending upon individual experience both professional and
private, has various predilections for certain models. For instance,
one person chooses verbal instruments as over against mathe-
matical. -.Another pov'verful factor is the worker’s cultural back-
ground. A scientist bred in a religious culture sees no incongruity
in using creative and Spiritual ingredients to account for a certain
event, 'whereas another person finds such elements extremely ob-
jectionable. In each case there is a thorough mixture of personal
experience with cultural conditions.
11
O ‘I 2 3 4» 5' 6
Figure I
K
O
D C
F E
G A H B
Figure 2 Figure 3
passive)
The Categorial System of von Hartmann. Modern categorial
systems reflect the various metaphysical or philosophic viewpoints
of their constructors. Hegel, for example, criticized the Kantian
organization because it was too abstract and formal. For Hegel
categories must be ultimately constitutive of things. Von Hart—
mann, who has treated the category problem most elaborately,
attempts to organize a categorial system by adopting the results of
the Hegelian formalistic criticism, adding the correction that cate-
gories, in addition to being logical, must include the nonlogical,
and even unconscious, characteristics of a world system. His re-
sults are indicated in the accompanying tabular scheme. For the
most part, the represented items are treated as they are presumed
to operate in the subj ective-ideal, obj ective-real, and metaphysical
spheres.
Von Hartmann’s Categories
A. Sense Categories
I. Sensation categories
I.
Sense quality
2. Sense quantity
a. Intensive quantity
b. Extensive quantity or temporality
II." Perception categories
Extensive quantity or spatiality
B. Thought Categories
I. Primitive category of relation
II. Categories of reflective thought
1. Categories of comparative thinking
2. Categories of separating and combining thought
i
CATEGORIAL SOURCES
Writers of contrasting cultural backgrounds locate the basis of
the universal and necessary thought elementsIn somewhat1dif-
ferent sources. We have just referred to the Kantian notionthat
categories represent a priori forms under which things must be or—
\ ' I
’ Dennes, Categories. P
Cassirer, Substance. ‘
Aiken, Notes.
0 Categories.
CATEGORIES AND SYSTEM BUILDING 113
ganized in knowledge. Essentially, this source of origin derives
categories from the ultimate character of mind. Mind is thus re—
garded as some sort of cognitive power, which, even if it does not
supply the laws of knowing, does provide the forms in which
knowledge of things is organized. Actually, of course, mind is
made to do more than synthesize objects for experience; by the
categorization technique it “produces” phenomena. The source
of categories, according to this View, lies in the individual—specif—
ically, in his cognitive power.
In contrast stands the View that the mind derives categories
secondarily from cultural sources. In Spencer’s type of evolution-
ism the basic categories for the individual mind are evolved
thrOugh hereditarily transmitted racial habits. Such a theory as
Spencer’s is Often taken to constitute an empirical doctrine. For
the members of the French school of social anthropologists, such
as Durkheim and Lévy—Bruhl, categories are forms of knowledge,
ways in which things and conditions must be cognized, and these
ways are derived from the characteristics of particular social or—
ganizations. The emphasis here shifts from individuals to groups,
from individual to collective mentality. It is part of the French
sociological doctrine that individual mentality reflects the group’s
general mentality. Aside from the difliculties involved in a con—
ception of social mentality, we confront the fallacious idea of es—
sential and‘ fixed forms without flexibility and without the local
functional character which actual categorization entails.
on
Even though writers categories depart considerably from the
traditional emphasis of the synthesizing power of the mind, as
represented, for example, by such a study as Windelband’s" they
do not escape the notion of ultimate and totalitarian analyses of
things. Turning toward the analysis of terminal properties only
partially modifies the interest in an underlying mentality capable
of reaching out to ulterior categorization processes.
To eschew both the direct and indirect connection of categories
with mental powers makes room for the operational enterprises
which persons foster either in furtherance of personal achieve-
ments or as part of large-scale undertakings in which many indi—
viduals participate. At once the sources of category making are
extended'indefinitely.
System.‘
114. PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
CATEGORIES AND CONCEPTS
Since the development of subjectivism and dualism, and their
application to logic, categories have been equated with conceptsf"
In other words, categories have been regarded as mental or psychic
entities which play a part in the operations of judging and reason-
ing. This identification, we have seen, attainedIts full floweringIn
the Kantian theory of categories.
Nothing is more certain than that this identification is based
upon the confusion of our reactions to things with those things
themselves. Notice the sharp transition from the Aristotelian cate—
gories as descriptive elements of things+or the referential ele—
ments of such descriptions—to the Kantian assumption that cate—
gories are the mental processes by which the creative mind organ—
izes objects and events (vol. I, p. 59). The Kantian doctrine is
essentially a rounding out of the spiritualistic principles developed
by Patristic and Medieval thinkers.
Even when concepts are not regarded as psychic states but as
forms of interbehavior, they are, not to be identified with cate—
gories. In operational situations categories are definite construc-
tions—that is, products developed for system-buildingipurposes.
As such they constitute manipulable objects. The range of their
character and use varies as the systems which they help to form
vary from simple classification and description of particular events
to large generalized ontological or epistemological structures.
'I
CATEGORIES AS INTERBEHAVIORAL PRODUCTS
From a logical standpoint categories constitute system—building
materials created for some specified enterprise. They become the
end products of interbehavioral processes in particular reference
fields. On such a basis they are never far removed from the opera-
tional situations out of which they arise. Not that categories are
capricious or arbitrary. Their interbehavioral origin permits us
to evaluate them on the basis of how the category constructor has
worked. Fundamentally the criterion is whether categories are de-
rived from contacts with events or simply imposed upon the latter.
Notice that whenever sets of categories are established as exclu-
sive or most basic, in the sense of the ultimate and complete Kant-
ian forms, the category systems are empty and unproductive.
Probably in no case'is it possible to achieve more than a relatively
I I6 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
∙ CATEGORIAL SPECIFICITY
Not only do categories differentiate themselves according to
kind of work—logical, scientific, etc.—but within any one type
the investigations call for particular sets of categories. A classic
scientific illustration is the derivation of work by the Ca-rtesians,
in contrast to the Leibnizian force. Accordingly, for Newton and
others following Descartes mass, force, and momentum are the
original categories, while for Huygens, following the Leibnizian
view, they are work, mass, and vis viva (energy).
' Categorial specificity bears directly upon the hierarchy or re-
duction principle in science. It is frequently, though improperly,
held that the sciences are hierarchical (chap. 13, p. 12), with
mathematics as the most fundamental. A variant of the hierarchical
view discriminates against mathematics as a science, but makes
physics basic and its categories the primary ones. Biological, psy—
chological, and anthropological events are regarded as reducible
to physical and chemical happenings, thus the physical categories,
such as protons, neutrons, and electrons, are made basic to those of
all sciences. ∙ ∙
FrOm'the specificity standpoint, however, each set of categories,
when found sufficient for the needs of a science, is irreducible. The
criteria, therefore, for setting up any set of categories are localized
in the investigative problems of the particular discipline. Two dis-
tinctive enterprises are involved: (a) setting up verbally unifying
systems and (b) constructing categories for systemizing events and
their observation.
I .
Mechanics
If we are looking for variation in the fundamental categories
employed to develop a scientific system we find it in the history
of mechanics. Originally the basic\ categories 'Of inertia, velocity,
force, acceleration, energy, and the implied categories of space,
time, and mass were regarded as powers, properties, and existences.
Only recently have they come to be considered as constructions
120 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
2 . Electricity
The electrical branch of physics provides many striking instances
of the origin and increase of categories. First, there were the
simplest categories of positive and negative electricity, later the
systemization of electrical knowledge engendered such categories
as inductance and electrical field. At still later stages the categories
of capacitance, conductance, and resistance elaborated the system.
With the evolution of electrical science, cptegories cross the me-
chanical borders and culminate in such products as electrical mass
and velocity. °
3. Geometry
In this most stable and deductive field there is a perennial shift
and reevaluation of categories as knowledge progresses. Only
when the geometrician is preoccupied with particular data—that
is, the solution of specific problems—can he overlook the evolution-
and multiplication of such basic categories as point, line, surface,
and solid. Such obvious geometrical transformations as in the de—
velopment of non-Euclidean systems is proof enough of cate-
gorial modification. For example, the solid or space of older Eu—
clidean geometry is certainly a different sOrt of space from that
evolved in the investigations of Grassman, Riemann, and others.
Nothing is more striking than the transformation of the categories
point, position, line, and extension into operational space. cate—
gories. In other words, simple absolute position evolves into a
relation, defined by triplets of numbersIn a system of coordihates.
The following statement of Brewster concerning Newton elfec-
tively indicates geometric shifting: -'
In imitation of Cavalieri, he called the momentary increment of a
line a point, though it is not a geometrical point, but an infinitely
short line, and the momentary increment of an area or surface he
called a line, though it is not a geometrical line, but an infinitely
narrow surface.11
x\
Brewster, Memoirs, p. 17.
CATEGORIES AND sYSTEM BUILDING 121
4. Everyday Categories
The categorizing series constructed by a political candidate
demonstratesIn the best possible manner the nature of categories.
Notice how he builds up a system of “my performarice.” To be
sure, the candidate may sincerely believeIn the political and social
improvements supposed to follow his election. Actually, however,
he is not referring to existing events. What happensIs that by
means of substitute stimulation he13 able to operate with a set of
categories which are products of his interaction with nonexistent
situations—namely, those situations he promises to bring about.
The fundamental import of such categories is that they represent.
modifications in present conditions regarded as unsatisfactory and
capable of improvement.
A similar set of categories may systemize a particular individ—
ual’s attitudes concerning actually existing conditions. As such they
are simply products of immediate interbehavior. In other words,
they do not represent any necessary analysis of things or conditions,
but stem from an individual’s views, reactions, or beliefs. While
the above is not an essential description of everyday categories,
inasmuch as such categories may be precisely like those so well
established in logical and scientific domains, an appreciation of the
nebulous and unstandardized processes of engendering categories
indicatesthat category products are not always formal or ultimate.
5. Religious Categories
Valuable ideas concerning categorization proceSses 'may be
gleaned from the theological problem of positive and neutral
categories centered in the negative theology developed from
Philo, through the Gnostics and Christian apologists, to Plotinus
and beyond. These writers struggled with the question: What
categories can be applied to the deity? Negative theology implies
the recognition that all categories are constructs and thus finite
in character. How, then, can categories, which are simply fixations
of qualities or characteristics observed from concrete interactions:
with things, apply to deities?
Even early theologians observed that the glorification of a deity
is not achieved by ascribing to him qualities which, in so far as
they also apply to mundane things, are clearly not sufficiently ex—
alted. To their credit they discovered that God could not be omni—
I 22 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
6. Dimensional Analysis
Dimensional analysis, as a domain of measurement, exemplifies
not only the construction and use of categories but also their in-
tegration into systems. Dimension categories serve as units for
deriving interrelations as functional systems. VelocityIs a structure
deriving from L and T as fundamental dimensions:
[V] = L]:
[T]
L is constructed to serve in whatever capacity is required to deal
with length as distance, interval, etc. V, as a derived unit, is a
local system capable of functioning as an item in more comprehen—
sive systemization. For example, velocity is only a subunit in ac—
celeration systems. When F'symbolizes acceleration, its relation
to V, L, and T is clear from the following:
[F]: [_]=[] l
V L
[Tl [T2]
Assuming that dimensional analyses concern specific types of
mensuration systems, we may ask whether the C.G.S.
unTIxts
or
dimensions are ultimate or basic, either as ontologic, phenomeno—
logic, or epistemic categories. The phenomenologic units are im-
∙
'2
Fairbanks, Philosophers, p. 67. ∙
CATEGORIES AND SYSTEM BUILDING I 23
mediately derived as a matter of course, since such units are ele-
ments of intolerable spiritistic systems. But, though with proper
interpretation, the ontologic and epistemic systems may be accept—
able, we still face the question whether they are unqualifiedly basic
and indispensable.
Although such a writer as Campbell believes that all funda—
mental measurements belong to physics (267),13 and that the
basic characteristic of physics is its propensity for measurement
(33f.), he does not regard length, mass, and time as basic magni-
tudes, even when to these three are added temperature, dielectric
constant, and permeability. This does not mean, however, that he
does not consider some magnitudes as basic (393), since he realizes
that of such are mensuration systems made. Which are funda—
mental depends upon the mensurational task at hand. Campbell
plainly asserts that measurement is a means toward an end, con—
sequently, the tools and procedures are dependent upon the opera—
tional systems in which they are found.
Dimensional analyses as systemological factors were appreci—
ated by the earliest students of the subject. As Larmor“ points
out, Newton originated the essentials of dimensional doctrine as
a means of comparing the properties of correlated systems, for
example, (a) particles of different systems, (b) particles and
bodies, and (c) resting and moving parts of systems.15 As is well
known, Fourier more explicitly worked out the theory of dimen—
sions and their eXponents in his development of mathematical
systems, or equations, in which the homogeneity of terms must be
maintained. The correlation of heat conductivity with other meas—
urements involved equations eXpressing necessary relations be-
tween common units of length, time, and weight, to which are
added temperature and heat quantity."
So far we have accepted the view that dimensions are quantita-
tive. But we must go further. If we begin with the operational
basis of categories, instead of with conventional notions of onto-
logical or epistemic postulates, we may allow for other sorts of
dimensions. Such dimensions imply nonadditive orders and ar-
9. Biology ‘
In no scientific domain are categorization principles better illus-
trated than in the descriptive and\ interpretative systems con-
structedIn the biological sciences. In \addition to the importation
of categories from other investigative fields, some are constructed
with unique application to biological events: Iéiological categories
CATEGORIES AND SYSTEM BUILDING 127
are differentiable on the basis of observational derivation or free
construction.
Biologists are undecided whether their categories should in~
cline more toward (1) structure, (2) function, or (3) both. On
the one hand, the organism is emphasized as distinctive and self-
maintaining. Here the fundamental categories are morphological
in type, such' as cell, tissue, and organ. On the other hand, since
biological systems are always. active and changing units, the actional
or physiological categories, such as metabolism, may be stressed.
Ecological events lend themselves best to interrelations of struc-
ture-function categories.
Change and action categories divide themselves into two series,
one of which has to do more with particular organisms, their growth
and coincident anabolic and catabolic processes, and the other
with such general processes as evolution, which is concerned with
the development of types, or individual forms.
Characteristic of the problematic, and perhaps speculative, bio-
logical categories are those which began historically with the cate-
gory of vital force, and which, especially in the modern embryo—
logical branch of biology, come under the heading of organizers,
determiners, etc. A unique form of this type of category is the
gene, which, on the one hand, is deductively constructed from
observations of happenings during reproductive cycles, and, on the
other, may be regarded as a freely constructed category for the
purpose of interpreting changes not easily observed but necessary
in accounting for observed happenings.
∙ Et/tical Categories
The number and type of ethical categories are dependent upon
the views of writers. concerning the nature of ethics. A very gen-
eral category of this field is that of the summum bonum. There
has always been an implicit recognition that the field of ethics
has to do with some sort of norm or value. The innumerable inter-
pretations “of what the summum bonum should be depend upon
various cultural situations with their foci in particular intellectual
formulations.
Obviously, ethical categories as constructs are primarily autistic.
This fact perhaps eXplains why ethicists have differed so radically
128 PSYCHOLOGY AND L0GIC
I 5.
Mathematical Analysis
Even a casual inspection of the constantly developing field of
mathematical analysis requires an elaborate dictionary merely to
list the categories. Because of the abstract relational nature of
mathematics, its general terminology comprises a unique set of
categories. As is true elsewhere, mathematical categories are de-
rived from operations performed upon crude data, and are thus
specific kinds of constructions. Important mathematical categories
are operation, continuity, field, function, rational, inductive, vari-
able, limit, parameter, constant, infinitesimal, infinite, operator,
magnitude, convergence, divergence, etc.
These categories, which have always impressed thinkers as
ultimates and as independent of particular enterprises, are def-
initely functional 5 they vary with the probléms, types of field, and
mathematical interest of the worker. The many interpretations
put upon such categories as the infinite and the infinitesimal are
sufficient to remind us of their operational and constructional char-
acter.
CHAPTER XVIII
UNlogics;
IVERSALS occupy an ambiguous position in conventional.
When mind and reasoning are regarded as transcend-
ent powers or ontological essences, disturbing problems inevitably
arise. Are universals concrete or abstract? Granted that they are
abstract, may they be contaminated with qualitative and content
residues, or must they be pure forms? Again, when logic is deeply
concerned with problems of class membership and class inclusion,
must classes be dispensed with as merely linguistic conveniences
because they are “not as genuine objects as their members are if
they are individuals? ”1
No ambiguity attaches to universals in interbehavioral logic.
Universals are products of system-building operations, but they
are something more than end points in the operational procedure,
in addition they constitute the raw materials of further system-
building operations. .This characteristic, it should be noted, uni-
versals share with relations, classes, kinds or species, mathematical
functions, and other constructional forms.
HISTORICAL TREATMENT or UNIVERSALS
A definite cultural continuity relates the current universals
problem to that of earliest antiquity. The natural history of uni-
versals constitutes a fascinating and informing story when con-
sidered as the behavior of persons called logicians who occupy
themselves with the universals issue.
Universals among the Greeks. Greek interest in universals may
be justly stated to have arisen out of a systemological problem.
The development of forms, ideas, definitions, and genera is surely
localized in the work of setting up Systems of knowledge (science)
or logic.
SinCe the Greeks did not Work with nonspatial, or mental, con-
Whitehead and Russell, Principia, p. 72; Russell, Principles, p. x.
I32 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
”Ibid., p. 36.
\
UNIVERSALS: COMPONENTS AND PRODUCTS I35
either logical or ontological, have centered around words. Such
is the case which Goethe describes:
Denn eben wo Begriffe fehlen
da stellt ein Wort zur rechten Zeit sich ein.
Thus words, in the form of assertions and statements, are em-
ployed to mediate and interrelate universals and particulars. Rus-
sell9 and Johnson” divide off and interrelate universal and par-
ticular terms by making the former into adjectives or predicates
of propositions (sentences), and the latter into substantives. How
little this subj ect-predicate'solution satisfies the participation ques-
tion becomes apparent when considering Johnson’s contention
that, while a substantive can only serve as the subject of a sentence,
adjectives can function either.as predicates or as subjects. For
example, in the sentence: “Punctuality is a fault,” “fault” may be
taken to be a secondary adjective. Russell objects, and asserts
that the proper handling of these words must be as follows: “For
all x, if x is unpunctual, x is reprehensible.”11 A “particular” or
an “individual” can be defined as “anything that can be the sub—
ject of an atomicproposition.” This is not true for “universals”—
that is, a predicable character or relation.
This treatment of participation is a modern linguistic form of
realism. Nominalism, too, mediates verbally between singulars
and generals. Current nominalists declare that universals are
names for properties abstracted from actual objects, events, or
behavior—triangularity from triangles, wisdom from wise be;
havior, blueness from blue hat, etc. In other words, universals are
abstractional products embodied in words or terms. There is justi—
fication for this notion in the sense that the referents for the auton-
omous terms triangularity, wisdom, and blueness are diHerent
from the referents of the terms wisdom (wise action), triangu—
larity (three—sided figure) 5 blueness (a blue hat).
The question now arises: What is the relation between the sub-
sistential references for universal terms (words) and concepts?
Notice that the latter, too, are regarded as nonexistents, repre-
sented by words. It is plainly indicated, therefore, that we should
Problems, chaps. 5, 9.
Logic, part I, p. I I.
1°
13Inquiry.
UNIVERSALS: COMPONENTS AND PRODUCTS I37
SPECIFICITY 0F FORMS
Universals are the specific products of abstracting and generaliz—
ing behavior such as we have described in Chapter I 3. These pro-
cedures take place in definite interbehavioral fields. It is encourag—
ing to find the specificity principle not only recognized, but appre—
ciated, in logical writings. For example, McGilvary17 asserts that
relations, even though generalized to a high degree, are specific.
This View follows from his general realistic philosophic standpoint.
Indeed, pragmatic realism has much in common ‘with an inter—
behavioral View, certainly there is considerable appeal in thel idea
that"universals are really always particulars. The fact that one
generalizes or constructs a universal does not detract from the
specificity of the situation in which the process takes place.,'
Specificity has to do with the particulars of the relations them-
selves. In other words, we have a Check on the conception that
there is a generality or universality of forms which gives them a
16
Reason, p. 2 o4.
Relations.
UNIVERSALS: COMPONENTS AND PRODUCTS I39
unique status different from particular things. In every case such
generalized or universalized relations constitute simple construc-
tions which are mere generalized referents of verbal propositions.
FORMS AS PRODUCTS
In carrying out all sorts of operations upon things it is neces—
sary to develop or create instruments for performing large-scale
operations in order to summarize, organize, and refer to things
(chap. I 6). In calculating we require a form which will span a class
of values, thus we create a variable. In comparing things we need
an instrument for carrying over from one relation to another.
Hence the construction of a relational form. This is a genuine con-
structional process derived from contacts with things.
Three sources Of raw materials from which to construct forms
or generals are:‘(a) things and events interacted with, (b) acts
themselves, and (c) the products which result from such acts. Let
us characterize each in turn.
(a) Thing or Event Sources
Recall that it was philosophical convention to classify all forms
as universals and relations. But when we start from actual contacts
with things we find that they result in the construction of many
types Of forms. The following list, while not exhaustive, illus-
trates a series of forms constructed from thing and event sources.
I. Qualities. Quality forms, traditionally known as universals,
are definitely derived from things, and for the most part are ab-
stracted from structural characteristics such as color and hardness.
2. Properties. Conditions of things and their changes provide
the basis for abstracting forms or generals such as lastingness, con—
tinuity, and irregularity.
3. Relations. These forms are abstracted either from parts or
aspects of stimulus Obj ects, or from some situation or complex in—
volving several objects. In the former case the complex consists
of the discernible features of a single thing—for example, front or
back, up or down. Out of a configuration involving several things
such relational forms as “between,” “higher,” and “lower” are
derived.
Notice that relations are features likewise Of the connections be—
tween Objects. For example, we interbehave with the relation or
I40 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
Farms
Thing constructs
System Components
Things
Objects (natural and artificial)
\
Relation constructs
Property constructs
Relations (discovered and
contrived)
Properties (observed or attributed)l
Number constructs Quantity (singularity and plurality)
Magnitude Dimensional extent
Terms Words, reference acts
Conventional logics are built from forms, though the builders
may not be aware that their materials are constructs produced from
specific manipulations of things. Conventional-(logical building is
carried on in two steps: (I) compounding forms-into propositions
UNIVERSALS: COMPONENTS AND PRODUCTS I43
and (2) organizing propositions into complexes and sets of propo-
sitions.
Propositions as Form Compounds. As constructs propositions
are compounds developed by elaborate abstractions from events.
The proposition P(Iron is a metal) compounds certain qualities
and certain substances for classificatory or manipulative purposes.
NO one probably would object to such a description of the formula—
tion procedure, nor to the implication that the products constitute
formulae. The question is: Can one, accept the total set Of implica-
tions?
Basically, we are occupied with persons operating upon things
in a remote way. No dualistic version of concepts or ideas is ad-
missible. We have already excluded all notions of mental states
as over against actual things. Nor are we concerned with a num-
ber of individuals (class aggregate) as against the individuals as
members. We are dealing, rather, with products of prior inter-
behavior with things.20 In Short, any logical view harboring uni-
versals, forms, symbols, or propositions which are identical with
things we regard as logistic and derived from historic identifica-
tion of thoughts, things, and words.
Propositional Complexes. Propositions organized into com—
plexes or minor systems are illustrated by syllogisms, implications,
sorites, etc. We must, however, differentiate Sharply between
the sentences which refer to, or stand for, the propositional chains
and the propositional complexes referred to or denoted. All such
formalistic systems take their place among those other systems
built on the basis of actual things, relations, acts, etc. A genuine
operational theory, by keeping clear the situations in which per-
sons are interoperating with their stimulus Obj ects, avoids the pit-
fall of distinguishing between generic and universal propositions
as absolute and inclusive types. Instead we handle interbehavior
with all sorts of things, abstractions, constructs, and so on.
The widely held View that when thinkers adopted the causal
notion to account for things they discarded mystic processes and
became exclusively occupied with events as caused by other events
is, however, scarcely true. The evolution of the causality construct
did not once and for all establish a mode of thinking concerned
only with laws derived from observed things and events. Actually,
the interest in cause in no sense excluded the mystical from the
explanations of natural happenings. Worse, from time to time
cause itself was made into a mystical process, for under this rubric
were placed innumerable magical forces which were presumed to
bring things aboutIn some unknown, and sometimes impossible,
manner.
Under simple cultural conditions causes have been regarded as
elementary agencies for producing various obj ects and events,
not infrequently the term cause refers to acts of personal creation.
Again, causes are powers exerted by an agent in carrying out some
purpose. As is well known, even thinkers of the, I7th‘.and early
18th centuries were not emancipated from such views. Hence the
controversy between Leibnizians, who believed the supreme power
so created the universe that it was everlastingly self-Operating, and
Newtonians, who held that the cosmic mechanism required oc-
casional divine intervention to run smoothly;
It is clear, then, that the causal construct has had an uneven
career in the history of thought. What lends credence to the belief
that among the Greeks cause became a definitely naturalistic idea is
the simple but straightforward presentation of Aristotle. He be-
gins with the problem Of knowing a thing and aSSErts that knowl-
edge depends upon cause or primary conditions.°
Thus he enumerates four causes: (I) material, that from which
a thing comes into being—the silver of the bowl, the bronze of a
statue, (2) the formal, in the sense of shape, pattern or formula
-——for example, the ratio 2: I, in the case of the octave, (3) the
primary source of the change, “whattmakes of what13
made,” an
’ Diels, Vorsokratiker, vol. II, p. IO.
One might argue that the very number and variety of causal
situations are so great as to accommodate the two grand generaliza-
tions that the universe is a set of necessary connections and that
science demands a universal causal principle. Even if this result
could conceivably be brought about by judicious deflation and
translation of the original assertions, their relevancy at once be—
comes severely limited. Similarly, by proper treatment the more
Specific formulations that we have called formal, epistemological,
and ontological may be adapted to certain phases of causal situa—
tions. In all cases in which generalized formulae are adapted to
specific instances it is the detailed variation of the events under
consideration which becomes emphasized. Causal principles are
the more cogent the closer they approach concrete events.
Keeping close to events makes irrelevant any large-scale formal
assertion. Important only‘are analyses and formulations that serve
to connect one event with others in a class. Specific causal formula-
tions exclusively enable us to make predictions” and in general
achieve some experimental control over certain situations.
readers to suppose that the formula “All men are mortal” repre-
sents a formal implication, and at the same time a causal law. N ow,
he says, the real possibility of an immortal man is compatible;l with
the truth of the formal implication. But the very supposition that
under certain conditions a man might live forever signifies the pos-
sibility of violating a causal principle And this goes counter to
the idea of a causal law.31
3°
Hofstadter, Causality.
Ibid., p. 259. ‘
INTERBEHAVIORAL LOGIC AND CAUSATION I 55
Hofstadter, Causality.
I 56 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
cause of an event we seek the reason “why” this event, and not
some other logically possible one, is occurring. It is chiefly the
linguistic influence which fortifies the belief that a causal investiga-
tion involves anything but the problem '“how” an event occursa4
—namely, how the constituent factors of things, their prOperties
and conditions, are organized in an event situation.
36
∙
Notlon. \.
How.
37 Russell, Reply, p. 701.
INTERBEHAVIORAL LOGIC AND CAUSATION 163
tion if one grants the occurrence of such events. Assuming the
correctness of the hypothesis that causation. consists of a pattern
of subevents or event factors we find a continuous series of inter-
behaviors with such events. The simplest level is that of every-
day or “commonsense” situations. Here Simple questions are
asked: the goal of the inquiryis a practical outcome of the inter-
action Of events. On the scientific level more significant questions
are posed, with a correspondingly greater capacity on the part of
the investigator to analyze the interacting factors, hence, a more
sophisticated procedure of interrelating events. The scientist, too,
works out elaborate CXperimental techniques for the dissociation
and technical reassociation of factorsIn order to discover their
variants andInvariants.
In more formal (logical) situations causal interbehavior pro—
ceeds on the basis of contacts with substitutes for highly analytic
data. The direct stimulus objects are kept at a remote distance for
the sake of achieving precise descriptions and interpretations of
causal factors and their interrelationships.
( 2) Causal Events. Causal events as data consist of particular
interrelationships of observed happenings. The essentially causal
feature comprises the copresence of the event components. Events
can be observed to occur through the addition and subtraction, the
separation and contigu‘ation of the factors. Certain chemical com—
ponents are present together, and only a temperature or pressure
change is necessary for a new chemical state to ensue. Again, a
slow chemical reaction may be speeded up by adding another com-
pound Or varying temperature or pressure. If, while describing
our investigation of an event we refer to our Observation, this has
nothing to do with the event itself, its factorial combinations
constitute things independent of our Observation or description.
In psychological terms, these combinations and recombinations of
factors and events are independent stimulus Objects with which
the observer interacts.
Now in some cases it may be legitimate to describe one factor
as agentive, causal, or key, since it may be the factor required to
complete the combination—lfor example, when a person facilitates
or'h‘astens the occurrence of an event by switching on the current
necessary an explosion. His behavior must be regarded as a
for
naturalcomponent of the causal system. It operates like any other
I64 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
B. Investigative Operations
A study of the pattern of causal investigation demands that we
diflerentiate between the two orders of observer and investigator.
The behavior of the operator mentioned in the agentive illustra—
tion above constitutes a first-order operation. His activity belongs
within the pattern of a causal system.
The second-order observer analyzes the work of the first Op-
erator as part of the causal data before him. He is especially in-
terested in the interaction of the experimenter as he unravels the
interrelated threads he finds among the materials with which he~
works.
Investigative causal operations can be demonstrated by consider-
ing the work of an experimenter as he arranges and rearranges
the factors in his event situations. We select for this purpose an
experiment by Hopkins.42
Beginning with the hypothesis that young animals grow nor-
mally on a diet of protein, fat, carbohydrates, mineral salts, and
water, the investigator discovers that when these substances are
purified and fed to animals they do not produce the assumed re—
sults. To groups of six rats each he fed purified milk casein (pro-
tein), lard (fat), sugar (carbohydrates), and salts obtained from
oat and dog—biscuit ash. In addition, he fed one group 2 c.c. of
milk per day. The milk-fed rats increased in weight normally,
while the control group without milk feeding began to lose
weight after 10 to I 5 days.
Assuming that the operations are well controlled and the re-
sults valid, the next step in the causal investigative pattern is to
‘1
For 5. comprehensive study of construction in logical situations see Kantor, Inter-
behavior. Scientist, p. 291f.
Gedrge,
‘3
I66 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
C. Constructions
Descriptions and interpretations of causal occurrences naturally
differ on the basis of the type of crude datum upon which they are
constructed. Causal theories based on construct data 'are very dif-
ferent from those based on independent event data. Even in the
case of independent event data, theory constructions may Show
divergences. One may set up descriptions and laws of causal events
which are altogether independent of human agency, such as the
tidal relationships between themoon and earth. Other construc—
tions Of causal factors involve the activities of the agent or in—
vestigator who deliberately produces certain ochanges in the crude
data.
Cause and Efect. Faithful to the traditional’ relation concep—
tion, writers on cause have maintained in their descriptions two
related factors, cause and efl‘ect. Critics of such a notion as neces—
sary or inevitable relation have pointed out that it is impossible
to keep these two factors distinct. Since we are dealing with event
patterns, the terms cause and efiect must serve specific descriptive
purposes. Accordingly, when they refer to stimulus Obje'cfs,'these
terms refer to prior and subsequent combinations of factors. Cause
and effect as constructive terms serve only to isolate particular
stages of Observed events.
Causes and Conditions. As we have seen (p. I 52), writers on
causation regard the term cause as standing for a single and unique
process or agency. From the standpoint of field theory, instead of
singularity, we meet with all sorts of combinations of factors.
Some writers‘13 insist upon the distinction between cause and con-
dition on the ground that cause implies a suflicient factor, and
condition a necessary one. This is good as far as it goes, but in
actual investigations a much larger number of diflerentiations
must be made. When we deal with concrete situations we perforce
discover innumerable degrees of availability or participation of
causal factors.
Causes and Causal Interpretation. Both in the event and in
∙
_its interpretation we may specify all sorts of
‘3
Ducasse, Nature, p. 58.
Causal
conditions and
INTERBEHAVIORAL LOGIC AND CAUSATION 167
relations, depending upon the investigator’s interest. From‘the
standpoint of specificity logic the investigator’s purpose is a definite
objective fact to consider when causes are to be determined. For
instance, there is a vast difference between an investigator’s in-
terbehavior with particular causal conditions—as in his attempt to
understand a certain disease or how X-rays are diffracted—and
that of an individual attempting to set up a generalized definition
for all possible causes. The latter-procedure can not yield any Sig-
nificant result, and the acceptance or rejection of such a formal
schema depends upon the formulator’s caprice.
Here is a convenient place to point out again that interacting
with concrete events is vastly different from interacting with ver-
bal or propositional substitutes for such events. The construction
of formal propositions achieves a certain degree of significance
only if the formulator takes account of concrete situations.
CAUSE AND SYSTEM BUILDING
Causal events as natural occurrences are completely independent
of- any person’s activity. Accordingly such events may be far re—
moved from logical or system-building behavior. Despite this fact
cause and system building may be brought very close together.
In the first place, causation is essentially systematic. Causal situa—
tions, as we have seen, comprise interrelations of factors, and this
in itself is System. Again, human behavior occupies an exceedingly-
large place as an integer in causal systems, as all scientific experi-
mentation testifies. Those who regard logic as system building
are therefore in a favorable position to conj oin logic and causatiOn.-
On'a systemological basis logic can be closely connected with causal
situations in two Ways: (A) as a general structurization en'ter-
prise'and (B) as a local instrumental procedure.
2. Method of Difference
Second Canon. If an instance in which the phenomenon under investigation
occurs, and an instance in which it does not occur, have every circumstance in
common save one, that one occurring only in the former; the“ circumstance in
which alone the two instances differ, is the effect, or the cause, or an indis-
pensable part of the cause, of the phenomenon.
0. Joint Method of Agreement and Difi'erence
Third Canon. If two or more instances in which the phenomenon occurs have
only one circumstance in common, while two or more instances in which it does
not occur. have nothing in common save the absence of that circumstance; the
circumstance in which alone the two sets of instances differ, is the effect, or the
cause, or an indispensable part of the cause, of the phenomenon.
3. Method of Residues
Fourth Canon. Subduct from any phenomenon such part as is known by
previous inductions to be the effect of certain antecedents, and the residue of the
phenomenon is the efiect of the remaining antecedents.
Wittgenstein, Tractatus.
Hedrick, Tendencies.
Metaphysics, Gamma, chap. 3.
"Ibid., chaps. I, 2.
I80 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
l
investigation, in 1ts widest and most abstract form, is dialectical in
‘the Sense of abstract reference and description.
In consequence, Aristotle makes no sharp distinction between
investigating things and linguistically organizing them. From our
standpoint this is indeed a naive and commonsense View, but it is
nevertheless objective in keeping clOse to actual things. There is
no sophisticated reduction of things to ideas or symbols, as in
later times. When Aristotle discusses the laws as principles of
being he sees no necessity to distinguish them from principles of
thought. On the contrary, for him.axioms or principles are at
once, in' different aspects, principles of existence and of reflection,
as well as of demonstration or argument.
The practical and commonsense—we may even say the opera—
tional—4character of the Aristotelian principles is demonstrated
by Aristotle’s variance in emphasizing them. The principle of con-
tradiction he regards as the most certain: "
The same attribute cannot at the same time belong and not belong
to the same subject in the same respect.15
Somewhat subordinate is the principle of middle exclusion, formu-
lated at the beginning of Chapter 7.
There cannot be an intermediate between contradictories, but of
one subject we must either affirm or deny any one predicate.16
The identity principle is subordinated to both of these.17 Identity
Aristotle treats as the problem of the meaning, and singleness of
meaning, of words, especially the words being and not being.
First then this at least is obviously true, that the word “be” or
“not be” has a definite meaning.18
For not to have one meaning is to have no meaning.1° There is
no question that he13 concerned with references to actual proper—
ties or attributes of specific things.
Though Aristotle13, no doubt, primarily interested1n common—
sense objects, with ordinary discourse and practical demonstration,
as a philosopher he naturally attempts to attain generality, even
1“Ibid.., 1005b,18fi.
1°
Ibid.., 1011b, 24.
it
'7
Ibid., 1006a, 2955 and 101 1b, 263.
Ibid., 1006a, 31. ‘
∙
19Ibid., 1006b, 9; 1006b, 13.
THE LAWS OF THOUGHT AND THINGS ' I81
absoluteness of formulation. Still, his formulation of abstract and
general principles has to do with concrete things in specific situa-
tions. Aristotle’s thought was always thought about things, not
a reaching out to transcendent and sophisticated ideas and entities
beyond the borders of spatiotemporal happenings (vol. I, chap. 3).
Not until the post—Aristotelian (psychistic) era of logic were
the practical principles made into regulatory laws for the conduct
of Reason. Only when logic became thoroughly formalized Could
the principles of identity, contradiction, and excluded middle be-
come universal and absolute laws of Reason which not only legis—
lated for things, but also subordinated. them to thought. This
formalization involved a different type of psychology from that
of Aristotle’s. Psychological events were no longer regarded as
functions of biological organisms, but as psychic or spiritual powers
independent of the organism and the things with which it inter—
acted. Since Plotinus, who was the essential transformer of Aris—
totelian Obj ective psychology, mind as Reason or Logos has been
considered not only as self—creative, but also as the source of all
things. '
∙ Vol. I, p. 113. ∙
THE LAWS OF THOUGHT AND THINGS 183
than mathematical abstractions more resort must be had to the
type of objects dealt with. Laws of logic in the latter case are not
so much concerned with abstract organizations of formal sentences,
and symbols as With specific things.
Current treatments '01? logical laws correspond more or less to
the historical divisions of philosophy—namely, Nominalism, Real-
ism, and Conceptualism (chap. 18, p. I32f., vol. I, p. 37f.). Ac-
cordingly, while all logicians associate logical laws with linguistic
materials on the ground that logic must be formalized, they may
stress (I) linguistic structure, (2) relations, or (3) classes.
(1) Those who emphasize linguistic forms may be identified
with the nominalistic tradition. For them logic ultimately reduces
to organizations of symbols, or to systems of tautologies. Such
logicians, when concerned with mathematical or symbolical materi-
als, become modernized into syntacticists. Logical laws for them
govern the relationship between formal sentences.
(2) Logicians emphasizing relations link themselves with the
realistic tradition in philosophy. They deal with formalized state-
ments concerning things represented by the laws. Thus, logical
laws take on the character of semantic rules. The more scientific
logicians Of this type—the modern extreme ontologists—regard
the things ordered by the laws as invariable relations of existence.
(3) Our third group, the logical epistemologists, emphasize
the formal aspects of knowledge. They want logical'laws to inte—
grate statementsOr formulae with data or relations. Logical
a"
Statistical.
190 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
u - p. 200.
Concernmg, '
192 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
11 Probability.
212 PSYCHOLOGY 'AND LOGIC
, .
TheorIe, . p. CXll..
Introduction,
1°
Todhunter, History.
PROBABILITY AND INTERBEHAVIORAL LOGIC 217
the analyses, or Kepler or Galileo, all are operating by way of a
simple ordering and counting of results bounded by the character
of the devices employed under the rules of the game.
There are two important arguments for accepting the conven—
tional View that the beginnings of probability study lie in the work
of Pascal and Fermat. In the first place, by their time analytic
operations had .become elaborate enough to be dignified by the
term theory. Workers responded to themselves as factors in the
probability situation. The question had been raised whether the
propositions of arithmetic were inconsistent. Moreover, Pascal
criticized Fermat’s solution of the Problem of Points. In general,
probability situations had become enormously complex. In the
second place, Pascal and Fermat formulated a theory that the en—
tire probability situation can be handled by the operational tech-
niques of permutation and combination.
Response-Centered Systems. Following a long developmental
period in which the calculation of chances was assiduously cul—
tivated by mathematicians interested not only in games but
also in mortality and life insurance, there appeared a system
pitched on a highly sophisticated plane. The work of combina¥
torial analysis and probability theory, carried on by Huygens,
Leibniz, the Bernoullis, Montmort, DeMoivre, Euler, D’Alem-
bert, Bayes, Lagrange, and Condorcet, culminated in the technical
construction of Laplace.
The outstanding characteristic of' Laplace’s system of proba—
bility is that it is response centered. Not only is probability re-
garded as a determination of things by a. calculating individual,
but personal psychological processes are emphasized. For this
reason Laplacian probability has been seriously condemned as
subjective. Laplace declared:
The theory of chances consists in reducing all events of the same
kind to a certain number of equipossible cases, that is to say, cases
such that we are equally undecided about their existence, and deter-
mining the number of cases favourable to the event of which- the
probability is sought. The ratio of this number to that of all the
possible cases is the measure of the probability which is no more than
a fraction whose numerator is the number. of favourable cases and
whose denominator is the number of all possible\cases."
1“Theorie, Introduction, p. iv.
218 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
This excerpt makes clear that, for Laplace, the power of intel-
ligence is such as to penetrate the mysteries of nature, even if it
has to begin with nothing but symmetrical ignorance. The difficulty
which critics find in the Laplacian View is that states of mind can
neither be measured nor calculated.
But ignorance and belief need not be regarded as states of mind.
Such an interpretation stands in complete disregard of the newer
objective psychological theory. After all, the situation must be
described as one in which Laplace, a mathematician, is operating
upon certain data. And there are degrees of efl'iciency of contact
with the events of which the probability or possibility is to be cal-
culated, or otherwise determined.
A: more substantial criticism than the charge of subjectivism
is that Laplace does not explicitly indicateohis actual contacts with
things. He is determining the ratio of favorable cases to the sum
of both favorable and unfavorable cases, and that means he is ob-
serving or otherwise interbehaving with events and Situations.
Event—Centered Systems. Thinkers who harbor mental states
in their intellectual households finally escape from subjective
probability systems by turning completely to Obj ective things. A
comprehensive~system was thus built up on the pattern of a ma—
terial or frequency theory. The frequency theory was proposed
by Ellis18 and Cournot,19 and established by Venn.20 An extreme
empiricist, Venn regarded his logical interest of attaining certainty
as satisfied only by turning away from subjective belief to the ob—
jectivity of series or frequencies.
The frequency theory of Ellis, Cournot, and Venn is an in-
comparable example of the discrepancy between a logician’s op-
erational procedures and his formal structurizatiQn, between his
practice and his theory. Venn assumed that he was avoiding sub—
jectivity, that he was dealing exclusively with external things or
conditions. Actually, of course, he was concerned with system
building, which offered him confidence in the data with which he
was interacting. His practice, however, belied his theory that he
was. not dealing with belief, conditions of ignorance, etc.
Such theory-practice discrepancy stems directly from the under—
“ Foundations.
Exposition.
Logic.
PROBABILITY AND INTERBEHAVIORAL LOGIC 219
lying mentalistic psychology. Had not Venn, like the frequentists
since his time, been dominated by mentalistic psychology, he
would have realized (1) that the a priorists whom he was attack-
ing were systemizing calculations and schemas having to do with
objective events, as DeMorgan and other belief proponents held,
and (2) that centering on objects is arbitrarily Selecting only one
interbehavioral factor. Accordingly, both the empirical frequent—
ists and the opposing rationalists ignore the fact that probability
situations may be of different kinds. What they could not know
at their time of historical development was that since there is no
mental, but only interbehavior, each type of probability system
really goes back to contacts of individuals with stimulus objects.
Because the empirical frequency system is so vigorously recom—
mended as obj ective, the paradox exists that objects and their fre—
quencies become dissipated into nebulous states of mind. Some de—
vice, therefore, must be invented to keep close to the basic situa—
tions giving rise to probability problems. Venn’s formulation that
probability is a body of rules for drawing inferences about classes
of events which combine individual irregularity with aggregate
regularity is an appealing one.
Propositional Probability. A decidedly new level of probability
systems emerged when probability problems became centered in
propositions instead of in responses or Objects. For one thing,
propositional probability mirrors a more complicated set of situa—
tions. It surpasses the relatively unsophisticated inclination toward
one pole or the other in what is essentially a bipolar situation. The
superior sophistication of propositional probability is measurable
in its greater or lesser articulation with operational processes.
While it does not renounce the psychology of mind, it still con-
stitutes a step toward an objective analysis of probability interbe—
havior. Such is the case when propositional relations are regarded
as unique and rational, and“ as referring to the conditions of things.
(a) Probability Propositions and Things. This form of prop—
ositional system, for which we choose Peirce as- an illustrative
proponent, is based squarely on Venn’s formula stressing the. ob—
servation of recurrences of events. Peirce modified the system of
emphasizing the quantitative precision which mathematical calcula—
tion supplies. Propositions are best interpreted as equations. This
is exemplified by his statement:
220 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
PROBABILITY IN SCIENCE
The hypothesis that scientific enterprises are inevitably occu-
pied with probability situations has become established only at the
cost of considerable struggle. Even now many writers accept the
proposition grudgingly, at best. Though science is obviously in—
vestigation—namely, interbehavior with events that are difficult
and changeable—scientists still cling to the notion that they are
seeking absolute knowledge. Hence their bewilderment when
relativity, discontinuity, and indeterminacy-are forced upon them.“
2°
Cf. Darwin, Logic.
226 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
things and events which set him his problems. In other words, to
determine probabilities on the basis of frequencies of occurrence is
to interbehave with probability circumstances. The tools we use,
such as propositions and various calculations, are only tools. Some
particular probability task may consist of sorting out and arranging
certain propositions concerning the presence, absence, and fre-
quency of various participating factors, but the probability enter—
prise itself is a more inclusive type of event.27
It is necessary to recognize that statistical or experimental
studies are only designed to discover. the natural properties and
relations of data. This means that scientists can not reject things
and events not subject to calculation or measurement. Such quali—
ties are as genuine and as real as mathematical relations. Indeed,
it is precisely the lesser availability of these cmeasurable properties
and relations that makes for probability enterprises.
numerical, but
are really based upon the abstraction of Specific
qualities or characters?
Unimportance of Equally Likely Cases. The classical theory
is also attacked because in the final analysis it consists only of a
mathematical calculation of permutations and combinations—
that is, the interrelationship of numbers. In simple cases of penny
tossing the probability V2 does not indicate whether the head or
tail actually will fall up. Or, in a more complex situation, knowing
that a geometrically symmetrical cube is also kinetically sym-
metrical—that is, possesses equal statical moments and moments
of inertia, yielding a probability of 1/6 of falling on any side—
does not enable one to know that it will aetually fall on any one
particular side.
Again, equally likely cases are said to beoinsignificant as against
the type of probability concerned with averages, dispersions, aver-
age error, probability function, and the law of 3error. The greater
importance of the latter is taken for granted because of its appli-
cation to scientific work in physics (kinetic theory, thermodynam—
ics), astronomy (star origin and distribution),
netic’s).
and biology (ge-
Principles, p. 206.
' Ibid., p. 200.
°Ibid., p. 198.
ANALYSIS OF PROBABILITY SYSTEMS. 239
come gradually more and more quantitative.”7 Again, Jevons is
counted among the forerunners of those who applied mathematics
even to economic data. Penetrating below the surface of his doc—
trine, we find it is concerned with much more than psychic or sub—
jective phenomena in the historical sense. In short, We should
not dismiss a probability doctrine simply because it resembles an
unacceptable theory, or is itself unacceptable in some form.
We can not reject this type of probability interpretation on the
ground that it is impossible to measure belief as a subjective
event, although, as we have indicated, the stress here is Upon the
response phase. The assumption is that events are not probable
but certain, and that our reactions to events, in the sense of knowl-
edge or belief alone, are probable. Since there can be no proba-
bility reaction without reference to an eVent, and since degree-of—
knowledge situations are not only authentic but occur frequently,
we must regard them as a genuine type of probability Situation.
Moreover, it would be very diflicult to support the idea that such
probability situations do not occasion various system—building op-
erations.
From the interbehavioral or field standpoint there is nothing
mysterious about the connection of “subjective states” or beliefs
with calculation. The earliest probability studies have been inter-
related with calculation, especially the processes of combination
and permutation. We need but recall that all probability theory
consists of constructions. derived in some sense from crude data.
True, such 'constructions do not always adhere closely to the data,
in the sense that the final theory adequately represents the original
events. This is scarcely surprising, since probability data them-
selves are problematic or inadequate. For the most part, then, the
theories represent considerable autistic construction based upon
the manipulation of mathematical processes. The result is a tend-
ency to abstract from event factors, which nevertheless may still
be available despite their general problematic character.
One more point. All mathematical or calculative processes are
interbehavioral and in the final analysis go back to contacts with
events. The fact that these events maybe relations—and therefore
permit a formal treatment irrespective of objects upon which
to act—makes possible the traditional purely formal manipulations.
'..Ibid.,'\p. 273.
240 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
Prinbiples, p. 2 38.
3‘
258 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
WHAT IS MEASUREMENT?
Although mensurational operations are readily inspected, few
attempts have been made to describe them. Even these few Show
disagreements and contradictions which can only be explained by
the greater influence which traditional philosophical ideas have
exerted upon measurement theory, as compared with mensura-
tional practice. Measurement described on the basis of what is
done in measuring situatiOns consists essentially of a series of sys—
temizing operations for ascertaining precisely the properties and
relations of things and events. Formally, measuring operations
constitute the organization of criteria, units, andstandards, and
the observation of the relative positions occupied by items with
respect to the scaling instruments. The emphasis must be placed
on thessystemizing- of, or structuring operations upon, things.1
In the Stinse of Stimulus objects, cf. vol. I, chap. 5.
266 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
1Ibid., p. 295.
i
a Quantitative, p. 34.0.
° Stevens, Theory, p. 1577.
LOGICAL ASPECTS OF MEASUREMENT 269
ment to this feature. It is a reasonable hypothesis that the applied—
mathematics theory stems from the Pythagorean tradition that
somehow numbers are the heart of reality. There are definite im-
plications here that require examination if they are not to pre—
judice measurement theory.
The Power of Mathematical Reasoning. Although the number—
assignment theory is really concerned with the concrete conditions
of applied mathematics or arithmetic, it harks back to the View Of
the great power of mathematical reasoning in science. The basic
idea is that mathematics purveys certainty and achievement.
Against this unwitting projection of mathematical reasoning-
into science there are powerful protests. We have quoted Hardy’s
declaration concerning the inapplicability of mathematical reason-
ing to the physical world.10 Similarly, Einstein raises a serious
question concerning the relationship between mathematical pro—
positions and events.
Insofern sich die Satze der Mathematik auf die Wirklichkeit be-
ziehen Sind Sie nicht Sicher, und insofern sie sicher sind, beziehen sie
sich nicht auf die Wirklichkeit.11
Furthermore, what of the recent developments of mathematical
thought which make plain that number is not the basis of mathe—
matics? Mathematics may perhaps be better regarded as a science
of order or, even more to the point, as a science Of relations. On
the latter bases we must modify our
of numberIn measurement.
views
concerning the place
SPECIFICITY 0F MEASUREMENT
In line with the prevailing universality of logical theories metro-
logical systems are naturally patterned as general and inclusive
"Physics, Account, Measurement.
Campbell, Physics, et passim ; Einstein, Meaning, p.
’3
I.
272 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
LEVELS OF MEASUREMENT
The mensurational data so far treated may be arranged on a
horizontal plane. Weighing, length measuring, scaling, and order-
ing activities may be set side by side. We have still to consider the
variations of measuring situations organized in the vertical dimen-
sion. Thus, we survey briefly the continuum ranging from the
practical Situations of everyday life, through the intervals of tech-
nological operations, to the most abstruse ordering procedures of
special and ‘general mathematical situations.
Practical Measurement. On this level the operations constitute
comparatively simple, sometimes crude, manipulations for ascer-
taining the values of the things handled. The qualities and prop-.
erties of objects are measured for some immediate purpose. On
the whole, practical measurement implies the mere application of
an already—existing measurement system or the simple coordina-
tion of means and ends.
The direct handling of obj ects characterizing the simplest meas-
uring situations may be illustrated by the following process of
fitting boards to a surface. The edge of one board is laid against
one boundary of the place to be covered, and the length required
is marked by matching with the other boundary. Then the strip
cut first is used as a standard for sawing as many more strips as
are required. When a ruler is used the process is somewhat indirect,
and thus the level becomes Slightly raised.
276 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
How high the practical level rises from the gross handling
indicated may be gauged by the amount of labor and ingenuity
required to make scales and standards for comparing things. The
primary operational emphasis, however, is on the things and
their manipulation. Since the things measured, together with their
circumstances, are the focal points, we add the following list to
suggest the range of practical measurement.
1) Things and properties (Size, length, area, volume).
2) Relations (number, quantity, magnitude).
3) Strength or intensity in relation to (a) function (electrical
resistance) or (b) efiect on other things.
4.) Rates (frequency according to various criteria): period,
time interval, speed, velocity, acceleration.
5) Behavior (what a thing does under c‘various circumstances).
The primary purpose of this list is to indicate the concrete oper-
ations useful or necessary for handling given "objects. The opera-
tions are as specific and as local as the things and Situations demand.
Techno-logical Measurement. When the obj ects to be measured
are small, complex, or extremely important, we reach a measure-
ment level in which the whole situation is no longer focused on
the objects. The operations take on a unique importance; the goal
of precision assumes a somewhat autonomous character. Techno—
logical measurement requires elaborate manipulative processes in—
volving specially designed apparatus. The operations include cal—
culation and sometimes actual research work. The most intricate
technological measurements may be said to establish the identity
and properties of things whose scientific existence is problematic.
Technological measurement operations are best observed in the
behavior of scientists as they construct their mensurational instru-
ments. While devising units and scales considerable research may
be'needed to establish the existence and value of things and events,
as well as ways of dealing with them. AS our examples we choose
the developments in measuring temperature, and electricity and
magnetism.
From the beginning of thermometer making by' Galileo and
Drebbel in the early years of the 17th century,15 workers desiring
to compare warmth differences had to contend with the problem
of bringing into system a Series of factors.“On the Side of things
Grimsehl, vol. II, p. 2, et passim.
LOGICAL ASPECTS OF MEASUREMENT 277
measured there were warmth changes to be correlated with ex-
pansions of substances like alcohol, air, mercury, and hydrogen
gas. Then scale points had to be determined, naturally, the melt-
ing point of ice and the boiling point of water were taken as stand-
ards. Magnitude and denomination of intervals required the de-
cision whether zero or 32 should mark the melting point of ice.
Whether 80, 100, or 212 degrees should be the boiling point
became a matter of specific system making.
More complex and more refined temperature systems were
developed with the evolution of knowledge concerning light,
energy, and the spectrum. Coincident with Ritter’s and Herschel’s
discovery of the ultraviolet and infrared extensions of the energy
spectrum was the development of Nobili’s thermopile and Lang-
ley’s bolometer. With the latter instrument:
Measurement of the charge in resistance could be made so pre-
cisely that temperature changes of one ten-millionth of a centigrade
degree were identifiable.16
Perhaps even more informative examples of the development
of technological measuring systems are found in the evolution of
electrical units and scales. Here we can only mention the complex
labors of Ohm which finally resulted in the system for measuring
electrical current, resistance, and potential difference, and the
work of Oersted, Ampere, Gauss, Weber, and others in establish—
ing the units called ampere, volt, coulomb, farad, etc.
Formal Metrology. When measurement as operation and sys—
tem becomes interesting in itself, and is thus made an object of
study, it attains the level of abstract constructional ordering.
Measurement on this level is quite remote from the practical and
technological circumstances of the other two levels. Formal me-
trology stresses a theoretical system-building interest. Accordingly,
speculative and general philosophical views are allowed free scope.
Stressing measurement systems as the objects of their study, metro—
logists concern themselves with abstracted relations of formal
geometric and analytic consistency structures. More particularly,
formal metrology centers about invafiant relations which can be
comprehended and fixated in deductive. systems.
The best illustrations Of systems on the present level are found
1°
Tayloi', Physics, p. 542.
278 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
MEASURING SYSTEMS
Measuring systems constitute the most practical and manipula—
tive of logical structures. On the whole, they are not constructed
except for some purpose beyond themselves, a fact which probably
accoisnts for the paucity of attempts‘to describe them explicitly.
Still, a formalizing description is of considerable importance, even
though for. the moment it
means disregardin‘gkthe fact that measur—
ing operations are always specific. According to. our plan, therefore,
LOGICAL ASPECTS or MEASUREMENT 283
of treating measuring systems by means of a generalized model21
we propose the following five-factor description, based on many
simple and complex Situations.
A. Acts of assumption and postulation.
B. Choosing and refining units.
C. Instruments and manipulations.
How many scales?
Scales and scale construction.
Bias in Scale making.
Scale application (mensuration).
Scale fitting operations.
Extrapolation and interpolation.
D. Recording. .
E. Statistical treatment.
A. Assumptions and Postulates of Measurement. In practical
situations the assumptions usually concern immediate operational
details—for example, the sufficiency and trueness of the devices
used, whether levers, rulers, galvanometers or other electrical in-’
struments.
When, as in the case of more theoretical measuring systems,
assumptionsare examined and evaluated, they become authentic
and sometimes significant postulates. Such is the assumption that
mathematical relations are somehow ultimate features not only of
measuring processes, but of the nature of nature itself. Because all
measurement involves comparison of relations, we expect numbers
to play a part in all measuring systems. It is a crucial question, how—
ever, whether to regard such numbers as metaphysical elements,-
rather than as operational factors in actual situations. We must not
overlook the inevitable postulate that the development of number
systems, as well as of mathematics in general, consists of a complex
cultural evolution, and consequently involves the activities of indi—
viduals. Among the interbehavioral implications we list the rela—
tively arbitrary nature of scales. In other words, units. and degrees,
or their variation, are selectively constructed. A competing postu—
late regards all measuring devices as ihstruments for achieving cer—
The effectiveness of this model is determined'by the amount of necessary detail
that can be included without overcrowding the exposition or overemphasizing any
element.
284. PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
tain purposes; thus the kinds of things worked with are kept well
in view. Whether or not mathematical relations constitute the
fundamental nature of these things13 a problem to be determined,
not an absolute assumption from which we must make our depart-
ure.
Though mensurational postulates are factors in a system, they
are nonetheless susceptible to scrutiny and estimation. When rank-
ing assumptions we place at the metaphysical pole the view men-
tioned above concerning the relational essence of things. At a some-
what lower point is the popular attitude that science consists of
measuring behavior, and that scientific data therefore comprise
nothing but the products of such behaviorlirrespective of what is
originally measured. On still lower levels, which approach more
closely the interbehavioral operations themselves, are the assump-
tions (a) that what13 measured13 a fair sample of the total sample,
and (b) that there13 or is not a population or a universe beyond the
larger sample.
B. Choosing and Refining Units. Within specific systems units
vary on the basis of the sort of thing measured. Also, the refine--
ment and improvement of units are differentially variable accord-
ing to the mensurative situations. Probably the simplest and most
satisfying systems are those in which the units conStitute parts of
the things measured, as in the so-called fundamental units—for
example, proportions of length and weight. The things measured
in these instances possess definite metrical properties which are
divided into convenient units.
More analogical are the essentially constructive units; for ex-
ample, all units derived and compounded from SO-called basic
dimensionsw—units of density, temperature, velocity, etc. The
as
units for all derived23 magnitudes may be regarded tools of com—
parison, their primary function being to indicate relative differences
of change or proportion between properties of things.
Those whose mensurational horizon- is not bounded by the addi-
tive constructs of physics, and who therefore have room for esti-
mating, assessing and judging systems, are free to construct other
2“As the most important of the properties that can be fundamentally measured,
Campbell (Measurement, p. 127) lists numbers, mass, volume, length, angle, period,
force, electrical resistance, current, and voltage.
:1 Campbell, Physics,
p. 346f.
LOGICAL ASPECTS OF MEASUREMENT 285
types of units. Such freedom is limited only by the exigencies of
the problem of ascertaining properties and relations of things and
events. In other words, the guiding principle is to carry out a piece
of work instead of applying formal and rigid specifications devel-
oped and suitable only for another situation.“
C. Instruments and Operations. Mensurative operations so fre-
quently consistiof handling instruments that the occupation with
apparatus and things measured constitutes a single complex factor
in mensuration systems. The primary instruments comprise scales
of which there are many sorts. Measuring involves the problem of
making a scale to fit the objects to be measured. Should we em-
phasize the comparison of things or merely fit Obj ects to arbitrarily
chosen scales? Some of these issues, as we have already implied,
hark back to philosophical views.
How Many Scales? The general trend of opinion is that there
are only a few kinds of scales. The tradition of primary and sec-
ondary qualities has influenced scientific writers to divide qualities
into additive and nonadditive types. Only the primary are consid-
ered fundamentally measurable. Alternate names for these quali-
ties are extensive and intensive. Writers so influenced allow only
four Scales. On the whole, physicists, in whose province one locates
the things capable of addition and subtraction, permit a limited
number'of-scales, while psychologists and social scientists are will-
ing to increase the list to accommodate less palpable items than
those Of physics.
The physicists’ scales, on the whole, are of two types. The first,
dealing with extensive or additive properties, is called a ratio
scale; the second, concerned with intensive or nonadditive mag-
nitudes, is named an interval scale.25 Psychologists and sociologists
are inclined to add two others—namely, a nominal and an ordinal
scale. The former is employed for identifying and classifying
things, the latter for arranging things in series?6
The standard for setting up this quadruple scale system is the
conventional opinion that measurement is the application of nu-
merals to things. Such a scale systems can only be justified when
this sentence suggests that we question the assumption that any science,
including physics, is the scientia scientiarunz.
2’
There is no uniformity, however, in term usage. Cf. Stevens, Theory.
Stevens, Classification.
286 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
Mea‘snrement, p. 1 3 5.
3
Spencer, Abrasives.
288 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
3’
Ibid.,p. 14.8.
290 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
’3
Sears, Measurements, p. 841.
294. PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
thing greater or less but never equal (p. 164.). Quantities, how-
ever, as the less abstract entities, can be equal in that they possess
the same magnitude. Russell illustrates his point by remarking
that “an actual footrule is a quantity; its length is a magnitude” (p.
159). Lenzen,46 who adopts this View, asserts that quantity is a
particular, while magnitude is a universal.
Less theoretical writers use the terms quantity and magnitude
interchangeably, but, inflUenced by mathematical abstractionism,
regard them as standing for some entity different from the actual
Objects measured. Both practical-and theoretical writers consider
magnitudes as some abstract property of extension and speak of
measuring magnitude or quantity. Such a paradox can easily be
avoided by taking into account that the measurer is trying to ascer-
tain the size of something, the amount ofosome quality, or the
character of some relation an object bears to another object. One
may then use the term magnitude for Size factors, and quantity for
amount units. Similarly, the term number, also used synonymously
with these two, might be reserved for relationship determination.
For number, order may also be important. In every case these
terms, singly and together, must be associated with dimensions of
obj ects as ascertained through mensurational procedures.
Since upon an operational basis measurement is'not Simply a
matter of constructing an abstract or logical mathematical system,
but rather an enterprise carried on for specific purposes, there is a
limit to the amount of reduction and elimination of that which is
measured.
Admittedly, there exists no accepted standard for the terms
quantity, number, and magnitude. Their use depends upon the
measuring job. When we abstract from actual things, hOwever,
number, quantity, and magnitude become indifferent or equivalent
terms, and can be adapted to any sort of metaphysical position.
MEASURING AND COUNTING
To clarify the relation between measuring and counting is to
cast considerable light upon measurement principles.
For Helmholtz measuring is a coiInting procedure when the
results are denominate or concrete numbers expressing the values
of magnitudes. The latter constitute objects,\_or attributes of ob-
Nature, p. 22.
LOGICAL ASPECTS OF MEASUREMENT 297
jects, which upon comparison permit the distinction of greater,
equal, or smaller.“7 Here the absorption of measurement by arith—
metic is plain, but the empiricistic atititude exhibited does full jus—
tice to the auspices under which measuring procedures Operate.
On more abstruse grounds rationalistic writers who assimilate
measurement to counting do so because of an adherence to some
absolutistic logit of numberJThe numerals attached to things in
measuring operations are regarded as symbols for the numbers be—
longing to a transcendental system of relations. It is for this fea—
'Son that the properties of addition and independence are made basic
to measurement.48 The statement that “The primary purpose of
numerals is to express facts about number’”9 is a clear indication of
the great influence abstract relations exert upon ideas concerning
measurement. This point is further enforced by the statement:
In order that the measurement shall be really satisfactory, the prop—
erty measured in this way must Obey the rules of arithmetic.50
When measurement is approached from a more concrete scien—
tific viewpoint, especially when the difficulties of precise determina-
tion of properties are apparent, measuring and counting do not
appear so closely related. In fact, the two are sharply separated on
the ground that, whereas counting involves cardinal numbers, and
no manipulation, measurement involves ratios and manipulatory
operations.51 On the surface this differentiation appears reasonable,
but unfortunately it is still based upon an insuflicient handling of
number problems. There is no consideration of actual mensura-
tional work and its relation to counting in concrete situations.
If we turn to specific interbehavior we find that in some cases
counting is measuring, while in others it is not. Counting is found
to comprise various kinds of operation when we depart from the
standpoint of mathematics and approach interbehavior with things.
Granting the interpretation that measuring is a process of ascer—
taining the properties of things, we must include counting and
calculating as measuring actions. Situations demanding knowledge
concerning numerical or quantitative properties imply that such
’7
Ziihlen, p. 35.
Campbell, Measurement, p. 127.
’9
Ibid., p. 122.
5°
Ibidi‘,\p. 1 27.
’1
Ritchie, Scientific, chap. 5.
298 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
1Matter, p. 33.
302 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
many rather than how far, or how long in duration, or how much,
we develop a counting system. Accordingly, the things dealt with
consist of unit objects which can be enumerated and added. The
operations constitute the behavior of the operator himself, unless
some recording machine (manual or electrical registration device—
“Geiger pulse counter”) is utilized.
In situations in which no apparatus is employed we must still
distinguish between the direct interaction with objects and the more
or less long-range operations performed in dealing with abstract
relations. Behavior such as uttering number names illustrates long-
range contacts with things.
(4) Calculating Systems. Generally speaking, calculative as-
pects Of metrology concern auxiliary features of gathering informa-
tion. Operations upon things are substitutive in character, and the
instruments consist of mathematical processes applicable to every
type of Obj ect.
The rules of proper identification and classification of items are
determined by the specific interbehavioral fields in which they oc-
cur. As substitution Operations calculation processes are involved
with recorded data specifying lengths, areas, volumes, numbers of
things, and so on. More specifically, the operations consist of mul-
tiplying, dividing, and the computing of averages, rates, correla-
tions, etc. Perhaps the most definite features of such systems are
various ratios—rates of production, motion, and changes of all
sorts.
( 5) Ordering Systems. TOO numerous to mention are the kinds
of things subject to this type of systemization. In fact there is
hardly any sort of object for which an ordering rule or standard
can not be contrived. Moving things into certain positions on the
basis of previously ascertained information concerning their quali-
ties and prOperties is the fundamental operation. When things are
not sufliciently tangible to be handled in this way they can be in-
directly ordered. Recall that among the enormous range of things
subject to ordering are traits of every variety—merits, achieve-
ments, actions, as well as social and cultural properties.
(6) Estimating Systems. Objects belonging to estimating sys-
tems are generally characterized as less definite and less manage-
able than objectsIn other systems. As a matter of fact, writers who
regard the physicist’s arithmetical metrology aSthe only genuine
METROLOGY AND METASCIENCE 303
type discriminate against estimating activities as measuring alto-
gether.’
The measurer’s Operations occupy a unique place, indeed a focal
position, in the metrological system. The ability to set up a system
depends to a great extent upon his eXpertness. In a genuine sense,
therefore, the operator himself constitutes the metrological instru-
ment. The diagnostician in medical practice, for instance, is a more
or less eflicient instrument qperating like a ruler, galvanometer, or
balance. One is reminded here of the early days of electrical science
when Cavendish used himself as a more or less sensitive galva-l
nometer. Concerning Cavendish’s work, Maxwell wrote:
Cavendish is the first verifier of Ohm’s law, for he finds by succes-
sive series of experiments that the resistance is as the following power
of the velocity, 1.08, 1.03, .980, and concludes that it is as the first
power. All this by the physiological galvanometer.3
Such incidents in the historical development of science suggest a
tolerance toward various as yet unstandardized metrological sys—
tems.
A distinctive type of estimating measurement system is that by
which the mass of the meson (mesotron) is determined. While
cosmic-ray mesons are too energetic to be treated directly by mag-
netic fields, the mass can be indirectly estimated.‘
Becausei‘of the interrelation of the charge, mass, and velocity
values of particles, the cloud-chamber technique furnishes photo—
graphs yielding the following quantities which can be employed in
a measuring system: (I) curvature of the track, (2) range of the
particle, ( 3) ionization per centimeter of path, and (4.) rates of
change of these quantities during the passage of the particle.
The character of the measuring system is illustrated by the fact
that while ionization does not depend greatly upon the mass it
does depend upon the velocity of a particle. To estimate the mass,
then, one must invoke the relationship between mass and velocity.
(7) Evaluating Systems. The measured things comprised
within the present type of system consist of second or higher-order
relations. The measurer’s interest is in the significance of things,
2'Cf. Johnson, Pseudomathematics.
’ Campbell and Garnett, Life, p. 402.
’ Stran‘athan, “Particles,” p. 520.
304. PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
10 Scientific, p. 138.
METROLOGY AND METASCIENCE 307
In order to balance a weight on one pan we can heap sugar plus
sand on the other. From an abstract standpoint the materials placed
on the pan are sufliciently homogeneous. Not SO when a specific
quantity of Sugar is called for. Only extremely abstract situations
can be satisfied by simple equality or inequality.
Abstractionizing measurement results from confusing concrete
measuring operations with generalized descriptions of them. Meas-
uring operations may be legitimately described as work done to ob-
tain numerals, but then the other features of the measuring situa-
tion must not be slurred over. Descriptions constitute verbal analo—
gies to measuring manipulation. However, generalizing and ab—
stracting must not be carried so far as to allow the equating of lin—
ear measurement with the measurement of energy, of strength of
materials, and of other processes leading to coeflicients of expan-
sion, torques, etc.
Thus, when describing measuring situations, it becomes illicit
abstraction to overstress the relational factors, so that arithmetic be-
comes the center and the model. Events are not arithmetic, though
arithmetical operations are events. Conventional descriptions of
measurement carry relations far beyond actual measurement situa-
tions.
The basic point here may be formulated as that oft—repeated
warning not to absorb events in descriptions. When quantum me-
chanical measurements are under consideration the question
whether we are dealing with waves or particles suggests that, un-
like ordinary physical descriptions made with direct reference to
Space and time, it is now expedient to resort to the relatively more
constructional description in terms of probabilities.11
\
" Einstein, Reply, p. 669..
1’
Process, p. 271.
METROLOGY AND METASCIENCE 309
tion as an operation he carries back to sensations. Accordingly, when
he can not assume the presence of sensations he questions the ex-
istence of events. The literature on quantum mechanics testifies to
the difliculties the psychistic view hasIn]ected into the problems of
cause, scientific Obj ectivity, and realityIn physics.
Modern objective psychology allows nowhere for the theory
that observation consumes the thing observed. No matter how in-
direct and remote the act of observation may be from the observed
object, the interbehavior is always the rock upon which all descrip—
tions and interpretations are founded. It may be helpful in illus-
trating this point to indicate a continuum of varying observational
interbehaviors.
In the case of macroscopic physics, the existential independence
of observed objects need never be questioned. But these objects
may be bound up with observation. Objects as perceived are inter-
dependent with the act of perceiving. The perceptive act, however,
does not create the perceived object. The psychologist is also con-
cerned with such independent objects as acts of persons—for ex-
ample, assertions which linguistically produce objects—and with
other no'less' independent objects once they are created, such as
the products of assertions—phlogiston, ether, and caloric. Though
such things exist only as human inventions they often constitute
objects lincultural situations as things talked about or believed in.
What is required is to distinguish (a) things whose existence is in—
dependent of human behavior but which come to be known, (b)
things in knowing relations, and (c) things existing only by human
construction.
Construction. Scientific construction consists basically of descrip-
tions or reports of what occurred during observational contacts with
events. To record or describe an event by constructing a protocol is
to create an index or representation of it. How simple or complex
the construction is depends upon the simplicity or complexity of the
events treated, the ease or difliculty of getting into contact with
things, and the type of interpretation needed. By interpretation is
meant, of course, the interrelation of present events with others Ob-
served at various previous or contemporaneous periods.
It follows that the measurement problems of modern physics de-
mand more complicated construction than the descriptions of classi-
cal meehanics, though the differences are Only difierences of de-
310 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
Cau\sality.
3"
3I2 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
hisvrecoil from the former problems. But even the more modest in-
volvement with indeterminacies maintains a too-close'attachment of
science to historical philosophy. What is determinism? The'proper
answer is suggested by the entire scientific enterprise. The event
with which the scientist begins may consist of closely interbehaving
factors which he measures and modifies in order to reach descrip—
tions and laws.
No inconsiderable portion of a scientist’s activity must be de-
voted to the elimination of wrong views and badly constructed or
unverifiable hypotheses. Many initial problems center in alleged
events . To sum up: In quantum measurements the analogical pro-
cedures based uponIn classical mechanics turnout to be unsuitable.
As we concluded our study of causation, the creative doctrine
must be discarded1n favor of sets of factors5n specific fields. This
View makes useless any question of indeterminism (I 72f.).
contrast between (a) and (b) types of system arises when the
latter consists of word structures which do not correspond to exist-
ing Objects.
I
11Ibid., p. 152.
1’
Lenzen, Nature, p. I.
328 PSYCHOLOGY AND LQGICI
Doubtless the higher the tower the more pristine the good
achieved from union with the universe; also the farther man
transcends the world of which he is a part. He neither profits from
Antaeus or the biblical tower builders, nor does he consider the
lesson implicit in concrete system building.
Tower construction as the unrestricted system building of. abso-
I
1:’° Russell,\Problems,
Ibid., p. ’250.
p. 248.
330 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
J.
Butler, The Analogy of Religion, Natural and Revealed, to the Consti-
:tution and Course of Nature. London, Bell, 1878.
Butterbaugh, G. I. A Bibliography of Statistical Quality Control. Seattle,
Univ. of Washington Press, 1946.
Campbell, L., and Garnett, W. Life of James Clerk Maxwell. London,
Macmillan, 1882.
Campbell, N. R. Physics: The Elements. Cambridge, Cambridge Univ.
Press, 1920.
An Account of the Principles of Measurement and Calculation.
London, Longmans, 1928.
Measurement and its importance for philosophy. Aristotelian So-
ciety, Supplementary vol. XVII, London, Harrison, 1938.
Quantitative estimates of sensory events (Final Report). The
fld‘vtmcement of Science, 1939- 1940, 1, 331-349.
Carmichael, R. C. The Logic of Discovery. Chicago, Open Court, 1930.
Carnap, R. Testability and meaning. Philosophy of Science, 1936, 3, 419-
4713The
1937: 431‘40-
two concepts of probability. Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research. I945. s. 513-532.
‘u‘ Remarks on induction and truth. Philosophy and Phenomenologi-
\cal Research 1945--,1946 5, 590—602.
336 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
Cohen, M. R.
Reasonand Nature. New York, Harcourt, Brace, 1931.
A Preface to Logic. New York, Holt, 1944.
Cohen, M. R.., and Nagel, E. An Introduction to Logic and Scientific
Method. New York, Harcourt, Brace, 1934.
Comrey, A. L. An Operational approach to some problemsIn psychological
measurement. Psychological Review, 1950, 57, 211-228.
Costello, H. T. The naturalism of Woodbridge. In Naturalism and the
Human Spirit '(Y. H. Krikorian ed.) New York, Columbia Univ:
Press, 1944.
Cournot, A. A. Exposition de la Théorie des Chances et des Probabilités.
Paris, Hachctte,1843.
Couturat, L. The principles of logic. In Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical
Sciences, vol. I, Logic, London, Macmillan, 1913. -
Crookshank, F. C. The importance of a theory of signs and a critique of
language in the study of medicine. In The Meaning of Meaning by
C. K. Ogden and I. A. Richards, Supplement II, London, Kegan
Paul, 1923.
Czuber, E. Warscheinlichkeitsrechnung und ihre Anwendung auf
Fehlerausgleichung, Statistik und Lebensversicherung. Vol. I, Leipzig,
Teubner, 1903.
Dadourian, H. M. Force in mechanics. Science, 1939, 87, 388-389.
Dantzig, T. Number: The Language of Science. New York, Macmillan,
I939C°
Darwin,C..G Logic and probability in physics. Philosophy
6
1939. 48- 64
of
Scienicle,
Davis, H. T, and Nelson, W. F. C. Elements of Statistics, with Applica—
tions to Economic Data. Bloomington, Principia Press, 1935.
Dennes, W. T. The categories of naturalism. In Naturalism and the Hu-
man Spirit (Y. H. Krikorian ed.) New York, Columbia Univ. Press,
I94-4- l‘
Descartes, R. See Haldane and Ross. -
Dewey, J. Logic. The Theory of Inquiry. New York, Holt, 1938.
Dewey, J., and Bentley, A. F. Definition. Journal of Philosophy, 1947,
44, 281-306.
BIBLIOGRAPHY 337
Knowing and the Known. Boston, Beacon Press, 1949. ’
Semat,
9H. Fundamentals of Physics. New York, Rinehart, 1945.
(Sheppard, W. F. Probability. In Encyclopaedia Britannica, vol. XXXI,
New York, Encyclopaedia Britannica, Inc., 1926.
Shewhart, W. A. Economic Control of Quality of Manufactured Product.
New York, Van Nostrand, 1931.
Statistical Method from the Standpoint of Quality Control. Wash-
ington, Graduate School, Dept. of Agriculture, 1939.
Sommerfeld, A. Atomic Structure and Spectral Lines. (H. L. Brase trans.)
vol. I, New York, Dutton (3rd ed.,) 1934.
Spaier, A. La Pensée et la Quantité: Essai sur la Signification et la Rea-lité
des Grandeurs. Paris, Alcan, 1928.
Spencer, L. J. Abrasives. In Encyclopaedia Britannica, vol. I, New York,
Encylopaedia Britannica, Inc. (14th ed. ), 1929.
Spinney, L. B. A Textbook of Physics. New York, Macmillan
1925.
(3rd ed. ),
Spinoza, B. Ethics. London, Dent (Everymamed. ), 1910.
Stebbing, L. S. A Modern Introduction to Logic. London, Methuenl(3rd
ed. ), 1942.
Stevens, S. S. A classification of scales ofmeasurement. Paper read before
The International Congress for the Unity of Science, September, 1941.
BIBLIOGRAPHY 34 5
On the theory of scales of measurement. Science, 1946, 103,
677-680.
Stranathan,J. D. The “Particles” of Modern Physics. Philadelphia and
Toronto, Blakiston, 1942.
Strong, E. W. Procedures and Metaphysics: a Study in the PhiIOSOphy
of Mathematical-Physical Sciences in the 16th and 17th Centuries.
Berkeley, Univ. of California Press, 1936.'
a priori knowledge, 150, 159; thing, world, 206, 224, 266, 270, 313; in
150f.; relation, 151-, event, 152, ∂∙ ∙ relation to Ob-
1685.; as universal, 152f. ; specificity servation, 311, 316.
of,15.2f, 159, 167, 171f.; and logical Constructional measurement, 274.
necessity, 154f.~, interrelation of field Constructs, logical instruments as, 94; as
components, 156f., 166; as correlation, causal data, 1615.; and causal law,
1565., I62; and statistics, 156; opera- 173; derived from events, 327.
tional theory in, 158f.; based on Contingency, of logical laws, 182, 186;
atomistic psychology, 1595.; constructs in science, 257; of measurement, 272.
as data for, 1615., 166; events as data Contradiction, law of, 175, 18of., 191,
for, 1635.; investigative operations in, 194, zoof.
165f.; interpretation of, 166f.; erect- Convergence principle, and generaliza-
ing a system Of, 1675.; instrumental tion, 18; in probability theory, 240.
systems of, 171f.; in scientific research,
'Correlation, and causation, 1565., 162.
171f.; paradoxes of, and quantum me- Cosmic systems, 76, 103,322, 3295., 333.
chanics, 172f.; and indeterminism, Counting and‘ measuring, 2965.
1725.; and measurement, 174, 305,
Counting systems, 301f.
311f. . Culture, influences system building, 7, 83,
Cause, vs. condition, 166; and e5ect, 166,
168. 90, 92, 106; in abstracting and gen-
Certainty, as aim of formal systems, 77, eralizing, 8§.; logical instruments re-
82; in probability theory, 207, 222f., flect, 92, 106; and categorization,
242. 112f., 116, 122,~‘129; causation theory
Chance, and probability theory, 204, 216, attached to, 1475., 159, 167, 216;
234.
and logical laws, 1795., 202; pre-
Chemical analysis, as operational system, suppositions of, and quantum me-
84f. . chanics, 317.
Classes, are systems, 58f.; as system ma-
terials; 72f.; as mathematical instru- Data, truth depends on, ”192.
ments, 101; and categories, 114f.; not Deduction, and system building, 86; and
restricted to formal structures, 1 15; as science, 86; vs. induction, .86, 229,
logical forms, 140; in analytical logics, 332; and probability, 205, 206, 211,
144; stressed by conceptualistic lO- 226, 228f., 255, 260.
gicians, 183. Definition, confusion concerning, 28, 35;
Classification, universalism in, 28; and concerned exclusively with words, 29,
Operationism, _29; defining by, 49f.; 37; formalistic and methodistic treat-
and language, 58; as system building, ments of, 29f.; One and Many prob-
58f., 118; criteria for, 59; may pre- lem in, 29; as search for essences,
cede definition, 59; and categorIcal 295.; and sensationistic psychology,
function, 118. 31; nominal, 31f., 41f.; real, 32,45;
Concepts, di5erentiated from things, 94; conceptual, 32f.; and symbolic logic,
as fixated behavior, 97; and categories, 33f.., 53; symbols confused with things
I 14;
as mental states, I 14; as forms of in, 33; syntactical, 33; absolutism‘\in,
interbehavior, 114; and universals, 33f., 46; semantic, 34; from inter-
I3 5.
Conceptualism, Kantian, 8, 114; in defi-
behavioral standpoint, 345. ., 36,
product vs. performance in, 35, 37;
45:.;f
nition, 32f., 36, 42; and universals, wide range of, 35; criteria for 35f.;
I32f., 137; logical laws treated on analysis of factorsIn, 36f.; by Conven-
basis of, 183. tion, 37; ostensive, 37, 41, 56; com-
Conditions, as constructional terms for pared with propositions, 38, 41; lin-
causes, 166. guistic factors in, 385.; relatidnto
Consciousness, threshold of, as psycho-
logical model, 106.
systembuilding, 40; and description,
40f. ; and meaning, 42f. ; and the in-
Consistency, of thinking, 187; as a law definable, 445. ; ambiguity and vague-
∙ of thought, 187, 201.
Construction, and abstraction, 4; in-
ness in, 465.; ‘classes of, 495.; fiat type
of, 52f. ; ∂ in, 535.; '
∙
10f.; mathematical equations derived not concerned with autonomous forms,
from 2; generalization a specific pro- 95; instrument construction in, 100f.;
cedure of, 13f., 22; and definition, categories inevitably involved in,
345.; categories originate out of, is relative, 125, primary categories.I of,
1155.; and universals, 1375.; causal,
158; and probability, 207f., 233f.; and
128; and universals, 131, types'
144; domain of law, 175; integrated of:
measurement, 272, 279; continuum of with events, 175, 200, 228; and .cul-
observational, 309f.; perception as, ture, 1795., 202; and ontology,
317; knowing as, 324. 183, 1885., 202; illicit extrapolation
Interbehavioral theory, and pragmatic in, 1885.; ‘verification in, 191f.; as
realism, 138.. sentential, 195,202; probability, guide
Interpolation, generalizing by, 17; in to, 204; and science, 228f., 3245.;
measurement, 291f. interbehavioral view'of, 319; and phi-
\
INDEX 351.
losophy, 321f., 328f.; and metalogic, Logical multiplexity, vs. logical uni-
322f.; and statistics, 332f. versalization in probability theory,
Logic of science, vs. logic of truth, 225. 2 5 5f.
Logical forms (see Universals), as things, Logical necessity (see Necessity).
136f.; as terms, 136f.; as thought, Logical positivism, 95, 100.
136f.; are interbehavioral products, Logically possible, the, 155.
137, 142; specificity of, 138f.; not Logos doctrine, 181
limited to universals, 139; thing or
event sources of, 1395.; qualities as, Magnification, generalizing by, 16; un-
139; properties as, 139; relations as, controlled, 2 56.
139f.; classes as, 140; behavior as Magnitudes, variety and specificity of,
source of, 140; numbers as, 14of.; 28 If.; “psychic” vs. physical nature of,
product sources of, 141 ; as abstractions 295i
and generalizations, 141; as system Material implication, 24.
components, 142f.; propositions as Material systems, comprise things, 615.;
compounds of, 143; in various logics, events, 71f.; relations, 72; classes, 72f.;
144 .. acts, 73; linguistic things, 73.
Logical instruments (see Instrument con- Mathematical systems, 795.
struction), ch. 16; employed also in Mathematics (see Numbers, Symbolic
science, 91f.; models, schemata, and logic), interbehavioral nature of, If.;
formulae as, 915.; and culture, 92, field operations in, 2, 82; formalism
106; exclude a priori principles, 92; in, 3f., 82, 197; reduced to logic, 3f.;
borrowing of, 93; originality in crea- as system building, 4; mysticism in, 7;
tion of, 93; autistic construction of, analogizing in, 15; as postulation,
93; specificity of, 94f.; interbehavioral 81f., 215f., 235; intuition in, 82; a
view of, 94f.; as orientational tools, domain of relations, 101f.; classes,
9 5; scientific instruments compared to, symbols, and algorithms as instruments
95f.; vs. nonlogical, 95f.; as miniature in, 101f.; instruments of, in physics,
systems, 96f.; as system items, 97; ma- 103; categorization in, 116, 130; evo-
terials of, 97f.; fixated behavior as lution of, 196f.; emancipation of,
source of, 97; for intellectual opera- a5ects logic, 197; and probability, 210,
tions, 985.; the syllogism and universe 2155., 2345., 245f.; measurement as
Of discourse as, 100; the system maker’s applied, 2675.; power of reasoning
techniques in producing, Io6f. by, 269; as science of order, 269; num-
Logical languages, 100. ber as the basis of, 269.
Logical laws, improperly interpreted, Meaning, and definition, 42f.
17 5; based upon observed events, Measurement, abstraction in, 10, 306f.;
175f.‘; as interbehavior, 176f., 186, defining by, 52; and dimensional
200; classical formulations of, 1775.; analysis, 12 3, 294; as creating things
as cultural products, 1795.; and tau- measured, 1 74, 308f. ; and the existence
tology, 179, 184, 195 ; ontological view problem, 174, 266, 270, 3085., 3135.,
of, 179, 183, 1885., 194f.; Aristotle’s 319; and causality, 174, 305, 311f.;
commonsense view of, 1795.; historical and probability, 228, 243, 247f.,
origins of, 1795.; suflicient reason, 3o5f.; place of, in logic, 265; theory
182, 185; current treatment of, cor- vs. practice in, 265f.; is system build-
responds to nominalism, realism, con- ing, 265, 271, 2995., 318; unsatisfac-
ceptualism, 183; and syntacticism, 183; tory constructional trends in, 266f.;
mind and reason as basis for, 184, indeterminacy principle in, 266, 319f.;
186f.; contingency of, 186; as system- as applied mathematics, 2675.; and
building enterprises, 186, 1995.; in numbers, 2685.; 297, 306; specifiicity
reasoning and thinking, 1865:; con- of, ~2715., 281; and calculation, 271,
nected with data, 1905.; related to 291f., 302; from interbehavioral
knowledge problems by epistemologists, standpoint, 272, 297, 314f.; requires
‘_1905.; role of language in, 1945.; specific objects, operations, and situa-
iden‘tified with mathematical laws, tions, 2725.; practical level of, 275f.;
1965.; are constructions, 200f.; use of, in science, 276f., ch. 24; technological
not\\ limited to logic, 200; and sys- level of, 276f.; formal level of, 277f.;
temOlogical behavior, 202f. quality and quantity in, 2785.; spec-
352 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
ificity of magnitudes in, 281f., 295f.; treatment Of, 16of.; continuity in,
systems of, 2825., 3005.; metaphysical 189i
or mathematical systems no criteria for, Natural science, place of language in, 48.
282; postulates of, 283f.; units of, Necessity, logical, and factual cause,
284, 2935.; instruments and operations 1545.; in logical laws, 1835., 202;
of, 285f.; construction of scales in, its metaphysical ‘use' in probability
2855.; philosophical bias in scale mak- theory, 222f.
ing, 288f.; and psychological scales, Negative categorization, 121.
288; interpolation and extrapolation Nominal scale, in measurement, 286f.
in, 291f.; statistical operations in, Nominalism, and definition, 31f., 36,
292f., 305; counting, 2965.; and 41f., 43; and universals, 132, 135,
modern science, 2995.; in microscopic 136; and logical laws, 183‘; in prob-
physics, 3005., 305, 320; evolution of ability theory, 257, 259.
systems of, 3005.; and quantum me- _Non sequitur, fallacy of, 25, 324.
chanics, 300, 305, 307f., 3105., 3175.; Nonnumerical frequency, and probability
Operator as instrument of, 303; Opera- theory, 2 52f
tions in, confused with descriptions, Normative principles, in logic and
307; construction and observation in, science, 175f.
3075.; brings mysticism into science, Numbers (see Mathematics), are con-
311f. ; objectivity in, 312f.°, and real- structions, 2, 8f.; 25, 26; abstraction
ity, 3135., theory of (metrology), in- Of, 8f.., 10, 65, 26, 306; as explanatory
tegrated with systemology (science of system tools, 99; as logical forms,
logic), 3185. 14of.; in measurement, 174, 2685.,
Mechanics, changing categories in, 119, 283, 286, 2965., 306; used to illus-
12 5. trate principle of verifiability, 193; as
Mentalism (see Dualism), 104f. supreme universals, 269f.; and objec-
Metalogic, the logical theorist’s philosoj tive reality, 270; glorification of, 270;
phy, 321f.; related to logical practice, and mental states, 270; nature of,
322f.- 295f.; interdependent with things, 306.
Metalogical
systems, 76.
Metaphysics (see Existence problem), 10; Objective necessity, vs. logical_'necessity,
and the category problem, 112; vs. 15°) 154-
science, 1 73; linguistic or nee-nominal- Objective psychology, speculative systems
istic, 259. handled by, 99.
Method systems, 75f. Objectivity, in treatment of natural
Methodistic logic, 144, 146f., 324. events, 16of.; and reality, 308; and
Methodology of science, 145, 172, 182, measurement, 312f.
260, 267. Objects, of thought, vs. logical laws,
I 88; as perceived, vs. act of perceiving,
Metrology (see Measurement), and logic,
3185. 309.
Microscopic events, and the determinism- Observation, in causal situations, 165,
indeterminism issue, 173f.; require 174; as interbehavior, 308f.; relation
to construction, 316.
. uniquely descriptive languages, 319f.
Ontology (see Existence problem), in
Mind, sensations as atoms of, 12; as locus
of essences, 32; as a cognitive power, categorization, 129; and universals,
113; as category source, 113; and the
134f., 141; in dialectical logics, 144;
universals problem, 136; theories of, andlcause, 145f., 147, 1505.; and
logical laws, 183, 1885.; confused
influence causation doctrine, 159f.;
changing ideas of, 184; as a unifying connection of, with logic, 202‘; and
probability, 207, 2565.
construct, 258. Operational principles, vs. a priori
Models (see Logical instruments).
Multiplicative abstraction, 12f. norms, 175. .
Operational systems, 845.
Mysticism, in logic, 3; in mathematics, Operationism, and definition, 29, 53f.,
7; and causation, 148; in science, 311. 5 5, 57; and-classification, 29; in sys-
tem building, 845.; in causal theory,
Naming, definition by, 49, 53. I58f., 215f.; ini'mathematics, 197f.;
Natural events, objective vs: rationalistic in truth-frequency theory, 250.
INDEX 353
Opposition, square of, as system product, tions, 2095., 2195., 2465., 2585.;
77f- Laplacian theory of, 21 15., 2345., 256,
Ordering systems, 302. 261; and plausibility, 212; many cri-
Organismic, instrument for social and po- teria for, 215; statistics in, 215, 221,
litical descriptiOn, 106. 227f., 236, 2405., 2605.; still bound
Ordinal scale, of measurement, 286f. by tradition, 216; origin of, in games
Ostensive definition, 56f. of chance, 2 16f., 234; response-centered
systems of, 217f.; event-centered sys-
Participation, doctrine of, and universals, tems of, 218f.; truth-frequency theory
134f. of, 220, 2485.; and necessity, 222f.;
Particulars, vs. universals, 132, 1335. and possibility, 224f.; potentiality and
Perception, subjected to abstracting and actuality in, 225; science inevitably
generalizing procedures, 9f.; causal occupied with, 2255.; and prediction,
theory of, 18; a priori basis of, 130; 23of.; interbehavioral design for analy-
as a creational process, 316f., consti- sis Of, 2325.; typical formulations of,
tutes interbehavior, 3 1 7. 2345.; as readiness to act, 24o; con-
Petitio principii, fallacy of, 324. vergence principle in, 240; as empirical
PhilosoPhy, definitional problems'In, 48; frequency, 2415., 244; as statistical fre-
‘categories of, 129; presuppositions of, quency, 2435.; as mathematical fre-
and probability theory, 206f., 257, quency, 245f.; as propositional rela-
259; specifications for an Objective tions, 2465.; intuition in, 247f., 258;
type of, 256; and logic, 321f., 328f.; and nonnumerical frequency, 2 52f.; as
presuppositions of, and system building, factorial coordination, 2535.; and log-
322, 332; abnegation motive in, 33of. ical multiplexity, 255f.; ontological
Physics, continuity of abstracted units in, problem in, 25 65.; as “rational recon-
12; instrument construction in, 102f.; struction” of scientific procedures, 260;
introduction of probability into, 227; systems for measuring, 3o4f.
metaphysics in, 314f. Probability calculus, 207, 210, 246, 2615.
Plausibility, and probability, 212. Propositions, and definitions, 33, 38, 41;
Polytomy, and dichotomy, 194. as constructional products, 143; and
Possibility, and probability, 224f. ’ deductive mathematics, 147; truth Of,
Postulation, defining by, 50; place of 191f., 198f.;,and probability, 2095.,
Constructor in, 805.; mathematics as, 2195., 2465.
81f.‘ Psychology, instrument construction in,
Potentiality, and probability, 225. 104f.; scale making in, 288.
Prediction (see Determinism), and the “Psychic magnitudes,” vs. physical mag—
problem of deduction, 86; and prob- nitudes, 288.
ability, 23of.
Prescription, definition by, 52f. Quality, as logical form, 139; measure-
Probability, unique place of, in logic, ment of, 2785.
204; involves system'building, 204f.; Quantity, measurement of, 2785., 281;
paradox of, 204; many situational as property of things, 28o; confusion
types of, 205; absolutism in theory of, concerning its referent, 295f.
206f.; calculation in, 2065., 210, 220, Quantum mechanics, 8, 12, 645., 96; and
245f., 2615.; phiIOSOphical presupposi- causation, 172, 305; and statistical
tions and problems in, 206f., 256f.; frequency, 243; and measurement, 274,
and certainty, 207f., 222f., 242, 244, 3075., 313f.; avoidance of metaphysi-
246; as equipossible ratio, 207, 217, cal questions in, theory of, 326.
2 345.; applies to all complex situations,
207f.; truth as a form of, 208, 223f.; Ratio scales, 2885.
as quantity of knowledge, 208, 2375.; Rationality, in causal theory, I59f., 172;
,of single events, 208, 210f., 242f., in probability theory, 220f., 2 34f.,
251f.,263; specificity of, 208f., 2125, 246_f. ‘
23.5, 255,263; as degree of belief, 208, Realism, 32, 1-32, 135f., 202.
209, 212, 218, 223f., 2385.; froni
interbehavioral standpoint, 208; fre-
Reality, sought in numbers, 270; and ob-
jectivity, 308; problem of, in quantum
∏ theory of, 209, 210, 213f,, mechanics, 3135.
218f., 221, 235, 2415.; and proposi- Reasoning, principles for regulating,
354- PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC
problems, 171 ; vs. mensurational prac- System builder, role of, in systemization,
tice, 2995. 6o, 81, 106.
Scientific method, 145, 172, 182, 260, System building, cultural basis of, 7,' 83,
267. 87, 90, 92, 106; as interbehavior, 59,
Scientist, the, seeks absolute knowledge, 60. 73. 93. 97. 106. Io7. 114,1field
225f.; as a measuring instrument, 303. hypothesis in, 60; vs. system product,
Semantic definition, 34. 6o,\8\7, 325f.; interrelation of Opera-
Sensations, events reduced to, 8; are ab- tions and materials in, 86f.; continuity
stractions, 12f.; in causal theory, 16of., of, 99f.; categories are instruments of,
164; are constructs, 311. 108f., 115f;;\theory of, and metrologi—
'Sentences (see Propositions), substituted cal science, 318f.-, specificity of, 32 5;
for cause, 154, 162; verifiability of, unrestricted, 99,‘ 330.
1905., material for system building, System products, vs. system building, 60,
196; 198f.; identified \with events, 81, 87, 32 5f ; investigative schema for,
INDEX 355
6of.; types and characteristics of, 615., Universality in science, 1 89f.
885. Universals (see Logical forms), as formal
Systemology, integrated with metrology, elements, 94; similar to categories,
2995. 114f.; in interbehavioral logic, 131,
1375.; ambiguity of, in conventional
Tautology, in logical laws, 179, 184, logic, 131; products of system build-
188; in sentence systems, 190, 192; ing, 131; historical _ treatment of,
formal logic concerned with, 195.
Terms (see Language, Symbols), uni-
1315.; vs. particulars, 132, 1335.;
abstracting and generalizing products,
as
versals, as, 136f. 132, 138; current treatment of, 1335.;
Thermodynamics, categories in, 125f. spatiotemporality, as criterion of,
Things, confused with symbols, 39; as I33f.; character value of, 134; as
system materials, 61; universals as, words or terms, 135f.; and concepts,
136f.; as sources of logical forms, 135f.; involved with language, 136;
1395.; causes as, 15of.; existence of, as things, terms, or thoughts, 136f.;
vs. knowing, 173f., 324; not created interbehavioral vs. mentalistic-psycho-
by measurement, 174, 308f.; Aristotle’s logical description of, 137f.; are par-
objective organization of, 180; lan- ticulars, 138f.; numbers, as supreme,
guage substitutes for, 194; specificity 269£
of measured, 272f. Universe, the, an illicit construction, 24.
Thinking, as a generalized power, 1865.; Universe of discourse, as logical instru-
consistency of, 187; as interbehavior, ment, 100.
zoo.
Thoughts, logical forms as, 136f.; laws Vagueness, and definition, 465.
of, ch. 20. Value, category of, 124f.
Truth, as a form of probability, 208; vs. Verbal assertion, vs. operational achieve-
existence, 223. ment, 189.
Truth—function (matrix) systems, 78f. Verbal symbols, vs. actual things, 181.
Truth value, of sentences, 1915., 198f.; Verbalism (see Language, Symbols,
interpretation of, 198; determined on Terms), in definition, 3 1 f.
basis of specific conditions, 199. Verification (see Truth), vs. verifiability,
192f.; and truth, 198.
Universalism, in logic (system building), Vitalism, 311f.
175,378, 179, 181f., 1835., 187, 192,
I99. 255f-
NAME INDEX
Adams, 62, 310n. Carnap, 211, 260.
Aiken, 112n. Carnot, 92', 126.
Ampere, 277. Carus, 1 5211.
Ancillon, 259. Cassirer, 112n.
Angstrom, 63. Cavalieri, 12o.
Aristotle, 14, 30, 57n., Ing., 132, 148, Cavendish, 303.
'
1795.,
193. _ Child, 114n.
Avey, 184n. Church, 37n., 198.
Churchman, ‘26on., 28In.
Bain, 176n. Clausius, 189.
Ballard,‘318n., 319n. Cohen; 25n., 46n., Son” 86nq 138)
Balmer, 625., 655. 145n., 176n., 178n., 134D” 188n4
Bartlett, 288m. 229D” 321B.
Bayes, 217. Compton, 689
Beck, 164n. Comrey, 281n.
Becker, 198. Condorcet, 217. a
Becquerel, 43. Costello, 47.
Bell, 1a., 3a., 8In., 93n., 197n. Coulomb, 64.
Benjamin, 279n., 280n. Cournot, 218, 241.
Bentley, 28n., 42n., 53, 310n. Couturat, 3711.
Berenda, 315n. Crookshank, 124n.
Bergmann, 260a. Czuber, 2 59. ∙
Berkeley, 174, 316.
Bernoulli, Jacob, 217, 236, 237. Dadourian, I In.
Bernoulli, Johann, 217, 237. Daggett, 84n.
Bertrand, 204. D’Alembert, 217, 260, 291.
Birkho5, 22n., 304n. Dantzig, 93n.
Black, 198n. Darwin, 225a.
Bode, 61f. Davis, 49B.
Bogoslovsky, 178n. De Finetti, 240.
Bohr, 15, 645., 305n., 307, 311, 315n. De Méré, 234.
Boltzmann, 316. De Moivre, 217.
Boole, 178n., 182, 187, 259. De Morgan, 219, 238.
Born, 93n. Dennes, 112n.
Bosanquet, 144. Descartes, 7 5f., 1 I 7.
Brackett, 65. Dewey, 28n., 42n., 53; 56n., 94, 1.141,
Bradley, 24, 144.
Brahe, 226.
143n., 146n., 147, 184n., 193.
Diels, 148n. ∙
'
Braun, 326. Dingle, 8n., 24n., 96. l
Kemble, 211f.
Gauss 53. 277. 293. 294.
Kepler, 217, 226, 234.
George, 165n., 29on.
_Gibbs, 189. Keynes, J. M., 22013., 236f., 243n.,
Ginsburg, 18n. 2465., 258, 259.
Goethe, 135, 258. Keynes, J. N., 176n., 185.
Goldenweiser, 118. Klein, 101.
Gotshalk, 152n. Kneale, 146n., 23on.
Grassmann, 120, 197. von Kries, 236.
Greenwood, 206n.
Grimsehl, 52n., 276n., 314n., 326n. Lagrange, 217.
Lamont, 33m.
Haas, 66.‘ Langley, 277.
Haldane, 75n. Laplace, 172, 2165., 235, 237.
Hamilton, 185, 197. Larmor, 123.
Harding, 124n. Layzer, 310n., 313n., 314n.
Hardy, 21, 269. Le Chatelier, 326.
von Hartmann, 11on., IIIf. Leeuwenhoeck, 308.
Hawkins, 211. Leibniz, 182, 195, 217, 237, 246.
Heath, 6, 56. Lenzen, 8n., 174n., 296, 313n., 32711.
Hedrick, 179n., 198n. Leucippus 147.
Hegel, 76, 111, 144, 178. Leverrier, 62.
Heisenberg, 227, 299. Lévy-Bruhl, 113.
Helmholtz, 267, 295, 296. Lewis, 58n., 192m, 193n., 199.
Hempel, 98n., 156n., 26on. Lillie, 104n.
Herodotus, 298. Lindsay, 116n.
Herschel 61, 238, 277, 308. Linnaeus, 104.
Hilbert, 81. Locke, 31, 224.
Hobbes, 151. Loeb, 310n.
Ho5man, 10m. Lotka, 24n.
Hofstadter, I54, 155n. Lotze, 41.
Hopkins, 165. 'Lyman, .645.
Horst; -290n.
Houston 8n. ‘McGill, .91‘.
Hume, 8, 19, 15of., 153, 156, 159f., McGilvary, 134, 138.
I73. 224. 23I. 316. 33I- McGregor, 288n.
Huygens 117, 217, 237. Mach, 4f., 6, 8, 12, 316.
358 PSYCHOLOGY AND LOGIC