Hancock Matthews 2001
Hancock Matthews 2001
Community Safety
Major changes are taking place in the crime control industry and by association
in the discipline of criminology itself. These changes, which involve the adop-
tion of local partnership approaches, new forms of managerialism as well as the
blurring of distinctions between crime, disorder and community safety, have
been described as constituting a watershed for criminology. Bringing together
nine original articles from leading national and international authorities on
these issues, this book is both a product of and a reflection on the changing
state of play. The articles address, from a range of different perspectives, the
changing nature of regulation in contemporary society and the simultaneous
reconstruction of the communities which are being regulated. Crime, Disorder
and Community Safety also offers a timely commentary on government attempts
to address questions of inequality and social exclusion as well as issues relating
to ethnic minorities and young people.
Index 241
Illustrations
Tables
1.1 The binaries of social exclusion 43
8.1 Household and area risk factors for household property crime 202
8.2 Indices of individual and area deprivation and affluence 206
8.3 Property crime victimisation, deprivation and affluence 207
8.4 Correlation between property crime victimisation,
(a) household deprivation (b) household affluence, within
levels of areas deprivation 208
8.5 Risk factors for household property crime victimisation
by level of area deprivation 209
9.1 Risks of domestic burglary by household type 232
9.2 OCU rate variability by offence types 236
Figures
6.1 Arrests and searches: London 1997–1999 150
6.2 Searches, population and suspects: London 1998–1999 152
6.3 Recorded racial incidents in England and Wales, 1991–1999 157
6.4 Trends in types of racial incidents recorded by the
MPS, 1997–2000 158
6.5 Victims and suspects of racist incidents by ethnic group, 159
MPS 1997–2000
7.1 The Crime and Disorder Act (1998) 170
8.1 Inequality and property crime 203
8.2 Property crime rates and poverty concentration 210
9.1 Property crime by area crime levels 229
9.2 Property crime by area victim prevalence 230
9.3 Property crime by area victim concentration 231
9.4 Inequality at force and OCU level 233
Contributors
This book developed out of a series of seminars and workshops which took place
in London and Luton in 1998. The seminar series was funded by the ESRC
through their Research Seminar Series. We would therefore like to thank the
ESRC for their support. We would also like to thank all those who took part in
the seminar programme. The participants included Afshan Ahmet, Rob Allen,
David Barrett, Jon Bright, Charlie Burr, Adam Crawford, Helen Edwards, Robin
Fletcher, Roger Grimshaw, Lynn Hancock, Simon Harding, Tim Hope, Mike
Hough, Michael Hutchinson-Rees, George Kelling, Alan Marlow, Kate Painter,
Ken Pease, David Porteous, Nick Tilley, Norman Warner and Paul Wiles. We
would also like to thank Julie Grogan for her assistance in organising the
various meetings and the staff of Middlesex University who provided the neces-
sary administrative support.
Roger Matthews and John Pitts
October 2000
Introduction
Beyond criminology?
Roger Matthews and John Pitts
Introduction
It used to be fashionable to claim that criminology was in crisis (Bottoms and
Preston 1980; Young 1986). This diagnosis reflected a general mood of uncer-
tainty and called for a reconsideration of the appropriate focus of criminological
investigation. The mood, however, has changed over the past few years and a
growing number of books and articles have appeared which suggest that crimi-
nology is currently in the process of fragmentation and dissolution (Ericson and
Carriere 1994). These recent developments have been attributed to changes in
the nature of social relations and to associated changes in the organisation of
social control (Garland 1996; Lea 1998). No longer, it is argued, is the state
purely concerned with individual acts of deviance. Increasingly, the focus is on
security and the control of aggregate populations differentiated according to
assessments of risk and dangerousness. The emergence of the so-called ‘risk
society’ has brought in its wake new modes of inclusion and exclusion (Sibley
1995; Young 1999). Some critics propose that these changes have in turn
eroded the conventional boundaries between social science disciplines as the
objects of investigation begin to overlap and as narrow and parochial interests
become less relevant.
Paradoxically, while some academics are beginning to mourn the demise of
criminology as a discipline, the size of the crime control industry and the
number of students studying criminology in many countries around the world is
rapidly growing (Braithwaite 2000). In England and Wales the official annual
cost of crime control currently stands at £8.2 billion, and this is projected to
increase to £10.6 billion by 2003–4. These costs do not, of course, include the
millions of pounds spent every year by private individuals and commercial
organisations. Recent reports from the US indicate that in some states expendi-
ture on crime control has exceeded that on education, while the amount spent
by federal, state and local governments in 1996 was a staggering $120 billion for
civil and criminal justice. This represented a 70 per cent increase over the
previous year (Currie 1998; Bureau of Justice 2000).
The growing number of people studying criminology is on the one hand a
function of the massive increase in media time dedicated to crime and
2 Roger Matthews and John Pitts
duced new concerns, a wider range of issues and perspectives and generally
enriched the subject area. At their worst they were irrelevant and indulgent.
Much of the debate centred around the ‘real’ meaning of crime and the
construction of a ‘proper’ criminology. While these critical, radical, feminist and
realist criminologies attempted to change the focus of criminology, they
succeeded in reshaping and to some extent re-ligitimating, the subject. More
recent contributions, however, have been concerned less with the reorientation
of the subject and more with its demise. This change of perspective has been
stimulated by widespread socio-economic developments and changing forms of
governance which have been associated with globalisation and the transition
from modernity to late modernity – or as some would have it, postmodernity
(Bauman 1995; Harvey 1989). These changes, in turn, involve a unique histor-
ical mutation in which the distinctions between crime and disorder are
becoming increasingly blurred and both are becoming incorporated within the
wider framework of community safety. In this process it is becoming increasingly
difficult to treat crime as a discreet object of study and to sustain criminology as
a distinct academic discipline.
during the 1980s to address the issue of crime, and a number of agencies have
become increasingly involved in the prevention and reduction of different
forms of crime. The logic of these developments was endorsed and extended by
the Morgan Report (1991), whose recommendation that the responsibility for
crime prevention and community safety should be devolved to local authorities
was implemented by an incoming Labour government. The subsequent passing
of the Crime and Disorder Act (1998) consciously linked crime control with
disorder and saw both as part of a more comprehensive community safety
strategy (Hughes 1998).
The shift from crime prevention to community safety has extended the terms
of reference and made everything from crime and incivilities to environmental
issues part of a more comprehensive agenda (Muncie 2000). The fact that
community safety is as elusive and loosely defined a term as crime only serves to
extend the open-endedness of this new agenda. Crime has increasingly become
fused with disorder and both have become enveloped within the more general
notion of community safety, despite the fact that the focus of the three terms,
the nature of the events involved, the established forms of intervention
employed and the characteristics of the victims is remarkably different. It is not
so much that crime has become normalised but rather it has become absorbed
within a more complex set of overarching relations. This widening of the frame
of reference has been reflected in the language and concepts which have been
used by policy-makers to address these issues. Such terms as ‘dangerousness’,
‘anti-social behaviour’, ‘security’ and ‘social exclusion’ are necessarily ill-defined
(Brown and Pratt 2000). The wide-ranging terminology represents a shift away
from the style of language that has been used in relation to the ‘war against
crime’, which talks of ‘targets’ and ‘campaigns’. From this ‘get tough’ crime
control perspective, the claim is that there are a relatively small number of
offenders, victims, groups, neighbourhoods (‘hot spots’) who are ‘responsible’ for
a disproportionate amount of crime and victimisation. However, as the issue of
crime becomes further integrated into the wider matrix of community safety the
focus necessarily shifts to aggregate problem populations – the underclass, the
marginalised and the socially excluded. Consequently, a hybrid discourse is
emerging which at one moment identifies the problem as a limited number of
deviant individuals, while at another regards whole sections of the population
as a problem. Whereas the war against crime is seen as something which can be
‘won’ and criminals reformed or deterred, the terms ‘underclass’ and the ‘socially
excluded’ come close to suggesting a permanent condition which has to be
managed rather than eliminated (Feeley and Simon 1994). Policy-makers and
practitioners espouse military metaphors and then in the same breath refer to
social support and individual needs. This new hybrid discourse is appearing in
various local authority-generated policy documents and in the newly established
sites such as local authority community safety forums. The multi-agency forums
are well situated to cultivate this ambiguous discourse since they typically incor-
porate the coercive powers of the police alongside the more welfare-oriented
approaches of social services and education departments. The formalisation of
Introduction: beyond criminology 5
these multi-agency interventions has created new alliances and new lines of
responsibility. Importantly, the role of the key regulatory agencies is changing
significantly in this process. The police in particular have been ‘let off the hook’
and can now legitimately claim that neither crime control nor community
safety is their sole responsibility (Kinsey et al. 1986). At the same time, they are
required to participate in a wider range of interventions which shifts the
balance of their work away from crime control and towards public order and
social work functions.
It has in fact been evident for some time that crime is related to almost every
other negative indicator in society – poor health, limited educational facilities,
unreliable transport, bad housing and the more serious environmental problems.
Indeed, these negative indicators predictably overlap to the extent that high
crime areas also rank high on every other scale of social and economic misfor-
tune. Thus, multiple victimisation (the tendency for the same individual or
household to be a victim of a range of hazards) is becoming a more appropriate
point of reference than the more linear concept of repeat victimisation, which
has shown that individuals and victims are subject to serial forms of victimisa-
tion (Genn 1988; Farrell and Pease 1993; Sparks et al. 1977). Multiple
victimisation is the logical counterpart of multi-agency intervention, since one
of the original justifications for developing a multi-agency approach was the
recognition that a range of different agencies often intervene independently in
the lives of certain individuals in response to the various manifestations of the
same underlying problem.
The implications of this broader focus on the inter-related and the socially
and geographically concentrated nature of social problems is threefold. The first
is that crime may begin to lose its privileged position among other social prob-
lems. It may be the main problem in certain areas and for certain individuals,
but in the majority of places it will only constitute one component of an inte-
grated matrix of hazards. Second, it calls for a more comprehensive mode of
theorising and a consequent shift away from the preoccupation with piecemeal
and situational measures to forms of explanation which are more comprehen-
sive and can account for the concentration and compounding of different types
of victimisation. Social support theory provides one way of addressing these
issues. Its basic proposition is that the best predictor of the areas and households
with high levels of multiple victimisation are not those with low levels of social
control, as conservative criminologists have argued, but rather those with low
levels of social support (Cullen 1994). The difficulty, however, in a post-welfare
era is that the traditional networks of state and social support are themselves in
the process of dissolution and transformation. Consequently, introducing appro-
priate systems of support requires the development of new, innovative,
interventionist strategies. The third implication is that because multiple victim-
isation moves beyond a preoccupation with specific crimes, it then raises the
wider issue of social justice. The culmination of these processes may possibly
result in the radical reorientation of criminology, both as a framework of inter-
vention and of investigation. It will, however, almost certainly foster forms of
6 Roger Matthews and John Pitts
The state of affairs described here arises largely where government has
vacated territory which it once organised, resourced, nurtured and presided
over with political authority – even if contested authority – but for which it
nevertheless will not or cannot abandon all responsibility. Where once it
willed the means, now it tends to prescribe the ends while others are left to
supply the means; and as with all instrumentally-oriented practices, the
logic governing the attainment of ends is the logic of rules. In short, where
government was, now audit regulation and management is. And so,
inevitably, this social ego is pervaded by obsessional anxieties and
behaviours about the loss of control.
(Cooper and Lousada 2000: xx)
Thus, the Crime and Disorder Act (1998), in handing new responsibilities over
to local authorities and local multi-agency partnerships, prescribes the goals
they should pursue, the targets they should achieve and the time scales in which
they should operate, but not the means for their achievement. However, as
Cooper and Lousada (2000) suggest, the anxieties about the political legitimacy
and electoral credibility engendered by this new form of ‘hands-off’ governance
leads to an unprecedented concern with the management of implementation,
which is specified in such detail that what at first sight appears to be an exercise
in devolution upon closer inspection looks to be a franchising operation.
‘Product support’ is provided via a steady flow of ‘evidence-based’ data about
‘what works’ and ‘pilot studies’ of new administrative arrangements and modes
8 Roger Matthews and John Pitts
certain logic and coherence on its own, but when ‘joined-up’ they produce
unanticipated tensions.
Take the very notion of decentralisation itself. This derives from a master
metaphor which sees political power in terms of centre and periphery. We
are asked to imagine such things as deviants being drawn away from the
centre, or the periphery being awarded the power that belonged to the
centre. But this metaphor rests on a largely unexamined view of state
power, which at times leans towards the most extreme forms of elitist
centralism, at other times towards the most amorphous forms of pluralism.
(Cohen 1987: 377)
In relation to implementation there was also a naïveté about the role and
interests of these newly formed or reconstructed agencies. It became apparent
that the agencies had their own specific interests, not least of which was their
own preservation and expansion. Less clear was the increasingly intricate
network of policy formation and implementation, the financial links and pecu-
niary constraints which were imposed, the hierarchical relations which
developed, and the growing pressure for these apparently autonomous and inde-
pendent bodies to pursue the same goals and adopt the same management
practices which had been previously developed in the existing state agencies.
Alongside such uncertainties was a lack of clarity about the ways in which
newly state-sponsored agencies were being established to monitor, assess, guide
and regulate the ‘independent’ agencies, such that the apparent cost savings
which were claimed were in some cases more than swallowed up by the costs of
monitoring and supervision.
The criticisms of the decentralisation strategy which surfaced in the mid-
1980s, however, did little to slow down this process, although they may have
influenced its direction. Privatisation in its various forms continued to be
promoted, particularly in relation to policing, crime prevention, the use of secu-
rity equipment and the contracting out of prison management (Johnston 2000;
Matthews 1989). The rapid development of multi-agency partnerships encour-
aged the involvement of the private sector alongside voluntary and statutory
agencies.
In the UK in the 1990s the decentralising impulse took a slightly different
turn following the implementation of the recommendation of the Morgan
Report (1991) to devolve responsibility for crime control and community safety
to local authorities. Emphasis was placed upon multi-agency partnerships and
the establishment of community safety strategy groups which were to be
responsible for assessing the nature of crime in each locality, developing a
community safety strategy and monitoring interventions. During the 1980s, the
Introduction: beyond criminology 11
Disorder
Since the 1980s there has been a growing concern in official circles, as well as
in local communities, with the issue of disorder. This concern, however, has not
entirely been stimulated by an increase in disorder in all its forms on our city
streets. Certainly there has been an increase in the visibility of certain types of
disorder, such as graffiti, vagrants and homeless people on the streets, aggressive
begging, and more recently ‘squeegee merchants’, while a number of urban
centres in Britain have become sites of disorder at the weekends involving
predominantly young people (while other centres, in contrast, have become
desolate and neglected). In many urban centres, however, the number of public
demonstrations and riots and the level of public drunkenness has remained
fairly stable, and in comparison to twenty or thirty years ago is more contained.
Thus in explaining the growing concern with disorder we cannot identify a
simple causal sequence which sees these responses, both by the general public
and by official bodies, as a direct result of a general increase in disorder itself.
The explanation instead must lie in the ways in which these incidents are
perceived and the changing levels of toleration which is expressed by different
groups in different localities. As Lynn Hancock and Roger Matthews argue in
Chapter 4, the term toleration is a critical but largely unexplored concept in
understanding changing public attitudes towards crime, disorder and commu-
Introduction: beyond criminology 13
nity safety, since the level and nature of public tolerance will condition which
activities members of the community are willing to put up with and those
which they are not.
The changing conceptions and responses to street prostitution in the UK
since the 1950s provides an example of how public tolerance and social sensibili-
ties have changed. Although the visibility of street prostitution decreased in
most urban centres following the implementation of the recommendations of the
Wolfenden Report (1957), a number of residents groups across the country
campaigned vigorously for the removal of prostitution from their neighbour-
hoods. This resulted in street patrols by residents, and in some localities vigilante
squads were established. The groups involved a diverse mix of local residents and
included individuals drawn from different religious and ethnic backgrounds.
Their justification for establishing citizen patrols was that the police and local
authorities were not interested in dealing with the problem. This was predomi-
nantly a ‘bottom-up’ community-based movement involving a number of
like-minded but independent groups in a number of different urban locations.
The sociological question which arises is why these groups of residents, often
living in poor transient communities – which the literature suggests should have
low levels of informal control – mobilised so effectively around this issue in an
attempt, as they saw it, to win back ‘their’ streets and neighbourhoods (Matthews
1993). Previous generations had put up with the noise and disturbance associated
with street prostitution for years, but clearly a shift occurred in terms of public
tolerance and this appeared to be bound up with changing conceptions of defen-
sible space and changing expectations about privacy, security and risk. No small
factor in this equation was the role of women living in ‘red light’ districts who
felt they were living under a curfew and that they and their children should have
the right to walk freely in public spaces without fear of harassment or intimida-
tion. The mobilisation of local residents around this issue served to increase
confidence and was a source of empowerment for many local residents groups.
Dealing with disorder, as Zygmunt Bauman (1995) has observed, can have a
cleansing and cathartic effect: it represents a form of social purification.
Because of the continuous and quasi-legal nature of prostitution, the police
were ill-equipped to deal with the issue, and although a series of ‘vice squads’
were established in the 1970s, their methods relied mainly on the mobilisation
of the criminal law which appeared increasingly heavy-handed, inequitable and
inappropriate, particularly since many of the residents came to regard female
prostitutes as victims rather than offenders (Benson and Matthews 2000). In
many instances, residents were opposed to prostitution not prostitutes.
Therefore, they looked for different, non-legal and more appropriate ways of
addressing the problem which involved a combination of social and situational
measures. In some ways the growing concern with disorder reflected both the
increasing aspirations of citizens and the mobilisation of social movements
which were interested in defending, and where possible, improving urban life.
Increasingly, disorder in its various forms provides a bridge between crime on
the one hand, and community safety on the other. Just as it is the case that
14 Roger Matthews and John Pitts
certain forms of disorder involve illegalities (such as ‘soliciting for the purposes
of prostitution’), they also involve ‘quality of life’ issues which readily fuse with
growing concerns about environmentalism, health, transport and community
safety in general.
As George Kelling (1987) has pointed out, whereas crimes are mainly events
or acts which occur in a specific time and place, disorder constitutes a condition.
It represents not so much a direct confrontation between an individual victim
and offender, but an ongoing process which affects whole neighbourhoods. The
articulation of these concerns was presented in George Kelling and James Q.
Wilson’s article, ‘Broken Windows: The Police and Neighbourhood Safety’,
published in Atlantic Monthly in 1982. The article hit a nerve, or rather a series
of nerves, and its extensive international influence and the debate which it
generated is testimony to its significance both as an attempt to explain the link
between crime disorder and community safety and to provide a practical guide
for intervention. The immediate appeal of the article was that it offered a way
out which was both plausible and potentially cost-effective. The authors
claimed that there was a clear link between low level disorder, crime and neigh-
bourhood decline. They argued that the visible evidence of graffiti and public
drunkenness indicates that an area is a vulnerable target for criminal activities.
This prompts more mobile and respectable families to move away, with the
consequence that the existing system of informal controls breaks down, crime
and incivilities proliferate and eventually the neighbourhood slips into decline.
Thus Wilson and Kelling argue that:
at the community level disorder and crime are usually inextricably linked
in a kind of developmental sequence. Social psychologists and police offi-
cers tend to agree that if a window in a building is broken and if it is left
unrepaired, all the rest of the windows will soon be broken. This is as true
in nice neighbourhoods as in run-down ones.
(Wilson and Kelling 1982: 78)
The novelty and the attractiveness of this thesis lies in its emphasis on the
added value of intervening at the most immediate and accessible level. In oppo-
sition to those forms of crime control which concentrated on serious crime,
Wilson and Kelling offered a strategy which promised significant benefits by
dealing promptly with low level disorder, incivilities and minor offences. In this
way they promised to turn declining neighbourhoods around and to salvage
those who were in danger of ‘tipping’ into decline (Hope 1999).
The ‘Broken Windows’ thesis was for many years held up as the new wisdom
of criminology. However, it also became the object of criticism from a number
of directions. These critiques generally took one of three forms. Most commen-
tators took issue with the claimed developmental sequence between disorder,
crime and urban decline. In opposition, they argued that this account captured
at best only one side of the dialectic and at worst distorted the real develop-
mental sequence which was in fact the opposite of the one proposed by Wilson
Introduction: beyond criminology 15
and Kelling. Critics argued that it was urban decline which was more likely to
affect the housing market, family stability and the composition of neighbour-
hoods and that as these elements changed informal controls would tend to
break down and the vulnerability of affected populations would increasingly
make them more attractive targets for crime and disorder (Matthews 1992).
Second, it was suggested that the thesis did not clearly differentiate the signifi-
cance and the social meaning of different kinds of disorder. Although it was
accepted that disorder was a loosely defined category, the important differences
between say prostitution and graffiti, or between homeless people sleeping in
doorways and rowdy youths became blurred (Sampson and Raudenbush 1999).
This conceptual slippage led to a third problem, the critics claimed, which was
that Wilson and Kelling failed to distinguish between policing problems and
welfare problems. Moving the homeless on or arresting them for loitering was
seen by many as inappropriate – the problems were merely put out of sight and
it failed to address the real causes, such as the shortage of available work or
affordable accommodation. In Chapter 5, George Kelling provides a response to
these critiques and restates the need to take issues of disorder seriously while
providing some suggestions of the ways in which the ‘Broken Windows’ thesis
might be developed and implemented.
Other critics have argued that disorder can have its uses and have pointed to
the dangers of attempting to suppress every form of disorder since this can result
in sanitised cities in which street life, in its various forms, becomes conspicu-
ously absent (Sennett 1970). Alternatively, the fight against disorder can
produce ‘fortress cities’, in which the use of public space is curtailed and law
enforcement is built into the very bricks and mortar of the urban landscape. In
Los Angeles, heralded by many as the city of the future, the fight against crime
and disorder has resulted in what Mike Davis (1998) has identified as the
creation of a series of ‘social control districts’ which embody new forms of
spatial discipline. These include: abatement districts, in which the traditional
police powers over nuisance are extended to the removal of graffiti and prostitu-
tion; enhancement districts, in which those committing certain offences within a
specified radius of designated public institutions can have their penalties
increased; containment districts which are designed to quarantine potentially
endemic social problems and, more usually, certain social types; and exclusion
districts, in which designated pariah groups are excluded from public spaces or
even city limits. Engaging in urban life in cities like Los Angeles becomes a
matter of moving between a series of ‘security bubbles’, which may take the
form of malls, offices or gated communities. It is a world in which order is
organised in relation to strict spatial divisions producing new geographies of
inclusion and exclusion.
Defined in this way, ‘social exclusion’ is inextricably bound up with the notion
of citizenship. Further, it was the related issues of citizenship and ‘exclusion’
which Jacques Delors, who was a close political associate of Mitterrand, intro-
duced into the vocabulary of the European Union, most notably in the Delors
Report, Growth, Competitiveness and Employment (1993). Social exclusion and
citizenship both have a central role in contemporary political discourse in the
UK, but because the voluntaristic variant of the underclass thesis has such a
firm purchase within that discourse, there is always the sense that social exclu-
sion may be self-inflicted and that discussions of citizenship accentuate the
responsibilities of young people at the expense of their civil, political and
economic rights (Pitts 2001). However, the question of citizenship, and more
particularly whether a citizen’s race or culture has a bearing upon the service
he or she might receive from the police, was forcefully posed by the
Macpherson Report (1999) on the murder of Stephen Lawrence. Marian
FitzGerald, in Chapter 6, assesses the impact of Macpherson on the policing of
black and Asian citizens and the extent to which the policies which emerged
following the publication of the Macpherson Report have contributed to their
safety.
In order to respond to what is seen as the development of a more divided
society in which the gap between the rich and poor appears to be ever
widening, the Labour government established the Social Exclusion Unit. In its
major strategy document, it states that:
Over the last generation, this has become a more divided country. While
most areas have benefited from rising living standards, the poorest neigh-
bourhoods have tended to become rundown, more prone to crime, and
more cut off from the labour market. The national picture conceals pockets
of intense deprivation where the problems of unemployment and crime are
acute and hopelessly tangled up with poor health, housing and education.
They have become no go areas for some and no exit zones for others.
(Social Exclusion Unit 1998)
Our research reveals that the beliefs of inner-city residents bear little
resemblance to the blanket media reports asserting that values have
plummeted in impoverished inner-city neighbourhoods or that people in
the inner-city have an entirely different value system. What is so striking
is that despite the overwhelming joblessness and poverty, black residents
in inner-city ghetto neighbourhoods actually verbally endorse, rather
than undermine, the basic American values concerning individual
initiative.
(Wilson 1996: 179)
The term social exclusion, however, fits well with the view that social depri-
vation is multifaceted and with the suggestion that the issues are wider than
poverty alone and involve moral considerations and notions of identity. It also
fits well with the commitment to multi-agency interventions. The implicit
suggestion, however, that the problem is overwhelmingly one of distribution, or
redistribution, has been challenged by those who see the focus on the under-
class and the socially excluded as a distraction from the development of a more
diverse and tolerant society, on the one hand, and by those who argue for a
more thoroughgoing economic and social reorganisation, on the other (Bowring
2000; Young 1990).
Introduction: beyond criminology 19
Conclusion
The shifting emphasis from crime control to community safety which has been
institutionalised in local authority-based partnerships in the UK has been
described as a ‘sea change’ and a ‘watershed’ with some justification. The formal
coupling of crime and disorder in the Crime and Disorder Act (1998) and the
incorporation of both within the wider framework of community safety has had
a number of significant consequences, for criminology and for how crime is seen
in relation to other hazards. Although the crime control industry continues to
grow, the privileged position which crime has been accorded in recent years is
coming under question. New styles of governance are emerging and the
Introduction: beyond criminology 21
References
Abel-Smith, B. and Townsend, P. (1964) The Poor and the Poorest, London: G. Bell and
Sons.
Audit Commission (1996) Misspent Youth, London: the Audit Commission.
—— (1999) Safety in Numbers, London: the Audit Commission.
Barr, R. and Pease, K. (1990) ‘Crime Placement, Displacement and Deflection’, in M.
Tonry and N. Morris (eds) Crime and Justice: An Annual Review of Research, Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Bauman, Z. (1995) Life in Fragments: Essays in Postmodern Morality, Oxford: Blackwell.
Benson, C. and Matthews, R. (2000) ‘Police and Prostitution: Vice Squads in Britain’, in
R. Weitzer (ed.) Sex for Sale, New York: Routledge.
Blagg, H. and Smith, D. (1989) Crime and Social Policy, London: Longman.
Bottoms, A. (1995) ‘The Philosophy and Politics of Punishment and Sentencing’, in C.
Clarkson and R. Morgan (eds) The Politics of Sentencing Reform, Oxford: Clarendon.
—— and McWilliams, W. (1979) ‘A Non-treatment Paradigm for Probation Practice’,
British Journal of Social Work, 9: 159–202.
—— and Preston, R. (1980) The Coming Penal Crisis, Edinburgh: Scottish Academic
Press.
22 Roger Matthews and John Pitts
Bowring, F. (2000) ‘Social Exclusion: Limitations of the Debate’, Critical Social Policy,
20(3): 307–30.
Braithwaite, J. (2000) ‘The New Regulatory State and the Transformation of Crimi-
nology’, British Journal of Criminology, 40: 223–38.
Brown, M. and Pratt, J. (2000) Dangerous Offenders: Punishment and Social Order,
London: Routledge.
Bureau of Justice (2000) Expenditure and Employment Statistics, US Department of Justice.
On-line. Available: www.ojp.usdoj.gov/bjs/eande.htm
Cain, M. (1990) ‘Realist Philosophy and Standpoint Epistemologies or Feminist Crimi-
nology as a Successor Science’, in L. Gelsthorpe and A. Morris (eds) Feminist
Perspectives in Criminology, Milton Keynes: Open University Press.
Clarke, R. (1992) Situational Crime Prevention: Successful Case Studies, New York: Harrow
and Heston.
Cloward, R. and Ohlin, L. (1960) Delinquency and Opportunity, London: Routledge and
Kegan Paul.
—— and Fox-Piven, F. (1972) Regulating the Poor: The Functions of Public Welfare,
London: Tavistock Publications.
Cohen, S. (1985) Visions of Social Control, Cambridge: Polity Press.
—— (1987) ‘Taking Decentralisation Seriously’, in J. Lowman, R. Menzies and T. Palys
(eds) Transcarceration: Essays in the Sociology of Social Control, Aldershot: Gower.
Cooper, A. and Lousada, J. (2000) The Meaning of Welfare, London: Venture Press.
Crawford, A. (1998) Crime Prevention and Community Safety: Politics, Policies and Prac-
tices, London: Longman.
Crimmens, D. and Pitts, J. (1999) Positive Residential Practice: The Lessons of the 1990s,
Lyme Regis: Russell House Publishing.
Crowther, C. (2000) ‘Thinking About the “Underclass”: Towards a Political Economy of
Policing’, Theoretical Criminology, 4(2): 149–67.
Cullen, F. (1994) ‘Social Support as an Organising Concept for Criminology’, Justice
Quarterly, 11(4): 527–59.
Currie, E. (1986) Confronting Crime: An American Challenge, New York: Pantheon.
—— (1988) ‘Two Visions of Community Crime Prevention’, in T. Hope and M. Shaw
(eds) Communities and Crime Reduction, London: HMSO.
—— (1998) Crime and Punishment in America, New York: Metropolitan Books/Henry
Holt and Company.
Dahrendorf, R. (1994) ‘The Changing Quality of Citizenship’, in B. van Steenbergen
The Condition of Citizenship, London: Sage Publications.
Davis, M. (1998) Ecology of Fear: Los Angeles and the Imagination of Disaster, New York:
Henry Holt and Company.
Donzelot, J. and Roman, J. (1991) Le déplacement de la question sociale, in J. Donzelot
(ed.) Face à l’exclusion, Paris: Editions Esprit.
Ericson, R. and Carriere, K. (1994) ‘The Fragmentation of Criminology’, in D. Nelken
(ed.) The Futures of Criminology, London: Sage.
Farrell, G. and Pease, K. (1993) Once Bitten, Twice Bitten: Repeat Victimisation and its
Implications for Crime Prevention, Crime Prevention Unit Paper, no. 46, London:
HMSO.
Farrington, D. and West, D. (1993) ‘Criminal, Penal and Life Histories of Chronic
Offenders: Risk and Protective Factors and Early Identification’, Criminal Behaviour
and Mental Health, 3: 492–523.
Introduction: beyond criminology 23
Feeley, M. and Simon, J. (1992) ‘The New Penology: Notes on the Emerging Strategy of
Corrections and its Implementation’, Criminology, 30(4): 452–74.
—— (1994) ‘Actuarial Justice: The Emerging New Criminal Law’, in D. Nelken (ed.)
The Futures of Criminology, London: Sage.
Garland, D. (1996) ‘The Limits of the Sovereign State’, British Journal of Criminology,
36(4): 445–71.
—— and Sparks, R. (2000) ‘Criminology, Social Theory and the Challenge of Our
Times’, British Journal of Criminology, 40: 189–204.
Genn, H. (1988) ‘Multiple Victimisation’, in M. Maguire and J. Pointing (eds) Victims of
Crime: A New Deal?, Milton Keynes: Open University Press.
Giddens, A. (1992) The Transformation of Intimacy, Cambridge: Polity Press
—— (1998) The Third Way: The Renewal of Social Democracy, Cambridge: Polity Press.
Graham, J. and Bowling, B. (1995) Young People and Crime, London: Home Office.
Hannah-Moffat, K. (1999) ‘Moral Agent or Actuarial Subject: Risk and Canadian
Women’s Imprisonment’, Theoretical Criminology, 3(1): 71–94.
Harvey, D. (1989) The Condition of Postmodernity, Oxford: Blackwell.
Hirschi, T. (1969) The Causes of Delinquency, California: University of California Press.
Home Office (2000) Review of Crime Statistics: A Discussion Document, London: HMSO.
Hope, T. (1999) ‘Crime, Community and Inequality: The Rise of Disorder in British
Public Policy’, inaugural professorial lecture, University of Keele, October.
Hughes, G. (1998) Understanding Crime Prevention: Social Control, Risk and Late Moder-
nity, Buckingham: Open University Press.
Ignatieff, M. (2000) Virtual War: Kosovo and Beyond, London: Chatto and Windus.
Johnston, L. (2000) Policing Britain: Risk, Security and Governance, Harlow: Longman.
Kelling, G. (1987) ‘Acquiring a Taste for Order: Community and Police’, Crime and
Delinquency, 33(1): 90–103.
Kinsey, R., Lea, J. and Young, J. (1986) Losing the Fight Against Crime, Oxford: Blackwell.
Krisberg, B. and Austin, J. F. (1993) Reinventing Juvenile Justice, London: Sage Publishing.
Lea, J. (1998) ‘Criminology and Postmodernity’, in P. Walton and J. Young (eds) The
New Criminology Revisited, London: Macmillan.
Leonard, E. (1982) Women, Crime and Society: A Critique of Criminological Theory,
London: Longman.
Levitas, R. (1998) The Inclusive Society? Social Exclusion and New Labour, London:
Macmillan.
Lewis, O. (1966) La Vida: A Puerto Rican Family in the Culture of Poverty: San Juan and
New York, New York: Random House.
Loveday, B. (1999) ‘The Impact of Performance Culture on Criminal Justice Agencies in
England and Wales’, International Journal of the Sociology of Law, 27: 351–77.
McMahon, M. (1990) ‘Net Widening: Vagaries in the Use of a Concept’, British Journal
of Criminology, 30(2): 121–50.
Maguire, M. and Pointing, J. (1988) (eds) Victims of Crime: A New Deal?, Milton
Keynes: Open University Press.
Marris, P. and Rein, M. (1967) Dilemmas of Social Reform: Poverty and Community Action
in the United States, New York: Atherton Press.
Martinson, R. (1974) ‘What Works? Questions About Prison Reform’, The Public
Interest, Spring: 22–54.
Matthews, R. (1989) Privatising Criminal Justice, London: Sage.
—— (1992) ‘Replacing Broken Windows’, in R. Matthews and J. Young (eds) Issues in
Realist Criminology, London: Sage.
24 Roger Matthews and John Pitts
Wilson, J. and Kelling, G. (1982) ‘Broken Windows: The Police and Neighbourhood
Safety’, Atlantic Monthly (March): 29–38.
Wilson, J. Q. (1975) Thinking About Crime, New York: Basic Books.
—— and Herrnstein, R. (1985) Crime and Human Nature, New York: Simon and
Schuster.
Wilson, W. J. (1987) The Truly Disadvantaged: The Inner-city, the Underclass and Public
Policy, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
—— (1994) Citizenship and the Inner-city Ghetto Poor, in B. van Steenbergen The Condi-
tion of Citizenship, London: Sage Publications.
—— (1996) When Work Disappears, New York: Knopf.
Young, I. (1990) Justice and the Politics of Difference, New Jersey: Princeton University
Press.
Young, J. (1986) ‘The Failure of Criminology: The Need for Radical Realism’, in R.
Matthews and J. Young (eds) Confronting Crime, London: Sage.
—— (1999) The Exclusive Society, London: Sage.
1 Identity, community and social
exclusion
Jock Young
Introduction
For the majority of social commentators, community safety programmes to
control crime and anti-social behaviour are an exercise in the obvious.
‘Community’ is a wholesome, homogeneous entity waiting to be mobilised,
‘safety’ is a risk free end state – the self-evident goal of public desire – whilst
‘crime’ and ‘anti-social behaviour’ are entities which are readily recognisable by
any decent citizen. Indeed, the trio – community, safety and crime – become
elided together, each term defining each other. Thus the intense, socially rich
interacting community is seen to be the very antithesis of crime and is indeed
the place and source of all safety.
Nowadays, as Adam Crawford puts it, ‘the attraction of the notion of
“community” unites and transcends the established … political parties’ (1997:
45). He goes on to write that ‘community … is cleansed of any negative or crim-
inogenic connotations and endowed with a simplistic and naïve purity and
virtue’ (ibid.: 153). Thus problems of crime and disorder are ascribed to a malaise
of community and their solution is seen as the regeneration of community. Such
a perspective can readily be seen as an aspect of modernity, in particular the
social engineering characteristic of the post-war period. This was a period
wherein slums were cleared, towns were planned and ‘rational’ communities
were constructed – the apotheosis being the ‘new town’ developments, the more
mundane and commonplace being the modernist tower blocks interspersed with
family maisonettes and bleak gardens characteristic of the post-war city.
It has been the role of critical criminology to stand outside such conventional
wisdoms and to problematise each of these seeming certainties. Community
becomes seen as a reality lacking coherence, a rhetoric invoked to ensure the
domination of one group over another, a key instrument of social exclusion.
Safety becomes a curtain for fear, the miscalculation of risks, the denial of
excitement and the excuse for xenophobia towards outgroups. Finally, crime and
anti-social behaviour are social constructs which are bestowed by the powerful
on disapproved behaviour but with no essential reality or core. In fact, their
definitions are frequently contested within localities and adherence to criminal
values can even be a dominant aspect of community.1
Identity, community and social exclusion 27
If one wishes to travel anywhere one must know what terrain one has to travel
over, what means of travel are available and last, and by no means least, where
one wants to go. In reality over the last twenty years the terrain, the structure of
society, has radically changed, effective means of intervening in the social world
have profoundly altered and, most important, the metropolis of possibility and
desire in which we find ourselves has altered beyond recognition.
The last third of the twentieth century witnessed a remarkable transforma-
tion in the lives of citizens living in advanced industrial societies. The Golden
Age of the post-war settlement, with high employment, stable family structures
and consensual values underpinned by the safety net of the welfare state, has
been replaced by a world of structural unemployment, economic precariousness,
Identity, community and social exclusion 29
Crime and its control is a prime site for essentialisation. Who, by definition,
could be a better candidate for such a negative ‘othering’ than the criminal and
the culture that he or she is seen to live in? Thus the criminal underclass,
replete with single mothers living in slum estates or ghettos, drug addicts
committing crime to maintain their habit and illegal immigrants who commit
crime to deceitfully enter the country (and continue their lives of crime in
order to maintain themselves), have become the three major foci of emerging
discourses around law and order of the last third of the twentieth century. These
types can be summed up as the welfare ‘scrounger’, the ‘junkie’ and the ‘illegal’.
This triptych of deviancy, each picture reflecting each other in a late modern
portrait of degeneracy and despair, comes to dominate public discussion of social
problems. As the discourse develops, their ontologies become distinct and
different from ‘normal’ people, their social norms absent or aberrant, their
natures frequently racialised and rendered inferior. Crime, a product of our
society, becomes separated from the social structure: it is viewed as a result of
distinct aetiologies, it embodies differing values, it emanates from distinct and
feared areas of the city. It is these areas that are contrasted with the organic
community where social trust and harmony are seen to reside.
• intergenerationality;
• an embeddedness of the individual in locality;
• intense face-to-face interaction;
• much direct information with regard to each other;
• high level of informal social control;
• provision of a localised sense of identity.
The obverse of the organic community is the anomic community, the locality
without norms and the inevitable consequence of this is seen to be the prolifer-
ation of crime and anti-social behaviour. This formulation is wrong on two
scores. First, there is no direct one-to-one relationship between strong commu-
nity and crime. Second, even slum estates have strong social networks. Thus
the organic community could easily support criminal values. As Adam
Crawford nicely puts it:
The logic behind this association between the lack of ‘organized’ commu-
nity and crime is that, conversely, more community equals less crime. …
This benevolent understanding of community is highly misleading. In some
instances ‘community’, i.e. its communal normative values, itself may be
32 Jock Young
The recent research of Sandra Walklate and Karen Evans (1999) in Salford
corroborates Crawford’s comments.4 But the important conclusion from this is
that although intense community does not necessarily inoculate against crime,
it does exert considerable levels of social control – which may influence law-
abiding or criminal behaviour.
Conversely, the image of the sink estate, the inner-city ghetto or the satel-
lite slum is often seen as in a state of anomie. The immune system of informal
control is down and gross social pathology abounds. But even a brief visit to
one of these estates quickly dissipates such a notion. Mothers congregate
around the local school at delivery and collecting times, they discuss the
teachers, their kids, and this and that. Older children hang out at the entrance
to the tower blocks, or along the road by the shops, men meet in the pubs and
betting shops. Networks can be seen everywhere; divided, of course, by all the
axes of age, gender, ethnicity and economic situation, but certainly no lack of
an informal system or anomie in a sense of normlessness, or ‘Broken Windows’
because no one knows each other (Wilson and Kelling 1982). Ironically,
because of structural unemployment, poverty and both geographical and social
immobility, the stigmatised estates of the so-called underclass allow greater
social interaction than on middle-class dormitory estates on the edge of cities.
Here, there is usually a quick turnover of residents, dual time-consuming
careers of husband and wife, the bussing of children to relatively distant schools
and little time except at the weekend to interact with anyone – even with one’s
own family.
The work of Janet Foster has helped to dispel such images of the normless
community. In her study of the London housing estate ‘Riverside’, she notes:
ence tenants’ perceptions of the estates on which they live, and how
different individuals and groups, who have had little or no choice in their
housing allocation, manage to co-exist.
(Foster 1997: 126)
Here, Sennett notes that modern capitalism drives people to seek identity in
community. But Hobsbawm counters that it is precisely the self-same late
modern capitalism which has destroyed community and rendered destitute the
bank of social trust that underwrote it. The local community becomes increas-
ingly more invoked as a place of identity and moves to become a major part of
the rhetoric of political mobilisation just at the time that it is transforming. In a
well-known passage, Hobsbawm writes:
The organic community is, however, in decline, affected by both the globalisa-
tion of the economy and of culture. Manufacturing industries shrink and in
many instances disappear leaving areas bereft of work, service industries prolif-
erate often with small sizes, commuting increases to and from work, local
cultures become less self-contained and more penetrated by the global. They
become, in Giddens’ (1990) evocative term, ‘phantasmagoric’, constituted by
the ghostly presence of distant influences.
I argue that this paradox of a search for identity in community when organic
community is failing, and whose failure to provide tradition and embeddedness
is a core reason for the search for identity, is not nearly as cataclysmic as either
Sennett or Hobsbawm maintain. In part, this is because they cannot envisage
the notions of association and trust outside of the image of the face-to-face,
organic community.
Writers in cultural studies note the fashion in which the late modern community has
lost its mooring in the locale – in the coincidence of the social and the spatial. Thus
Mike Tomlinson (1999) talks of its ‘deterritorialisation’, whilst John Thompson
(1995) refers to the notion of ‘despatialised commonality’ and, perhaps a little more
elegantly, Joshua Meyrowitz (1989) talks of ‘the generalised elsewhere’. Important
here is the way in which people through the various media can share experiences
and identity despite the separation of physical distance. This is not to deny locality –
people after all must live somewhere – but it is to point to the diminution and trans-
formation of the local community and the rise of the virtual community.
John Thompson (1995: 85) usefully classifies social interaction into three
groups:
What is new are the developments in the latter two groups. Portable telephone
companies are presently the fastest growing firms and e-mail communication
Identity, community and social exclusion 37
has become part of everyday life for many people. But even before this, the old-
fashioned landline telephone has had a major impact on people’s lives. Thus
Barry Wellman and other social network analysts have long pointed to the way
in which social technology has liberated people from dependence on spatial
locality. He argues that it makes more sense to perceive of personal communities
and networks rather than communities of neighbourhood (Wellman 1982).
Indeed, as Meyrowitz (1989) wryly comments: ‘access to nonlocal people is
now, via the telephone, often faster and simpler than access to physical neigh-
bors’. Furthermore, within mass media the rise of multi-media and the vast
expansion of choice in radio and television allow the development of niche
audiences and subcultures (see McRobbie and Thornton 1995). Indeed the
mass media take up a surprisingly larger and larger proportion of people’s lives.
In England and Wales, for example, watching television and listening to the
radio constitute 36 per cent of the waking life of the average citizen (figures
from Social Trends 2000).
Thus on one hand the local is penetrated by the global in terms of distant
events, consumer choices and values (such as those emphasising lifestyle choice,
feminism, meritocracy, etc.), and on the other hand, virtual communities
develop on the back of the local which incorporate images, reference groups,
favoured characters and celebrities from a global repertoire and involve both
mass media and mediated interaction.
This late modern mixture of local and virtual community can clearly enhance
people’s ability to realise identity, yet it is also a prime site of misrecognition,
and a threat to one’s status and identity.
We have emerged from a world of neighbours and entered what has increas-
ingly become one of strangers. Here we have the old theme in social
science of a shift from community (crudely, the familiar, interpersonal and
village-centred life of pre-industrialism) to associations which involve the
mixing of people unknown to one another save in specific ways such as bus
conductor, shop assistant, and newsvendor (crudely, the urban-oriented
way of life of the modern). Ever since at least Simmel we have appreciated
how disorienting and also often liberating the transfer from closed commu-
nity to a world of strangers can be. The city may fragment and
depersonalise, but in doing so it can also release one from the strictures of
village life. With the shift towards town life comes about a decline in
personal observation by neighbours and, accompanying this, a weakening
of the power of community controls that are exercised on an interpersonal
Identity, community and social exclusion 39
Recent technology means that neither time nor space is the fixed frame-
work of our routines. … The result can be globalised cultures, no longer
fixed in time or space, from which we choose and indeed make a series of
different choices. Television representations based on the culture of
40 Jock Young
The notion of who you are becomes constructed on a much wider stage in late
modernity. To understand this one must look at the late modern self and its
reference points. Joshua Meyrowitz (1989), in a seminal article, develops the
work of Charles Cooley and George Herbert Mead on the generalised other.
The self according to the symbolic interactionist tradition is given reality by its
reflections in the significant others around us. Cooley calls this ‘the looking
glass self’, and Mead terms it ‘the generalized other’ – we see ourselves through
our perceptions of others’ perceptions of us. According to Meyrowitz, the rela-
tive decline in community and the rise in the media has:
We can expand this idea a little further, since the series of other reference points
against which we judge ourselves fairly or unfairly treated in comparison with
others, widen out as does our knowledge of what is fairness and unfairness and its
distribution. Reference groups are much less attached to locality in late modernity,
for instance, as Bottoms and Wiles (1997) pointed out, the culture of Australia or
the west coast of America can be as ‘real’ to British youth as anything else.
How does this relate to crime and its control? What has happened is that
people’s notion of their self (and hence their sense of shame, of losing self-
respect when certain norms are transgressed), the actual norms themselves – the
informal mores which structure behaviour, the feelings of discontent which
provide the wellsprings of criminality and the vocabularies of motive and justi-
fying circumstances of crime – to a greater extent than ever before are a product
of discourses which are of a global rather than a local nature.
Relative deprivation, for example, is global in its comparison points: aspira-
tions jump frontiers, discourses about crime (including notions of fear, risk and
danger) are a free-floating commodity of a world media, the informal mores of
everyday life (including the introduction of new and more or less stringent defini-
tions of deviance) are constituted within public cultures which are global in their
reach. Indeed, the twin impact of cultural and economic globalisation penetrates
the local, moulding aspirations and changing opportunities, so that the causes of
crime can invariably be tied to global processes. All that is consistently local
about crime itself (and here only conventional crimes) is its actual impact – the
burglary of the dwelling, the violence on the street, the brutality in the home.
But let us return to the pressing problem: the maintenance of order among
lightly engaged strangers. In late modernity the generalised other immediately
presented to the self in the organic community by the reactions of neighbour
and local friend becomes potentially more remote. Deviance is less likely to be
directly observed, there are more nooks and crannies in the contemporary
world, but the weakening of the local is accompanied by the rise of the ‘gener-
alised elsewhere’: our notions of respectable and proper behaviour are then a
product of a wider interaction and a more public discourse. Thus our feelings of
shame and guilt are no longer solely constituted by the face-to-face encounter,
but shame and guilt scarcely vanishes. Indeed it might well be argued that in a
society where identity is both precarious and sought after, the need for the
recognition of social worth is all the more pressing.
One difference between those ‘high up’ and those ‘low down’ is that the
first may leave the second behind – but not vice versa. Contemporary cities
are sites of an ‘apartheid à rebours’: those who can afford it, abandon the
filth and squalor of the regions that those who cannot afford the move are
stuck to. In Washington D.C. … there is an invisible border stretching
along 16th Street in the west and the Potomac river in the north-west,
which those left behind are wise never to cross. Most of the adolescents left
behind the invisible yet all-too-tangible border never saw downtown
Washington with all its splendours, ostentatious elegance and refined plea-
sures. In their life, that downtown does not exist. There is no talking over
the border. The life experiences are so sharply different that it is not clear
what the residents of the two sides could talk to each other about were they
Identity, community and social exclusion 43
This eloquent expression of the dual city thesis is wrong, not in its sense of divi-
sion, but in its sense of borders. For the borders are regularly crossed and the
language spoken on each side is remarkably similar. The most obvious flaw in
this argument is that of gender: maids, nurses, clerical staff move across borders
into work everyday. Women, as William Julius Wilson argues in When Work
Disappears (1996), are more acceptable to the world outside of the ghetto than
their male counterparts. It is after all ‘home boys’ who stay at home. But bell-
hops, taxi drivers, doormen, maintenance men regularly ply their way across the
invisible borders of Washington, DC. It is not, therefore, just through television
that the sense of relative deprivation of the poor is heightened; it is in the
direct and often intimate knowledge of the lives of the affluent.
The decline of old industries and the shift to an economy based on knowl-
edge and skills has given rise to a new class: a workless class … Today the
greatest challenge for any democratic government is to refashion our insti-
tutions to bring this new workless class back into society and into useful
work, and to bring back the will to win.
(Tony Blair, speech at the Aylesbury Estate, Southwark, 2 June
1997, cited in Peck 1999)
In Britain the work of the Social Exclusion Unit (1999a), set up under the New
Labour administration, explicitly regards its task as the integration of what it
sees as socially disorganised communities into the mainstream. This task is
explicitly aimed at reducing the levels of crime and disorder within society as a
whole. So, once again, we have a notion of the dual city. But the political aim
here is overtly inclusionist and can fittingly be seen as a social democratic
attempt to tackle the correlate of social problems occurring in the poorest part
of society. Here a key concept is the notion of the welfare dependency of the
poor and the emancipating effect of work in transforming their lives.
The danger of the concept of social exclusion is that it carries with it a series
of false binaries: it ignores the fact that problems occur on both sides of the line,
however much one has clusters in one area rather than another and, more
subtly, it conceals the fact that the ‘normality’ of the majority is itself deeply
problematic.
Thus in the first respect, as we have seen, unemployment, poverty and
economic insecurity is scarcely unknown outside the designated areas – indeed
quantitatively they are overall more prevalent in the supposedly secure majori-
tarian heartlands of society than they are in the selected minority of ‘excluded’
areas. And the same, of course, is true of illicit drug use, community disorganisa-
tion, unstable family structures, etc. In the case of the notion of ‘the normal
majority’ it assumes that, in this world, class differentials are somehow insignifi-
cant, that paid work is an unambiguous benefit, that ‘stable’ family life is
unproblematic, licit psychoactive drug use is less a problem than illegal drug
‘abuse’, and so on. Furthermore, it assumes that the transition from the socially
excluded to the socially included majority via the vehicle of work will miracu-
lously solve all these problems.
The centrality of work to the process of inclusion cannot be overemphasised.
Being a member of society, being included, means being in work and useful work
means paid work, labour sold in the market place. As Ruth Levitas clearly puts it:
of contemporary politics and the media: events are publicly examined and
debated by turning to representatives of various ‘communities’. There can be no
doubt that such a formulation has some foundation. A whole series of what
Nancy Fraser calls ‘subaltern public spheres’ occur where genuine debates occur
and which can by careful argument and presentation influence the debate
within the more general public sphere. A key example which Fraser gives, is
that of second wave feminism which as a new social movement has elaborated
extensive networks, journals, activist groups and discussion centres. Further-
more, such activism has produced broad debate in the wider public sphere over
a whole series of issues concerned with crimes against women: sexual harass-
ment, rape, domestic violence, etc., many of which has resulted in changes in
public attitudes and a broad raft of legislation. But it would be wrong to see such
sections of the population as late modern equivalents of the organic community.
Nancy Fraser, in her essay ‘Sex, Lies and the Public Sphere’ (1997), discusses
the 1991 struggle over the confirmation of Clarence Thomas as an associate
justice of the US Supreme Court who was nominated as only the second
African American on the Court in US history. Thomas was accused of sexual
harassment by Anita Hill, a black female law professor who had served as
Thomas’ assistant at the Equal Employment Commission in the 1980s. Fraser
takes us through a fascinating account of the discourses surrounding this
struggle: for discourses of gender, race and class each entered the public arena as
the debate developed. What became clear was that there was no clear line from
women, from blacks, from the middle- or working-class white males. It was not
that self-conscious ‘communities’ of a sort existed, particularly in this context of
American multiculturalism, but that each divided and crossed in their alliances.
A result was what Fraser (1997) called ‘the fracturing of the myth of homoge-
neous ‘ “communities” ’. As a result, she continues, it would be better to
consider:
We start then from noting how the notion of ‘community’ has changed remark-
ably in late modernity but, further to this, that what takes its place is not simply
a series of discrete multicultural communities with both local and virtual
dimensions, which both criss-cross and are contested. The community loosens
46 Jock Young
its mooring in the locality and the various public discourses no longer have any
one-to-one relationship to a specific section of the population.
Conclusion
It is now time to bring the threads of this discussion together. The problem of
crime is inevitably one of order, to tackle crime we must, therefore, involve
the politics of distribution and the politics of recognition. We must, in short,
intervene both on a material and a symbolic level. This chapter has been
concerned largely with the latter although it has been argued that without
some form of redistribution any considerable reduction in crime is unlikely.
The significance of the symbolic level has changed remarkably with the tran-
sition to late modernity. First, a more individualistic society generates greater
and greater demands for self-actualisation and recognition. Second, the
increased sense of disembeddedness makes, at the same time, a sense of secure
identity more and more precarious. Third, a potent solution to this ontolog-
ical uncertainty is that of essentialism. Fourth, such a fake sense of solidity is
more easily achieved by denigrating others. And finally, such a dehumanisa-
tion of others can be a potent facilitator both of crime (particularly violence)
and a punitive attitude towards the criminal. It is therefore crucial that we
attend to the problems of identity, arguing for policies which ensure a sense of
self-worth and actualisation yet which do not rest upon the fake premises of
essentialism where others are systematically denigrated and then abused. Not
the least reason for this is that such a sense of identity brings with it the
informal norms which apportion praise and shame and help control predatory
crime towards others.
Nancy Fraser, in Justice Interruptus (1997), develops an extremely useful
typology of the politics of reform based on the two dimensions of redistribution
and recognition. Reform, she argues, must recognise the necessity of changes in
both these areas, assuaging the failings of distributive justice and misrecognition
and devaluation. But to this dichotomy she adds a further distinction: between
the politics of affirmation and the politics of transformation. Affirmative poli-
tics merely involves the surface transfer of resources without changing the basic
underlying divisions whereas transformative politics seek to eliminate the basic
underlying structures of injustice (see Young 1999; Mooney 2000). Thus in the
area of redistribution affirmative remedies involve, for example, coercing the
underclass into the labour market at extremely low wages. Their underclass
position is merely reproduced this time within the lower reaches of the market
place (see Levitas 1996). This dragooning of people from one category of exclu-
sion to another (‘getting the people to work’, as the Social Exclusion Unit
[1999a] put it, with its cheerless double entendre) is experienced all too
frequently, not as inclusion but as exclusion, not as the ‘free’ sale of labour but
as straightforward coercion. Relative deprivation would, of course, not be solved
by such ‘inclusionary’ politics and the sources of discontent which are liable to
generate high crime rates would be unabated. Transformative redistribution, on
Identity, community and social exclusion 47
the other hand, would involve such measures as retraining so that jobs could be
gained and then rewarded on a meritocratic basis – thus putting a genuine
element of equality into equal opportunity policies, the recognition of non-paid
work (e.g., child rearing, caring for ageing parents) as of vital importance for
social reproduction, the creation of viable childcare infrastructures for women
with children, and the enforcement of a minimum wage on a level which allows
the individual an existence which is neither demeaning nor severely straitening
in circumstance. Above all, it would not fetishise paid work – it would not view
such work as the vital prerequisite for full citizenship, for acceptance and inclu-
sion in society.
An affirmative politics of recognition does not question the various essen-
tialisms of difference. That is, in the case of conventional multiculturalism,
what is stressed is the need for the positive recognition of various groups on
equal terms, for example: Irish, African-Caribbean, gays, women, etc. In
contrast, transformative politics seek to break down and destabilise the cate-
gories by questioning the very notion of fixed identity and essence. Thus the
invented notion of tradition is challenged, the overlapping, interwoven nature
of what are supposedly separate cultures stressed, and the ambiguity and blurred
nature of boundaries emphasised. Diversity is encouraged and, where non-
oppressive, celebrated, but difference is seen as a phenomenon of cultures in
flux not essences which are fixed.
In the case of crime and punishment, the critique of essences both in crim-
inal victimisation and in punishment is a high priority. The category of hate
crimes must be widened out in the realisation that a considerable proportion of
acts of violence involve vocabularies of motive which debase and dehumanise
the victim (see Young 1990). Thus not only crimes against gays and blacks, but
against women, the elderly, the poor, etc. In terms of our response to crime it is
vital that the essentialism which runs through the discourses about crime and
its causes is thoroughly debunked. Important, here, is to confront and shatter
the triptych which locates crime spatially and socially in three loci – the under-
class, the drug user and the immigrant. Such a combination, portrayed as
interdependent and very frequently racialised, is presented as the major source
of crime and disorder in our society.
Against this we must emphasise that crime occurs throughout the structure
of society and that its origins lie not in a separate aetiology but in the structure
of society and its core values. The identification of a distinct criminal class is an
endeavour bound to failure. Politicians forget this at their peril. As I write, the
British Prime Minister Tony Blair roundly castigates drunken hooligans one
week and calls for robust legislation to bring them under control when in the
next week his own 16-year-old son is arrested for drunkenness in London. A
year previously, the Home Secretary, Jack Straw, famous for his tough on crime
approach and the appointment of a drug Czar, is awakened from sleep by a tele-
phone call from the police informing him that his son has been arrested for
selling drugs. As the perceptive journalist Joan Smith (2000) put it:
48 Jock Young
The Government’s responses are off the cuff and authoritarian … Again
and again it reveals an us-and-them mentality as though there are only two
Britons: decent God-fearing folk whose only transgression is the occasional
parking ticket and a violent, anti-social sub-class whose members habitually
exploit drugs and alcohol and deliberately go out deliberately looking for
trouble.
(Smith 2000: 13)
At the start of this chapter I discussed the need to chart the journey into late
modernity. It was necessary to examine the terrain, chose our means of travel
and be clear as to our destination. We have seen how the terrain has changed
dramatically: employment, family, community – the structure of society, has
become less secure, boundaries blur, identities are less and less fixed, place and
social category become less determinate in prescribing behaviour, vocabularies
of motive lose their mooring in discrete parts of the structure – we have entered
the period of what Bauman (2000) graphically calls ‘liquid modernity’. And this
terrain has become a more risky place both in terms of crime and disorder and
in terms of demonisation and scapegoating. On the one hand, the organic
community has diminished and fragmented becoming much less capable of
controlling the rising tide of crime and discontent, whilst on the other hand,
community itself becomes reinvented as a mythical Gemeinschaft which serves
to exclude and essentialise others.
Yet the organic community of the past is in terminal decline, although not
into a black hole of atomistic individuals devoid of trust as the more dystopian
of commentators would have it. For it has reformed into the late modern
community: virtual and mediated in part and global in its reach which touches
down at the local sometimes substantially but always intermittently in the biog-
raphy of each individual. It is in this new community, the ‘generalised
elsewhere’, where old identities are discarded and new identities reconstructed.
It is here both in the more general public sphere and the host of subaltern
publics where concepts of appropriate and inappropriate behaviour, and the
criteria of social worth and opprobrium are regularly debated. Never have so
many people looked at so many people: never in human history has there been
such a degree of reflexivity about human behaviour. The paradox of identity, of
course, is that it is precisely at the point in history where it becomes most
apparent as a social construction that there is a widespread desire for essence
and fixity. The importance of the new social movements here is vital. For they
become the key axes of the debate about gender, ethnicity, or relations with
other species and the environment. The worry, of course, even here, is the
tendency to essentialise whether it is anti-racists who give credence to ‘race’,
radical feminists who essentialise masculinity and femininity or gay rights
activists who begin to believe in the biological basis of homosexuality.
Furthermore, as Fraser (2000) points out in a recent essay, it is necessary to
recognise the need to tackle the institutionalised patterns which maintain such
essences. For example, the institutionalised racism within police practice which
Identity, community and social exclusion 49
Work in the sense of that which involves self-realisation and creativity, is not,
of course, dead but secure, paid, full-time employment for life is considerably
diminished and where it exists does not have this quality. Hence the title of
Gorz’s book ‘Reclaiming Work’. Work, like the community, needs to be refor-
mulated if we are to seek to provide the basis of identity and social worth.
Lastly, let us look at our final destination. The transition to late modernity is
one which involves the most dramatic changes in the fabric of society. Anthony
Giddens (1990) describes it like a juggernaut sweeping all solid institutions
aside, Francis Wheen (1999), in his recent biography of Marx, wryly notes how
the images of globalisation and the metaphor of the ‘melting’ of all that seemed
solid in the Communist Manifesto is prescient more of the present time than in
50 Jock Young
the nineteenth century. Indeed there is more than a slight resonance of today
when we read of a world where there is ‘uninterrupted disturbance of all social
conditions, everlasting uncertainty and agitation … fixed, fast-frozen relations,
with their train of ancient and venerable prejudices and opinions are swept
away’. Such changes with heavy irony swept away the fossilised state socialist
regimes of Eastern Europe just as they transform our lives in the West.
Community, work, the family – all the major institutions of social order, face a
transformation. Whether this is in the direction of greater equality and a sense
of self-worth or towards inequality and essentialism is the central hub of the
politics of the future.
Notes
1 And, of course, such a process of deconstruction has been characteristic of critical
analysis throughout the humanities and the social sciences. What is worth noting is
that the period in which critical criminology emerged in the late 1960s and early
1970s was at the cusp of change within which dramatic transformations were occur-
ring throughout the social fabric of advanced capitalist societies. The early critiques
were, so to speak, a harbinger of what was to come and what, at that time was a rele-
vant yet perhaps technically peripheral critique of modernity, has become a pressing
and key concern of any social analysis of late modernity.
2 In fact she points to a shift from one to the other so that ‘the struggle for recognition
is fast becoming the paradigmatic form of political conflict in the late twentieth
century’ (Fraser 1997: 11). Her predictions as to the decline of the social democratic
politics of class are undoubtedly incorrect: what her own work vividly shows is that
the discourses of both class and identity politics co-exist even in the United States
(see, for example, her remarkable essay on the Clarence Thomas case in her book
Justice Interruptus [1997]), as also does her discussion of methods of social transforma-
tion lean heavily on the co-existence of both dimensions (of which more later).
Indeed, her distinction between the politics of distribution and recognition and the
strategies needed to overcome maldistribution and misrecognition are of great use
and versatility.
3 I have paired the concepts of distributive justice and relative deprivation and
misrecognition and ontological deprivation. Fraser’s distinction echoes the tradi-
tional Weberian distinction between class and status and it is significant that
Runciman (1966) in his original, although largely unexplored, discussion of depriva-
tion utilised as I am doing here relative deprivation on both these dimensions. In a
recent essay, Fraser (2000) acknowledges the Weberian influence on her work.
4 Of course, all of these authors rediscover that which was a mainstay of traditional
subcultural theory. Such is the amnesia in criminology that the pivotal work of
Cloward and Ohlin (1961), particularly in their discussion of the organised and
disorganised slum, is not built upon.
References
Back, L. (1996) New Ethnicities and Urban Culture, London: UCL Press.
Bauman, Z. (1998) Globalization, Cambridge: Polity Press.
—— (2000) Liquid Modernity, Cambridge: Polity Press.
Beck, U. (1992) Risk Society, London: Sage.
Berman, M. (1983) All That’s Solid Melts Into Air, London: Verso.
Identity, community and social exclusion 51
Jacobs, J. (1961) The Death and Life of Great American Cities, New York: Random House.
Levitas, R. (1996) ‘The Concept of Social Exclusion and the New Durkheimian Hege-
mony’, Critical Social Policy, 16(46): 5–20.
Luttwak, E. (1995) ‘Turbo-Charged Capitalism and its Consequences’, London Review of
Books, 17(21): 6–7.
McRobbie, A. and Thornton, S. (1995) ‘Rethinking Moral Panic for Multimediated
Social Worlds’, British Journal of Sociology, 46(4): 559–74.
Matthews, R. (1988) ‘Reassessing Informal Justice’, in R Matthews (ed.) Informal Justice?,
London: Sage.
Meyrowitz, J. (1985) No Sense of Place: The Impact of Electronic Media on Social Behaviour,
New York: Oxford University Press.
—— (1989) ‘The Generalized Elsewhere’, Critical Studies in Mass Communication, 6(3):
326–34.
Mooney, G. and Danson, M. (1997) ‘Beyond Culture City: Glasgow as a Dual City’, in
N. Jewson and S. MacGregor (eds) Transforming Cities, London: Routledge.
Mooney, J. (2000) Gender, Violence and the Social Order, London: Macmillan.
Mooney, J. and Young, J. (2000) ‘Policing Ethnic Minorities’, in B. Loveday and A.
Marlow (eds) Policing After the Stephen Lawrence Inquiry, Lyme Regis: Russell House.
Morley, D. and Robins, K. (1995) Spaces of Identity, London: Routledge.
Murray, C. (1984) Losing Ground, New York: Basic Books.
Nightingale, C. (1993) On the Edge, New York: Basic Books.
Peck, J. (1999) ‘New Labourers? Making a New Deal for the “Working Class” ’, Environ-
ment and Planning Government and Policy, 17: 345–72.
Plummer, K. (1995) Telling Sexual Stories, London: Routledge.
Robins, D. (1992) Tarnished Vision, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Ross, A. (1999) The Celebration Chronicles, New York: Balantine.
Runciman, W. (1966) Relative Deprivation and Social Justice, London: Routledge and
Kegan Paul.
Schelsky, H. (1957) ‘Ist die Dauerreflektion institutionalisierbar?’, Zeitschrift für Evange-
lische Ethik, 1: 153–74.
Sennett, R. (1991) The Conscience of the Eye, London: Faber.
—— (1998) The Corrosion of Character, New York: W. Norton and Co.
Smith, J. (2000) ‘Mr Blair gets a wake-up call from the real world’, Evening Standard, 6
July: 13.
Social Exclusion Unit (1999a) Bringing Britain Together: A National Strategy for Neigh-
bourhood Renewal, London: The Stationery Office.
—— (1999b) Teenage Pregnancy, London: The Stationery Office.
Social Trends (2000) 2000 Edition, London: The Stationery Office.
Thompson, J. (1995) The Media and Modernity, Cambridge: Polity Press.
Tomlinson, M. (1999) Globalization and Culture, Cambridge: Polity Press.
Walklate, S. and Evans, K. (1999) Zero Tolerance or Community Tolerance, Aldershot:
Ashgate.
Webber, J. (1992) ‘Individuality, Equality and Difference: Justification for a Parallel
System of Aboriginal Justice’, in R. Silverman and M. Nielsen (eds) Aboriginal Peoples
and Canadian Criminal Justice, Toronto: Butterworths.
Webster, F. (1995) Theories of the Information Society, London: Routledge.
Wellman, B. (1982) Studying Personal Communities in East York (research paper no. 128),
University of Toronto: Centre for Urban and Community Studies.
Wheen, F. (1999) Karl Marx, London: Fourth Estate.
Identity, community and social exclusion 53
The life of any family and any community depends on accepting and
discharging the formal and informal obligations we owe to each other. The
politics of ‘us’ rather than ‘me’ demands an ethic of responsibility as well as
rights.
(Blair 1998: 14)
In sum, the Third Way is premised upon the short-comings of traditional social
democratic ideals that the ‘good life’ can be delivered through the (Keynesian)
welfare state, whilst seeking simultaneously to tame, ride and steer the appar-
ently ‘inevitable’ juggernaut-like pressures of globalisation, including the free
flow of capital, finance, trade, technology and information. Alongside these
global pressures is a growing salience of ‘place’ and locality. Global pressures, it
is argued, are refracted and interpreted through local meanings, identities and
sensibilities (Giddens 1991). As a result, there appears to be an increasingly
profound relationship between globalised conditions and local circumstances in
which the nature of the nation-state’s capacity to exercise political control is
called into question. In this sense, community safety both reflects a field of
policy that it is saturated with wider concerns about contemporary social
change and is a referent for an unfolding form of governance.
prime motto for the new politics, no rights without responsibilities’ (Giddens
1998: 65).
The New Labour government, elected in May 1997, wasted little time in
identifying and selecting crime control as a major plank of public policy upon
which its fortunes in office would hinge and upon which it should be judged. It
clearly sees ‘flagship’ pieces of legislation such as the Crime and Disorder Act
(1998) and the Youth Justice and Criminal Evidence Act (1999) as key
elements in the implementation of Third Way politics in the field of law and
order. The Home Secretary, Jack Straw, has suggested that the statutory commu-
nity safety partnerships established by the Crime and Disorder Act (1998)
alongside measures such as the anti-social behaviour orders (ASBO) and child
curfews will help bind together and empower communities to fight crime.
Through these and associated measures he declared:
various functions and the need to do all that they reasonably can to prevent
crime and disorder in their area, thus requiring local authorities to anticipate
the potential crime consequences of their policies. As the Home Office
Consultation Document noted, this will ‘give the vital work of preventing
crime a new focus across a very wide range of local services … putting crime and
disorder considerations at the very heart of decision making, where they have
always belonged’ (Home Office 1997: para. 33). Consequently, some commen-
tators have gone so far as to suggest that like ‘a wolf in sheep’s clothing’ this
section could come to constitute one of the most important parts of that Act
(Moss and Pease 1999).
Moreover, through the required community consultation processes in the
implementation of community safety strategies and community representa-
tion in local partnerships there is the potential to encourage a stronger and
more participatory civil society. This theme is continued through the restora-
tive justice elements in the youth justice reforms and particularly the
involvement of voluntary panel members on youth offending panels (under
the 1999 Act, currently being piloted), which attempt to reproduce forms of
‘community conferencing’ at the heart of the youth justice system in England
and Wales.
Together, many of the reforms inspired by Third Way politics potentially
afford a more holistic and problem-oriented approach to crime prevention and
community safety (Crawford 1998a). As such, they may allow a fundamental
shift in the way we govern crime and its prevention. Moreover, they challenge,
both implicitly and explicitly, many of the taken-for-granted modernist assump-
tions about professional expertise, hierarchical competence and specialisation,
as well as state paternalism and monopoly. In their place, the new politics offers
more plural understandings of and social responses to crime, drawing together a
variety of organisations and stakeholders, in the public, voluntary and private
sectors as well as from among relevant community groups in ways which are
problem-focused rather than defined according to the means most readily avail-
able for their solution. As such, they may allow a systemisation and
co-ordination of effort, expertise and information and a democratisation of
control through greater community empowerment.
Nevertheless, in this chapter I want to focus upon a number of sites of
tension, ambiguity and ambivalence in both Third Way politics and the manner
in which they are being implemented. I do so because it is in these conflicts and
tensions that we find some of the key determinants of contemporary law and
order policy and practice, as well as central components guiding the future
shape of crime control.
dynamics which infuse New Labour’s crime control policies (see Downes 1998;
Newburn 1998) nor do they exhaust the range of influences upon change, but it
is my contention that they are key elements within these, both of specific
import and worthy of particular attention. Moreover, they expose and reveal
some of the central and broader tensions, ambiguities and ambivalences in
Third Way thinking more generally.
Communitarianism
As the above quotes already suggest, Third Wayism draws upon a communi-
tarian philosophy, notably that espoused by Amitai Etzioni (1993; 1997a),
whose work has explicitly sought to influence (Etzioni 1997b), and has
impressed, the Labour leadership (Blair 1995; 1996). Such ideas have been
advanced in Britain by the Demos think-tank (see Leadbeater 1996) and such
commentators as Henry Tam (1998). This influence expresses itself in the
diverse appeals to ‘community’ as a focus of moral renewal. As Etzioni
suggests:
Communities often have strong moral voices and hence can help maintain
a social order that draws significantly on value commitments … communi-
ties also share sets of values and reaffirm them, encourage members to abide
by these values, and censure the members when they do not.
(Etzioni 1997a: 123)
Managerialism
Second, there is both an explicit and implicit managerialism at the heart of
New Labour’s reforms. In many ways, recent policy initiatives have intensified
the New Public Management (NPM) reforms introduced under previous
Conservative governments since the mid-1980s. These reforms have seen a
significant restructuring of the public sector and the role of the state, as well as
the introduction of a new regulatory style and managerial culture. NPM reforms
represent a cluster of ideas and strategies which variously have sought: to hive
off certain traditional aspects of public service delivery to the private sector;
introduce private sector management methods to the public sector; flatten
bureaucratic hierarchies; measure performance by results set against clear objec-
tives; disaggregate separable functions into quasi-contractual or quasi-market
forms; introduce purchaser/provider distinctions; open up provider roles to
competition between agencies and private interests; and advocate a ‘closeness
to the customer’ (see Hood 1991; 1995; Clarke and Newman 1997).
Under New Labour the managerialist urges to objective setting, performance
measurement and output-fixation, notably through ‘league table’ comparison,
has reached a new zenith. This is particularly apparent with regard to crime
control in the Crime and Disorder Act (1998) and the managerial processes
introduced to implement the local crime and disorder strategies. Lord Warner, a
senior policy adviser to the Home Secretary during the conception and passage
through Parliament of the Crime and Disorder Act (and now the Chair of the
Youth Justice Board of England and Wales), described the Act as reflecting ‘a
much more managerial feel about how you implement election promises’
(Warner 1998).
The Third Way recognises the limits of government in the social sphere,
but also the need for government, within those limits, to forge new partner-
ships with the voluntary sector. Whether in education, health, social work,
crime prevention or the care of children, ‘enabling’ government
strengthens civil society rather than weakening it, and helps families and
communities improve their own performance … New Labour’s task is to
strengthen the range and quality of such partnerships.
(Blair 1998: 14)
Networks of interlaced agencies drawing from the public, private and volun-
tary sectors are heralded as alternatives to a primacy upon bureaucracies and
markets as the bedrocks of the new governance.
Far from wrestling with this conundrum, Third Way proponents sidestep it,
leaving a vacuum too easily filled with today’s dominant managerialist dogma,
which often resembles little more than the ‘marketisation of the public sector’,
through the injection of private sector management ideas, such as those popu-
larised by Osborne and Gaebler (1992).
More fundamentally, the ‘unholy Trinity’ has encouraged a pluralisation of
services and service providers. Managerialist reforms and appeals to community
involvement in policing and crime control have enticed new actors and active
citizens into what was once perceived as the sole responsibility of the public
police. As a consequence, we have witnessed the fragmentation and dispersal of
policing and control. Fragmentation, itself, has been encouraged by the intro-
duction of privatisation and quasi-markets through purchaser/provider splits
where services could not easily be privatised. We can no longer speak (if we
ever could) of a state monopoly in crime control and policing (Jones and
Newburn 1998). They have become shared, as diverse agencies, organisations,
groups and individuals are implicated in these tasks. This has produced a
complex array of networks, partnerships, interlaced alliances of organisations
and active citizenry that transcend the ‘public’ and ‘private’ spheres constituting
hybrid mixes of plural agencies, places and functions.
In many senses, the establishment of the new community safety partnerships,
by the Crime and Disorder Act (1998), will encourage and entrench this
process of fragmentation of service delivery (and service providers) at a local
level. The logic of the Act and the Guidance (Home Office 1998) which
accompanies it is to encourage a pluralisation of local service providers and
networks. It does so, not only by transcending the traditional workings of
particular local agencies, but also by opening up new policy arenas, encouraging
partnerships across and between the public, voluntary and private sectors. In
addition, the emphasis upon a locally-grounded, problem-solving methodology
encourages new local players to enter the field. However, the (unintended but
logical) consequence of this is to exacerbate co-ordination and undermine the
effectiveness of steering mechanisms.
This process of fragmentation itself has generated a demand for co-ordina-
tion and the conditions for the emergence of ever newer networks and
62 Adam Crawford
lematic. The same analogy applies equally well to community safety – and other
so-called ‘wicked issues’ – which, as the Morgan Report reminded us, ‘is a
peripheral concern for all the agencies, and a truly core activity for none of
them, even those agencies which explicitly include crime prevention within
their objectives such as the police and the probation service’ (1991: 15, para.
3.15). However, the managerialist reforms which increasingly have pervaded
criminal justice organisations with their emphasis upon performance measure-
ment, financial control and responsiveness to ‘customers’ for whom services are
delivered have not disrupted this image significantly and perversely may have
strengthened it (Shapland 2000). They have strengthened intra-organisational
control but often at the expense of concerns for inter-organisational relations (a
point to which I return below), thus exacerbating fragmentation. The supreme
paradox of managerialist reforms is that they are increasingly undermined by
plural partnerships and networks while simultaneously weakening the effective-
ness of the partnerships and networks that they spawned. They induce a
landscape which is simultaneously joined-up but fragmented.
had one overriding failure – they left government less, rather than more,
able to solve the important, ‘wicked’ problems that most concern electors:
how to cut crime. … The vertical links between departments and agencies
in any one field and professional groups such as the police, teachers, doctors
and nurses are strong. The horizontal links are weak or non-existent.
(Perri 6 1997: 9–10)
Managerialist reforms have served, perversely, to increase the isolation and intro-
spection of many criminal justice agencies and other public sector organisations
drawn into community safety partnerships. They have done so in four principal
ways. First, managerialist reforms focus upon efficiency, economy and value for
money, on hierarchical control and on the clear distribution of authority and
responsibility (Rhodes 1997: 55). They are primarily concerned with internal re-
organisation. Managerialist reforms encourage an intra-organisational focus that
pays little attention to the task of managing inter-organisational relations. Scant
regard is afforded to the more complex process of negotiating shared purposes,
particularly where there is no hierarchy of control. Managerialism may suit hier-
archical line management structures but is largely inappropriate for managing
horizontal inter-organisational networks. There are fundamental tensions
between a ‘partnership’ approach and aspects of the intra-organisational focus of
managerialist reforms.
Second, the intra-organisational focus on ‘outputs’ and performance
measurement can make agencies concentrate their energies upon their core
tasks and activities at the expense of peripheral ones. Managerialist reforms
focus attention upon narrowly construed service delivery to ‘customers’ of a
particular segment of criminal justice at a given time and place within the
process, rather than upon cross-cutting, horizontal accountabilities and respon-
sibilities. Where a partnership approach envisages corporate decision-making
on behalf of a number of actors, managerialism conceives of compartmentalised
and independent responses coupled with an intra-organisational focus on objec-
tives and results. The emphasis upon intra-organisational performance
measurement fails to recognise that partnerships inherently blur the boundaries
between, and the roles of, the incorporated organisations, such that individual
contributions cannot easily be separated off and disentangled from each other
without undermining the nature of that contribution.
The recent development of ‘corporate’ performance indicators has gone
some way towards tying diverse agencies into the production of collective
goods which transcend the competency or capacity of individual agencies –
such as community safety. Yet, this does not resolve two dilemmas. First, there
are problems that arise with regard to any conflicts between intra-organisa-
66 Adam Crawford
Under the present conditions authority can hardly be located any more: it
has become shared, parcelled, delegated, conditioned, subjected to approval
and correction … In a word: authority has become elusive.
(Peters 1986: 34)
concentration upon ‘easy’ or ‘soft’ targets: those which are more likely to yield
positive results, consequently diverting attention and resources away from (and
possibly writing off all together) more problematic areas or intractable crime
problems.
In sum, managerialist reforms are essentially hierarchical and as such antithet-
ical to the management of complex networks: they emphasise inward-looking
and myopic forms of performance measurement and output fixation which often
work against holistic governance. As a consequence, they often fail to address
‘wicked issues’, focusing upon narrowly defined, measurable elements of a
problem. They are simultaneously wide-angled but tunnelled vision.
Despite its technical discourse, the audit is also a system of values and goals
which are inscribed in the official programmes which both demand and
encourage it. It helps shape public conceptions of the problems for which it is
the perceived solution. As such, ‘it is constitutive of a certain regulatory or
control style which reflects deeply held commitments to checking and trust’
(ibid.: 7). Audit is not merely a technical solution to a problem: ‘it also makes
possible ways of redesigning the practice of government’ (ibid.: 11). Audits have
as their primary object organisations and their sub-systems of control, as such
audits are concerned with the control of control (ibid.: 128).
It is unsurprising, therefore, that the community safety partnerships have, at
their very heart, a process of audit. In many senses, this process differs from
traditional financial audits, but nevertheless the core idea of independent
checking through informational evidence remains a key factor. Moreover, the
audit process incorporates wholesale the language of managerialism, thus
constructing afresh the nature of local crime problems: how they should be
measured and managed. It seeks to shape public expectations, redefine success
and failure and construct new forms of authority and legitimacy.
Appeals to ‘community participation’, ‘active citizenry’ and ‘consumer
sovereignty’ also imply a scepticism of professional expertise. They feed off
critiques of ‘self-serving professional élites’ and claim to represent a challenge to
the ‘cosy cultures of professional self-regulation’ (Power 1997: 44). Here lies an
appeal to open up a new circuit of power between the demands of communities
and individuals as against those of criminal justice agencies. Where once we
were told to ‘leave it to the professionals’ now we are enjoined to active partici-
pation in a ‘self-policing society’ (Leadbeater 1996). As concerns over
‘vigilantism’ have demonstrated, this circuit of power is a problematic and
volatile one.
Paradoxically, technologies such as audits and inspections are contrived, in
part, in the hope of restoring trust in organisational competence. Moreover,
they presuppose and necessitate trust in themselves as instruments of verifica-
tion and control. And yet, rather than resolving trust deficits they tend to
multiply and disperse these into the fabric of the organisational environment.
They disrupt trust relations by replacing traditional forms of trust in the profes-
sional use of discretion with forms of audit and inspection. Relations of trust in,
Joined-up but fragmented 69
and between, functionaries which have traditionally allowed large scope for
policy discretion have been significantly curtailed in recent years by managerial
reforms. They have encircled trust, by reducing the boundaries of discretion and
rendering it subject to inspection and budgetary constraint.
As such, managerialist reforms institutionalise forms of distrust. However,
recourse to audits, performance measurement, contracts and inspections does
not necessarily destroy trust – as some have argued (Broadbent et al. 1996) – but
rather reconfigures it. Trust and the contractualisation of relations are not
mutually exclusive. In many senses, contracts presuppose a certain degree of
trust. The new governance does not obliterate trust altogether, in fact it necessi-
tates that trust is placed in new ‘guardians of trust’: auditors and inspectors. But
this is a different form of trust, involving a ‘second order’ relationship.
Ultimately, however, these systems of control are themselves the subject of
questions as to their competence. The trust that new technologies demand must
itself be the subject of ‘verification’ (Crawford 2000b).
Whilst it is the government’s explicit intention that the audit process should
be a developmental one, in that the Crime and Disorder Act (1998) establishes
a strategy cycle in which the audit process is revisited every three years, there
are legitimate concerns that in practice this may be undermined by competing
pressures. These arise in large part because the veracity of the audit process
becomes bound up with target setting and performance measurement. It would
seem that the quality of the data which informed the first round of audits
published in early 1999 was both limited and variable. Nevertheless, the very
process of striving to meet the targets set on the basis of the audit baseline lends
a legitimacy to the audit itself and shrouds it from critical gaze. For, to question
the baseline is to question the process, and hence the very purpose of measure-
ment. Rather than providing a foundation for informed dialogue and
negotiation, the audit process demands that its efficacy is trusted. The concern
is that in the ‘audit society’ the strategy cycles will become less a process of
institutional learning and problem-identification or merely the basis for discus-
sion but more, in Power’s words, ‘ritualised practices of verification whose
technical efficacy is less significant than their role in the production of organi-
sational legitimacy’ (Power 1997: 14).
Moreover, the reality is that, once set up, baselines and audit processes exert
a dynamic of their own. Continuity and comparability often rein back innova-
tion and development. These problems are compounded by difficulties of
measurement and the inadequacies of information available. Setting meaningful
targets and determining performance indicators for dealing with ‘disorder’ or
‘anti-social behaviour’ are inherently problematic. Public definitions of disorder
and community safety are inconsistent. Different audiences define the same
behaviour differently. Furthermore, many of the neighbourhoods with high
levels of crime and incivilities are inscribed by a general lack of consensus about
such issues. In England and Wales, the Crime and Disorder Act (1998) provides
no statutory definition of disorder nor is it defined in the accompanying
Guidance (Home Office 1998). In practice, no standard systems for monitoring
70 Adam Crawford
In sum, managerial reforms exhibit factors which make trust more valuable
and simultaneously render it more difficult to sustain. They corrode trust and
encourage distrust at the moment in which trust is perceived to be a precious
commodity – as the basis for communal self-regulation, managing networks and
inter-organisational negotiation – such that the increasing demand for trust
coexists alongside the institutionalisation of distrust. Moreover, the new tech-
nologies which seek to respond to trust deficits themselves demand that their
efficacy is trusted, whilst generating information which is of limited use.
Hence, competition and comparison are seen as key criteria through which to
require authorities to demonstrate improvements in services. And yet, unlike
the first two criteria they appear particularly problematic with regard to commu-
nity safety partnerships.
First, there is a contradiction between competition between service
providers, on the one hand, and the process of managing networks of service
providers – notably on the basis of negotiated equilibrium – on the other hand.
Managerialist reforms by creating quasi-markets and injecting competition into
community safety can serve to produce new sites of inter-agency conflict
(Raine and Willson 1997: 88). They encourage low levels of interdependence,
which may leave inter-organisational networks unstable. Moreover, competi-
tion can serve to undermine both reciprocity and trust. The cultures conducive
to managing collaborative partnerships and constructive networks are rooted
more in the identification of shared values, mutual trust and the respect of
common principles and diverse contributions than in competitive market
mentalities or managerial performance comparison. The skills necessary for co-
ordinating and steering horizontal networks are more concerned with
enhancing commitment through management by negotiation. Rhodes (2000:
355–6) likens such skills to those of ‘diplomatic virtues’ which are far removed
from those of the ‘head-kicker macho-manager’, the ‘individualist entrepreneur’
or the ‘bureaucrat’.
Second, comparison as an element of competition can introduce negative
dynamics into community safety given the capacity of crime and disorder to
divide populations and excite fears and anxieties. Moreover, there are signifi-
cant difficulties in drawing meaningful comparisons given the very different
nature of local crime and disorder problems in differing communities. Certain
forms of crime and associated problems are heavily concentrated in specific
geographic areas. Furthermore, there are dangers that community safety is not
a rationalistic ‘zero sum’ endeavour. Safety is relative and relational: one area’s
sense of security and ‘place’ within the city, may be defined, in large part, in
contradistinction to the perception of other areas’ insecurity. In other words,
to feel safe in your own area may necessitate the identification of other, less
safe areas or urban ‘badlands’. Hence, competition and comparison in commu-
nity safety may serve to fuel dynamics of social exclusion and ghettoisation.
72 Adam Crawford
the utopias of egalitarianism, which some might wish, but are hierarchical
formations, structured upon lines of power, dominance and authority.
Communities are intrinsically exclusive – as social inclusion presupposes
processes of exclusion – and may solidify and define themselves around notions
of ‘otherness’ potentially infused with racialised overtones. Challenging and
disrupting established community order, its assumptions and power relations
may be a more fundamental aspect of a progressive politics. As such, nostalgic
appeals to community as the basis of moral order may often be incongruous with
the radical transformations necessary to realise modern institutions of gover-
nance through partnerships.
In short, it is debatable the extent to which the Third Way quest for commu-
nity is a reworking of tradition or a force for democratic renewal. Rather, it may
simply constitute nostalgia disguised as modernisation.
David Garland (1996; 1999) relates this duality of ‘the commonplace and
the catastrophic’ to much deeper (structural) interpretations of crime in late
modernity, as a product of a decentring of state governance of crime. These two
visions Garland refers to as the ‘criminology of the self’ and the ‘criminology of
the other’ respectively:
Not only are these antagonistic accounts the product of dilemmas of contempo-
rary state governance, as Garland suggests, but they also find a particular
expression in ambiguities within Third Way politics.
This tension helps to explain the moral vacillation in the apparently contra-
dictory processes of ‘defining deviancy down’ (Moynihan 1993) and ‘defining
deviancy up’ (Krauthammer 1993) which are simultaneously found in the
Crime and Disorder Act (1998). In one instance, we see a normalisation of
‘crime as everyday life’, whereby in response to high crime rates government
relaxes notions of deviance and allows previously deviant behaviour to become
‘acceptable’ or even ‘normal’, thus limiting the level of demand placed upon
criminal justice systems. This is to be found in governmental strategies through
the spread of situational crime prevention whereby individuals are increasingly
responsible for their own personal safety and the security of their possessions. In
another instance, the increasing concern for incivilities, anti-social behaviour,
disorder and quasi- or sub-criminal activities constitute an inverse process of
‘defining deviancy up’. Here, the previously ‘normal’ is declared deviant and the
deviant is unmasked residing within the normal. Perversely, this can have the
consequence of increasing the demand for crime control and judicial interven-
tions. Janus-faced, the Third Way expresses two distinct visions of crime, the
criminal and the role of criminal justice.
More fundamentally, these tensions express themselves in ambivalent polit-
ical responses. Strategies of responsibilisation through appeals to community
involvement and plural partnerships beyond the state co-exist with declarations
of sovereign authority, notably through punitive sentiments as evidence of the
state’s commitments and strengths. However, this is also to be found with regard
to policing. At one moment, crime rates are portrayed as beyond the compe-
tence of the police alone, as under the new rhetoric ‘we are all responsible for
crime’. In a different moment, however, the government as part of its Crime
Reduction Strategy has set targets for the police, notably with regard to
domestic burglary, to reduce crime by certain measurable amounts within a
certain time-span, as if the police’s capacity for action in this field were
somehow restored. As Garland argues, state sovereignty over crime is simultane-
ously denied – as being ‘beyond the state’ – and symbolically reasserted –
76 Adam Crawford
through periodic episodes of hysterical and populist denials of the state’s limita-
tions (1996: 462). The limitations of traditional criminal justice – police,
prosecution and punishment – are recognised in certain instances only to be
discounted or ignored in others. This dualistic denial and recognition produce
volatile shifts in the state’s presentation of its own capacity for effective action
in crime control.
This ambivalence also expresses itself in the uncertain integration of victims
within criminal justice (Crawford and Goodey 2000). The victim has become a
pivotal figure within contemporary criminal justice and yet victim input
remains circumscribed and ambiguous. The recent concern for victims, their
rights and needs, has found inconsistent political expression. Victims needs are
concurrently embraced and ignored, as illustrated by the integration of victims
within the post-sentencing process through victim contact work by the proba-
tion service (see Crawford and Enterkin 1999). The interests of victims have
simultaneously been used in the service of severity, in the service of offenders
and in the service of systems’ efficiency (Crawford 2000a: 292). The awkward
position of the victim within the complex balance between state/offender and
public/private interests expresses itself in the uncertain relation between passion
and reason as well as between moral punitiveness and instrumental offender
management in Third Way politics.
On Garland’s (1996) account, punitive rhetoric and policy are as much a
product of problems of state sovereignty and legitimation as they are a rational
response to the problems of crime. And yet, he implies that this oscillation and
ambivalence are a product of late modern conditions which produce dilemmas
for state governance. Whilst this broader canvas is insightful and helps us locate
the manner in which similar issues affect different societies it does not accord
sufficient attention to the different cultural and political expressions that these
contradictions can take. The manner in which ambivalence is played out in the
policy field takes on a political form. Hence, these contradictions are also a
product of ‘political incoherence’ (O’Malley 1999), notably, although not
exclusively, the ‘unholy Trinity’ – of appeals to communitarian ideals, gover-
nance through partnership and managerialist implementation – at the heart of
Third Way politics. As I have argued, it is through the analysis of these more
specific aspects of political incoherence that we can identify the sites of contra-
diction, ambiguity and ambivalence around which the future shape and
direction of community safety is likely to unfold.
Notes
1 I borrow this phraseology from Taylor’s (1997) article of the same title.
2 An alternative and altogether more cynical interpretation of this ambiguity lies in
the unwillingness of central government to be explicitly too prescriptive in order to
avoid the counter-accusations from local government, police and other agencies that
if central government wish to require them to engage in specified tasks then dedi-
cated funding should be made available, in order to fulfil such a requirement. The
Crime and Disorder Act (1998) whilst imposing a statutory duty upon local authori-
Joined-up but fragmented 77
ties and the police to establish community safety partnerships did not provide any
new or dedicated resources.
3 In the first fourteen months since they came into effect in April 1999, there had
been no youth curfews implemented and only eighty ASBOs taken out in England
(The Times 29 June 2000). This low use rate has been perceived to be problematic by
the government, which is strongly encouraging greater usage (SEU 2000: 41). The
government now believes that ASBOs should not be viewed as a method of ‘last
resort’, which appears to depart significantly from their initial intentions (Labour
Party 1995).
4 The status and role of bodies like the Audit Commission in recent years have
become increasingly ambiguous, albeit with considerable influence. Its work often
bears little correspondence with traditional depiction of the word audit. Its role
frequently appears more consistent with that of a catalyst for organisational change.
As Day and Klein (1990) suggest, the Audit Commission is in the position of ‘a
policeman constantly tempted to turn consultant’.
References
Audit Commission (1996) Misspent Youth: Young People and Crime, London: Audit
Commission.
—— (1998) A Fruitful Partnership: Effective Partnership Working, London: Audit
Commission.
—— (1999) Safety in Numbers: Promoting Community Safety, London: Audit Commis-
sion.
Blair, T. (1995) ‘The Rights We Enjoy Reflect the Duties We Owe’, The Spectator
Lecture, 22 March.
—— (1996) New Britain: My Vision of a Young Country, London: Fourth Estate.
—— (1998) The Third Way: New Politics for the New Century, London: Fabian Society.
Bottoms, A. E. (1995) ‘The Philosophy and Politics of Punishment and Sentencing’, in
C. Clarkson and R. Morgan (eds) The Politics of Sentencing Reform, Oxford:
Clarendon, 17–49.
Bratton, W. J. (1997) ‘Crime is Down in New York City: Blame the Police’, in N. Dennis
(ed.) Zero Tolerance: Policing a Free Society, London: Institute for Economic Affairs, 29–42.
Broadbent, J., Dietrich, M. and Laughlin, R. (1996) ‘The Development of Principal-
Agent, Contracting and Accountability Relationships in the Public Sector:
Conceptual and Cultural Problems’, Critical Perspectives in Accounting, 7(4): 259–84.
Brownlee, I. (1998) ‘New Labour – New Penology?: Punitive Rhetoric and the Limits of
Managerialism in Criminal Justice Policy’, Journal of Law and Society, 25(3): 313–35.
Cabinet Office (1999) Modernising Government, Cm 4310, London: HMSO.
Charlesworth, J., Clarke, J. and Cochrane, A. (1996) ‘Tangled Webs? Managing Local
Mixed Economies of Care’, Public Administration, 74: 67–88.
Clarke, J. and Newman, J. (1997)The Managerial State, London: Sage.
Crawford, A. (1997) The Local Governance of Crime: Appeals to Community and Partner-
ships, Oxford: Clarendon.
—— (1998a) Crime Prevention and Community Safety: Politics, Policies and Practices,
Harlow: Longman.
—— (1998b) ‘Community Safety and the Quest for Security: Holding Back the
Dynamics of Social Exclusion’, Policy Studies, 19(3/4): 237–53.
—— (2000a) ‘Salient Themes Towards a Victim Perspective and the Limitations of
Restorative Justice’, in A. Crawford and J. Goodey (eds) Integrating a Victim Perspec-
tive within Criminal Justice, Aldershot: Ashgate, 285–304.
78 Adam Crawford
Labour Party (1995) A Quiet Life: Tough Action on Criminal Neighbours, London: Labour
Party.
Leadbeater, C. (1996) The Self-Policing Society, London: Demos.
Morgan, J. (1991) Safer Communities: The Local Delivery of Crime Prevention Through the
Partnership Approach, London: Home Office.
Moss, K. and Pease, K. (1999) ‘Crime and Disorder Act 1998: Section 17 a Wolf in
Sheep’s Clothing?’, Crime Prevention and Community Safety, 1(4): 15–19.
Moynihan, D. P. (1993) ‘Defining Deviancy Down’, American Scholar, 62, Winter:
17–30.
Newburn, T. (1998) ‘Tackling Youth Crime and Reforming Youth Justice: The Origins
and Nature of New Labours Policy’, Policy Studies, 19(3/4): 199–212.
O’Malley, P. (1999) ‘Volatile and Contradictory Punishment’, Theoretical Criminology,
3(2): 175–96.
—— and Palmer, D. (1996) ‘Post-Keynesian Policing’, Economy and Society, 25(2):
137–55.
Osborne, D. and Gaebler, T. (1992) Reinventing Government: How the Entrepreneurial
Spirit is Transforming the Public Sector, Reading, Massachusetts: Addison-Wesley.
Perri 6 (1997) Holistic Government, London: Demos.
Peters, A. A. G. (1986) ‘Main Currents in Criminal Law Theory’, in J. M. van Dijk, C.
Haffmans, F. Ruter and J. Schutte (eds) Criminal Law in Action: An Overview of
Current Issues in Western Societies, Arnhem: Gouda Quint, 19–36.
Power, M. (1997) The Audit Society, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Raine, J. W. and Willson, M. J. (1997) ‘Beyond Managerialism in Criminal Justice’,
Howard Journal, 36(1): 80–95.
Rhodes, R. A. W. (1996) ‘The New Governance: Governing without Government’,
Political Studies, 44: 652–67.
—— (1997) Understanding Governance: Policy Networks, Governance, Reflexivity, and
Accountability, Milton Keynes: Open University Press.
—— (2000) ‘The Governance Narrative: Key Findings and Lessons from the ESRC’s
Whitehall Programme’, Public Administration, 78(2): 345–63.
Shapland, J. (1988) ‘Fiefs and Peasants: Accomplishing Change for Victims in the Crim-
inal Justice System’, in M. Maguire and J. Pointing (eds) Victims of Crime: A New
Deal?, Milton Keynes: Open University Press, 187–94.
—— (2000) ‘Victims and Criminal Justice: Creating Responsible Criminal Justice Agen-
cies’, in A. Crawford and J. Goodey (eds) Integrating a Victim Perspective within
Criminal Justice, Aldershot: Ashgate, 147–64.
Simon, J. (1995) ‘They Died with Their Boots On: The Boot Camp and the Limits of
Modern Penality’, Social Justice, 22(1): 25–49.
Social Exclusion Unit (1998) Bringing Britain Together, a National Strategy for Neighbour-
hood Renewal, London: Cabinet Office.
—— (2000) Anti-Social Behaviour, Report of Policy Action Team 8, National Strategy
for Neighbourhood Renewal, London: Cabinet Office.
Straw, J. (1998) ‘Building Social Cohesion, Order and Inclusion in a Market Economy’,
Paper presented to the Nexus Conference on Mapping out the Third Way, 3 July.
Tam, H. (1998) Communitarianism: A New Agenda for Politics and Citizenship, Hound-
mills, Basingstoke: Macmillan.
Taylor, A. (1997) ‘ ‘‘Arm’s Length But Hands On’’. Mapping the New Governance: The
Department of National Heritage and Cultural Politics in Britain’, Public Administra-
tion, 75(3): 441–66.
80 Adam Crawford
Tilley, N. (1995) Thinking About Crime Prevention Performance Indicators, CPU Paper no.
57, London: Home Office.
Warner, N. (1998) ‘The Crime and Disorder Bill’, presentation to the ESRC Research
Seminar on Crime Prevention and Community Safety, King’s College, London, 27
March.
Weatheritt, M. (1993) ‘Measuring Police Performance: Accounting or Accountability?’,
in R. Reiner and S. Spencer (eds) Accountable Policing: Effectiveness, Empowerment
and Equity, London: Institute for Public Policy Research, 24–54.
Wilson, J. Q. and Kelling, G. (1982) ‘Broken Windows: The Police and Neighbourhood
Safety’, Atlantic Monthly, March: 29–37.
Young, J. (1992) ‘Ten Points of Realism’, in J. Young and R. Matthews (eds) Rethinking
Criminology: The Realist Debate, London: Sage, 24–68.
3 Evaluation and evidence-led
crime reduction policy and
practice
Nick Tilley
making use of evidence about inputs, outputs and outcomes (Leigh et al.
1999). An aspiration of the Crime Reduction Programme is to assemble
evidence of what works most cheaply to deliver effective crime reduction. This
is a critical agenda: it suggests a move from the use of professional authority or
of tradition as a warrant for action. Instead, policy and practice will be
dictated by hard evidence about what works and at what cost. The develop-
ments in relation to crime reduction are consonant with those presently
washing through the criminal justice system, and indeed through much social
policy and practice. Health, education, welfare, employment, economic regen-
eration, housing, and so on, are all being subjected to similar disciplines of
evaluation and evidence.
It clearly makes sense for evidence and evaluation to play a part in the devel-
opment of policy and practice. The issue that is addressed in this chapter,
however, is how they should do so. In the first part of this chapter I wish to
express doubts about four propositions:
In the second part of the chapter I present what I consider to be a ‘realistic’ way
of taking forward evidence-based policy and practice.
Four doubts
Methodological issues
All evidence, including that from recorded crime, crime surveys, records of
convicted offenders, accounts of emotional responses to crime, etc., is socially
constructed (see Bottomley and Pease 1986; Maguire 1997). Data on crime
reflect the way they have been assembled. This is not simply a matter of data
sometimes being improperly, and hence corrigibly, collected. Rather, data are
always a product of the social processes through which they are generated (see
Cicourel 1964). Moreover, the range of available evidence, however
constructed, is always circumscribed. Clearly, all facts about everything cannot
be assembled – data collection is, and has to be, selective (Ragin 1994). Policy
Evidence-led crime reduction policy 83
that is led by available evidence risks focusing on the easily measurable simply
because it is easily measurable.
Evidence does not speak for itself. Reasoning, imagination and values are
needed to draw conclusions from it (see Weber 1949). Evidence can be
collected and used to test, and potentially to falsify, conjectures about patterns,
though even here tested conjectures are not proved – they remain fallible
(Popper 1972) and are often disputed. Even in the less contentious world of
natural sciences and mathematics, it is only over time that a consensus may
emerge (Lakatos 1978).
If we assume that evidence does corroborate conjectures about patterns, this
does not mean that these patterns will be sustained over time. The social world is
subject to continuous change. One source of change is the understanding of actors
in the social world. In the case of crime prevention the preventer adapts to the
offender and the offender to the preventer. Each innovates and creates an
unstable environment for the other (Ekblom 1997). Policy and practice may need
to anticipate events on the basis of informed theory, rather than wait for evidence
that patterns are already present (see Foresight Crime Prevention Panel 2000).
Practical issues
Even if the methodological difficulties could be overcome, there are significant
practical obstacles to evidence-led policy and practice. No government can be
without a policy on crime; no criminal justice system can be suspended pending
evidence. Workers within the existing institutions cannot do nothing whilst
waiting for evidence to lead them. Much policy and practice has to proceed
without a research lead. Policies and practices cannot disregard public opinion
(Tilley and Laycock 2000). Politicians need to attend to the views of the elec-
torate, even when those views are not congruent with what the available
evidence suggests. Furthermore, elections create a periodic imperative for politi-
cians to show results. This, of course, opens a window for evidence to play a
part. It is liable, however, to lead to policies and practices offering relatively
quick fixes to take precedence over measures whose effect is only likely to be
felt in the longer term.
Established policies and practices will often constitute obstacles to evidence-
led changes, especially where there is already a public commitment to them, or
where there are vested interests in maintaining them (Weiss 1976).
away from the home for several hours. In simple misdemeanour domestic
assaults, cases were referred at random to one of the three responses. A six-
month follow-up checked the frequency and seriousness of any future
domestic violence. As ever, implementation and data collection were less
than perfect. Yet both official records and victim interviews showed that
repeat domestic violence was lowest for those where arrest had been the allo-
cated response. Official records revealed that there had been repeat incidents
in 10 per cent of arrest cases, in 19 per cent of the advice cases, and in 24 per
cent of the ‘send suspect away’ cases. On the basis of their findings, and
notwithstanding clearly stated caveats, the authors of the report note that:
‘the preponderance of evidence in the Minneapolis study strongly suggests
that the police should use arrest in most domestic violence cases’ (Sherman
and Berk 1984).
Domestic violence is of significant social concern and, unsurprisingly, on the
basis of the Minneapolis conclusions many US police departments adopted an
arrest policy. Sherman (1992) notes that 10 per cent of cities with a population
of over 100,000 made arrest the preferred police choice in 1994, 43 per cent in
1986, and 90 per cent in 1988. Further RCTs were conducted in other cities in
the US (Sherman 1992) with mixed results: in three cities mandatory arrest
increased repeat domestic violence, but in another three cities the level of
violence was reduced. This invites the question: why did the impact of manda-
tory arrest vary? The RCTs themselves can throw little light on this. They were
designed to see whether or not the initiatives worked in reducing repeat
domestic violence. Collectively they show that mandatory arrest can reduce
domestic violence, but it can also increase it. It is shown to be effective, but the
problem is that its effects vary.
Following the series of RCTs on mandatory arrest and domestic violence
there is some plausible post-hoc speculation to explain the mixed findings and
some (non-experimental) evidence is adduced for it. That is, it is believed that
arrest may anger unemployed people in marginal communities, whose disposi-
tion to violence is thereby increased. In middle-class communities, however, it
is believed that it shames people who are employed, and they are then chas-
tened and deterred (Sherman 1992). The structure of these explanations brings
out something of the weakness of the RCT method in so far as they highlight
the fact that the same measure may work in different ways and thus have
different effects according to variations in the circumstances of those involved.
The preoccupation of RCTs with net effects obscures this general feature of
interventions (see also Pawson and Tilley 1997: 34–46).
RCTs are not always practicable. If areas are the unit of analysis, for example,
it may not be possible to find and fund sufficient numbers for random allocation.
Random selection of experimental areas is not always politically viable.
Isolating/insulating members of experimental and control groups may not be
achievable. And so on. In these circumstances, the next best quasi-
experimental methods are conventionally preferred. These involve identifying
‘matched’ control and experimental groups to maximise their comparability.
86 Nick Tilley
This approach falls short of the standards of random allocation since there may
be significant differences between the experimental and the control groups,
which would automatically be eliminated through random allocation.
Ray Pawson and I have looked at the best British study undertaken using this
approach (for a detailed discussion see Pawson and Tilley 1994). The study, by
Bennett (1991), reports the evaluation of a police patrols initiative aiming to
reduce the fear of crime. This initiative was tried because some American evalu-
ation research had found that contact patrols had been associated with a fall in
fear of crime. Bennett reports on two experimental sites, in London and in
Birmingham, and two composite controls, chosen because of their high crime
rates and ‘visual indicators’ of disorder including graffiti, broken windows, crim-
inal damage and litter. He monitored implementation in the experimental areas
by measuring time spent by the police in the area and the contacts made by the
police with the public. He found no fall in fear of crime in the experimental
areas compared to the control areas. Other output and outcome measures, for
example those relating to recent sightings of police, perceptions of the area, and
informal social control practices, produced a mixed picture in the two sites. Thus
Bennett’s is a simple, if expensive, before-and-after experimental/composite
control comparison study with programme activity-level monitoring. It is a
classic of its type. Unfortunately, at its conclusion we know little of how the
programme was delivered or experienced. Encounters are more than just making
contact: what is said, who is spoken to, how interaction is managed are impor-
tant elements of a study, and Bennett’s report lacks this kind of information. Our
knowledge of the estates is reduced to their comparability in a number of superfi-
cial respects. The quality of community life and organisation is not considered
(except for an unremarked variation in measurements of ‘level of satisfaction’
and ‘sense of community’ in the two experimental sites, not relevant in what
were composite controls). There is no explanation for the variations in outcome,
nor for the differences between the British and American results. At the end of
the initiative we are little the wiser, other than knowing that in these two places
the intended fear reduction outcome was not achieved. We could certainly not
conclude that in another place police contacts patrol would not lead to a reduc-
tion in fear of crime.
The underlying problems here repeat those of the mandatory arrest series of
studies. How programmes have effects varies by the circumstances in which
they are introduced. This will mean that different outcomes will occur.
Sophisticated though they are in technical terms, Bennett’s quasi-experimental
methods railroad over this.
1997). Sherman and his associates use a scale from 5 to 1, where, notwith-
standing the disastrous effects they may have as evidenced by the mandatory
arrest for domestic violence débâcle, the highest score – ‘5’ – is given to RCTs.
The next ‘best’ studies most closely corresponding to RCTs are awarded 4, and
so on. The interventions are then classified under four headings: ‘what works’,
‘what doesn’t work’, ‘what’s promising’ and ‘what’s unknown’. The result is in
my opinion dangerous nonsense.
In recent accounts of this mega overview of evaluations, the Maryland group
has used the same headings, but added interesting comments, which seemingly
acknowledge some of the problems. For example, under ‘what works’, they say:
Here they recognise that the positive outcomes which programmes bring about
are contingent on context, that where programmes are found to have been
effective this does not mean that they can be expected to have the same results
elsewhere. The effectiveness is dependent on circumstances. The same results
will only be brought about in similar settings. This suggests that identifying
what is salient in the setting is crucial if transferable lessons are to be achieved.
What counts as a ‘similar’ setting is not self-evident. Here, then,‘what works’ is
adjusted and qualified to become ‘what works in (saliently) similar settings’.
Over the issue of ‘what doesn’t work’, however, context-dependency is curi-
ously forgotten. Under the heading ‘what doesn’t work’, the Maryland group says:
The weakest aspect of this classification (into ‘what works’ etc.) is that
there is no standard means of establishing external validity: exactly what
variations in program content and setting might affect the generalisability
of findings from evaluations. In the current state of science, that can be
accomplished only by the accumulation of many tests in many settings with
all major variations on the program theme. None of the programs reviewed
in this report have accumulated such a body of knowledge so far. The
conclusions drawn in the report about what works and what doesn’t should
be read, therefore, as more certain to the extent that all conditions of the
programs that were evaluated (e.g. population demographics, program
elements, social context) are replicated in other settings. The greater the
difference on such dimensions between evaluated programs and other
programs using the same name, the less certain the application of this
report’s conclusions must be.
(Sherman et al. 1998: 6)
This is fine as far as it goes, but it begs questions about salience of similarity and
difference. It is impossible to replicate ‘all conditions’. This would require the
same people, same houses, same time, same geography, same age, same external
political events, same offender populations, etc. Such a requirement is utopian
and therefore absurd. A judgement has to be made about what matters in terms
of similarity, both in terms of the intervention measure itself and in terms of the
contexts in which it is introduced. The key question, therefore, is: what ‘popu-
lation demographics, program elements, social context’, etc. need to be the
same, and why? And this is precisely the issue which the experimental approach
consistently misses or fudges.
Though the Maryland group do not say so in so many words, once it is
conceded that context is crucial for the effects produced, the only conclusion
that can be drawn from their review is that there is quite compelling
evidence that some measures can be associated with intended outcomes. In
relation to any given measure it is necessary to have only one strong study to
establish this. Any study which does not find that the intended outcome has
followed cannot conclude that the measure cannot produce that outcome.
What goes for intended outcomes goes, of course, also for unintended
outcomes of interventions. For the same reasons these too will be contextu-
ally contingent.
Instead of the bold headings used in the Maryland overview, which proclaim
‘what works’, ‘what doesn’t work’, ‘what’s promising’ and ‘what’s unknown’, the
authors’ concessions suggest that more accurate headings would be more
circumspect. They might read ‘what’s been found to work somewhere at some
time’, ‘what’s not yet been found to work anywhere, but might do so in the right
conditions’, ‘what seems to work somewhere’ and ‘what might work somewhere
at some time’. Less snappy to be sure, but less misleading, too. The worry is that
the Maryland study headlines will be taken at face value and that their proper
qualifications will be disregarded
Evidence-led crime reduction policy 89
Cost-benefit analysis
Cost-benefit analysis tries to standardise inputs and outcomes and to assign
them a common currency. In this way it is expected to provide an objective,
technical basis for choosing between competing priorities. It assumes that the
causal relationship between measures introduced and outcomes achieved can be
established and quantified with some confidence. This is clearly not generally
the case. For reasons already given, measures produce different outcomes across
space and time, and traditional evaluation methods have been unable
adequately to capture this.
What count as costs and benefits is not self-evident and what is included
may be quite narrowly circumscribed or it may be very wide-ranging. Inputs may
include: funds specifically allocated from the public purse for the programme;
funds allocated for a variety of purposes including those related to the
programme; programme-relevant private sector, individual and household
90 Nick Tilley
describe what they are expected to do. In the worst cases the recipe books will
reflect the prejudices of a central authority rather than the practitioner. In the
best cases they may reflect evidence about what has been shown to work in
some context for some subjects. Where untutored, counterproductive discretion
is used then recipe books will be useful and damage will be reduced by requiring
their employment. Where situations are relatively stable (as in the kitchen),
many benefits may follow from the creation of recipe books and requirements
that they be followed. McDonald’s illustrates well the profit to be made by stan-
dardisation. The company’s Hamburger University is presumably a model that
others in the business of vocational training for standardised service delivery
should follow.
Enforcing the adequate may dispense with the truly awful. It will also inhibit
the brilliant. McDonald’s may serve up something better than a dog’s dinner,
but it will be worse than the fashionable London restaurant the River Café.
Enforcing the adequate is in effect to engage in mediocratisation. Evaluators
steering us towards it belong to a new class of evidence-based mediocrats.
In the light of some experience of crime reduction efforts in Britain, there
are examples of dogs’ dinners (Tilley et al. 1999). There are also calls for recipe
books. One role for evaluators might be to contribute to recipe books (and to
help eliminate recipes that don’t work). Another is to help identify CMOCs
that policy-makers and practitioners can use intelligently to determine what
evidence suggests would make sense in differing conditions. Reflective practice
requires the intelligent deployment of principles or theories, which have been
refined through a series of evaluation studies. The elements of theory that will
be transferable/applicable relate to causal mechanisms which may be triggered
and/or inhibited in specified types of contexts to effect changes in behavioural
regularities in the intended direction. Evidence is assembled to arbitrate
between/refine theories for practitioners to apply reflectively.
There are real risks of standardisation and mediocratisation in crime reduction
and in evaluation studies designed to inform standardising and mediocratising
processes. The apparently competent may turn out to be dangerously incompe-
tent. One example of the dangers of crass mediocratisation in crime prevention
comes from just that use of mandatory arrest for domestic violence as a means to
reduce repeat incidents produced in the experiments discussed earlier in this
chapter. Indeed, on the basis of the Minneapolis experiment and the six subse-
quent studies, Sherman (1992) has concluded that mandatory arrest laws should
be repealed, and there should be ‘structured police discretion’. The mandatory
arrest for domestic violence research seems to suggest that informed discretion is
better than either ignorant discretion or substitution of rule-book recipes for it.
Conclusion
Evidence is useful for policy and practice: for informing decisions about priori-
ties and for identifying promising responses to deal with problems. Most social
scientists will welcome the present government’s expressed commitment to see
96 Nick Tilley
more use made of evidence. The evidence-led agenda, however, promises too
strong a role for evidence. Evidence is useful, of course, for checking ideas, but
it is good ideas that have survived critical scrutiny that are needed for effective
policy and practice. The orthodox experimental paradigm for evaluation asks
the wrong question and comes out with misleading and inconsistent answers.
Evaluation studies need to be realistic if they are to be informative. Such studies
require theoretical sensitivity as well as technical skills. The lessons they will
most usefully generate are not crass and unconditional suggestions that
measures will or will not work. What they will do is help develop tested theory
of what works for whom, in what circumstances, and this should help practi-
tioners and policy-makers think through their responses to issues and problems
with a better chance of producing their intended outcomes.
Even with this realistic understanding, however, there are crucial value ques-
tions at stake in policy and practice, and in the theories behind them, that
cannot be sidestepped by reference simply to the authority of empirical social
science.
References
Adams, J. (1995) Risk, London: UCL Press.
Atkins, S., Husain, S. and Storey, A. (1991) The Influence of Street Lighting on Crime,
Crime Prevention Unit Paper no. 28, London: Home Office.
Audit Commission (1999) Safety in Numbers: Promoting Community Safety, London:
Audit Commission.
Bennett, T. (1991) ‘The Effectiveness of a Police-initiated Fear-reducing Strategy’, British
Journal of Criminology, 31: 1–14.
Bottomley, K. and Pease, K. (1986) Crime and Punishment: Interpreting the Data, Milton
Keynes: Open University Press.
Chapman, T. and Hough, M. (1998) Evidence Based Practice: A Guide to Effective Practice,
London: Home Office.
Cicourel, A. (1964) Method and Measurement in Sociology, New York: Free Press.
Dhiri, S. and Brand, S. (1999) Analysis of Costs and Benefits: Guidance for Evaluators,
Crime Reduction Programme, Guidance Notes 1, London: Home Office.
Ekblom, Paul (1997) ‘Gearing Up Against Crime: A Dynamic Framework to Help
Designers Keep Up with the Adaptive Criminal in a Changing World’, International
Journal of Risk, Security and Crime Prevention, 2: 249–65.
Foresight Crime Prevention Panel (2000) Just Around the Corner: A Consultation Docu-
ment, London: Department of Trade and Industry.
Gendreau, P. and Ross, R. (1987) ‘The Revivification of Rehabilitation’, Justice
Quarterly, 4: 349–408.
Goldblatt, P. and Lewis, C. (1998) (eds) Reducing Offending: An Assessment of the
Research Evidence on Ways of Dealing with Offending Behaviour, Home Office Research
Study no. 187, London: Home Office.
Gould, S. J. (1981) The Mismeasure of Man, New York: Norton.
HMIC (1998) Beating Crime, London: Home Office.
Knuttson, J. (1984) Operation Identification: A Way to Prevent Burglaries? Report no. 14,
Stockholm: National Swedish Council for Crime Prevention.
Evidence-led crime reduction policy 97
Introduction
The recently published Home Office Statement of Purpose informs us that its
aim is:
To build a safe, just and tolerant society, in which the rights and responsi-
bilities of individuals, families and communities are balanced, and the
protection and security of the public are maintained.
(Home Office 1998)
This claim appears at first sight to be eminently commendable and there are few
in Britain who, if asked, would not identify with some if not all of these objec-
tives. However, as has been pointed out, rather than strive to develop a more
tolerant society, recent British government policies have been associated with
the ‘regimentation of opinion, moral closure, the repression of dissent and insti-
tutional intolerance’ (Hughes 1998). In contrast to the stated aim of promoting
greater levels of tolerance government policy has expressed a profound intoler-
ance for a range of activities including noisy neighbours, squeegee merchants,
youths hanging around the streets as well as other forms of ‘anti-social’
behaviour (Muncie 1999). Significantly, most of the activities which have
become the object of official intolerance in recent years are, in themselves, rela-
tively innocuous. Nevertheless, we are reminded that we are now engaged in a
‘war against crime’ and a ‘war against drugs’, although it is not clear whether
these are two fronts of the same war or two different wars. Either way, the
language of war presents offenders as the enemy to be defeated or dominated,
rather than helped or tolerated. At the same time the emphasis on zero toler-
ance, or selective intolerance as it has been more accurately described, has been
actively pursued by different agencies and given considerable official support.
Being ‘tough on crime and the causes of crime’ means, according to the Home
Secretary Jack Straw, the instigation of ‘tough and consistent prison sentences
for serious criminals’, and he insists that the ‘purpose of our criminal justice
system is to catch and punish offenders not to make excuses for them’ (Straw
1999). Within this punitive paradigm, the focus is largely on punishment, inca-
Crime, community safety and toleration 99
What is toleration?
‘Toleration’ is a term, which like ‘community’, is virtually devoid of any nega-
tive associations. Tolerance suggests respect for others, a recognition of
individual rights, as well as an acceptance of individual difference and social
diversity. It is, however, not an expression of benevolence, but rather it
embodies a sense of disapproval and implies a degree of suffering or sufferance
(Yovel 1998). The working definition of ‘tolerance’ which is widely used is:
‘The deliberate choice not to interfere with conduct or beliefs, with which one
disapproves’. In this way we might distinguish tolerance from indifference and
from those situations where there may be no real choice over whether to take
action or not. Thus in examining the exercise of toleration we need to know
100 Lynn Hancock and Roger Matthews
account for the reversals and ambiguities which have been identified in the
deployment of punishment historically and that it is not very useful in
explaining a number of contemporary developments, such as the decline of the
rehabilitative ideal, the emergence of the ‘new penology’ and the ‘new correc-
tionalism’ with its return to boot camps as well as the use of chain gangs
alongside the development of other ‘decivilising’ processes (Pratt 1998;
Vaughan 2000).
A more focused and grounded approach which has linked the issue of tolera-
tion to expressions of punitiveness has been presented by Leslie Wilkins and
Ken Pease (1987) who have suggested that one of the cultural determinants of
society’s penal climate is its relative egalitarianism. That is, they claim that the
greater the society’s tolerance of inequality, the more extreme the scale of
punishment is likely to be. Just as those at the top are seen to receive dispropor-
tionate rewards for their achievement so those at the bottom end of the social
scale who ‘fail’ are punished particularly severely. Thus, countries that have a
highly individualistic and competitive ethos, they argue, and in which there is a
high degree of inequality will tend to be comparatively severe in the use punish-
ment. Mobilising solid comparative evidence, however, to test this hypothesis is
difficult given the limited nature of the available data (Pease 1994). The
United States is the usual point of reference in debates over relative punitive-
ness, particularly since currently it has in excess of two million people
incarcerated. However, while there is evidence that the US tends to impose
longer sentences for a range of crimes, the use of incarceration itself is not, in
general, too dissimilar from European countries (Langham and Farrington
1998). Variations between European countries provide only limited support for
the hypotheses, while it is clear that the use of imprisonment, for example, in
different countries is also likely to be conditioned by other factors such as the
availability of non-custodial sanctions and the degree of social and political
stability. Nevertheless, it remains a relevant and plausible hypothesis.
One of the few attempts to analyse explicitly the role of tolerance in shaping
systems of punishment was the study by David Downes (1988) of the different
use of sanctions in England and Wales and in the Netherlands. Downes saw the
different approaches to the use of imprisonment and alternatives to custody in
these two countries as a function of ‘contrasts in tolerance’. He attributes the
relatively low use of incarceration in the post-war period in the Netherlands to
a greater level of tolerance than existed in England and Wales, although he
points out that Dutch tolerance does not involve a ‘blanket acceptance of all
manner of behaviour and opinion’. Rather, it is a selective strategy based on a
‘politics of accommodation’ which relies less on scapegoating and the exclusion
of deviants and instead provides a more integrative approach. Herman Franke
(1990) in a critical review of Downes’ Contrasts in Tolerance, emphasises that
tolerance is not of one piece and therefore it is inappropriate to talk about a
‘culture of tolerance’. Instead, there is a need, he argues, to examine the history,
the political context, the composition and orientation of criminal justice agen-
cies as well as the role of the media in influencing the exercise of tolerance.
Crime, community safety and toleration 103
If we are correct in our claim that toleration is germane to the whole crimi-
nological enterprise, then why should it be that criminologists have historically
been reticent to engage with this concept? We can suggest three main reasons.
First, the issue of toleration is seen to be located in political philosophy which is
a discipline that remains relatively unexplored by criminologists. Although it is
the case that much of the more interesting criminological work in recent years
has been that which has vicariously lifted ideas and materials from other disci-
plines – particularly sociology, urban studies and cultural studies – successful
forays into the world of political philosophy have been less frequent. Second,
toleration does not lend itself easily to direct measurement, since its exercise
involves inaction as well as action. Since toleration is also a relational, complex
and multi-faced activity its study requires a more imaginative and sophisticated
form of analysis than is normally undertaken by criminologists. Third, an exam-
ination of toleration is likely to draw researchers into the perplexing areas of
norm creation, systems of classification, and probably the area in which they
feel most uncomfortable – morality (Bauman 1995; Cohen 1979).
Why tolerate?
It is clear that whatever one’s beliefs are that one cannot express intolerance
towards everything one dislikes or disapproves of. Toleration, therefore, is
necessarily selective. The critical issues are how toleration is constructed,
changed and expressed. Strategic decisions are often made in relation to prag-
matic and moral considerations. The problem of analysis is that pragmatism and
moralism tend to be interconnected. The main pragmatic consideration, often
suggested by utilitarians, is that the benefits of toleration may outweigh the
harms. Toleration may also enable us to mitigate or avoid damaging social
conflict. The difficult question is, however, how do we make a distinction
between acts which should be prevented and punished and those that should be
permitted and tolerated. Harm itself is not a sufficient criterion of intolerance
since the notion of harm is open to wide interpretation and comes in a multi-
tude of different forms, while the decision about whether and how to respond
will be conditioned by a range of other moral and practical considerations.
Primary amongst these considerations is the relation between the activities
to be tolerated and the level of social support which is available. According to
Richard Taub and his colleagues (Taub et al. 1984) in their study of community
transition in Chicago, the exercise of tolerance is conditioned by the quality
and the quantity of local amenities. The factors, they suggest, that will influ-
ence the capacity of different individuals and groups to tolerate different
activities will include the organisation and density of housing, the seriousness of
other local problems and the range and quality of amenities. It is also suggested
that the level of tolerance is not just a function of the level of absolute depriva-
tion in an area but often a consequence of relative deprivation. That is,
intolerance is seen to arise from the gap between what people have got and
what they expect (Campbell 1991). The focus on relative deprivation may go
some way to explain the apparent paradox which has been reported that it is
those groups located near the top as well as those at the bottom of the social
scale who exhibit the greatest level of punitiveness (Brillon 1988).
In everyday discussions of toleration reference is often made to ‘thresholds’
and to ‘the limits of tolerance’, which suggests that there are critical points in
the exercise of tolerance at which a qualitative change occurs. In this point of
transition it would seem that activities which were once tolerated take on a
different significance. The implications of this observation are that it is not
only the number of incidents which is important but the point at which a
Crime, community safety and toleration 107
threshold of toleration is crossed. Thus it may be the case that seven or eight
prostitutes working in a certain locality may be acceptable and although local
residents may not particularly approve of the activity they are willing to tolerate
it. However, at a certain point the visibility of, say, twelve women regularly
working on the streets transforms the nature of the activity such that it is seen
to ‘swamp’ or change the neighbourhood in a way that local residents are no
longer willing to tolerate, and they call on the authorities to do something
about it. This scenario appears by and large to have occurred in various parts of
Britain during the 1980s, and although the relevant authorities were slow to
respond to growing public pressure many residents groups took it upon them-
selves to deal with the problem (Matthews 1993). The other important
implications of this observation are that firstly we need to give greater attention
to the impact of crime and disorder in different areas and that, second, we need
to identify the thresholds of tolerance. In this way we might become less
concerned with the rise and fall of recorded offences – or with strategies which
simply aim to reduce crime and disorder or other problems by an arbitrary
amount – and instead develop a greater regional and local sensitivity to varia-
tions in the thresholds of toleration.
shapes local crime rates by defining what is acceptable behaviour and by estab-
lishing normative structures which guide both the definitions of ‘problematic
situations’ and how they are categorised. A communitarian notion of toleration
is bound up with the defence of the community and the decision of whether to
exercise tolerance or not will be conditioned by how valuable the community
under threat is. Therefore, actions which may appear to be fairly innocuous can
have a cumulative impact on the community and consequently can become the
object of intolerance. However, in promoting intolerance the communitarian
has to give due consideration to the level of harm inflicted as well as the
capacity of the community to absorb or deflect these ‘anti-social’ activities as
well as considering the consequences of stigmatising or marginalising the
offender since this may cumulatively weaken the community. It is also necessary
for the communitarian to distinguish between interventions which are practi-
cally designed to improve community safety and those interventions which are
more symbolic and are designed to regenerate moral obligations between citi-
zens (Crisp 1992; Gutman 1985).
In general, the communitarian critique can be seen as providing a corrective
to certain liberal conceptions of the autonomous self-propelling individual,
although liberalism has not been without its defenders (Kymlicka 1989). As
Allen Buchanan (1989) has pointed out, this ongoing debate between liber-
alism and communitarianism has operated on a number of different levels and
that in trying to think through these important issues it is useful to distinguish
between radical, moderate and cautious communitarians. It is only in its radical
version that communitarianism rejects outright the significance of individual
rights and the liberal conception of freedom. In its more moderate version it
concedes the importance of certain rights, but denies the priority which the
liberal attributes to them. In its more cautious variant it urges those who value
community not to abandon the framework of individual rights, but rather to
appreciate the role which individual rights can play in protecting communities
under certain historical conditions. In opposition to the radical communitarian
he argues that the defence of individual rights of association, to pursue religious
beliefs and the right to political participation need to be defended and that:
Although research has shown that community organising in some locations can
make a difference (Sampson et al. 1997), the ability of residential communities
to withstand the impact of different forms of crime and incivilities will depend
in large part on the available resources and their access to support networks
(Cullen 1994; Matthews 1992).
If it is the case that the cautious communitarian can establish some degree of
compromise with the liberals over rights, there still remains a major split
between those communitarians who prioritise the community and community
controls and those liberals who see crime control and community safety as an
individual responsibility within a market-driven framework. This tension is
located at the heart of current government thinking on ‘law and order’. In the
Crime, community safety and toleration 113
Conclusion
In general, a number of social and political commentators seem to agree that
toleration is an important element in the functioning of liberal democracies. But
debates continue about where to draw the line between tolerance and intoler-
ance and how such ‘moral’ decisions are linked to images of the ‘good society’.
Increasingly, criminologists have become aware that toleration plays an impor-
tant, if not pivotal, role in the construction of crime and in influencing crime
control policies. As we move into a situation in which the public are an increas-
ingly important point of reference in providing information, co-operation and
legitimacy within a restructured system of regulation a greater awareness of what
the public want and what they are willing to accept has gained greater promi-
nence. Alongside these organisational imperatives there have been growing
demands for security from different social groups and a greater willingness to
participate, at some level, in the development of community safety.
These developments have opened the door to greater community involve-
ment in decision-making and to the introduction of new forms of accountability.
The shifting responsibility for crime control and community safety to local
authorities has been identified as a ‘sea change’ or a ‘watershed’ in policy devel-
opment in Britain, introducing new forms of governance (Crawford 1997).
There is now a clear sense of the limits of the nation-state and that there is no
way back to the centralised forms of regulation which characterised previous
periods. The watch words are now diversity, flexibility, cost-effectiveness and
risk management.
Crime, community safety and toleration 115
re-examination of crime and control and this in turn, we have suggested, will
involve the mobilisation of certain basic organising and sensitising concepts
such as toleration.
References
Bauman, Z. (1995) Life in Fragments: Essays in Postmodern Morality, Oxford: Blackwell.
Bayley, D. (1994) Police for the Future, New York: Oxford University Press.
Box, S. and Hale, C. (1986) ‘Unemployment, Crime and Imprisonment: The Enduring
Problem of Prison Overcrowding’, in R. Matthews and J. Young (eds) Confronting
Crime, London: Sage.
Braithwaite, J. (1989) Crime, Shame and Reintegration, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
—— and Pettit, P. (1990) Not Just Deserts: A Republican Theory of Criminal Justice,
Oxford: Clarendon.
Brillon, Y. (1988) ‘Punitiveness, Status and Ideology in Three Canadian Provinces’, in
N. Walker and M. Hough (eds) Public Attitudes to Sentencing, Aldershot: Gower.
Buchanan, A. (1989) ‘Assessing the Communitarian Critique of Liberalism’, Ethics, 99
(July): 852–82.
Burney, E. (1999) Crime and Banishment, Winchester: Waterside Press.
Campbell, A. (1991) The Sense of Well Being in America, New York: McGraw Hill.
Cohen, M. (1998) Culture of Intolerance, New Haven: Yale University Press.
Cohen, S. (1979) ‘Guilt Justice and Tolerance: Some Old Concepts for a New Crimi-
nology’, in D. Downes and P. Rock (eds) Deviant Interpretations, Oxford: Martin
Robertson.
Crawford, A. (1997) The Local Governance of Crime: Appeals to Community and Partner-
ships, Oxford: Clarendon.
—— (1998) Crime Prevention and Community Safety, London: Longman.
Crisp, R. (1992) ‘Communitarianism and Toleration’, in J. Horton and P. Nicholson
(eds) Toleration: Philosophy and Practice, Aldershot: Avebury.
Cullen, F. (1994) ‘Social Support as an Organising Concept for Criminology’, Justice
Quarterly, 11(4): 527–59.
Dennis, N. (1997) (ed.) Zero Tolerance: Policing in a Free Society, London: Institute of
Economic Affairs.
Doob, A. and Roberts, J. (1988) ‘Public Punitiveness and Public Knowledge of the Facts:
Some Canadian Surveys’, in N. Walker and M. Hough (eds) Public Attitudes to
Sentencing, Aldershot: Gower.
Downes, D. (1988) Contrasts in Tolerance: Post-war Penal Policy in the Netherlands and in
England and Wales, Oxford: Clarendon.
Dworkin, R. (1977) Taking Rights Seriously, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
Elias, N. (1994) The Civilising Process, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Etzioni, A. (1993)The Spirit of Community, New York: Crown Publishers.
—— (1997) The New Golden Rule, London: Profile Books.
Foucault, M. (1979) History of Sexuality: Volume 1, Allen Lane: Penguin.
Franke, H. (1990) ‘Dutch Tolerance: Facts and Fables’, British Journal of Criminology,
30(1): 81–94.
—— (1992) ‘The Rise and Decline of Solitary Confinement’, British Journal of Crimi-
nology, 32(2): 125–43.
Crime, community safety and toleration 117
Fraser, N. (1997) Justice Interruptus: Critical Reflections on the Post-Socialist Condition, New
York: Routledge.
Garland, D. (1990) Punishment and Modern Society, Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
—— (1996) ‘The Limits of the Sovereign State: Strategies of Control in Contemporary
Society’, British Journal of Criminology, 36(4): 445–71.
Giddens, A. (1998) The Third Way, Cambridge: Polity Press.
Goffman, E. (1963) Stigma: Notes on the Management of a Spoiled Identity, Englewood
Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Gutman, A. (1985) ‘Communitarian Critics of Liberalism’, Philosophy and Public Affairs,
14(3): 308–22.
Hancock, L. (2001) Community, Crime and Disorder: Responses to Change in Urban Neigh-
bourhoods, London: Palgrave.
Harrison, R. (1992) ‘Tolerating the Offensive’, in J. Horton and P. Nicholson (eds) Toler-
ation: Philosophy and Practice, Aldershot: Avebury.
Herbst, S. (1998) Reading Public Opinion, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Hirst, P. (1997) From Statism to Pluralism, London: UCL Press.
Home Office (1998) Annual Report, Cm. 3908, London: HMSO.
Honneth, A. (1995) The Struggle for Recognition, Cambridge: Polity Press.
Hope, T. (1995) ‘Community Crime Prevention’, in M. Tonry and D. Farrington (eds)
Building a Safer Society: Strategic Approaches to Crime Prevention, volume 19, Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Horton, J. and Nicholson, P. (1992) (eds) Toleration: Philosophy and Practice, Aldershot:
Avebury.
Hough, M. and Roberts, J. (1999) ‘Sentencing Trends in Britain: Public Knowledge and
Public Opinion’, Punishment and Society, 1(1): 11–27.
Hughes, G. (1998) Understanding Crime Prevention, Buckingham: Open University Press.
Jessop, B. (1994) ‘Post-Fordism and the State’, in A. Amin (ed.) Post- Fordism: A Reader,
Oxford: Blackwell.
Johnston, L. (1996) ‘What is Vigilantism?’, British Journal of Criminology, 36(2): 220–36.
Kymlicka, W. (1989) Liberalism, Community and Culture, Milton Keynes: Open Univer-
sity Press.
Langham, P. and Farrington, D. (1998) Crime and Justice in the United States and in
England and Wales, 1981–96, Bureau of Justice Statistics, Washington DC: US
Department of Justice.
Lea, J. (1992) ‘The Analysis of Crime’, in J. Young and R. Matthews (eds) Rethinking
Criminology: The Realist Debate, London: Sage.
McIntyre (1981) After Virtue, London: Duckworth.
Maffesoli, M. (1996) The Time of the Tribes: The Decline of Individualism in Mass Society,
London: Sage.
Marcuse, H. (1965) ‘Repressive Tolerance’, in R. P. Wolff, B. M. Moore Jr. and H.
Marcuse (eds) A Critique of Pure Tolerance, Boston: Beacon Press.
Matthews, R. (1992) ‘Replacing Broken Windows: Crime Incivilities and Urban
Change’, in R. Matthews and J. Young (eds) Issues in Realist Criminology, London:
Sage.
—— (1993) Kerb-Crawling, Prostitution and Multi-Agency Policing, Paper 43 Crime
Prevention Unit Series, London: Home Office.
—— and Young, J. (1992) ‘Reflections on Realism’, in J. Young and R. Matthews (eds)
Rethinking Criminology: The Realist Debate, London: Sage.
118 Lynn Hancock and Roger Matthews
Walzer, M. (1983) Spheres of Justice: A Defence of Pluralism and Equality, New York: Basic
Books.
Wilkins, L. and Pease, K. (1987) ‘Public Demand for Punishment’, International Journal of
Sociology and Social Policy 7(3): 16–29.
Young, I. (1990) ‘The Ideal of Community and the Politics of Difference’, in L.
Nicholson (ed.) Feminism/Postmodernism, New York: Routledge.
Young, J. (1999) The Exclusive Society, London: Sage.
Young, W. and Brown, M. (1993) ‘Cross National Comparisons of Imprisonment’, in M.
Tonry (ed.) Crime and Justice: A Review of Research, volume 17, Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
Yovel, Y. (1998) ‘Tolerance as Grace and as Rightful Recognition’, Social Research, 65(4):
897–921.
5 ‘Broken Windows’ and the
culture wars
A response to selected critiques
George L. Kelling
Introduction
Since the publication of my article, ‘Broken Windows: The Police and
Neighborhood Safety’, in the journal Atlantic Monthly in 1982, it has caused
considerable consternation in much sociological, legal and criminological litera-
ture.1 Its main ideas, however, are widely accepted by policy-makers in most cities
in the United States. These include most police and criminal justice agencies,
neighbourhood organisations and local political leaders – regardless of their
ethnicity, race or political orientation. Intellectually and politically, ‘Broken
Windows’ grew out of the centre right. Professor James Q. Wilson, a well-known
neo-conservative, co-authored the original ‘Broken Windows’ article. New York’s
Mayor Rudolph Giuliani, also centre right, and Commissioner William Bratton
gave ‘Broken Windows’ unprecedented publicity when it was implemented as
policy and practice in New York City. The Manhattan Institute, a thriving conser-
vative New York urban think-tank, is one of its strongest intellectual strongholds.
This chapter argues that the middle/left liberal criminological establishment has
been held captive for decades by the radical individualism of the far left. The
consequence has been that liberals, traditionally champions of cities, have aban-
doned them. The stridency of the far-left attack on ‘Broken Windows’, indeed its
nastiness, signifies its desperation. It also signifies the intellectual stinginess of the
near left, as it attempts to reposition itself in relation to the issue of disorder.
‘Broken Windows’
‘Broken Windows’ is a metaphor. It argues that just as a broken window left
untended is a sign that nobody cares and leads to more damage, so disorder left
untended also signifies that nobody cares and leads to fear of crime, more
serious crime and urban flight and decay. The original article, and subsequent
writings, have put forward the following points:
evolved in the United States during the mid- and late 1980s and, for me at
least, are inseparable from this context.
Professor Wilson and I continue to be pleasantly surprised by the original
article’s ‘legs’. It has been reprinted often, is available on the Internet, has been
reported by Atlantic Monthly as one of its most popular articles, has been trans-
lated into several languages, has engendered countless ‘Broken Windows’ police
programmes, and has been applied to probation, education, health and other
professional endeavours. Most visibly, it has been associated with the historic
reductions in crime in New York City. Both Mayor ‘Rudy’ Giuliani and his first
Police Commissioner, William Bratton, are outspoken advocates of a ‘Broken
Windows’ approach to policing. Fixing Broken Windows is now being translated
into Polish, Portuguese and Spanish.
The original article also spawned immediate and often vitriolic attacks. The
National Institute of Justice (the research arm of the US Department of Justice)
issued a request for a proposal the same year that ‘Broken Windows’ was
published to test the article’s thesis that crime was linked to disorder. After the
research was designed, the US Attorney General quashed it as being too contro-
versial. Professor Samuel Walker published the first academic critique in 1984.
Others followed. Former Kansas City, Missouri and San Jose, California Police
Chief Joseph McNamara has been the most vitriolic practitioner opposing
‘Broken Windows’, primarily on radio and television talk shows and in news-
paper op-ed editorials (McNamara 1997). Among other allegations, ‘Broken
Windows’ supposedly gives rise to racism, ‘wars’ on the poor, police brutality
and criminalises the homeless. At least one author has labelled James Q. Wilson
and myself as racists – ‘aversive’ racists at that (Stewart 1998).2 These critiques
have not exactly been in lightweight journals. They include the Yale and
University of Michigan law journals, both representing prestigious law schools
in the US (Harcourt 1998; Stewart 1998).
On reflection, the academic and professional assaults are not surprising.
Certainly Professor Wilson foresaw them. By the early 1980s, his neo-conser-
vatism had already alienated many criminologists and he predicted that merely
by writing with him I would fall under academic suspicion.3 Professor Wilson’s
reputation notwithstanding, ‘Broken Windows’ is controversial in at least two
overlapping yet distinct respects. First, it directly challenges the reigning ‘root
causes’ of criminal justice ideology – not surprising given the traditional liber-
alism of sociology/criminology. Second, it runs head-on into the ‘culture war’
raging over the competing demands of individual rights and community interests.
Criminal justice
The reigning criminal justice ideology in the US is a direct outgrowth of
President Lyndon Johnson’s 1960s crime commission and its 1967 report, The
Challenge of Crime in a Free Society. A conceptual offshoot of the ‘War on
Poverty’, Challenge emphasises the tragic consequences of racism, poverty and
social injustice and links them to crime, social disorder and violence
‘Broken Windows’: a response to critiques 123
(President’s Commission, 1967). These broad social problems are the ‘root
causes’ of crime. Not surprisingly, their amelioration is fundamental to
preventing crime and violence. Police, prosecutors, corrections and criminal
courts comprise a criminal justice system whose purpose is to process offenders –
murderers, rapists, robbers, burglars and others who commit serious offences.
Minor offences and ‘victimless’ crimes should be actually or virtually decrimi-
nalised to end the ‘overreach’ of the criminal law.
The most obvious policy implications of the report are, of course, that basic
structural changes are required in American society to reduce crime: wealth
redistributed, racism ended and social injustices rectified. Beyond this, the
report has two major sets of recommendations. First, the relationship between
criminal justice agencies and minorities must be improved, partially by ensuring
that minorities are represented among police, prosecutors, corrections and
courts. Second, the criminal justice system should be improved through
enhanced planning, technology and modernised administrative processes
(recruitment, training, supervision, etc.).
It is impossible to exaggerate to non-Americans the extent to which these
ideas permeate criminology, criminal justice academic programmes and criminal
justice practice in the US. ‘Root causes’ became conventional wisdom, in
popular as well as professional culture. At its extreme, the premise is stretched
to a syllogism: crime is caused by poverty, racism and social injustice; police can
do nothing about these problems; ergo, police can do little, if anything, about
crime. The business of justice agencies is processing cases. To the extent that,
say, police can have an impact on crime, it is by being the front end of the
‘system’: arresting serious offenders and forwarding them for processing.
One can be concerned about the problems of poverty, racism and social
injustice and still be unhappy with this formulation. Indeed, one can find much
in The Challenge of Crime in a Free Society with which to agree: its calls for
lawfulness in the justice process; the urgency with which it calls for improving
the relationship between criminal justice agencies and minority communities;
and its mandate that minorities must be recruited, hired and promoted in crim-
inal justice. In each of these areas, the document was genuinely and
appropriately revolutionary (President’s Commission, 1967).
As a primer of crime control, however, the President’s report was a disaster.
The ‘root causes’ assumption has never stood up to rigorous analysis. Crime
varies too much by time, demography, economy, region and country to be
attributed to such structural characteristics. Moreover, the ‘system’ metaphor is
so entrenched and self-apparently ‘true’ that it thwarts careful scrutiny about
how agencies actually function. The reality that criminal justice agencies,
almost literally, never talk to each other and often work at cross-purposes is
obfuscated by the power of the metaphor. The idea that such agencies could
plan together was, at best, ahead of its time and remains optimistic today –
although there now are some wonderful examples of what can result when they
do (Kennedy 1997). Also, the report looked solely to government to solve the
crime problem by declaring a ‘war on crime’ – akin and complementary to the
124 George L. Kelling
United States’ other domestic war, the ‘war on poverty’. The private sector,
funding and sponsoring by far the largest crime control capacity in the United
States, is completely disregarded in the report. Likewise, citizens and commu-
nity organisations are relegated to consumers of professional crime control
agents: they are to be good observers, reporters and witnesses – and to increase
their financial support of criminal justice agencies. Finally, most of the ‘system
improvement’ agenda – improved recruiting, training, supervision, co-ordina-
tion and technology – has been on the table since the 1920s in the US.
Regardless, ‘root causes’ ideology largely held crime prevention hostage until
well into the 1990s in the US.
This shift towards unfettered individualism affected every facet of personal and
public life: the family, church, education, sex roles, medicine, housing, mental
illness, law, commerce, drug policy, and so on. But nowhere are these competing
demands – between individual rights and community interests – more
discernible than in matters of criminal justice policy. Regarding ‘serious’ crime –
murder, rape, assault, robbery and burglary – criminologists/sociologists have
quarrels, however, a broad consensus exists that these crimes need to be taken
seriously. While issues like sentencing, the death penalty, the transfer of juve-
niles to adult court, and others are debated heatedly, at least agreement exists
that felonies should be taken seriously.
For minor offences – begging, prostitution, public drinking, graffiti, and so on
– the cleavage is yawning. The far left – including a good share of sociologists,
criminologists and civil rights lawyers and advocates – not only does not want
‘Broken Windows’: a response to critiques 125
rules, and regulations of civil contact between people are facilitated and,
when these social control functions break down, to assist restoration of
street equilibrium.
(Kelling 1978: 111)4
next morning and the matter would be dismissed. From the point of view of
most police the matter had been handled: a gun was confiscated and the person
spent the night in jail (Kelling 1999).
Bratton, however, saw the matter differently in the subway and, later, city-
wide:
Discovering that such a high percentage of fare beaters was carrying weapons
was one of those ‘eureka moments’. And, in Jack Maple’s fertile street-smart
mind, arresting someone with a weapon provided additional possibilities. Did
the person have more guns? Where did he get the gun? Who else had guns and
was carrying them? As Bratton put it when referring to the impact this had on
the subway: ‘After a while, the bad guys wised up and began to leave their
weapons at home’ (Bratton 1998: 154).
The true potential of this finding, however, was only to become apparent
after Bratton became Commissioner in New York City. With over 2,000
murders a year, most of them committed with handguns, New York City was in
the midst of a bloodbath during the late 1980s and early 1990s. And New York
City wasn’t alone: name the American city and violence was spinning out of
control. Something had to be done about gun carrying, but just what basically
stymied police, policy analysts and researchers. Research had been largely
fruitless. Sherman, Shaw and Rogan, for example, published the ‘Kansas City
Gun Experiment’ in 1995. Funded by the National Institute of Justice, this
study did little more than refine and endorse conventional police practice: use
of traffic stops to search cars when officers felt their safety was threatened;
asking citizens to submit to voluntary searches of their cars; looking into
stopped vehicles for weapons; and other forms of consent searches including,
for example, glove compartments (Sherman et al., 1995). In the meantime,
criminological pundits were loudly proclaiming that we had not seen the worst
violence yet: a second ‘baby boom’ cohort would soon turn loose a new gener-
ation of predators.
But in this context, Bratton and Maple saw investigative opportunities in
police order maintenance activities – specifically about the issue of gun
carrying. Despite the epidemic of gun violence, Jack Maple notes the NYPD’s
lackadaisical attitude about confiscating guns:
128 George L. Kelling
Taking guns off the street didn’t seem to interest the [detective] squads at
all. During the previous year patrol made almost 9,000 arrests for crimes in
which a firearm was confiscated, but the entire Detective Bureau developed
only four confidential informants to help identify gun sellers and took, as a
result, fewer than fifty additional guns off the street.
(Maple 1999: 26)
But Maple was not just concerned about special or detective units. ‘All …
arrests made must be viewed as opportunities to do more debriefings’ (Maple
1999: 26). Based on the subway experience this principle, of course, included
arrests for minor offences. Someone arrested for public urination? Question him.
Does he have a weapon? Where did he get it? Does he know someone who
carries a weapon? Where did that person get the weapon? For Maple, quality of
life arrests were a potential treasure trove, not just for guns, but for other forms
of contraband as well.
And this, of course, brings us to a critical issue, both about the whole idea
of ‘Broken Windows’ and the current political and professional controversies in
New York City. An important serendipitous finding – that many fare beaters
were felons carrying weapons – added a new dimension to the ‘Broken
Windows’ idea. Probably I should not have been surprised. Street cops prob-
ably could have told me about this all along and they might have, however, it
just never registered. Nonetheless, police leaders expanded order maintenance.
Heretofore, police saw it as a means to reduce citizen fear of crime and prevent
crime by restoring order, empowering citizens and maintaining neighbour-
hood/community standards. Now, police understood it to be an investigatory
tool as well, not the least for getting weapons off the street.
In the context of the national furore over gun-related violence and 2,200
murders a year in New York City – most of them with handguns – this was a
big-time finding. It was highly dramatised in 1996 after a man brutally
assaulted three women near Central Park. He was identified when fingerprints
at the scene of the assault matched those taken earlier when he was arrested
for fare beating. Maintaining order gained new meaning for line cops: it was
not just a matter of dealing with obstreperous citizens and unpleasant condi-
tions; it was an opportunity to apprehend some serious offenders. Like traffic
enforcement earlier, where stops had potential beyond maintaining safe and
orderly automobile and pedestrian movement, order maintenance put police
into contact with serious trouble-makers and gave them opportunities to check
for weapons, drugs and other contraband. But like traffic stops as well, it
opened new possibilities of excesses in the name of contraband reduction,
especially guns.
In the New York City context of the early 1990s, it was a small step from
order maintenance activities as part of routine police activities to ‘stop and
frisk’ by special anti-crime units attempting to reduce gun carrying. Guns were a
major problem; disorderly behaviour, like traffic offences before them, provided
the legal basis to stop persons on the street. The focus, however, shifted from a
‘Broken Windows’: a response to critiques 129
myself. The far left’s animosity towards Giuliani is so rabid, and their anti-police
feelings so passionate, that one would hardly hope for a careful reading of the
text. Moreover, I had no right to be surprised. I had entered the political arena
by authoring an op-ed piece in the Wall Street Journal about the incident.
Nor do I expect much quarter from civil rights and advocacy lawyers in the
central arena in which ‘Broken Windows’ and order maintenance issues are
being fought: the courts. It is in the nature of the advocacy process, really an
extension of political processes, that briefs and writs will contain misrepresenta-
tions like ‘criminalising the poor’ and ‘police harassment of minorities’ in
litigation when discussing order maintenance and ‘Broken Windows’.
I had expected something else, however, from academic critics writing in,
say, prestigious academic journals like The American Sociological Review. Before I
say what I expected in academic circles, let me indicate what I had not
expected. I had not expected that people would agree with me or would not see
potentially negative consequences of ‘Broken Windows’ policies. My hope,
instead, was for ‘second order agreement’. By second order agreement, I mean
that people who disagree put forward opposing points of view accurately, if not
convincingly.10 Most academic critiques of ‘Broken Windows’, even the best,
have not been characterised by such intellectual forthrightness nor, I would
add, honesty.
I have responded to many of the more outrageous misrepresentations (‘aver-
sive racist’, etc.; see Kelling 1998). Moreover, I have ignored many criminological
ditherings (Foucault and techniques of punishment, and whether or not ‘Broken
Windows’ constitutes a legitimate ‘theory’). My interest here is in what is
happening in liberal/left criminology and why ‘Broken Windows’ sticks in their
craw as much as it does.
The fact is that liberals lost cities – politically and intellectually. In the post-
1960s era, liberals, including most American criminologists, simply walked away
from disorder, fear of crime and serious crime and their impact on neighbour-
hoods and communities. Early twentieth-century Progressives/liberals were the
great defenders of public spaces and neighbourhood interests. They mapped an
agenda of what was wrong with cities and took concrete steps to remedy the
wrongs. Now, political conservatives reign in most American cities.11
Hunter University Professor Fred Siegel has written about the transformation
of liberals:
process rights. But like every revolution, it had its victims. In the new
climate in which drug use was redefined as a ‘victimless crime’ and purity of
legal procedure took precedence over the safety of the community, people
who had once been shackled by the inequities of the law found themselves
trapped by a pervasive lawlessness. Delivered into the tender mercies of the
streets, the most vulnerable among us have suffered immeasurably.
(Siegel 1992: 37)
Nowhere did liberals lose touch as badly as in crime control policy. The
liberal crime control agenda, stuck as it was in ‘root causes’, was completely
overwhelmed by conservatives, especially in sentencing policy. ‘Truth in
sentencing’ and ‘three strikes and you’re out’ carried the day in policy innova-
tions. The major political crime control battles raged over gun control (liberals
for, conservatives against), capital punishment (conservatives for, liberals
against) and drug legalisation (a funny mix on each side) – all largely symbolic
issues that said little or nothing about what could be done today to prevent
crime. In the meantime, neighbourhood residents could tell you that the kids
who were stealing hubcaps from cars would soon be stealing the cars if some-
thing wasn’t done pretty soon. They could tell you as well that if you made the
cars theft-proof, some of the youths would find a way to steal them anyway –
and they did. They simply hijacked them at gunpoint, increasing the danger.
Police and criminal justice agencies in Newark, New Jersey, for example,
became such a joke that kids would steal cars and, to provoke police who were
forbidden to chase them, bump into police cars to ‘air-bag’ them in the hope
that police would get angry enough to get into ‘hot pursuits’. It was a game:
even if they were arrested, nothing would happen. In a world without mean-
ingful sanctions for minor offences, some youths – not most, but a lot – spun
out of control and by the time they were entering their late teens were starting
to accumulate felony records. And then it was too late. ‘Three strikes you’re
out’ and ‘truth in sentencing’ ended the joke, but only after innumerable minor
offences and many other serious crimes. Now, liberals like to castigate conser-
vatives and ‘authoritarian elements’ for the tragically high imprisonment rate
in the US, but liberals should be looking to themselves as well to attribute
blame.
Regarding police, the liberal agenda paid little attention to their crime
control potentials – after all, since crime was linked to structural features of our
society what could police do except process offenders? Community policing, at
least in its early days in the 1980s, was widely viewed as ‘soft’ policing –
providing services and seeking community approval – to such an extent that it
was widely rejected by most practising police officers. Generally, criminological
liberals lauded community policing because it was ‘nice’ policing characterised
by great concern for establishing good relationships to communities and neigh-
bourhoods. Community policing might enhance criminal investigation as a
consequence of its access to information; however, the inherent aggressiveness
of community policing was largely lost on most criminologists. Traditional
132 George L. Kelling
policing was inherently passive and non-intrusive: patrol, wait for a crime to
happen, and then respond. The response might appear forceful – fast car, lights,
siren – however, its premises and execution were reactive. Community policing
was far more intrusive and aggressive than traditional policing. More crimes
came under the purview of police (minor offences as well as serious), their
source of authority was broadened to include civil as well as criminal authority,
and police got out of their cars to ‘re-police’ public spaces, streets and neigh-
bourhoods. Nonetheless, until very recently, the agenda of most criminologists
for police was limited to civilian review, corruption control and reduction of
abuse – all focusing on what police should not do rather than what they should
do. Even problem solving, an enormously powerful, and inherently aggressive,
tool first articulated by Herman Goldstein, took on an ideological edge as well.
For example, in New York City the resolution of ‘squeegeeing’ – extortion of
money from automobile drivers under the guise of washing car windows at busy
intersections – was not a problem-solving exercise according to some of its
advocates, because it did not deal with the ‘root causes’ of squeegeeing.12 And,
of course, all of this came to a head when Giuliani and Bratton mobilised the
NYPD around very specific crime control goals and succeeded beyond anyone’s
dreams. They not only reduced crime, they ‘called their shots’ and explicitly
challenged the premises of root cause criminology. Liberals fumed: this is not
community policing; police are ‘cooking the books’; the crime reductions are
the result of structural changes – demography, the economy, changing drug use
patterns; and finally, well, the NYPD might be reducing crime, but at the unac-
ceptable cost of high-handed ‘stop and frisk’ practices and the abuse of citizens,
especially minorities. Never mind that in New York City murders are down
1,600 a year and robberies 60,000; that civilian deaths from police shootings are
down from 41 in 1990 to 11 in 1999; or, that allegations of abuse of force are
down by over 1,000, during a time when 8,000 officers were added to the
NYPD.
In fact, liberals ceded crime control as an issue to conservatives. The radical
left notion that order maintenance is really racism, cultural imperialism, ‘crimi-
nalisation of the poor’, ignores the plain reality that liberals refuse to
acknowledge: poor and minority neighbourhoods are being ravaged by disor-
derly persons and conditions and the refusal of officials to take neighbourhood
priorities seriously.
It is in this context that I will briefly address two critiques of ‘Broken
Windows’. One, ‘Replacing “Broken Windows”: Crime, Incivilities and Urban
change’ by Roger Matthews (1992), is written from a British point of view.13 It
is well known in both Britain and the US and has shaped many commentaries
on ‘Broken Windows’.14 The second is ‘Systematic Social Observation of Public
Spaces: A New Look at Disorder in Urban Neighborhoods,’ by Robert J.
Sampson and Stephen W. Raudenbush. The most recent critique, it was
published in the prestigious American Sociological Review. Both are important
articles by established social scientists. I have no doubt that the latter article
will become as influential as the first. It already has been put forward in the
‘Broken Windows’: a response to critiques 133
first call for experimentation. Then we add: ‘The second answer is also a hedge
– many aspects of order-maintenance in neighborhoods can probably best be
handled in ways that involve the police minimally, if at all’ (Wilson and
Kelling 1982: 36).
Notwithstanding the substance of ‘Broken Windows’, or its cautious
exploratory tone, Matthews’ critique degrades from an interesting discussion of
valid substantive and policy issues about which there is ample opportunity for
honest disagreement, into a diatribe that has little to do with ‘Broken
Windows’ theses, tone, or spirit. Examples abound. Matthews writes: ‘When
the public report these problems [rowdy youths, etc.] to the police, it is often
not because they want a heavy-handed, truncheon-wielding army of police offi-
cers descending on their neighborhood’ (1992: 37) Who suggested a
heavy-handed, truncheon-wielding army? This is absolutely out of the spirit of
what was written. Matthews goes on: ‘Wilson’s and Kelling’s contention is that
the police are the key to controlling disorder’ (ibid.: 38) In fact, as the quote
from ‘Broken Windows’ above demonstrates, we say the opposite. Nonetheless,
continuing in this line, Matthews avers:
[T]hey advocate more ‘get tough’ policies, greater use of imprisonment, and
the extension of selective incapacitation. At the same time, they want, not
only more legal sanctions, but also endorse the use of extra-legal tactics by
the police and seem to suggest that the appropriate response to intimida-
tion and harassment on the street is more intimidation and harassment by
the police.
(Matthews 1992: 43)
‘Broken Windows’: a response to critiques 135
In plain language, this means that robbery is related to disorder. The authors,
however, are dismissive of what might be one of their most interesting findings:
‘Only for robbery does the estimated effect of disorder remain large’ (page 629).
Only for robbery? Isn’t robbery a serious problem?16 Since the only other violent
crime analysed is homicide, the rarity of which almost precludes a statistical
link to disorder, this is a rather cavalier dismissal. And, by the way, where is
aggravated assault in this analysis? If one is to make claims about measures of
violence, ignoring aggravated assault is a glaring omission
To be fair, ‘A New Look’ raises an important issue that is obscured by the
need to put ‘disadvantage and collective efficacy’ in the best light and to
diminish ‘Broken Windows’. In respects, the ‘Broken Windows’ formulation –
disorder to fear to serious crime to urban decay – is oversimplified. Clearly,
whatever causal sequencing is ultimately developed, ‘serious crime’ is an over-
simplified aggregation of a complex range of offences, some of which are forms
of debt settlement, others predatory, while others are situational. For example,
I would be hard pressed to say that all categories of robbery are sequentially
linked to disorder. The estranged lover who demands back rent from his
former roommate at gunpoint is probably not much affected by disorderly
behaviour or conditions. Plenty of other examples could be given from each
legal category of offence. My guess is that the main contribution of Sampson
and Raudenbush here is that while they do not disaggregate the crime data
themselves, their preliminary results on homicide and robbery suggest that
future analyses require disaggregation to establish sequencing, precursors, or
causes.
The final issue has to do with how Sampson and Raudenbush portray
‘Broken Windows’. Throughout the article, the authors exaggerate differences
between their findings and ‘Broken Windows’, ignore similarities and limit their
presentation of ‘Broken Windows’ policies to their construct: ‘strong “Broken
Windows” ’– whatever that may be.
Apparently by ‘strong version’ they mean something like the following:
‘What we would claim, however, is that the current fascination in policy circles
(see Kelling and Coles 1996; Kelling 1998) on cleaning up disorder through law
enforcement techniques appears simplistic and largely misplaced, at least in
terms of directly fighting crime’ (1999: 638). Note the citations: they suggest
that Kelling and Coles either reflect or contribute to such a narrow approach.
This is a deliberate misrepresentation. Fixing Broken Windows argues for a subtle
and nuanced approach to dealing with neighbourhood problems. Both ‘Broken
‘Broken Windows’: a response to critiques 139
Windows’ and Fixing Broken Windows are extremely cautious about the poten-
tials of police to control crime on their own. Fixing Broken Windows, for
example, while maintaining that police had an impact on crime in New York
City during Giuliani’s and Bratton’s administration, further argued that it was
only understandable in the context of the efforts of business improvement
districts (BIDs), the transportation authority, neighbourhood groups, the evolu-
tion of a community court and other community efforts (Kelling and Coles
1996: Chapter 4). Fixing Broken Windows argues for services, collaborations,
involvement with citizens, problem solving, involvement of the faith commu-
nity and private business and provides examples of all. (I suppose this was
acknowledged to me in a note that Sampson attached to a copy of the article in
which he indicates, ‘The results are complex and we think the ‘‘softer’’ version
of “Broken Windows” is more compatible with the data’ [personal communica-
tion, undated.]) ‘Softer’ version? I think I know what this means: it is a contrast
to the ‘tough’ version of ‘Broken Windows’ – nothing more than Sampson and
Raudenbush’s construct in the first place. To be sure, neither Wilson nor Coles
and I back away from law enforcement, but Fixing Broken Windows is very
explicit in its rejection of highhanded police tactics. Anyone who has read it is
well aware of this.
Reading Sampson and Raudenbush carefully, it is clear that their article is
misleading; ‘Broken Windows’ is inexcusably misrepresented. Moreover, the
idea, professed in their article, that: ‘This article is part of a larger effort to build
a social science of ecological assessment’ (Sampson and Raudenbush 1999: 639)
is pretentious. As a matter of fact, police researchers have been struggling with
measurement problems in neighbourhoods for decades. Sampson and
Raudenbush simply failed to learn from them – as is evident when their
research is compared with that of Braga (1999) and his colleagues. Sampson
and Raudenbush’s acceptance of the limitations of their sampling design in the
name of ‘advanced systematic social observation’ reflects a stunning lack of
‘street smarts’.
It does not take much imagination to understand, however, what is going
on here. The article was written and disseminated to gain maximum atten-
tion: it disproves ‘Broken Windows’; it is a major methodological
breakthrough. The dawning has taken place and left-centre criminologists and
sociologists are aware that ignoring disorder and minor offences is simply
unsustainable. Their quandary appears to be how to say something that
protects root causes and yet does not acknowledge that conservatives were
correct, both when they argued that minor offences mattered and that, if
police and criminal justice agencies were to take citizens’ concerns seriously,
and do something realistic about them, serious crime could be reduced short of
solving all of society’s problems. This does not mean that police can do it
alone or that poverty, racism, social injustice and family breakdown (the
equivalent of ‘root causes’ for the political right) should not be addressed.
They should be in their own right. But crime prevention should not be held
hostage to solving these problems.
140 George L. Kelling
Conclusion
The last decade of the 1990s proved to be a pivotal one for criminology and
criminal justice. The liberal ‘rediscovery’ of disorder and its consequences in
neighbourhoods represents a significant shift in criminological thinking. I have
no quarrel with liberals who want to ‘spiff up’ the idea a bit to make it more
palatable. This is exactly what the liberal New Yorker journalist Malcolm
Gladwell is doing in The Tipping Point, a trade book now approaching the best-
seller list in the US (Gladwell 2000). He argues that, in many respects, liberals
were right all along adding, provocatively, that Mayor Giuliani is really a liberal
when it comes to crime. Conservatives, he maintains, view character as the
source of crime. Liberals, on the other hand, maintain that social context
explains crime. Their mistake is that they view context too broadly: poverty, et
al. What is important is the immediate context. While Gladwell specifically uses
‘Broken Windows’ as a prime example, context is a core concept in both situa-
tional crime prevention (Cornish and Clarke 1986) and routine activity
analysis (Felson and Cohen 1980) as well. This explains, for Gladwell, why
circumstances changed so dramatically in New York’s subway: a small change in
the context, eradicated graffiti and ended fare beating, achieved a tipping point
that altered how people, including those disposed to crime, behaved in the
subway. But Gladwell makes his own points positively; he has no need to
diminish the insights of others – even conservatives.
My quarrel instead is with ‘scholarly’ works that deliberately attempt to
‘spin-off’ of ‘Broken Windows’, distort it, and in so doing, denigrate it, and then
use the distortion to enhance their own work. The shame is that just as the
importance of Gladwell’s ‘tipping points’ is not diminished by his forthright
recounting of ‘Broken Windows’ in New York’s subway, Sampson and
Raudenbush’s ‘collective efficacy’ would not have been diminished by a simi-
larly straightforward presentation of ‘Broken Windows’. Their work is important
in its own right; they don’t have to devalue it by misrepresenting other points of
view. My own guess is that their views will converge very nicely with ‘Broken
Windows’ as research progresses. (Putting aside the problems of sampling and
homicide data, it would be fascinating to disaggregate robberies to see if types of
robberies are related to types or levels of disorder.)
If the issue of the accurate representation of ‘Broken Windows’ was a mere
academic quibble, I would have been loath to respond to either of the above
articles. History has a way of sorting these things out. But the debate is not
academic; it is about crime control now. Political tracts are fine in the current
policy debate, but they should not be confused with scholarly work. Finally, if
Wilson and I had ‘only’ been right about the link between disorder and robbery,
I still would be delighted.
I would like to thank Catherine M. Coles, William Sousa and Michael Wagers
for their comments on drafts of this chapter. I would also like to thank Marissa
Potchak for her research assistance.
‘Broken Windows’: a response to critiques 141
Notes
1 The full explication of ‘Broken Windows’ is found in the original article, cited
above, and in George L. Kelling and Catherine M. Coles (1996) Fixing Broken
Windows: Restoring Order and Reducing Crime in Our Communities, New York: The
Free Press, and in George L. Kelling, ‘Broken Windows’ and Police Discretion,
National Institute of Justice Research Report, NCJ178259, October 1999.
2 Gary Stewart, ‘Black Codes and Broken Windows: The Legacy of Racial
Hegemony in Anti-Gang Civil Injunctions’, The Yale Law Journal, vol. 107, no. 7,
May 1998, pp. 2249–79. An ‘aversive’ racist, according to the author, is a smart
racist. One can tell that someone is a racist when he or she doesn’t talk about
race.
3 In a somewhat amusing example of attempts to redeem me from this encum-
brance, one doctoral student (not from Rutgers) has indicated to me that he is
working on a paper in which he conducts a contextual analysis of the original
‘Broken Windows’. He has identified what parts of the paper are the ‘good’ parts –
and I authored them – and what are the ‘bad’ parts – and they are authored by
Wilson. However, I was not a stranger to such ‘suspicion’. The Kansas City
Preventive Patrol Experiment (Kelling et al. 1974) had already put me at odds
with most of the police establishment during the 1970s. Moreover, the sociolog-
ical/criminological establishment, for example Albert Reiss Jr., had attacked the
Kansas City study even before its publication (personal experience and communi-
cations).
4 While this paper is relatively obscure, it represents for me an initial foray into
what later crystallised as community policing: seeking local legitimacy; the local
configuration of problems; the need for decentralised decision-making; the links
between order maintenance and crime control; the role of citizens in crime
control, etc.
5 Giuliani withdrew from the race in late May 2000 as a result of the discovery that he
was suffering from prostate cancer.
6 For those who don’t know the history, Bratton was chief of the transit police from
April 1990 to 1992. He then returned to Boston. In 1994 he returned to NYC as
Commissioner under Giuliani. Later, during Bratton’s administration, the transit
police were absorbed by the NYPD.
7 Fare beating was an unusually serious problem. Up to 250,000 people a day were
not paying their fare. This not only created an extraordinary sense of the subway
being a lawless place out of control, but the loss of income threatened the entire
infrastructure of the subway. Transit officials estimated losses at over $100 million a
year.
8 The use of laws against disorderly behaviour has also been an important means of
controlling gang behaviour – right now, a dangerous mix of drugs, drug selling, ‘turf’
and guns. Such matters have appeared in the US Supreme Court on at least one
occasion (Chicago v. Morales) and are bound to occur in the future. While the
Supreme Court invalidated one Chicago law that gave the police broad discretionary
authority to order gangs to ‘move on’, the Court literally invited Chicago to redraft a
somewhat more limited ordinance.
9 For a detailed discussion of this event, and the reasons he believes that it was not an
example of police abuse, see, James Fyfe (2000) ‘Reflections on the Diallo Case’.
10 This phrase, for me at least, has its origins with Mark H. Moore, my colleague in the
Kennedy School of Government at Harvard University.
11 I write political conservatives rather than Republicans because mayors like Daley in
Chicago and John Norquist in Milwaukee are not Republicans, but are conservative
nonetheless. Norquist, for example, has taken an extremely strong stance against the
use of federal funds in cities – once a funding mainstay of the liberal urban alliance
(Norquist 1999).
142 George L. Kelling
References
Bittner, E. (1967) ‘The Police on Skid Row: A Study of Peacekeeping’, American Socio-
logical Review, 32: 699–715.
Bowling, B. (1999) ‘The Rise and Fall of New York Murder: Zero Tolerance or Crack’s
Decline’, British Journal of Criminology, 39(4): 531–54.
Braga, A. (1999) ‘Problem-oriented Policing in Violent Crime Places: A Randomized
Controlled Experiment’, Criminology, 37(3): 541–80.
Bratton, W. (1998) Turnaround, New York: Random House.
Chaiken, J. (1975) The Criminal Investigation Process: Volume II. Survey of Municipal and
County Police Departments, The Rand Corporation, R-1777-DOJ.
Chicago v. Morales, 1998 (97–1121), 177 Ill. 2d 440 687 N.E. 2d53.
Cornish, D. B. and Clarke, R. V. (1986) Situational Prevention, Displacement of Crime and
Rational Choice Theory, London: HMSO, 1–16.
Felson, M. and Cohen, L. (1980) ‘Human Ecology and Crime: A Routine Activity
Approach’, Human Ecology, 8(4): 389–406.
Fukuyama, F. (1999) The Great Disruption: Human Nature and the Reconstitution of Social
Order, New York: Basic Books.
Fyfe, J. (2000) ‘Reflections on the Diallo Case’, Subject to Debate. A Newsletter of the
Police Executive Research Forum, 14: 4.
Gladwell, M. (2000) The Tipping Point: How Little Things Can Make a Big Difference,
Boston: Little, Brown, and Company.
‘Broken Windows’: a response to critiques 143
Walker, S. (1984) ‘ “Broken Windows” and Fractured History: The Use and Misuse of
History in Recent Patrol Analysis’, Justice Quarterly, 1(1): 75–90.
Wilson, J. Q. (1999) Foreword in George L. Kelling and Catherine M. Coles, Fixing
Broken Windows: Restoring Order and Reducing Crime in Our Communities, New York:
The Free Press.
—— and Kelling, G. L. (1982) ‘Broken Windows: The Police and Neighborhood
Safety’, Atlantic Monthly, March: 29–38.
6 Ethnic minorities and
community safety
Marian FitzGerald
Introduction
The 1999 Macpherson report into the murder of the black London teenager
Stephen Lawrence set the tone and the content of the British government’s
commitments to ethnic minority communities on issues of crime and commu-
nity safety. These commitments were unprecedented in that not only were they
explicit and high profile but they were also attached to a wide-ranging
programme of action. This chapter examines what has been achieved to date
with regard to two key issues addressed by the programme of action – stop and
search and racist incidents. I raise a number of questions which will need to be
resolved if the government is to meet these specific commitments in the
context of its commitments to community safety more widely.
In March 1999, the Home Office, the Lord Chancellor’s Department and the
Attorney General published a Strategic Plan for 1999 to 2002, along with a
Business Plan for its implementation in the first year. The plans represented a
‘new approach in working together’, and the Foreword from the three ministers
invokes a protean notion of ‘community’. One of the priorities they identified
was ‘improving the confidence of the community as a whole, but especially the
ethnic minority communities, in the criminal justice system’ (Home Office
1999a). That is, the priority is based on the notion of a single community, but
there is a further assumption that – within a minority section of this community
– there is also a multiplicity of communities.
The context in which the government made this commitment was strongly
influenced by the report of the inquiry into the death of the black teenager,
Stephen Lawrence. Shortly after coming to office in 1997, the Home Secretary
appointed the senior judge Sir William Macpherson of Cluny to ‘inquire into
the matters arising from the death of Stephen Lawrence on 22 April 1993 to
date, in order particularly to identify the lessons to be learned for the investiga-
tion and prosecution of racially motivated crimes’ (Macpherson 1999: 6).
Three members were appointed to assist Sir William – a black bishop, the
retired deputy chief constable of a provincial force and the chair of the Jewish
Council for Social Responsibility. Late in 1997 they began a series of public
hearings which continued until the summer of 1998. These were largely
146 Marian FitzGerald
concerned with the murder itself and its investigation. Part two of the inquiry
began in the autumn of 1998, when they turned their attention to the investi-
gation and prosecution of racially motivated crimes. Eschewing ‘a narrow
interpretation of our terms of reference’, they chose at this stage to broaden
their focus to what they perceived to be the central problem, ‘the lack of trust
which exists between the police and the minority ethnic communities’
(Macpherson 1999: 311).
The report was eventually published in February 1999; and its overall
conclusion was that ‘the investigation was marred by a combination of profes-
sional incompetence, institutional racism and a failure of leadership by senior
officers’. It defined the problem of ‘institutional racism’ as:
The problem was not peculiar to the Metropolitan Police Service (MPS), it
affected all police services; and other institutions and organisations could not be
complacent: ‘Collective failure is apparent in many of them, including the
Criminal Justice system’ (ibid.: 321). The report made seventy recommenda-
tions, all of which were accepted by the government, albeit a small number
were accepted only in principle or subject to ‘further consideration’; and a
month after the report appeared, the Home Secretary published his Action Plan
for implementing them (Home Office 1999b). The process was to be overseen
by a steering group personally chaired by the Home Secretary. The success of
the Action Plan was to be measured ‘using existing indicators in 1999/2000’,
but ‘more comprehensive indicators’ would be put in place from 2000 onwards
(Home Office 1999b: 3).
Even though the main body of the report was taken up with the first part of
the inquiry and part two was covered in just six of its 300-plus pages, most of its
recommendations related to part two. They were addressed to a range of agen-
cies in addition to the police, including government departments and local
authorities. Those addressed to the police included a number which focused on
stop and search and racist incidents. Police performance in both areas featured
strongly in the report’s description of the ‘central problem’ of ethnic minorities’
lack of trust in the police. For many years they have also served as a dual focus
of research into issues concerning ethnic minorities in Britain as victims and as
suspects of crime.
The data available on both stop and search and racist incidents are of partic-
ular symbolic importance in showing the extent to which the government is
meeting its stated commitment to ethnic minorities. Setting the figures in
Ethnic minorities and community safety 147
context, though, and examining the trends they show highlights a number of
largely unacknowledged tensions between these commitments and other
government priorities.
At the time of writing, published statistics for all forces were available only
up to the end of the financial year 1998–99. This means that the last two years
in these series effectively reflect, first, the situation inherited by the govern-
ment on coming to office; and second, the year of the Macpherson Inquiry.
The figures were published in the now annual Home Office publications on
‘race and the criminal justice system’. These were originally instigated under
s95 of the 1991 Criminal Justice Act and are commonly referred to as ‘s95
publications’.
In addition to these national figures, the Performance and Information
Bureau of the MPS provided me with statistics ad hoc on both stop and search
and racist incidents for the year 1999–2000. These shed further light on devel-
opments in London in the year following the Macpherson report. While
London may not be typical of other areas, it is the force most directly affected
by the inquiry; and, as this chapter highlights, it has a major influence on the
national statistics for both searches and racist incidents.
Statistical sources
Although police stops have long been a major source of tension between black
people and the police, it was not until 1993 that any obligation was placed on
forces systematically to monitor the issue. The 1984 Police and Criminal
Evidence Act (PACE) had already required all police forces to provide the
Home Office with raw figures on searches undertaken following a stop under s1
of the Act; and London had consistently accounted for nearly half of the
national total. Since concerns about the searching of black people in the capital
predated PACE (not least as an important factor in triggering the Brixton riots
of 1981), the MPS had already kept an ethnic breakdown of the figures for some
years. Numerous studies, however, supported widespread anecdotal evidence
that recording across all forty-three police forces in England and Wales was very
unreliable (Brown 1997).
At first, the police inspectorate (HMIC) simply asked forces to monitor
which of their records related to white people and which to a generic category
of ethnic minorities – even though the existing research suggested that this
would mask the extent of searches on black people relative to whites. Three
years later, though, the Home Office asked for the non-white category to be
broken down into ‘black’, ‘Asian’ or ‘other’ minorities (FitzGerald and Sibbitt
1997). The first published Home Office figures covered the financial year 1996
to 1997, and they compared the numbers of recorded searches with the 1991
Census population figures for each police force. The 1997 figures confirmed
that, on this yardstick, black people were significantly more likely to be
148 Marian FitzGerald
searched by the police than white people but there was no comparable over-
representation of Asians. This pattern was repeated again the following year –
that is, the year which ended just as the Macpherson Inquiry got underway.
Recent trends
Figures for the year during which the Macpherson Inquiry was conducted,
however, showed a fall of 15 per cent in the number of black people searched in
England and Wales, with a more modest drop (6 per cent) for Asians. Read
superficially, the figures might imply that the inquiry was already proving effec-
tive in reducing the level of searches on black people relative to whites. In fact,
the national figures give a misleading picture of trends for two inter-related
reasons.
The first is that the different minority populations are not distributed evenly.
Nearly two-thirds of all black people (62 per cent) live in London and the next
largest black community is in the West Midlands which accounts for a further 9
per cent. The Asian population is more dispersed; but again the main areas of
settlement are London and the West Midlands, which account respectively for
35 and 16 per cent of the population. By contrast, only 17 per cent of the white
population lives in these two conurbations put together. What happens in these
two force areas, therefore, will significantly affect any presumed ‘national’
picture for both the black and the Asian group; and it may distort their national
showing relative to the white population. In effect, national trends for black
people are largely determined by what happens in London.
The second reason why the national figures are misleading is that there is
wide variation in the recorded use of the power by different forces. The Home
Office ‘s95’ figures (Home Office 1999b) gave a national figure of twenty-two
PACE searches per thousand population in 1997 and 1998; but the figures for
individual forces ranged from four to just under a hundred. For London the
number was fifty-one per thousand; but in the West Midlands it was only nine-
teen. In the year of the Macpherson Inquiry, the national average remained the
same; but the London figure fell to forty-five per thousand and that in the West
Midlands to eleven. Yet there was almost no change in the proportion of
searches on black people in either area. In London the proportion of black
people searched fell by one percentage point (from 26 to 25 per cent); but in
the West Midlands it rose from 14 to 15 per cent, with a higher rise for Asians
(from 17 to 20 per cent).
The apparent fall in the proportion of searches on black people during the
year of the inquiry, therefore, did not represent any marked drop in searches on
black people per se. It was largely due to the fall in searches on all groups in
London. Meanwhile, the rise in the proportion of black people searched in the
West Midlands had no effective impact on the national figures, despite the rela-
tively large number of black people in the area. This was because the fall
occurred in a force which contributed relatively little to the national total in
the first place.
Ethnic minorities and community safety 149
Developments in London
On closer inspection, the figures for London show that this fall during the year
of the Macpherson Inquiry was especially precipitate in the early part of 1999 –
the point at which the report was awaited. At the same time there was a signifi-
cant increase in recorded crime in London; and sections of the media were
sympathetic to claims by some police officers that the two phenomena were
associated.
Anticipating the wider criticisms the inquiry was likely to level at them, the
MPS had begun to try to seize the initiative. Its new approach to tackling racist
incidents is described in the next section; but it had also recognised stop and
search as a key issue on which action was needed. At the beginning of 1998,
therefore, it designated five pilot sites (later increased to seven) to try out a new
approach to stop and search. The initiative largely consisted of intensified
scrutiny of two things: officers’ performance within and across the pilot sites;
and statistical data. Its stated aims were to ensure that the power was used both
more effectively and fairly. Progress was to be closely monitored throughout and
the results were to be evaluated at the end of the first year.
In the course of this monitoring and evaluation it became apparent that the
data already held by the MPS were a potentially rich source of new insights into
the pattern of searches and the factors which drove these. Research into the
impact of the pilots required more detailed analyses of these data than had ever
previously been undertaken, and it generated further information ad hoc to
complement these analyses (FitzGerald 1999a; 1999b).
Effectiveness
The interim evaluation report in the summer of 1999 showed a marked
improvement in the arrest rate from searches – which has conventionally been
used as the key measure of success. However, it also showed that this success
should not be taken entirely at face value. Although the MPS was known to
record a higher proportion of its searches than other forces (FitzGerald and
Hale, forthcoming), it became apparent that many searches in London were
still going unrecorded. Where searches resulted in an arrest, officers might
simply not bother to complete a record for the search in addition to doing the
paperwork for the arrest. Once the search figures were put under the twin spot-
lights of the pilots and the Macpherson Inquiry, this provided a major incentive
to rectify these omissions. Thus the apparent improvement in the arrest rate
gave the impression that the power was being targeted more effectively; yet
much of it was probably due simply to improved statistical housekeeping.
The focus on the improved arrest rate distracted attention from a develop-
ment which was arguably far more important in terms of effectiveness. It was
taking place in the context of a major fall in searches overall which had set in as
the Macpherson Inquiry started. The fall in searches became more precipitate as
the inquiry moved into phase two and dropped more sharply still in anticipation
of the report. While the burst of statistical housekeeping referred to above meant
150 Marian FitzGerald
that the number of arrests attributed to searches held up for a while, by the last
quarter of 1998 they too started to plummet. While the improved arrest rate was
being represented as a success, in practice searches were now contributing far less
to arrests overall (see Figure 6.1).
It cannot be assumed, however, that the fall in arrests from searches had any
serious consequences for community safety. The largest proportion of arrests
from searches was for drugs; and data from the pilot sites confirmed that by far
the majority of these drugs arrests were for personal possession of small amounts
of cannabis. Cannabis use is not believed to be causally associated with other
types of offending; nor does it appear to be a matter of public concern – except
inasmuch as the fact that it is illegal may serve to legitimate potentially discrim-
inatory police searches (Young 1994; Runciman 2000). The second largest
category of searches was for stolen property; and a fall here also seemed unlikely
to have any significant impact on the crime figures. Burglary is by far the largest
category of property crime, but only a small minority of burglaries are cleared up
through arrests of any sort and only a small minority of these would have been
the result of a search (see FitzGerald and Sibbitt 1997: 70).
On the other hand, searches for offensive weapons and firearms or for going
equipped to steal or burgle together accounted for under 15 per cent of search
arrests early in 1998. Their relative insignificance in the context of searches
overall meant that their potential importance in the context of community
safety was largely overlooked. Yet searches for offensive weapons and firearms or
for going equipped to steal or burgle consistently produced the majority of all
Ethnic minorities and community safety 151
arrests for these preparatory offences. So, while the decrease in searches gener-
ally might have little influence on levels of crime overall, the fall in arrests in
these particular categories might nonetheless have a disproportionate impact.
The claims of a link between the rise in crime and the fall in searches
overall, seemed almost certain to be spurious; although they were as difficult to
disprove as to prove using the administrative statistics available. Academic
analysis, however, did find a completely counter-intuitive statistical relationship
between the sudden fall in searches and the marked rise in crime which
followed in the early months of 1999 (Penzer 1999). The explanations for this
finding are likely to be complex. It cannot be taken to imply that the fall in
searches per se caused a rise in crime or even that the rise in crime was directly
linked to the fall in searches for offensive weapons, firearms and going
equipped. However, other research has found an association between a sudden
fall in the use of searches and a rise in crime (NACRO 1997). The findings
from the MPS study suggest that it is worth undertaking further work to explore
the reasons for this pattern; and this might usefully focus on the preventive
effect of the power – both direct and indirect.
With regard to the ethnic patterns in the search figures, the study exposed
numerous complexities in interpreting local statistics. It established that
comparisons with the local population in general were irrelevant and potentially
misleading for many reasons, not least because of the non-resident population
represented in the search figures. In some areas people from outside the area
accounted for the majority of those people searched; but there were further
ethnic variations within this. The two main influences on the ethnic patterns in
the search figures, though, appeared to be age and the extent to which different
groups featured among the suspects described in crime reports. This is illustrated
by Figure 6.2 which compares the pattern of searches on different ethnic groups
in London with: (a) the population at large; (b) the population of secondary
school age; and (c) the descriptions of suspects of crime.
Figure 6.2a shows the basis on which ‘disproportionality’ has usually been
calculated. It confirms the extent to which, measured in this way, black people
are over-represented in the search figures in relation to their presence in the
population at large. Yet Figure 6.2b shows that this ‘over-representation’ reduces
considerably when age is taken into account since there are important varia-
tions in the age structures of the different ethnic groups. This is especially
relevant in the context of community safety. For the young and the old may be
thought of as different communities of interest whose conflicting needs may
sometimes be difficult to reconcile. In many areas white people will constitute a
much higher than average proportion of the old population while ethnic
minorities constitute a much higher than average proportion of the youth popu-
lation than is apparent from figures for the population as a whole. In over half
of the thirty-two London boroughs, ethnic minorities account for 45 per cent or
more of the school age population; and in some they constitute a majority of
the young people in the area (FitzGerald 2000). This not only highlights the
importance of controlling for age with some precision when making inter-
ethnic comparisons. It also flags up the danger of racialising what are essentially
age-related differences by the uncritical use of crude ethnic statistics.
In fact, the closest match for the ethnic composition of the search figures in
Figure 6.2 is with descriptions given to the police of suspects of crime (6.2c).
Importantly, the study also showed that black people were no more likely than
white people to be stopped by police officers acting entirely on their own discre-
tion. It established that black people who were searched were as likely as white
people to have previous criminal records and they were arrested at the same rate
following searches. Taken together, the evidence strongly suggested that – far
from disappearing – disproportionality would actually get worse if officers were
allowed only to search people in connection with crime reports. The only
obvious way of achieving a reduction in the ethnic differential between black
and white people in the search statistics, therefore, might be to weight the
police response to victims of crime according to their description of the suspect.
Yet it is hard to imagine how such an approach could be acceptably presented in
the context of local community safety strategies, regardless of any implications
for their successful implementation.
154 Marian FitzGerald
On the other hand, the research identified significant issues with regard to
searches on Asians which had been overlooked in a debate framed by tradi-
tional assumptions about (dis)proportionality. As Figure 6.2a also shows, Asians
were not searched disproportionately when compared with their presence in the
population at large or even in relation to their presence in the school age popu-
lation (6.2b). However, they were searched more than would be expected from
descriptions of suspects in crime reports (6.2c). Moreover, this disparity was
much starker in the few areas with relatively large Asian populations. At the
same time, the arrest rates from searches for Asians at the beginning of the
study were much lower than for white or black people; and those searched were
much younger than the average for all groups. Proportionately many fewer of
the Asians had criminal records; they were more likely to be searched in groups;
those groups tend on average to be larger; and a higher proportion of searches
on Asians were for drugs.
In other words, the Asians – and in particular the poorer, younger groups
within this supposed community – were at special risk from the use of the power
as a mechanism of social control. Their age structure meant that the cohort at
the peak age for offending was now much larger than in the past, so increasingly
large numbers of these young people had begun to experience the confronta-
tional way in which the power was often applied. In so far as it was starting to
criminalise them for possession of cannabis, the study argued that searches
might yet prove the equivalent of the ‘Sus’ laws which did so much damage to
police relations with the parallel generation of black youth twenty years ago
(Demuth 1978).
For black people the implications of the research were different. They chal-
lenged the orthodox view that the ‘over-representation’ of black people in the
figures relative to their presence in the population at large could serve as a
proxy measure for police discrimination. But this did not imply that there was
no particular cause for concern in relation to black people. Rather, black people
were disproportionately suffering from the abuse of the power to harass people
‘known’ to the police. It also meant that the overbearing and aggressive manner
of officers (whether or not they were using the power legitimately) was having a
disproportionate impact on black people – including black people who were
innocent of any crime. The bottom line, however, was that the extent to which
the power is used would make little difference to ‘disproportionality’ as tradi-
tionally conceived. Whether the power was used more or whether it is cut back
to the minimum, the black-white ratio within it was unlikely significantly to
change.
Implications
Taken together, these findings posed a need for new thinking both about the
effectiveness of the power and about whether it was being used fairly. Searches
in general were not being used effectively to tackle crime. Although they had
fallen dramatically, the fall had not occurred as the result of any explicit inter-
Ethnic minorities and community safety 155
vention – still less one which was coherently designed to target the power better
or to address the problems associated with it. Yet, from the point of view of
community safety, there was more risk associated with this sudden fall than
might have been expected and some types of search (albeit a minority) might
yet prove indispensable for the prevention of crime unless equally effective and
more acceptable alternatives could be found.
At the same time, the disproportionate impact of the power on black people
and the potential for damage to police relations with future generations of
young Asians added particular urgency to the need to tackle generic problems
with the way the search power was used. However, it was essential to recognise
that these were problems which affected the community as a whole and to
tackle them as such. Any attempt at remedial action which conceived of the
problems as if they only affected the ethnic minority communities, would be
treating symptoms rather than causes. The danger was that these problems were
simply being scaled down until the Macpherson effect dissipated while crime
would remain at the level to which it had risen during the time when the fall in
searches was at its sharpest. Meanwhile, trends in recorded racial incidents also
give cause for concern. They too call into question conventional interpretations
based on simple headline statistics and suggest that these data also need to be
seen in a wider context.
Racist incidents
Statistical sources
The issue of racial violence and harassment had long been a problem for
minority communities in certain areas, but the issue reached the national policy
agenda in the late 1970s and early 1980s. In 1985 the Association of Chief
Police Officers responded to sustained criticism of the police response by
adopting an all-embracing definition of a ‘racial incident’. This attempted to
overcome the frequent tensions between ‘victims’ and officers’ perceptions of
racial motivation by requiring forces henceforth to record all incidents reported
to them in which it appears to the reporting or investigating officer that the
complaint involves an element of racial motivation, or which includes an alle-
gation of racial motivation made by any person. That is, the definition
deliberately embraced non-criminal forms of harassment and it did not require
racism to be the primary motivating factor. Hard evidence was not required,
only a perception or ‘an allegation’ and officers were not to have the final deci-
sion about whether the incident should be recorded as racially motivated.
These figures, too, were soon requested by HMIC – albeit forces were only
asked for a raw number. There was no suggestion that it might also be relevant
to break the figures down by offence type or by the ethnicity of the victims and
perpetrators. Publication of force totals was ad hoc at first, but the figures were
among the few sources of relevant statistics available in 1991, so they appeared
in the s95 publications from the outset. Meanwhile, the Home Office British
156 Marian FitzGerald
Crime Survey (BCS) had introduced an ethnic oversample in 1988; and in the
same year it asked a question about racial harassment (Mayhew et al. 1989).
Victims were asked if they believed what had happened to them was racially
motivated. However, the question was only asked of black and Asian respon-
dents and, while the survey covered threats as well as crimes, it did not cover
the low level nuisance behaviour which was typical of much harassment.
A study carried out by the Home Office in 1997 showed that few police
forces collected detailed figures on the racial incidents they recorded (Maynard
and Read 1997). Where these were available, though, they broadly confirmed
the consistent pattern of victims’ experiences described by the British Crime
Survey and earlier studies (FitzGerald and Ellis 1989). Unsurprisingly, the
largest single category of racist incident (38 per cent) was ‘verbal abuse’, which
is the most common currency of antagonism – whether between individuals or
groups. Along with damage to property, verbal abuse accounted for well over
half of all incidents across the fourteen forces covered by the study, with miscel-
laneous ‘assaults’ making up a further 21 per cent. Only 2 per cent of racial
incidents were classified as ‘serious crimes’.
In the same year, the Crown Prosecution Service published the first report of
its ‘Racial Incidents Monitoring Scheme’. This included a breakdown of the
type of charges put by the police to the Crown Prosecution Service (CPS) in
the previous year which the CPS viewed as racially motivated. It too showed a
preponderance of less serious offences, with 49 per cent classified as public order
and a further 14 per cent as criminal damage. Just over a quarter (27 per cent)
were assaults (CPS 1997).
Part one of the Macpherson Inquiry was concerned with the most serious of
all racially motivated offences: murder. But in part two it specifically criticised
the police for failing to realise: ‘the impact of less serious, non-crime incidents
upon the minority communities’(Macpherson 1999: 313). It recommended a
simplified version of the ACPO definition and it insisted on changing the term
‘racial’ to ‘racist’. The new definition adopted by the Home Secretary and by all
police forces was: ‘an incident which is perceived to be racist by the victim or
any other person’.
Recent trends
Despite its limitations, the BCS had become increasingly important as a bench-
mark against which to measure trends in the police figures. For it not only
reflected the underlying levels of harassment experienced by victims, it also
asked them whether they had reported incidents to the police. The police
figures steadily began to rise through the early 1990s (see Figure 6.3). Although
the British Crime Survey showed no change in the underlying rate of racist
victimisation, it did suggest that there was a significant shortfall in the numbers
of incidents being recorded by the police relative to those reported to them
(Aye-Maung and Mirrlees-Black 1994; FitzGerald and Hale 1996a; Percy 1998).
Since there was no evidence of any significant increase in levels of reporting
Ethnic minorities and community safety 157
either, the gradual rise in the police figures up to 1996 mainly represented a
closing of this recording gap.
As with searches, the Macpherson Inquiry appeared already to have had a
significant impact on the racial incident figures before it even reported.
Following year-on-year rises of less than 10 per cent since the first s95 report,
the records for the financial year 1998 to 1999 showed a 66 per cent increase
(see Figure 6.3).
Developments in London
Meanwhile, the MPS had been proactive on the issue of racial incidents as well
as with regard to stop and search. The Race and Violent Crimes Task Force, set
up at New Scotland Yard in August 1998, rapidly began to establish a high
profile in the media and elsewhere. Under the charismatic leadership of Deputy
Assistant Commissioner John Grieve, it publicly took a robust – even aggressive
– approach to tackling racism. It mounted poster campaigns, opened the MPS
to its critics by setting up a lay advisers group to assist it and took road shows
out to public meetings across London. Within the force, the unit also spawned a
wide range of initiatives to raise standards and to improve performance and co-
ordination, including increasing the intelligence available for dealing with what
it increasingly referred to as ‘hate crime’.
The term ‘hate crime’ subsumed both racial and homophobic incidents. In
recent years, both of these had increasingly fallen within the remit of
‘Vulnerable Persons Units’ which had developed somewhat ad hoc primarily to
deal with domestic violence. Seizing the opportunities for restructuring in the
move to borough-based policing, the Race and Violence Crimes Task Force had
a specialist unit set up in each area. The core business of the units was their
responsibility for racial and homophobic incidents as well as domestic violence
(although there were some local additions to this), but the term ‘vulnerable
158 Marian FitzGerald
persons’ was dropped. Despite the fact that their remit was limited to specified
groups of victims, the new units were named ‘Community Safety Units’.
While the total number of recorded incidents in England and Wales rose
nationally by 66 per cent in 1998–1999 (i.e., the year of the Macpherson
Inquiry), they increased by 188 per cent in London. This meant that the MPS
now accounted for nearly half of all recorded racial incidents; and if London is
removed from the total, the percentage increase in 1998–1999 would have been
50 per cent instead of 66 per cent. Figures available from the MPS at the time
of writing showed a further, even larger increase for 1999–2000. The number of
racial incidents recorded in London rose a further 211 per cent in the year
following publication of the Macpherson report.
However, the more typical forms of victim experience appear consistently to
have accounted for a much smaller proportion of incidents in London than
those recorded elsewhere. The 1997 Home Office study, for example (op. cit.),
showed that only 12 per cent of incidents were classified by the MPS as verbal
abuse compared with an average of 38 per cent for all the forces in its sample.
The CPS monitoring report showed a similar pattern. In 1998–1999, 50 per
cent of charges were for public order offences in non-London forces compared
to 28 per cent for assault; but the MPS figure for both was 37 per cent. This
relative absence of incidents of low level harassment recorded by the MPS was
identified as a problem by the police inspectorate in a report on community and
race relations conducted in 1999. It fully acknowledged the pioneering work of
the Race and Violent Crimes Task Force, but it specifically noted that ‘the MPS
was failing to capture those incidents referred to by some as low level harass-
100
80
60
40
20
Figure 6.4 Trends in types of racial incidents recorded by the MPS, 1997–2000
Source: MPS Performance Information Bureau (PIB)
Ethnic minorities and community safety 159
80
70
60
50
40
30
20
10
0
Figure 6.5 Victims and suspects of racist incidents by ethnic group, MPS 1997–2000
Source: MPS Performance Information Bureau (PIB)
ment, but which in fact do so much damage to the quality of life of victims’
(Home Office 2000: 48).
The London figures during and after the Macpherson Inquiry show huge
increases but they show little evidence to suggest that the concerns of
Macpherson and the inspectorate with regard to ‘low level harassment’ are
being addressed. The recorded increases were primarily in relation to crime
rather than non-crime, and there was a further change in the balance of types of
crime within this. Notifiable offences came to account for a much higher
proportion of the crime incidents, and a progressively higher proportion of these
were violent offences (see Figure 6.4).
Meanwhile, the MPS figures also present a more complex picture of the
ethnicity of victims and of suspects than has been apparent from the terms in
which the debate around racial incidents has usually been conducted. The
debate has tended to assume that the victims of racism were primarily – if not
exclusively – members of visible ethnic minorities and that the perpetrators
were white. Yet both official definitions embrace all incidents irrespective of the
ethnicity of the victim or the perpetrator, and the London figures had always
shown a higher number of white victims than might have been supposed.
Following the publication of the Macpherson report, the proportion of
victims of racist incidents recorded as white actually increased in the MPS. In
1999–2000, the proportion of white victims of racist incidents in London nearly
equalled that of Asians, with a slightly smaller proportion of victims recorded as
black. Meanwhile, although whites were still the main perpetrators (see Figure
160 Marian FitzGerald
Implications
The statistics published by the Home Office tell us little about the real scale or
nature of the problem of racist harassment and even less about how effectively
the problem is being tackled. However, the BCS and the CPS reports provide
some check, and the detailed information held by the MPS is capable of shed-
ding further light on the situation in London.
With regard to the scale of the problem, the sudden increase in the crude s95
figures in 1998–1999 could have been due to any or all of three developments:
(a) an increase in reporting; (b) an increase in the reported incidents which
were actually recorded by the police; and/or (c) an increase in the underlying
problem. Unfortunately, the BCS did not over-sample ethnic minorities in
1998, so there is no authoritative means of telling the extent to which each of
these factors was implicated. Some tentative inferences can, however, be drawn.
It seems likely that reporting will have increased during a sustained period of
sympathetic media coverage. High-profile statements of commitment by senior
police officers may have encouraged more victims to report in the expectation
that they would be taken seriously. Also, the Macpherson Inquiry had empha-
sised the extent to which racism could be implicit as well as explicit and this
may have encouraged more victims who were reporting crimes additionally to
identify any racist element to these. If so, this would also help to explain the
increase in the MPS figures; for one would expect the serious crimes which were
such an important component of this increase to have been reported in any
event.
Additionally, though, the increase in the figures may include a backlash
element. The 1999 study of searches (FitzGerald 1999a) produced incidental
material which suggested that publicity surrounding the Macpherson Inquiry
was indeed creating resentment among some white people. They believed that
ethnic minorities were receiving privileged treatment; and several officers I
interviewed spontaneously reported being taunted by white youths claiming
that the police were picking on them because they no longer dared to search
black people. One officer described a similar backlash among white victims of
crime as follows:
You know, people come up to you and they say ‘I’ve just had this bloke
smash the windows of my car in. What are you going to do about it?’ And
you say ‘I’ll take a report and that’s the best I can do.’ And they’re turning
round now and they’re saying ‘I suppose, if I was a black person you’d have
detectives down here looking at my car’, etc.
Anecdotally, it had always been claimed that some white victims of crime
where the perpetrators were black have insisted de facto that these incidents
Ethnic minorities and community safety 161
were racially motivated. It seems entirely possible that such reporting may have
increased in the context of the inquiry; and this would help to explain the
increase in the proportion of white victims and of black suspects in the MPS
figures.
Recording also seems likely to have increased as a result of the inquiry which
is likely to have catalysed the pace at which the police had already begun to
close the recording gap identified by the BCS. Alongside this, though, a back-
lash element may also have been at work. Thus the officer quoted above had his
own views on white victims’ perceptions that black victims would receive
special attention. He had added, ‘They’re probably right’.
The HMIC report had also noted:
The view was widespread [among police officers] that the rationale behind
the definition of racist incidents and the prescriptive approach to their
recording was to provide a preferential service to minority ethnic commu-
nities thereby prejudicing the policing needs of the rest of society.
(HMIC 2000: 44)
This suggests that some officers may themselves have actively connived in the
white backlash by recording the type of perverse reporting referred to above.
Both reporting and recording in this instance would, of course, fall strictly
within the letter of the definition – even though they ran directly counter to its
spirit.
The white backlash to the Macpherson Inquiry, however, will not only be
reflected in the increase in the incidents reported to and recorded by the police.
It seems almost inevitable that it also produced a rise in the underlying level of
racial violence and harassment. The findings of existing studies of the actual
and potential perpetrators of racial violence and harassment suggest that many
come from marginalised groups within the white population. As justification for
their activities, they draw heavily on perceptions of preferential treatment for
minorities such as those cited above (Sibbitt 1997; Hewitt 1992 and 1996).
While the increase in the underlying level of racial violence and harassment
may have occurred for reasons beyond the control of the police, it adds urgency
to the need to show that the problem is being tackled effectively once it has
occurred. However, the evidence of improvement here is, at best, limited. The
most obvious measure of effectiveness comes from the CPS reports and from
MPS data regarding judicial disposals, although these relate only to the
minority of cases which are considered for prosecution. They show some
improvement, but it is by no means commensurate with the scale of increase in
the numbers of incidents recorded or their greater seriousness.
In 1998–1999 – the year which saw a 66 per cent overall increase in
recorded incidents and a 188 per cent increase in London – there was also an
increase in the number of actual charges involving racial motivation put to the
CPS by the police. However, for England and Wales as a whole, the rise was
only 10 per cent; and if the figures for London are removed it was only 4 per
162 Marian FitzGerald
References
Aye Maung, N. and Mirrlees-Black, C. (1994) Racially Motivated Crime: a British Crime
Survey Analysis, London: Home Office.
Bridges, L. (2000) ‘Limiting the Right to Jury Trial – Half Truths and False Assump-
tions’, Statewatch, 10(1): 17–19.
Brown, D. (1997) PACE Ten Years On: A Review of the Research, London: Home Office.
Crown Prosecution Service (1997) CPS Racist Incident Monitoring Scheme: Report on Year
Ending 31 March 1997, London: Crown Prosecution Service.
Demuth, C. (1978) Sus, a Report on the Vagrancy Act 1824, London: Runnymede Trust.
Euteneuer, R. (1999) Education in London: Key Facts, London: London Research Centre.
FitzGerald, M. (1999a) Searches in London: Interim Evaluation of Year One of Programme
of Action, London: Metropolitan Police. Online. Available: http://www.met.police.uk/
mps/htm
—— (1999b) Searches in London: Final Report, London: Metropolitan Police. Online.
Available: http//www.met.police.uk/mps/htm
—— (2000) London Borough Profiles: Social and Crime Characteristics. London, London:
London School of Economics and South Bank University. Online. Available:
http//www.policingforlondon.org (September 2000).
FitzGerald, M. and Ellis, T. (1989) ‘Racial Harassment: The Evidence’, in C. Kemp (ed.)
Current Issues in Criminological Research, Bristol: Bristol and Bath Centre for Criminal
Justice.
FitzGerald, M. and Hale C. (1996a) Ethnic Minorities: Victimisation and Racial Harass-
ment: Findings From the 1988 and 1992 British Crime Surveys, London: Home Office.
—— (1996b) ‘Ethnic Minorities and Fear of Crime’, unpublished paper presented to
ESRC workshop on Fear of Crime. Manchester, 18 April.
—— (forthcoming) ‘Stops, Searches and the Limitations of Ethnic Data’, Howard
Journal.
FitzGerald, M. and Sibbitt, R. (1997) Ethnic Monitoring in Police Forces: A Beginning,
London: Home Office.
Flatley, J. (1999) Social Care in London: Trends in Social Services’ Activity 1993–97,
London: London Research Centre.
Flood-Page, C. and Mackie, A. (1998) Sentencing Practice: An Examination of Decisions in
Magistrates Courts and the Crown Court in the mid-1990’s, London: Home Office.
Her Majesty’s Inspectorate of Constabulary (2000) Policing in London: ‘Winning Consent’
– a Review of Murder Investigation and Community and Race Relations Issues in the
Metropolitan Police Service, London: Home Office.
Hewitt, R. (1992) Sagaland: Youth Culture, Racism and Education: A Report on Research
Carried out in Thamesmead, London: University of London and London Borough of
Greenwich.
—— (1996) Routes of Racism: The Social Basis of Racist Action, Staffordshire: Trentham
Books.
Home Office (1999a) Criminal Justice System: Strategic Plan 1999–2002 and Business Plan
1999–2000, London: Home Office, Lord Chancellor’s Department and Attorney
General’s Office.
—— (1999b) Statistics on Race and the Criminal Justice System: A Home Office Publication
Under section 95 of the Criminal Justice Act 1991, London: Home Office.
—— (2000) Statistics on Race and the Criminal Justice System, London: Research, Devel-
opment and Statistics Directorate, Home Office.
Hood, R. (1992) Race and Sentencing, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
166 Marian FitzGerald
Jeffers, S., Hoggett, P. and Harrison, L. (1996) ‘Race, Ethnicity and Community in three
Localities’, New Community, 22(1): 111–26.
Macpherson, W. (1999) The Stephen Lawrence Inquiry, London: The Stationery Office.
Mayhew, P. Dowds, L. and Elliott, D. (1989) The 1988 British Crime Survey, London:
Home Office.
Maynard, W. and Reed, T. (1997) Policing Racially Motivated Incidents, London: Home
Office.
Metropolitan Police Performance Information Bureau: all statistics cited provided ad hoc
to the author on request.
NACRO (1997) The Tottenham Experiment, London: National Association for the Care
and Resettlement of Offenders.
Penzer, J. (1999) Reported Crime and PACE Stop and Search Activity: An Investigation of
the Possible Relationship, London: London School of Economics. Online. Available:
http://www.lse.ac.uk/Depts/statistics/ (26 October 1999).
Percy (1998) Ethnicity and Victimisation: Findings From the 1996 British Crime Survey,
London: Home Office.
Runciman, R. (2000) Drugs and the Law: Report of the Independent Inquiry into the Misuse
of Drugs Act 1971, London: The Police Foundation.
Sibbitt, R. (1997) The Perpetrators of Racist Harassment and Racist Violence, London:
Home Office.
Yinger, M. (1986) ‘Intersecting Strands in the Theorisation of Race and Ethnic Rela-
tions’, in J. Rex and D. Mason (eds) Theories of Race and Ethnic Relations, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Young, J. (1994) Policing the Streets: Stops and Search in North London, London: Centre for
Criminology, Middlesex University.
7 The new correctionalism
Young people, Youth Justice
and New Labour
John Pitts
The current system for dealing with youth crime is inefficient and expensive,
while little is being done to deal effectively with juvenile nuisance. The
present arrangements are failing the young people – who are not being
guided away from offending towards constructive activities. They are also
failing victims – those who suffer from young people’s inconsiderate
behaviour, and from vandalism and loss of property from thefts and
burglaries. And they lead to waste in a variety of forms, including lost time,
as public servants process the same young offenders through the courts time
and again, lost rents, as people refuse to live in high crime areas; lost busi-
ness, as people steer clear of troubled areas; and waste of young people’s
potential.
(Audit Commission 1996: 96)
The present system replicates the inconsistent parenting which most young
offenders have received, making it necessary to replace it with a fast, effi-
cient system with a progressive, comprehensible sentencing tariff, which
offers the consistency and predictability which replicate ‘good parenting’.
(Perfect 1998)
Pre-emptive interventions
A remarkable feature of the 1998 Act is that it allows pre-emptive formal inter-
vention with children and young people below the age of criminal responsibility
(10 years), including those who have committed no offence but are deemed
likely to do so, or who are deemed by the police and the local authority to
constitute a nuisance in their neighbourhoods. These measures will, necessarily,
draw more younger children and their parents, via Parenting Orders, into the
purview of the justice system. These pre-emptive interventions are civil
170 John Pitts
measures but, in the cases of the Anti-Social Behaviour Order and the
Parenting Order, breaches may be dealt with by criminal sanctions.
person subject to a Referral Order, and having been sentenced for his or her
offence in the Youth Court, will be referred to a Youth Offender Panel. The
constitution of these panels has yet to be finalised but it is likely that they will
mirror the Scottish Children’s Hearings in which there is both a professional
and a lay presence. These panels will then decide on the type of programme the
youngster should pursue. It is likely that the emphasis will be on victim-offender
reparation and other ‘restorative’ interventions (Haines 2000). Whatever the
merits of the Referral Order, the Danish experience suggests that it is likely to
generate a higher volume of re-appearances in court, as a result of breaches of
the Order, than the Conditional Discharge it replaces (Mehlbye et al. 1998).
Whereas a breach of the Conditional Discharge required the young person to
re-offend, to be detected, apprehended, charged, prosecuted and found guilty, a
breach of the Referral Order requires only that the youngster fail to attend a
session of the programme.
A failure to successfully complete a Referral Order will probably result in the
imposition of an Action Plan Order, a Reparation Order or a Supervision Order
by the Youth Court. The Act specifies that youngsters would not normally
receive more than two community penalties so the imposition of such orders for
a young person who has already completed or breached a Referral Order would,
in effect, constitute a ‘last chance’.
The assumption that the bulk of young offenders will, as a result of participa-
tion in the ‘evidence-based’ programmes of victim-offender mediation, mentoring
and cognitive-behavioural change which underpin these orders, be made to desist
from offending is, as I argue below, rooted in a particularly optimistic reading of
that evidence (Pawson and Tilley 1997; Matthews and Pitts 1998).
Incarceration
In consequence, children and young people who breach an Action Plan,
Reparation or Supervision Order, or re-offend following their completion, are
likely to receive the new, partially indeterminate, Detention and Training
Order (DTO) or have a ‘residence requirement’ inserted in their Supervision
Order. This threatens to increase significantly the numbers of children and
young people in custody. Indeed, in September 2000 the numbers of youngsters
sentenced to custody was up 11.5 per cent on the preceding year. The ‘fast-
tracking’ of persistent young offenders, who are now more likely to make a
separate court appearance for each offence, or offending episode, exacerbates
this tendency. This process will gain further momentum in 2001 with the intro-
duction of the ‘three strikes’ sentencing strategy for young burglars, introduced
in Michael Howard’s Crime Sentences Act (1994). At this point, it is likely
that the numbers of 12 to 14 year olds sentenced to Detention and Training
Orders will increase substantially, quickly filling the 200 available places in the
new Secure Training Centres and placing even greater pressure upon Prison
Department young offender provision. And here lies one of the paradoxes of
New Labour’s new youth justice strategy.
172 John Pitts
The different types of facilities for young people that constitute the secure
estate are in need of major reform. Current arrangements are both inconsis-
tent and unsatisfactory. Young offender institutions are too large. Bullying
and abuse of one young offender by another occurs too often while the
education offered is often poor.
(Youth Justice Task Force 1998: 3)
Inasmuch as the YJB may strive to develop a rational, effective and humane
youth justice system and raise standards of provision and practice within the
secure estate, its efforts are being systematically undermined by the logic of a
system which, by default rather than design, is drawing in larger numbers of
less problematic children at a younger age, and pushing them through the
system more quickly. This systemic tendency is compounded by unequivocal
signals sent to the Youth Courts by the Prime Minister, the Home Secretary
and senior Home Office ministers that they should take a tough line on youth
crime.
This tension between the political and professional spheres is nowhere more
evident than in the case of Secure Training Centres (STCs). These were
proposed by the Conservative administration in 1993, and were resisted by the
then Shadow Home Secretary Tony Blair, who argued, correctly, that the
evidence pointed to the folly of bringing together the most difficult and
disturbed children in the country under one roof (Hoghughi 1983). However,
STCs were subsequently embraced by Shadow Home Secretary Jack Straw in an
attempt to beef-up New Labour’s ‘law and order’ profile in the run-up to the
1997 General Election. Medway STC opened in the spring of 1998. The YJB
required that staff were vetted in accordance with the recommendations of the
Warner report, Choosing with Care (1996). Accountability was ensured by the
recruitment of a resident Home Office monitor to ensure ‘contract compliance’,
and regular inspections by the Social Services Inspectorate. The rights of
inmates were to be vouchsafed by creating easy access to a variety of ‘watchdog’
organisations: Childline, The Samaritans, and the Voice of the Child in Care,
this latter organisation also providing ‘independent visitors’.
Thus, Medway STC represented the ‘cutting-edge’ in ‘institutional trans-
parency’. Yet in the Centre’s first seven months of operation, more than 100
assaults on staff were recorded along with £100,000 worth of damage. Over this
same period, thirty-five of the original 100 staff resigned. In June 1998, the
London newspaper, the Evening Standard, reported that:
More than 30 police wearing riot equipment had to use dogs to quell the
disturbance at the Medway Secure Training Centre. Three staff were
injured and windows smashed as 15 children, many wielding snooker cues
The new correctionalism 173
and balls, ran riot last night. It was an hour and a half before the incident
was brought under control.
(Evening Standard, 26 June 1998: 1)
This was, more or less, a re-run of the scenes which had accompanied the
launch of the similarly hyped DHSS Youth Treatment Centre in Brentwood,
Essex, in the mid-1970s. Like Medway, Brentwood had also attempted to bring
some of the most difficult and disturbed children in the country together under
one roof.
The Social Services Inspectorate submitted a damning report on Medway
STC in January 1999, recommending that it be shut down and that the other
four STCs under construction, at an estimated cost of £30 million, should be
put on hold. Government minister Paul Boateng, recently transferred from the
Department of Health, where he launched the Quality Protects initiative to
safeguard children in residential care, refused to be drawn on the issue of
closure, referring to the Medway trainees as ‘little monsters’.
Political imperatives displace professional considerations and ethical
concerns while the problems identified by the Youth Justice Task Force, far from
being ameliorated, become more acute. Similar tensions afflict the Youth
Offending Teams.
the UK in 1908, the YOTs assemble in one place, on a statutory and fully
funded basis, the ‘minimum sufficient network’ (Skynner 1974) of agencies,
professionals and expertise necessary to make a ‘holistic’ response to the
multiply disadvantaged young people who find themselves at the hard end of
the youth justice system. Moreover, by dint of its multi-agency, multi-disci-
plinary structure, the YOT may also serve as a catalyst for positive change in the
local authorities, the police, probation and voluntary sector services from which
YOT personnel are seconded.
However, responding effectively to the troubled youngsters who find their
way to the YOTs may take a long time and require the development of sensitive
referral protocols with a range of agencies, plus regular follow-up contact. In a
study of 270 young people involved with an inner London YOT (Jones 2001),
180 people (45 per cent) had been placed on the Local Authority Child
Protection Register at least once. Most had spent some time in local authority
care and the majority had a parent with recurrent mental health problems.
But the sheer volume of cases generated as a result of the propensity of the
new system to draw in new populations and speed their progress through it (the
Association for Youth Justice estimates an increase of 150 per cent per year,
based on pre-1998 levels of throughput) means that in many YOTs professional
staff, irrespective of their area of expertise, are simply concerned with the super-
vision of Court Orders.
These Orders are increasingly underpinned by offence-focused programmes
devised, and in some cases quite literally scripted, by the Home Office
Offending Behaviour Programme Unit or the Community Justice National
Training Organisation (Pitts 2000a and b). These programmes aim, quite
explicitly, to eliminate the exercise of judgement or discretion on the part of
the professionals administering them in order to avoid compromising
‘programme integrity’. This means that efforts to develop reflexive, holistic,
responses to youngsters in trouble, in which specialists come together to devise
programmes which will not only challenge young people’s behaviour, but also
address the underlying problems associated with their offending, is jeopardised,
and in some cases abandoned. Moreover, preliminary results from the forth-
coming YJB evaluation of ‘pilot’ YOTs suggest that professionals may be
spending less time in face-to-face contact with young offenders than in 1996,
when Misspent Youth bemoaned the paucity of professional contact with young
offenders.
On 25 September 2000, Jack Straw announced new measures, involving the
use of electronic tagging and voice verification systems, to keep Britain’s ‘2,500
most persistent tearaways’ under twenty-four hour surveillance (Guardian, 25
Sept. 2000: 6). He had earlier announced a cash injection to create several
thousand more probation officers. While at a political level this is an obvious
attempt to ‘steal a march’ on New Labour’s right-wing critics, it may also indi-
cate that the government is concerned that correctionalism has not fulfilled its
early promise, and is now seeking more direct, certain and cost-effective
measures with which to control young offenders.
The new correctionalism 175
Dejuvenilisation
The onus on children’s rights in the new youth justice is, however, in tension
with the attempt to erode the distinctiveness of the juvenile jurisdiction and to
ascribe greater levels of culpability to juveniles. As Jonathan Simon (2001) has
argued, the erosion of the juvenile jurisdiction in the US has been powered by
the belief amongst ‘opinion-formers’ and policy-makers, hostile to both
‘welfarism’ in youth justice and the welfare state in general, that the rehabilita-
tive responses developed in the 1960s and 1970s had failed and that only the
re-assertion of patently retributive responses would restore moral hegemony and
176 John Pitts
Failing families
In the 1980s the ‘family’, and in particular the criminogenic, lower-class,
‘welfare-dependent’ family, became a key focus for neo-liberal politicians and a
newly emergent neo-liberal intelligentsia. Their lament, in essence, was that
the rules of civilised social life were no longer observed, that absolute moral
values and their associated norms and practices had been trashed and aban-
doned by irresponsible ‘intellectuals’ on the one hand, and lower-class
malcontents on the other hand. Moreover, a culture, which had once placed a
premium on duty and responsibility, had now been supplanted by a culture of
complaint, dependency and entitlement. Thus, they rejected the traditional
ethos of the welfare state, which emphasised the rights of poor families, focusing
instead upon the economic burden placed by welfare recipients upon the hard-
working majority. In its dealings with families, they maintained, the welfare
state has been counterproductive because it:
failed to reinforce the work ethic; the goal of self sufficiency, self support
and self-initiative; the importance of intact families; the fiscal responsi-
bility of the parents to the child; and the notion of reciprocity, the idea
that recipients have a social obligation to perform in return for receiving
assistance.
(Karger and Stoesz 1990: 65, cited in Glennester and Midgley 1991)
In the US, Charles Murray (1994) had argued that the US government
should scrap its Aid to Families with Dependent Children programme (AFDC),
Medicaid, Food Stamps and Unemployment Insurance, in order to ‘drive young
women back into marriage’. Imported to do a similar job in the UK by the influ-
ential right-wing political journalist Andrew Neil and the Sunday Times
newspaper, Murray argued that:
the civilising process cannot occur in communities where the two parent
family is not the norm, and this will turn out to be as true in England as
America. The real problem with the ‘alternative’ of unmarried parenthood
is that it offers no ethical alternative for socialising little boys. For males,
the ethical code of the two-parent family is the only game in town.
(Murray 1994: 26)
Journalist Melanie Phillips (1994) was one of the first erstwhile left-leaning
celebrities to embrace what Murray described as the New Victorianism in the
UK, and in an article for the Observer newspaper she gleefully monitored its
colonisation of metropolitan opinion in the 1990s:
Peter Lilley and Sue Slipman, doughty defender of single parents, are
suddenly singing in close harmony. In a speech last week, the Social
Security Secretary blamed low pay and unemployment for turning young
men into unmarriageable prospects. Miss Slipman talks about how the
178 John Pitts
collapse of the male role through lack of work is manufacturing the kind of
yob no self-respecting woman would choose as a spouse. Suddenly a govern-
ment widely assumed to be hostile to single mothers seems to agree that the
real problem is men. … The question being asked is how can we civilise
young men when family structures, employment and moral authority are so
weakened?
(Phillips 1994: 27)
In a somewhat similar vein, but coming this time from the ‘post-Marxist left’,
Beatrix Campbell (1995) argued that unemployment and the ‘collapse of the
male role’ had forced men back into spaces which, by day, have traditionally
been occupied by women. However, she states that far from:
Thus, for Campbell, there is ‘an underclass’ but it is a gendered underclass made
up exclusively of men. What united these critiques was their conflation of
moral and fiscal concerns which found expression in a desire for the state to
control the bad behaviour of young men and their feckless fathers while,
Slipman and Campbell excepted, withdrawing support from their welfare-
dependent mothers.
These attempts to locate the origins of crime in the lower-class family ranged
from the blatantly rhetorical (Phillips 1994), through the pseudo-scientific
(Dennis 1997; Murray 1994), to accounts which inferred an aetiology from
empirically established correlates. Crime and the Family (1993) by Utting et al.,
drew upon data generated by West and Farrington’s (1973) Cambridge study of
‘delinquent development’ to argue that ‘the tangled roots of delinquency lie, to
a considerable extent, inside the family’. This timely publication paralleled, and
gave considerable impetus to, New Labour’s growing interest in the lower-class
family and in crime. Thus, by 1995, New Labour’s emergent ‘family policy’ was
virtually synonymous with its ‘criminal justice policy’. Indeed, the advent of the
Parenting Order in the 1998 Act must be seen against the backdrop of New
Labour’s high-profile commitment to the rejuvenation of the family as an ‘effec-
tive caring and controlling social unit’, and the pre-eminence it ascribed to
what Jack Straw described as family forms characterised by ‘two participating
parents’. As Tony Blair declared in his speech to the 1995 Labour Party confer-
ence: ‘a young country that wants to be a strong country cannot be morally
neutral about the family.’
Clearly, families play an important role in determining whether, or to what
extent, children and young people become involved in a broad range of socially
deviant and illegal behaviours. However, the causal primacy ascribed to the
The new correctionalism 179
Professional perfidy
New Labour’s onslaught upon the lower-class family was paralleled by an
assault upon the public professionals responsible for keeping the lower-class
family in order. This critique owed much to the neo-liberal account of the role
of the welfare state in fostering a ‘culture of dependency’ and New Labour’s
neo-Thatcherite suspicion of local government and the political orientation of
members of the ‘social professions’. In post-Thatcherite Britain, anti-profes-
sional ire was characteristically directed against teachers and social workers,
although the police are not always exempt, as Campbell’s account of their
collusive involvement in the 1991 youth riots in England testifies (Campbell
1995).
Teachers were castigated as defenders of entrenched, outmoded and almost
invariably ‘permissive’, professional doctrines to which they apparently clung in
the face of ‘widely accepted contrary scientific evidence’, and ‘informed
opinion’. Social workers, for their part, were admonished for blundering into
normal families on the basis of ‘child protection’ hearsay while failing to protect
and control the children of the poor, even as they colluded with the fecklessness
and criminality of their parents. While the problem of youth crime was
presented as, first and foremost, a product of the moral failure of families, this
failure was, it appeared, nurtured and amplified by the stupidity, cupidity, collu-
sion, incompetence or sheer bloody-mindedness of the professionals who were
supposed to contain and educate them. These themes are articulated succinctly
in The Blair Revolution by Peter Mandelson and Roger Liddle (1996). The
authors write:
180 John Pitts
programmes for which the level of certainty from available evidence is too
low to support generalisable conclusions, but for which there is some empir-
ical basis for predicting that further research could support such
conclusions.
(Sherman et al. 1998: 10)
However, should further research support such conclusions, the NIJ cautions,
these findings would only be valid if applied in ‘similar settings in other places
and times’. This raises important questions concerning whether, and to what
extent, the youth justice system of England and Wales might represent such an
analogous social context.
are taken into account the measurable impact of the cognitive skills training
programme evaporates (Pawson and Tilley 1997; Matthews and Pitts 1998).
Meta-analyses of evaluations of cognitive behavioural programmes suggest
that, for the programmes to be effective, certain key elements must be present.
In the case of high-risk offenders, programmes should occupy between 40 and
70 per cent of the offenders time (Gendreau 1996) and should last for at least
twenty-three weeks (Lipsey and Wilson 1998). In addition to matching the
duration and intensity of programmes to the ‘risk’, ‘criminogenic needs’ and
‘learning styles’ of offenders, programme providers must attempt to match the
programme to the offender’s personality characteristics. ‘High anxiety’
offenders, for example, do not respond well to confrontation, ‘egocentric’
offenders show a poor appreciation of the victim’s perspective, while offenders
with both ‘below average’ and ‘above average’ intellectual ability tend to be,
respectively, perplexed or under-stimulated by cognitive skills programmes
(Fabiano et al. 1991). Meta-analyses also show that programmes are successful
only if providers relate to juveniles in ‘interpersonally sensitive’ and ‘construc-
tive’ ways and are trained and supervised appropriately. Moreover, in the case of
more serious young offenders, ‘relapse prevention programmes’ need to be
employed in the community to monitor and anticipate problematic situations
and train offenders to rehearse alternative behaviours (Vanstone 2000).
Alongside this, programme staff need to be active in linking young people into
other services which meet their needs. However, even when all these criteria
are achieved the average recidivism rate remains relatively high at around 50
per cent (Andrews et al. 1990). Similarly inconclusive results are reported by
Maurice Vanstone (2000), although he reports positive, if not statistically
significant, rehabilitative outcomes in some UK programmes for motivated
adult offenders.
The community penalties administered by the YOTs are unlikely to offer
either the levels of intensity or the consistency of application necessary to effect
change with the persistent or serious young offenders upon whom they will be
imposed. Meanwhile, if these interventions mix low- and high-risk offenders in,
for example, a drugs awareness or literacy element of the programme, they may
trigger an ‘interaction effect’ (Clear and Hardeyman 1990) in which offending
amongst low-risk groups, prematurely drawn into the system by the new
measures introduced by the 1998 Act, may escalate.
Theoretical problems
Beyond the frailty of the evidence about the impact of cognitive skills training
are other concerns about the flimsy theoretical rationale upon which cognitive
skills training is built. At its core is an assumption that offenders can be
taught new cognitive skills which will enable them to anticipate the conse-
quences of their behaviour for themselves and others, and so make
‘appropriate’ moral choices. It is assumed that if they can think ‘straight’ they
will go ‘straight’. In so reasoning, the purveyors of cognitive skills training, like
184 John Pitts
Restorative justice
The fundamental precepts of restorative justice hold that when an offence is
committed, both the immediate victims and the communities to which they
belong have been harmed and that the relationship which has been fractured by
that offence is in need of restoration. In this perspective, the primary victims
are those most directly affected by the offence, but others, such as family
members of victims and offenders, witnesses and other members of the affected
community, are regarded as having been victimised by the offence. The restora-
tive justice process encourages victims to participate in defining the obligations
of offenders, who are then offered opportunities to understand the harm they
have caused to victims and the community and to devise a way of making resti-
tution. In this process, obligations to victims take priority over sanctions or
obligations to the state. In its original form, restorative justice emerged as a
local, colloquial and informal alternative to formal systems of retributive justice
administered by state agencies (Christie 1977; Braithwaite and Daly 1994).
Latterly in most Western youth justice systems, as in the UK Crime and
Disorder Act (1998), restorative elements have been incorporated into an
avowedly retributive youth justice system.
initial ‘not guilty’ pleas and those involving peer violence. It proved easiest to
reach agreement in cases of 12 and 13 year olds involved in ‘criminal damage’.
It is important to note that when success rates for restorative justice
programmes are cited, they usually refer to victim-offender satisfaction rather
than offender reconviction.
Nonetheless, the Northants Scheme boasts of a 23 per cent reconviction rate
over a two-year follow-up period for the youngsters passing through its
programmes. However, although this is a cause for celebration, it is important to
note that the Northants Scheme is voluntary, operating outside and as an alter-
native to formal involvement in the youth justice system. Moreover, because
the scheme has only initial administrative contact with the most serious and
persistent offenders and is open to any child or young person who is appre-
hended for an offence, many of whom are low risk and unlikely to reoffend, it is
difficult to identify whether, or to what extent, the scheme, or natural ‘evapora-
tion’, accounts for its low reconviction rate.
The Northants Scheme offers a comprehensive range of rehabilitative,
educational, vocational and ‘use of leisure’ programmes alongside the restorative
elements; but hereby hangs a key methodological problem. Because restorative
justice is just one component of a more complex and extensive programme of
intervention, it is difficult, if not impossible, to isolate its effects.
In their meta-analysis of ten US ‘restitutive’ intervention programmes,
Lipsey and Wilson (1998) found little effect on the recidivism rates of ‘non-
institutionalised’ but persistent juvenile offenders. Van Hooris (1985) found
that restorative justice routinely failed to change the attitudes of ‘low-maturity
persistent offenders’. A study undertaken by Gendreau (1996), found even less
promising results in terms of recidivism, but divined an ‘interaction effect’
which resulted in an escalation of offending rates amongst low-risk offenders.
This was largely because referral into the programme put them at heightened
risk of non-compliance and, as a result, vulnerable to the penal sanctions
which could then be imposed upon them. On the other hand, these
programmes were deemed to be insufficiently intensive to meet the needs of
higher-risk offenders.
Theoretical problems
At the level of theory, there is an important question about the mechanisms of
change which are triggered by restorative interventions. We do not know
whether, or to what extent, young offenders can generalise their identification
with the particular victim they have harmed to an empathy with other poten-
tial victims. The Kirkholt study (Forrester et al. 1990) suggests that ‘burglars’
divide the world into legitimate and illegitimate targets, raising the possibility,
suggested by reconviction studies, that even restorative justice programmes
rated ‘successful’ by both victims and offenders may serve only to delegitimise a
specific victim, rather than all potential victims, in the minds of young
offenders.
186 John Pitts
Mentoring
New Labour has wholeheartedly embraced the idea of mentoring. A central
aim of its Quality Protects, Leaving Residential Care and Connexions
programmes, as well as its youth justice strategy, requires that each young
person should have a mentor. At present, the YJB funds approximately fifty
mentoring schemes in YOTs.
The term ‘mentor’ denotes a loyal, wise and trusted teacher, guide and friend.
In recent years in the US, mentoring, in the guise of ‘buddying’, ‘big broth-
ering’, ‘positive peer influence programs’ or ‘companionship therapy’, has been
utilised extensively with young people experiencing problems of academic
attainment, personal conduct and crime and violence. Mentoring was embraced
by African-American activists in the 1980s as a means of transcending the
barriers to social mobility occasioned by the profound socio-economic disadvan-
tages experienced by about one-third of black Americans, and the
‘institutionalised racism’ encountered by them all. This approach to mentoring
proceeds from the assumption that the mentor and the mentee share similar
aspirations, values and goals. What distinguishes the mentee is his or her lack of
access to opportunities for the realisation of these aspirations, values and goals.
Thus, mentoring becomes a tool for emancipation, a means whereby the
mentee is helped to navigate hostile social terrain.
However, as mentoring has spread, it has been adopted by a broad range of
educational, employment, social welfare and youth justice organisations with
different goals and different priorities. In the process the focus of mentoring has
shifted from advice, guidance and advocacy to a concern to ‘correct’ those
shortcomings in the mentee which prevent him or her from entering the social,
economic or moral mainstream. While ‘emancipatory’ mentoring is borne of a
critique of an inequitable social order which keeps lower-class young people
down, and out, ‘correctional mentoring’ finds the origins of such ‘social exclu-
sion’ within the mentee.
Government minister Margaret Hodge, for example, writing in The Times, notes
that: ‘Mentors can help to break the vicious circle. They are invaluable in
helping boys who lack a father figure at home. It could be simply by making sure
that they get up in time for school (The Times, 10 April 1998). In most
mentoring schemes, ‘role modelling’ is identified as the key medium of change.
The usual rationales for role modelling are redolent of the traditional
approaches to the teaching of history which assert that the young need heroes
with whom to identify and emulate. However, what a ‘role model’ actually is,
and the mechanisms whereby its positive or negative attributes are transmitted
to, and introjected by, the mentee is the subject of continuing controversy.
Methodological problems
However, these claims have tended to be most frequent in evaluations under-
taken by the agencies which provide mentoring programmes and they must
therefore be regarded with a degree of scepticism. Such evaluations may tend,
for understandable reasons, to ‘accentuate the positive’ and overlook, or under-
play, areas where no change occurs or where problems actually worsen. As with
certain evaluations of cognitive skills training programmes, some mentoring
schemes select their ‘control groups’ from young people who decline the offer to
join the scheme. The danger here is that they may then be comparing a group
of youngsters who are motivated to change with a control group which is not.
Other American research, on the effectiveness of mentoring with young
offenders, is far less encouraging. An analysis of the ten ‘best-evaluated’
mentoring programmes, carried out for the US Department of Justice in the
early 1990s (Brewer et al. 1995), suggests that ‘non-contingent supportive
mentoring relationships’ (i.e., programmes which did not utilise a cognitive-
skills training approach involving the systematic manipulation of rewards and
sanctions – but see above for a critique of cognitive-skills training), failed to
achieve their goals in terms of academic attainment, ‘dropping out’, behavioural
change or employment. This analysis also points to ‘interaction effects’, citing
evaluations which revealed significantly increased delinquency for young people
with no previous offences but significantly decreased recidivism for youngsters
with prior offences (Goodman 1972; Fo and O’Donnell 1974).
Hellen Colley (2000) points to a key problem at the heart of mentoring
programmes developed in furtherance of particular government policies:
It [the study] revealed significant gaps between the goals and assumptions
of the scheme, and the desires and needs of the mentees. Many mentees
and mentors felt unduly constrained by the tight focus. … Some mentees
developed resistance strategies to avoid scheme requirements, whilst others
were dismissed from the scheme. Some mentors accepted the young
person’s agenda whilst others tried to impose the official view. Either way
188 John Pitts
Inadmissible evidence
Although the Home Office and the Youth Justice Board make great play of the
fact that the correctional techniques which underpin the community-based and
custodial penalties in the youth justice provision of the 1998 Act are ‘evidence-
based’, the evidence is, at least, equivocal. Clearly it is much harder to specify,
institutionalise and regulate a restricted repertoire of professional practices, as
the Home Office, the Youth Justice Board and the agencies and organisations
associated with them aim to do, if the evidence upon which they are based is
shown to be ambiguous. As a result, these powerful ‘claim-making agencies’
tend to cite only the evidence which indicates that the theories and practices
they have championed ‘work’. Yet, as Pawson and Tilley (1997) argue, whether
or not an intervention ‘works’, in the sense that it promotes the desired
behavioural change in a young offender, may have little to do with the correc-
tional technique applied to them. Like Colley (2000), they challenge the
assumption at the heart of the new correctionalism, that programmes somehow
work ‘on’ individuals; arguing instead that programmes can only work ‘through’
individuals. They write:
Conclusion
The judicial and administrative arrangements brought into being by the Crime
and Disorder Act (1998) threaten to draw greater numbers of younger, less
problematic, children and young people into the youth justice system, to subject
them to modes of correctional intervention which have not been shown to be
The new correctionalism 189
References
Andrews, D., Zinger, R., Hoge, J., Bonta, P., Gendreau, P. and Cullen, F. (1990) ‘Does
Correctional Treatment Work? Clinically Relevant and Psychologically Informed
Meta-Analysis’, Criminology, 28: 369–404.
Audit Commission (1996) Misspent Youth: Young People and Crime, London: The Audit
Commission.
Braithwaite, J. (1979) Inequality, Crime and Social Policy, London: Routledge and Kegan
Paul.
—— (1981) ‘The Myth of Social Class and Criminality Reconsidered’, American Socio-
logical Review, 46: 36–57.
—— (1989) Reintegrative Shaming, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
—— and Daly, K. (1994) ‘Masculinities, Violence, and Communitarian Control’, in T.
Stanko and T. Newburn (eds) Just Boys Doing Business, London: Routledge.
Brewer, D., Hawkins, J., Catalano, B. and Neckerman, H. (1995) ‘Preventing Serious,
Violent and Chronic Juvenile Offending: A Review of Evaluations of Selected Strate-
gies in Childhood, Adolescence and the Community’, in J. Howell, B. Krisburg, J.
Hawkins and J. Wilson, Serious, Violent and Chronic Juvenile Offenders, London: Sage
Publications.
Campbell, B. (1995) Goliath, Britain’s Dangerous Places, London: Methuen.
Christie, N. (1977) ‘Conflicts as Property’, British Journal of Criminology, 17: 1–15.
Clear, H. and Hardeyman, C. (1990) ‘The New Intensive Supervision Movement’,
Crime and Delinquency, 36: 42–60.
Colley, H. (2000) What Do We Think We’re Doing? How Mentors’ Beliefs About Disaffec-
tion Influence the Process of Mentoring Disaffected Young People, Paper presented to
BERA Post-16 Special Interest Group, Milton Keynes.
Crimmens, D. and Pitts, J. (2000) Positive Residential Practice, Learning the Lessons of the
1990s, Lyme Regis: Russell House Publishing.
190 John Pitts
ILYJS (1995) Statement of Principles and Practice, London: National Association for the
Care and Resettlement of Offenders.
Johnstone, G. (2000) ‘Penal Policy Making: Elitist, Populist or Participatory’, Punishment
and Society, 2(2): 161–80.
Jones, K. (2001) ‘An Analysis of the Deviant Careers of Young People Placed Upon the
Child Protection Register of One London Borough’, unpublished M.Phil. thesis,
University of Luton.
Karger, H. J. (1991) ‘The Radical Right and Welfare Reform in the United States’, in H.
Glennester and J. Midgley (eds) The Radical Right and the Welfare State: An Interna-
tional Assessment, London: Harvester Wheatsheaf.
Lea, J. and Young, J. (1988) What is to Be Done About Law and Order?, Harmondsworth:
Penguin.
Lipsey, M. and Wilson, D. (1998) ‘Effective Intervention for Serious Juvenile Offenders:
A Synthesis of Research’, in R. Loeber and D. Farrington (eds) Serious and Violent
Juvenile Offenders: Risk Factors and Successful Interventions, Thousand Oaks: Sage
Publications.
Loveday, B. and Marlow, A. (2000) Policing After MacPherson, Lyme Regis: Russell House
Publishing.
Mair, P. (2000) ‘Partyless Democracy: Solving the Paradox of New Labour’, New Left
Review, March/April: 21–36.
Mandelson, P. and Liddle, R. (1996) The Blair Revolution, London: Faber.
Marquand, D. (1999) ‘Progressive or Populist? The Blair Paradox’, in D. Marquand (ed.)
The Progressive Dilemma: From Lloyd George to Blair, 2nd edition, London: Verso,
225–46.
Martinson, R. (1974) ‘What Works? – Questions About Prison Reform’, The Public
Interest, Spring: 22–54.
Matthews, R. and Pitts, J. (1998) ‘Rehabilitation, Recidivism and Realism: Evaluating
Violence Reduction Programs in Prison’, The Prison Journal, 78(4): 390–405.
Mehlbye, J., Sommer, B. and Walgrave, L. (1998) Confronting Youth in Europe: Juvenile
Crime and Juvenile Justice, Denmark: AKF.
Mika, H. and Zehr, H. (1997) Fundamental Concepts of Restorative Justice, Harrisonburg,
VA: Mennonite Central Committee USA.
Muncie, J. (1999) Youth and Crime, London: Sage Publications.
Murray, C. (1994) Underclass: The Crisis Deepens, London: Institute of Economic
Affairs.
NACRO Young Offenders Committee (1997) 3Rs: Responsibility, Restoration and Reinte-
gration, London: NACRO.
Newburn, T. (1995) Crime and Criminal Justice Policy, London: Longman.
Pawson, R. and Tilley, N. (1997) Realistic Evaluation, London: Sage Publications.
Perfect, M. (1998) unpublished speech on the 1998 Criminal Justice Act delivered to
the Crime and Disorder Conference, Anglia Polytechnic University, New Hall,
Cambridge, September.
Phillips, M. (1994) ‘Is the Male Redundant Now?’, Observer, 26 May: 27.
Pitts, J. (1988) The Politics of Juvenile Crime, London: Sage Publications.
—— (1992) ‘The End of an Era’, Howard Journal, 31(2): 133–49.
—— (1997) ‘Youth Crime, Social Change and Crime Control in Britain and France in
the 1980s and 1990s’, in H. Jones (ed.) Towards a Classless Society, London: Routledge.
—— (2000a) Youth Justice, Research Matters, Community Care/Reed Business Informa-
tion, April–October: 56–60.
192 John Pitts
—— (2000b) ‘The New Youth Justice and the Politics of Electoral Anxiety’, in B.
Goldson (ed.) The New Youth Justice, Lyme Regis: Russell House Publishing.
—— and Hope, T. (1998) ‘The Local Politics of Inclusion: The State and Community
Safety’, Social Policy and Administration, 31(5): 37–58.
Porporino, F. and Robinson, D. (1995) ‘An Evaluation of the Reasoning and Rehabilita-
tion Program with Canadian Federal Offenders’, in R. Ross and R. Ross (eds)
Thinking Straight, Ottawa: Air Training Publications.
Preston, R. H. (1980) ‘Social Theology and Penal Theory and Practice: The Collapse of
the Rehabilitative Ideal and the Search for an Alternative’, in A. E. Bottoms and R.
H. Preston (eds) The Coming Penal Crisis, Edinburgh: Scottish Academic Press.
Sampson, R. J. and Laub, J. (1993) Crime in the Making: Pathways and Turning Points,
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
——, Raudenbush, S. W. and Earls, F. (1997) ‘Neighbourhoods and Violent Crime: A
Multi-Level Study of Collective Efficacy’, Science 277 (15 August): (page nos. not
known).
Sherman, L., Gottfredson, D., MacKenzie, J., Reuter, P. and Bushway, S. (1998)
Preventing Crime: What Works, What Doesn’t, What’s Promising, Washington, DC: US
Department of Justice.
Simon, J. (2000) ‘From the Big House to the Warehouse: Rethinking Prisons and State
Government in the 20th century’, Punishment and Society, 2(2): 213–34.
—— (2001) ‘Entitlement to Cruelty: Neo-liberalism and the Punitive Mentality in the
United States’, in K. Stenson and R. Sullivan (eds) Crime, Risk and Justice, Devon:
Willan.
Skynner, R. (1974) ‘The Minimum Sufficient Network’, Social Work Today, 14 July.
Sutherland, E. (1934) Principles of Criminology, Chicago: J. B. Lippincott and Co.
Thorpe, D., Smith, D., Green, C. and Paley, J. (1980) Out of Care, London: Allen &
Unwin.
Utting, W., Bright, J. and Hendrickson, B. (1993) Crime and the Family, Improving Child
Rearing and Preventing Delinquency, Family Policy Studies Centre, Paper no.16,
London: Family Policy Studies Centre.
Van Hooris, P. (1985) ‘Restitution Outcome and Probationer’s Assessments of Restitu-
tion: The Effects of Moral Development’, Criminal Justice and Behaviour, 12: 259–87.
Vanstone, M. (2000) ‘Cognitive-Behavioural Work with Offenders in the UK: A History
of Influential Endeavour’, The Howard Journal, 39(2): 171–83.
Warner Report (1996) Choosing with Care, London: Department of Health.
West, D. and Farrington, D. (1973) Who Becomes Delinquent?, London: Heinemann.
Wikstrom, T. and Loeber, R.(1997) ‘Individual Risk Factors, Neighbourhood SES and
Juvenile Offending’, in M. Tonry (ed.) The Handbook of Crime and Punishment, New
York: Oxford University Press.
Wilson, J. Q. and Kelling, G. (1982) ‘Broken Windows: The Police and Neighbourhood
Safety’, Atlantic Monthly (March): 29–38.
Young, J. (1999) The Exclusive Society, London: Sage Publications.
Youth Justice Task Force (1998) The Final Report of the Youth Justice Task Force, London:
Youth Justice Board of England and Wales.
8 Crime victimisation and
inequality in risk society
Tim Hope
Introduction
We live in both a risk society (Beck 1992) and an exclusive society (Young 1999).
At the same time as we orient ourselves around the risks and dangers which we
see surrounding us in our everyday lives, so also do our social and political
arrangements lend themselves to the magnification of inequalities in access to
those goods which reassure, protect or expose ourselves to risk. As our percep-
tion of the ‘bads’ increases, so do we seek to garner the ‘goods’ which would keep
them at bay, trading on our capital reserves and capacities across the various
spheres of economy, community and culture. The ‘ontological insecurity’ which
the condition of late modernity inspires in us (Giddens 1990; Young 1999) fuses
with the apprehension of mundane insecurities, pressurising us to invest in the
means of risk avoidance (Hope and Sparks 2000). As we feel increasingly that the
public sphere alone can no longer guarantee sufficiently the public goods of
everyday safety (see Garland 1996), so we are thrown upon our own individual
and collective resources and strategies to acquire the private goods which would
remedy our perceived security deficit. And our incapacity to protect ourselves
from risk leads to frustration with government – still seen as the primary
provider of safety in modern society – and with ourselves, as a reflection of our
own powerlessness in the face of the risks and harms that surround us.
Yet, access to capital in one sphere – for instance, through income and
wealth – remains an important commodity for acquiring capital in another
sphere – for example, in ‘community safety’ – promising to buy ourselves out of
risk and into security. That the dynamic of consuming private security itself may
be inherently and literally unsatisfying (Loader 1997) is not in itself a guarantee
that we will not continue to consume at an ever increasingly voracious rate.
And if security is a relative or ‘positional’ good – one that acquires value for its
possessor to the extent that others do not possess it to the same degree (Hirsch
1977) – then to the degree that those with capital successfully pursue their
private strategies of risk avoidance, those without will become increasingly
excluded from access to the goods of private security (Hope 1999; 2000).
Existing social inequalities will thus be reproduced in the newer spheres of risk
and risk avoidance.
194 Tim Hope
The history of risk distribution shows that, like wealth, risks adhere to the
class pattern, only inversely: wealth accumulates at the top, risks at the
bottom. To that extent, risks seem to strengthen, not to abolish, the class
society. Poverty attracts an unfortunate abundance of risks. By contrast, the
wealthy (in income, power or education) can purchase safety and freedom
from risk.
(Beck 1992: 35, original emphases)
What differentiates the allocation of risks and safety between rich and poor
in risk society is precisely the individualisation which sunders traditional class-
based risks:
The ability to chose and maintain one’s own social relations is not an
ability everyone has by nature. It is, as sociologists of class know, a learned
ability which depends on special social and family backgrounds. The reflexive
conduct of life, the planning of one’s own biography and social relations,
gives rise to a new inequality, the inequality of dealing with insecurity and
reflexivity.
(Beck 1992: 98 original emphases)
As Pierre Bourdieu (1998) has shown in his various works, while the possession
of economic capital is a great enabler, the power of economic capital to shape
its possessors’ lifestyles and opportunities finds its expression and reinforcement
chiefly through its capacity to accumulate other forms of capital – social,
cultural, symbolic – which operate to achieve advantages for their possessors in
varying ways in diverse social spaces. In this respect, then, inequality in income
and status no longer ascribes a fixed quota of risk so much as it facilitates or
impedes the deployment of necessary and effective capital and capacities for avoiding
risk and/or acquiring safety. Though these acquisitions are achieved through indi-
vidualised strategies of everyday life, reflecting diversity and differentiation of
lifestyle and routine activity, their collective consequences and outcomes may
nevertheless reveal the aggregate inequalities of income and status that affect
the distribution of individual capacities and choices. The next part of this
chapter seeks to test this proposition in relation to the risk of property crime
victimisation.
because the victimising act itself is the result of a convergence of two separate
processes:
This convergence has been expressed also in terms of the conditions necessary
for a criminal event to happen – what has become known as the routine activity
approach, comprising the convergence of ‘suitable’ victims (or targets) and
‘motivated’ offenders in conditions (i.e., low ‘guardianship’) where it is unlikely
that a third party capable of exercising control over the situation will intervene
(Cohen and Felson 1979). Two basic distributions affecting the likelihood of
property crime victimisation risk can be distilled from this literature (for which
see Felson 1998; Miethe and Meier 1994):
Nevertheless, there are different social positions which the ‘rich’ and ‘poor’
are able to take up in relation to these risks (I use these terms for ease of presen-
tation, though advisedly).
200 Tim Hope
1 The rich have more valuable and attractive property to steal – and may be
relatively more casual in safeguarding it if they have full household insur-
ance and relatively low premiums and excesses – i.e., the phenomenon of
moral hazard (Litton 1982).
2 As more household members are likely to be in full-time employment, they
are more likely to leave their homes unattended during weekdays and holidays.
3 Their dwellings may be easier to enter unobserved – for example, larger,
detached houses in their own grounds may afford more opportunities for
unobserved and undisturbed access to property (Hope 1984; 1999; 2000;
Winchester and Jackson 1982; Maguire 1982).
Nevertheless, the rich may be less vulnerable than the poor because:
1 They are more likely to purchase or adopt a greater range of household secu-
rity measures, especially more expensive home surveillance systems (Hope
2000).
2 They may take greater security precautions in their everyday lives because
they may be more ‘risk-averse’ (Field and Hope 1990) – for example, by
believing they have much to lose from crime victimisation, including the
peace and tranquillity of their communities (Loader et al. 2000).
The ‘poor’ may also be more vulnerable to household property crime than the
rich, because they are less able to afford, or have available, security measures and
protection (Hope 2000). But they may be less vulnerable to victimisation
because, being poor or unemployed, they may be more likely to spend time in
the home environment, thus exercising more guardianship over their household
property (Cantor and Land 1985).
Exposure to risk
In the context of household property crime, exposure to risk primarily means
exposure to active property crime offenders. Here, the likelihood is that the
poor will be more exposed to risk than the rich because they are more likely to
live in areas where active property offenders are also likely to live (Wikstrom 1998).
People who live near poor people are also likely to be active in property
crime against the poor because:
2 Young males in poor areas may also be subject to less supervision and social
control in the community, and spend more time in public in the company of
their peers, all of which are conducive to the development of active crimi-
nality (see Wikstrom 1998).
3 They may also be more frequent property criminals because they have a need
for a greater return from crime – for example, to supplement income, or
support a drug habit (cf. Sullivan 1989) – or because their (poor) victims
yield a lower per offence return of valuable items.
4 They are less likely to travel to other areas to commit crime because (a) they
lack transport or (b) are averse to committing crime in unfamiliar areas,
where they might stand out (Bottoms and Wiles 1997).
As a corollary, the rich may be less exposed to risk than the poor because
they are more likely to avoid crime by living in the kinds of area which are
orderly (i.e., they do not contain active resident offenders or keep such potential
persons under some kind of social control), distant (i.e., not close to places
containing offenders) and/or buffered from criminal areas (i.e., there are other
areas or obstacles lying between them and source of criminals – see Hope 1999).
Nonetheless, some of the rich may be more at risk than other rich, or even
than other poor, if they live in closer proximity to the poor (see above) by
living in ‘mixed class’ neighbourhoods or ‘gentrified enclaves’ in otherwise
deprived urban areas (see Hope 2000; Hirschfield and Bowers 1997).
In sum, various considerations of both opportunities for crime and exposure
to risk result in differing predictions about the risks of household property crime
for the ‘rich’ and the ‘poor’ respectively. These contradictory predictions may be
enough to satisfy those who regard only universal consistency as ‘proof’ of any
axiom (e.g., Wilson and Herrnstein 1985). Because the rich are, in this case,
sometimes more at risk than the poor, then victimisation it is suggested must be
classless. Nevertheless, as will be suggested below, while the above predictions
are apparent only with other things being equal (as they are in multivariate, statis-
tical analysis) the likely reality is usually that other things are not equal. And
one of the key inequalities is that rich and poor have, in sum, unequal propensi-
ties towards the various opportunity and risk factors of property crime
victimisation.
Models of risk
A certain kind of approach to causation tends to see these as separate questions.
In this kind of reasoning, the existence of opportunities and exposure processes
are thought to indicate particular explanations of crime. For example, that
offending is a matter of rational choice on the part of the offender such that the
task of explanation is to demonstrate that these are general processes, irrespec-
tive of their observed correlation with other distributions, such as income and
wealth which, likewise, are taken to be indicators of competing explanations of
crime, offender motivation, or the absence of social control. In some versions of
202 Tim Hope
this approach, the causal contenders are required to ‘slug it out’ to see which one
wins outright. In other versions, the task is to apportion the explanatory spoils –
so much to this one, so much to that – so as to develop and test ‘integrated’
theories. Methodologically, these causal strategies require clear specification of
expected effects, the development of measurement indicators which are unam-
biguous (i.e., which either measure opportunity/exposure processes or those of
motivation and control), reliable sampling strategies, and the use of appropriate
multivariate techniques of statistical analysis (see Miethe and Meier 1994, for
an elaboration of this research strategy).
Although in the past we had only officially-recorded crime data, now we
routinely possess one other source of data containing potential risk factors
Table 8.1 Household and area risk factors for household property crime
Affluence?
cars per household (–)
deprivation index (–):
• overcrowded households
• large families
• housing association rental
• male unemployment
‘poor’ ACORN groups (+)
Source: 1992 British Crime Survey (BCS), 1991 UK Census (Osborn and Tseloni 1998; Ellingworth et al.
1997); 1996/1998 BCS, 1991 UK Census (Budd 1999).
Note: Household property crime includes: burglary, theft from dwelling and criminal damage to property
associated with the dwelling, its contents or grounds. A plus sign (+) = a positive risk factor (crime risk is
increased); a minus sign (–) = a negative risk factor (crime risk is reduced).
Crime victimisation and inequality 203
associated with particular opportunities and risks, part of the answer at least lies
in addressing two questions:
1 What is the appropriate level at which risk factors for household property
crime operate – are they a product of communities or individuals, and
which risk factors operate at which level?
2 How are rich and poor distributed within and between communities so that,
even if they had different propensities towards risk, the pattern of their
respective ecological distributions would result in the observed area pattern
of outcomes?
One strategy for research would be to allocate risk factors a priori to each
level – for example so that factors conjectured to be indexing the supply of
offenders would be allocated to the community level, while those indexing
opportunities would be allocated to the individual level (Miethe and Meier
1994). Yet while there may be some merit in this approach, again, it relies
upon unambiguous specification, not only in the measurement of indicators
but also in their allocation to the appropriate level. In practice, few data sets
are able to afford this, even if it were conceptually possible to do so with
respect to every risk factor. Yet even if the rich and poor had consistently
different types of risk propensity, we would still be left with how to handle the
possibility that the varying outcomes observed were due to the different distri-
butions of rich and poor within and between communities. In other words, we
need to consider how community and household risk interacts to produce
victimisation outcomes (Miethe and Meier 1994) and how such interaction is
conditioned by the respective distributions of rich and poor between and within
communities.
If we consider area level risk factors to have in common the possibility that
differences in victimisation represent differences in exposure to risk (in the
shape of active property offenders), then residents of poor areas will have more
exposure to risk than those in rich areas, because poor areas may contain or
attract more frequent and active property offenders than rich areas (Felson
1998: Chapter 2).
Consequently, how the different propensities of rich and poor to household
property crime victimisation are produced will therefore depend upon the
balance of opportunities to crime and exposures to risk attaching to individual
households, relative to the social context in which they are located. For example, we
might expect to observe some of the following interactions:
1 That the poor in poor areas have a higher risk than, say, the poor in rich areas
because, over and above the balance of opportunity and risk associated with
poverty, they are more exposed to risk by virtue of their area of residence.
2 The rich in poor areas also have higher risks than the rich in rich areas
because they are more exposed to offenders and have more goods to steal.
Crime victimisation and inequality 205
3 The rich in rich areas may have a higher risk than the poor in rich areas
because they present more opportunities.
Nevertheless, whether we can observe these interactions will also depend upon
how the individual rich and poor are distributed between rich and poor areas. In
this respect, the overall pattern of outcomes of property crime victimisation risk
– whether in respect of individuals or communities – will depend upon the class
mix distribution of potential risk propensities attaching to the rich and the poor
as they are distributed, ‘ecologically’, across the range of communities (see
Braithwaite 1979, for an investigation of the class mix hypothesis with regard
mainly to offending propensities). Even though the ‘modernisation risks’ of
property crime victimisation may be similar for rich and poor, the specific posi-
tions which they may be able to take with regard to these risks may vary
according both to their personal and social circumstances. The next section
provides an empirical investigation of these possibilities.
These are listed in Table 8.2. None of these indices constitutes a perfect
measure of affluence or deprivation, and some relevant BCS data are left out.
For instance, household income in the 1992 BCS has a high non-response rate
and may be unreliable – pace Pantazis and Gordon (1999) who conclude on the
basis of this variable that the rich experience more crime than the poor.
Nevertheless, the variables used aim to capture primary aspects of economic
206 Tim Hope
opportunity (e.g., educational level) and consumption (e.g., car access and
housing tenure) which have come to be seen increasingly as important surrogate
measures for income and quality of life (JRF 1995). Additionally, these variables
have already been used in multivariate models of risk (see Table 8.1). Finally,
given the binary nature of the indicators – and the observation that the
frequency distribution of victimisation is not normally distributed (Osborn and
Tseloni 1998), relatively simple descriptive and distribution-free statistical tech-
niques were used to investigate the possibility of interaction effects of the kind
noted above.
Table 8.3 shows the correlation between the various indices and property
crime victimisation. As a check on the validity of our indices, there is a strong,
Table 8.5 summarises patterns of risk according to the individual risk factors
used in our overall indices. In the least deprived parts of the country (first and
second quintiles), those most at risk are younger households, and those with
young children and/or two or more cars. Those least at risk are persons not in
work, including the elderly, and those who do not own a car. In the most
deprived parts of the country (fourth and fifth quintiles), those most at risk
include renters, families with young children, lone-parent households and both
young adults and the middle-aged. In both rich and poor Britain, then, there
would seem to be a clear divide in household property crime risk between the
younger population and the older, less mobile, and retired populations.
Arguably, much the same sort of risk processes apply: for instance, younger
households are more likely to leave their homes unoccupied and to have fewer
adults around the home environment to supervise activity (Felson 1998).
Additionally, the relatively more affluent households may also be more vulner-
able because of their possession of more desirable goods – in richer Britain these
may be the two-car-plus households; in poorer Britain they are likely to be the
middle-aged. Yet at the extremes of income, households may be able to buy (or
not buy) themselves out of risk. Thus, in affluent Britain, owners of detached
houses may be able to afford sufficient security in order to offset their attractive-
ness to burglars at the level of risk present in their communities (see Hope
1999; 2000); something perhaps unachievable for detached house dwellers in
poorer neighbourhoods, as their relatively greater risk in the fourth quintile
suggests. Similarly, in poorer Britain, renters may be more vulnerable to victimi-
sation than owners, not only because they are living in the same
neighbourhoods (e.g., social housing estates) as offenders but also because they
are unable to take many security precautions (Hope 2000).
Finally, how does the class mix of an area affect its crime rate? Looking at the
distribution of property crime rates between neighbourhoods, we can estimate
that around one-fifth of the victims of household property crime live in the 10
Crime victimisation and inequality 209
Table 8.5 Risk factors for household property crime victimisation by level of area
deprivation
Risk factor Q1 Q2 Q3 Q4 Q5
renter 0 0 + + +
not in work – 0 0 0 0
young + 0 + + +
children
lone parent 0 0 + 0 +
young adult + 0 + + 0
no car – 0 0 0 0
low 0 0 0 0 0
education
middle- + + 0 0 +
aged
two-plus + + 0 0 0
cars
detached 0 – – + 0
house
Source: 1992 British Crime Survey, 1991 UK Census
Notes: + signifies a positive risk; – signifies a negative risk; 0 signifies no significant risk. All differences in
means significant at p ⬍ .055 (Mann-Whitney U-Test)
per cent of the residential areas with the highest crime rates, and suffer over one-
third of the total of household property crime (which itself constitutes just under
one half of all victimisation recorded in the BCS). Over half of all property
crime – and over one-third of all property crime victims – are likely to be found
in just one-fifth of the communities of England and Wales. Conversely, the 50
per cent of communities of England and Wales with the lowest crime rates suffer
merely 15 per cent of household property crime victimisation, spread between a
quarter of victims (Hope 1996; 1997). Inequality in both individual and area
distributions go together – victims who are multiply (or repeatedly) victimised in
a given period are more likely to live in high crime rate areas than are other, less
frequently victimised victims (Osborn and Tseloni 1998; Trickett et al. 1992).
Figure 8.2 suggests, broadly, that this inequality in the distribution of commu-
nity crime risks is correlated with the ratio of the poor to the rich within the
community. It suggests not only that as the crime rate of the community
increases, so does the ratio between poor and rich within the community but also
that the concentration of the crime rate coincides with the increasing rate of
concentration of the poor. Thus, the 20 per cent of communities with the highest
crime rates not only have appreciably higher crime rates than other communities
but also have much greater numbers of the ‘poor’ relative to the ‘rich’.
Although the data presented here are relatively crude measures of risk and
social position they derive nevertheless from a representative national survey and
provide some guidance about crime victimisation risk, albeit roughly calibrated.
In general, they provide some evidence on the likely social risk positions of the
‘rich’ and the ‘poor’ with respect to property crime victimisation. Although the
210 Tim Hope
‘modernisation risks’ of residential crime – that is, the risk attaching to environ-
ment, occupancy, value and security – may be generally applicable to most
instances of victimisation and are therefore, in a broad sense, ‘classless’, the
specific social risk positions which rich and poor adopt in respect of these risks
vary considerably. Moreover, there does not seem to be any intrinsic risk
attaching to individual class position; rather, the risk of victimisation associated
with being rich or poor depends upon the social (community) context in which
individuals are located. And a primary feature of that social context is its class
mix: specifically, the concentration of the ‘poor’ relative to the ‘rich’. The
concluding section of this chapter considers some of the political ramifications.
expected by its citizens (Garland 1996). Yet, this responsibilisation strategy on the
part of the state vis-à-vis its citizens does not necessarily contain within it a
conception of the public good. Citizens are not being asked to carry out altru-
istic acts of intervention, such as to mount guard on other people’s homes, to
engage in self-denial, or to give up the desire for or possession of CD players or
portable televisions. Rather, they are being expected to attain security both for
themselves and in the aggregate, largely through the pursuit of their own indi-
vidual self-interest in the avoidance of risk. This is not unlike developments in
other areas of social welfare provision and may be part of an emerging ‘new
orthodoxy’ of welfare (Jordan 1998). Yet a core belief in rational self-interest is
no guarantee that the resulting outcomes in terms of the distribution of risk and
safety will be equitable nor, as important, deducible simply from the summation
of individual rational strategies. Rather, it will involve:
Class differences in income and wealth may result in different risk positions
occupied respectively by rich and poor via the resources and strategies which
affect individuals’ ability to avoid risk. Yet the collective consequences of individ-
uals’ strategies may produce inequalities in access to safety and the avoidance of risk.
We can illustrate some of the resulting problems with reference to the data
presented in this chapter.
Simply put, the likely most effective strategy of property crime risk avoid-
ance on the part of the poor is for them to remove themselves from high-risk areas
and live amongst richer neighbours. Reference to Table 8.4 suggests that if they
can get into the richest neighbourhoods their risk will greatly reduce, possibly
to the extent that they become less at risk than the rich. Unfortunately for
them, the most rational individual strategy for the rich to avoid property crime
is to avoid the poor. Risk seems to increase the greater the ratio of poor to rich in
a community (see Figure 8.2), and the rich in poor areas face a higher risk than
that of the rich in rich areas. Other things being equal (which they rarely are),
neither poor nor rich have intrinsic crime victimisation propensities which
they carry around with them (Table 8.4). So, in principle, the individual rich
do not have anything to fear from the individual poor by allowing them to live
alongside them (see Table 8.5). But they do seem to have something to fear by
way of increased risk if they allow too many poor to be their neighbours (Figure
8.2), presumably because this would increase the chances of living in closer
proximity to active offenders. Whatever the niceties of the situation, the strate-
gies of risk avoidance for rich and poor end up as radically opposed because,
212 Tim Hope
rationally, each would see the other as part of their solution to their individual
problems of risk avoidance.
ishes the more that the poor successfully overcome the barriers to sharing the
positional security advantages of the rich. As Table 8.4 and Figure 8.2 show, the
fewer the rich who live among them, the more their risk increases.
Thus, the defence of the better-off community against ‘encroachment’
becomes an important weapon in the preservation of neighbourhood values and
amenities, including security. Much community action in suburbs is ‘preserva-
tionist’ (Savage et al. 1992), not least with regard to anti-crime efforts (Skogan
1988), and better-off communities do have some advantages in generating
resources to defend themselves. The ‘weak’, overlapping ties which characterise
social relationships in better-off suburbs (see Baumgartner 1988; Loader et al.
2000) provide linkages between sources of power and influence within a
community (Granovetter 1973). These also provide opportunities for network
‘closure’, creating a collective reciprocity of social obligation from which social
capital can be generated (Coleman 1990). In turn, social capital can be
mobilised to create collective goods like community organisations and residents
associations. These groups can then cash-in the (symbolic and cultural) capital
which the neighbourhood holds with extra-communal sources of power, such as
public police and local government, to mobilise resources to preserve neigh-
bourhood amenities, including security (Skogan 1988). Without external
intervention, the market in private security becomes a struggle for positional
advantage amongst competing risk pools – a struggle to avoid the congesting
and crowding of positional security advantages. As Mike Davis observes of the
‘home-owner’ politics of the communities of Los Angeles:
In contrast to the rich, increasing poverty in the social mix of the commu-
nity seems to be associated with a greater victimisation of the poor (Figure 8.2).
Further, a concentration of poverty in the community results in a greater concentra-
tion of victimisation amongst the poorer sectors of such communities (Table 8.4).
And to the extent that the poor are excluded, whether consciously or not, from
the security pools of the rich, they face the danger of becoming trapped in the
risk pools of poor neighbourhoods and neighbours. In late modernity a key
characteristic of the communities of concentrated poverty is the concentration of
social dislocation (Waquant 1995; Lash and Urry 1994; Wilson 1987). The expe-
rience of destabilised neighbourhoods caught in a spiral of economic and social
deterioration is increasingly one where adverse circumstances ratchet together
to produce compounded social dislocations for both residents individually and
214 Tim Hope
do not benefit others less protected than themselves and, at worst, reinforce the
latter’s insecurity.
The collective consequences of crime risk avoidance in risk society is the
creation of risk pools dictated according to one’s social position, either by
choice or fate. The collapse of the state’s universal insurance policy against
crime victimisation risk (Garland 1996) may have induced a dynamic which
encourages the clubbing of private security (Hope 2000). As Jordan (1996) argues
with respect to social security in general, the logic of collective action – albeit
the unintended consequence of individualised strategies of risk pooling and risk
avoidance – may act to reinforce social exclusion – the transformation of indi-
vidual disadvantage into an ascribed social position. In a great many respects, in
risk society the threat of crime victimisation is not just a consequence of social
exclusion but also a contributory cause. The challenge facing government
remains whether and how to intervene – not just to reduce risk but also how to
distribute fairly the means for dealing with risk.
References
Barr, R. and Pease, K. (1990) ‘Crime Placement, Displacement and Deflection’, in M.
Tonry and N. Morris (eds) Crime and Justice, volume 12, Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Baumgartner, M. P. (1988) The Moral Order of a Suburb, New York: Oxford University
Press.
Beck, U. (1992) Risk Society, London: Sage.
Bourdieu, P. (1998) Practical Reason, Cambridge: Polity Press.
Bottoms, A. E. and Wiles, P. (1997) ‘Environmental Criminology’, in M. Maguire, R.
Morgan and R. Reiner (1997) The Oxford Handbook of Criminology, 2nd edition,
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Braithwaite, J. (1979) Inequality, Crime and Public Policy, London: Routledge and Kegan
Paul.
Budd, T. (1999) Burglary of Domestic Dwellings: Findings from the British Crime Survey,
Home Office Statistical Bulletin, no. 4, London: Home Office.
Cantor, D. and Land, K. C. (1985) ‘Unemployment and Crime Rates in the Post-World
War II United States: A Theoretical and Empirical Analysis’, American Sociological
Review, 50: 317–23.
Cohen, L. E. and Felson, M. (1979) ‘Social Change and Crime Rate Trends: A Routine
Activities Approach’, American Sociological Review, 44: 588–608.
Coleman, J. S. (1990) Foundations of Social Theory, Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.
Davis, M. (1990) City of Quartz, London: Verso.
Ellingworth, D., Hope, T., Osborn, D. R., Trickett, A. and Pease, K. (1997) ‘Prior Victimi-
sation and Crime Risk’, Journal of Crime Prevention and Risk Management, 2: 201–14.
Ewald, U. (2000) ‘Criminal Victimization and Social Adaptation in Modernity: Fear of
Crime and Risk Perception in the New Germany’, in T. Hope and R. Sparks (eds)
Crime, Risk and Insecurity, London: Routledge.
Feeley, M. and Simon, J. (1993) ‘The New Penology: Notes on the Emerging Strategy of
Corrections and its Implications’, Criminology, 30: 449–74.
Felson, M. (1998) Crime and Everyday Life, 2nd edition, Thousand Oaks, CA: Pine Forge
Press.
Crime victimisation and inequality 217
Field, S. and Hope, T. (1990) ‘Economics, the Consumer and Under-Provision in Crime
Prevention’, in R. Morgan (ed.) Policing, Organised Crime and Crime Prevention,
British Criminology Conference 1989, volume 4, Bristol: Bristol Centre for Criminal
Justice.
Garland, D. (1996) ‘The Limits of the Sovereign State: Strategies of Crime Control in
Contemporary Society’, British Journal of Criminology, 36: 445–71.
Giddens, A.(1984) The Constitution of Society, Cambridge: Polity Press.
—— (1990) The Consequences of Modernity, Cambridge: Polity Press.
—— (1998) The Third Way, Cambridge: Polity Press.
Granovetter, M. S. (1973) ‘The Strength of Weak Ties’, American Journal of Sociology,
78: 1360–80.
Hirsch, F. (1977) Social Limits to Growth, London: Routledge.
Hirschfield, A. and Bowers, K. J. (1997) ‘The Development of a Social, Demographic
and Land Use Profiler for Areas of High Crime’, British Journal of Criminology, 37:
103–20.
Home Office (1999) The Government’s Crime Reduction Strategy, London: Home Office
Communication Directorate.
Hope, T. (1984) ‘Building Design and Burglary’, in R. Clarke and T. Hope (eds) Coping
with Burglary: Research Perspectives in Policy, Boston, MA: Kluwer Nijhoff.
—— (1995) ‘Community Crime Prevention’, in M. Tonry and D. P. Farrington (eds)
Building a Safer Society: Strategic Approaches to Crime Prevention, Crime and Justice,
volume 19, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
—— (1996) ‘Communities, Crime and Inequality in England and Wales’, in T. Bennett
(ed.) Preventing Crime and Disorder: Targeting Strategies and Responsibilities, Cambridge:
Institute of Criminology.
—— (1997) ‘Inequality and the Future of Community Crime Prevention’, in S. P. Lab
(ed.) Crime Prevention at a Crossroads, American Academy of Criminal Justice
Sciences Monograph Series, Cincinnati, Ohio: Anderson Publishing.
—— (1999) ‘Privatopia on Trial? Property Guardianship in the Suburbs’, in K. Painter
and N. Tilley (eds) Surveillance of Public Space, Crime Prevention Studies, volume 10,
Monsey, NY: Criminal Justice Press.
—— (2000) ‘Inequality and the Clubbing of Private Security’, in T. Hope and R. Sparks
(eds) Crime, Risk and Insecurity, London: Routledge.
—— and R. Sparks (2000) (eds) Crime, Risk and Insecurity, London: Routledge.
Jordan, B. (1996) A Theory of Poverty and Social Exclusion, Cambridge: Polity Press.
—— (1998) The New Politics of Welfare, London: Sage.
JRF (1995) Joseph Rowntree Foundation Inquiry into Income and Wealth, volumes 1 and 2,
York: Joseph Rowntree Foundation.
Lash, S. and Urry, J. (1994) Economies of Signs and Space, London: Sage.
Litton, R. A. (1982) ‘Crime Prevention and Insurance’, Howard Journal, 21: 6–22.
Reprinted in P. O’Malley (1998) (ed.) Crime and the Risk Society, Aldershot:
Ashgate/Dartmouth.
Loader, I. (1997) ‘Thinking Normatively About Private Security’, Journal of Law and
Society, 24: 377–94.
——, Girling, E. and Sparks, R. (2000) ‘After Success? Anxieties of Affluence in an
English Village’, in T. Hope and R. Sparks (eds) Crime, Risk and Insecurity, London:
Routledge.
Logan, J. H. and Molotch, H. (1987) Urban Fortunes: The Political Economy of Place,
Berkeley: University of California Press.
218 Tim Hope
2 Discuss the linkage between distributive justice and its sub-types, retribu-
tive and restorative justice, and how this linkage has been invoked in crime
policy.
3 Outline the current distribution of crime opportunities, and conclude that
their extreme inequality, and linkage with other social indices, suggests
distributive unfairness.
4 Set out some policy suggestions which would have the effect of remedying
such unfairness.
The notion of parallel ‘spheres of justice’ has been elaborated and applied to
specific policy choices by Elster (1989; 1992) and Young (1994). The same
notion is of potential importance to a resolution of the opposition taken by
Fraser (1997) to exist between justices of recognition and redistribution. In
brief, complex equality permits the elaboration of a differentiated view of what
should be equalised, and specifies relationships between status of different types.
Recognition is achieved when the attribute recognised carries no penalty in
other spheres, when for example gender carries no cost in violent victimisation
and pension entitlements. Young’s (1990) first attribute of ideal city life, ‘social
differentiation without exclusion’, describes a state of independence of status in
different spheres.
Fraser (1997: 13) makes a clear distinction between justices of redistribution
and recognition. The first is socio-economic injustice, ‘which is rooted in the
political-economic structure of society’. Examples include exploitation;
economic marginalisation and deprivation. This is contrasted with cultural or
symbolic injustice. Here injustice is rooted in social patterns of representation,
interpretation and communication. Examples include cultural domination,
non-recognition and disrespect. The problem of the Marxian working class
instances the first type of injustice. That of the gay community instances the
second. Fraser points out that the first kind of injustice is remedied by denying
the specificity of the disadvantaged group. The second kind of injustice is reme-
died by asserting its specificity:
The upshot is that the politics of recognition and the politics of redistribu-
tion often appear to have mutually contradictory aims. Whereas the first
tends to promote group differentiation, the second tends to undermine it.
Thus, the two kinds of claim stand in tension with one another; they can
interfere with, or even work against, each other.
(Fraser 1997: 16)
The central distinction made by Fraser (and the elaborated view by Young
[1990; 1999]) must either shape the whole of this chapter, or be reconciled with
another approach. We believe that it is readily reconcilable with a ‘spheres of
justice’ approach to redistribution. Complex equality is achieved according to
Walzer when status is not transferable across spheres. The formulation of sphere
is the key to reconciliation with Fraser. In a differentiated society, spheres
proliferate. People occupy spheres by race, sexuality, profession and sporting
club allegiance. Walzer’s approach requires that status is not correlated across
spheres. Thus sexuality must not be translatable into professional success.
Attempts to do so are unfair (indeed, actionable under employment legisla-
tion). Thus a group suffering from injustices of recognition acts not by
de-differentiation but by asserting and seeking to establish the de facto separa-
tion of spheres. This approach requires similar action taken in respect of all
those in a disadvantaged set, not ad hoc action in respect of those who are in
the intersecting set of two forms of disadvantage. For example, it may involve
222 Paul Wiles and Ken Pease
bution of resources as between victim and offender. Victim support and crim-
inal injuries compensation also represent attempts to promote distributive
justice and this remains possible even when an offender’s identity is not known.
Retribution, restoration, victim compensation/support and distribution as
modes of justice are linked through their attempts to establish a balance of
effort and advantage between citizens. Viewed thus, retribution, restoration and
compensation are simply means of moving towards distributive justice in the
wake of an offence. Distributive justice can be seen as the overarching notion,
with retribution, restoration and compensation becoming relevant (in the
service of promoting distributive justice) once a crime has been committed. The
debates on race and sentencing note that the formulation of the criminal law
itself can generate patterns of ethnicity among offenders, on the basis of differ-
ential criminalisation of lifestyles. This well illustrates the limits of distributive
justice achievable through the operation of a criminal justice system.
Classifying retribution as a form of distributive justice seems contentious. It
could be argued that it is precisely the appeal of these responses that they do not
involve any redistribution of resources. But the sanctions of criminal justice do
involve a redistribution of resources. A two-year prison sentence delays the
development of a career and family life by two years, in comparison with imme-
diate colleagues. An eye for an eye redistributes visual impairment. A fine
redistributes disposable income. The problem appears to us to be a consequence
of equating the search for distributive justice with policy choices which improve
the lot of people. Criminal justice is perhaps unique in seeking distributive
justice by deliberately disadvantaging people, but it is no less redistributive for
that. One can as well equalise height by chopping off the legs of the tall as by
good nutrition of the short.
In what follows, the distinction will be made between initial distributive
justice and contingent distributive justice. The former concerns allocation
across society. The second concerns re-allocations, which follow disruptions of
distribution occasioned by an offence. It should be stressed that the distinction
concerns the circumstances of application of fair distribution, not the point at
which fairness is to be decided. Fairness should be determined in advance. Only
its application is contingent. The principles of retributive justice are general.
Their application is contingent on case facts.
often because initial distributive injustice has been taken into account. When
sentences are deemed unduly harsh, this is often because of a failure to take
initial injustice into account. Because these are matters of judgement, the same
sentence may be judged both too severe and too lenient. This is typically the
case where women have killed abusive partners. Also, probation officers and
social workers invite criticism from the press when they use the decisions of
retributive justice as a springboard in the attempt to remedy actual or perceived
distributive injustice. These hoped-for remedies dispense ‘goodies for baddies’
where holidays, driver education and the like are offered to the errant and
denied to the righteous.
In a society where no one is deprived by initial distribution, retribution (at
least towards adults) could be dispensed without any angst on the part of the
punisher,1 and ‘goodies for baddies’ would be perverse. In the real world, where
systemic or individual distributive injustice is presumed to intrude, and the
language of the court conspires in that presumption, all criminal justice
personnel have to make judgement calls about how the degree of a sanction must
be adjusted in individual cases. Arguments about juvenile justice and means of
dealing with mentally disordered offenders are difficult because of differing
presumptions about the proper scope of remediation of past distributive injustice.
This is not to say that offenders who have experienced initial distributive
justice (in so far as society can dispense it) are easy to sentence. Initial injustice
starts at conception. Are genes distributed in a just way? Are we the victim of
injustice if we have genes making for risk-taking and shortness of temper? Is
short stature, and consequent feelings of inferiority and tendency to violence,
the product of parental smoking and poor nutrition? The Dworkin formulation
described above, and as developed by Arneson (1989) and Cohen (1989), offers
at least a way of thinking about these issues. The central shift is from welfare
equalisation to resource equalisation. Since resources include native talents,
compensation is necessary for inequalities in resources for which individuals are
not responsible. This requires a sense of community or fraternity, and requires
the talented not to be self-regarding.
In sum, the language, pronouncements and decisions surrounding caution,
prosecution, sentence imposition, sentence administration and release – in fact,
all decisions dealing with criminal offenders – become difficult in so far as issues
of initial distributive justice are taken to interact with contingent justice.
Apologetic retribution follows when punitive intervention is moderated by
reason of presumed initial distributive injustice. Distribution blindness occurs
when punitive intervention is greater by the neglect of such injustice.
Apologetic retribution and distribution blindness are the Scylla and Charybdis
of offence contingent justice.
In the foregoing, there was too easy a transition from discussions of contigent
justice to concerns about what to do with offenders. Leslie Wilkins (1999),
instancing his work in preventing aircraft accidents, repeatedly bemoaned the
reduction of the problem of crime (paralleling the crash) to the problem of the
offender (paralleling the pilot or ground crew). Historically, offence contingent
226 Paul Wiles and Ken Pease
justice has been centred on the offender. Sanctions are generally tempered or
wholly by-passed on the basis of the offender’s failure to receive distributive fair-
ness in the past. Offender-oriented crime reduction methods are based upon
belated attempts to afford distributive justice to perpetrators. This translates
into those applications for crime prevention funding providing facilities for
offenders. It is interesting that all long-term person-oriented crime prevention
programmes are focused on offenders, or those at risk of becoming offenders,
rather than victims or those for whom victimisation is a future hazard.2 Even if
effective, this assigns to crime victims a secondary role, whose future protection
is dependent upon the response of perpetrators to efforts made on their behalf.
The fact of a crime leads to two sets of responses, one through the detection and
processing of putative offenders, the other to direct protection of the person and
property of the victim. Distributive justice is perceived to be important for the
offender and to be achieved to benefit the victim only through the achievement
of change to the perpetrator.
Is it a fact of nature that the allocation of long-term person-oriented crime
prevention has to be centred upon the perpetrator rather than the victim? It is
not. The sad fact is that we know little of how victim careers work. We know a
great deal about how offender careers work. Victimisation surveys such as the
British Crime Survey (see, for example, Hales and Stratford 1997) are cross-
sectional, and do not allow us to view the trajectory of crime victimisation
across a lifetime. Just as notions of fairness in criminology have been over-
whelmingly discussed in relation to the offender, so the inequities of crime
distribution from the victim perspective have been neglected. Farrell et al.
(2001) propose an accelerated longitudinal design using data from the US
National Victimisation Survey, to yield some early answers.3 The introduction
of a longitudinal element into the British Crime Survey will in due course show
something about how victim careers develop, but the modest extent of the
longitudinal element means that it will be many years before a picture emerges
to rival the proposed accelerated longitudinal design from the American data.
The fact that we are having to play catch-up on a topic of such importance is
astonishing.
balance of effort and advantage between citizens. Second, some of the most
difficult issues in criminal justice come with the interaction between retribu-
tive/restorative justice and presumptions about the causal role of distributive
unfairness in causing offending. Third, while notions of fairness to offenders are
well theorised, no similar development has taken place with respect to crime
victims. This is reflected in the absence of research on victim careers, by
contrast with the extensive research on criminal careers; and finally, thinking
about the distributive fairness of crime opportunities (in preference to the fair
distribution of safety or risk) incorporates both victims and offenders as people
to whom justice must be done.
The shape of the curve shows that the 10 per cent of areas with most crime has
more than double the amount of crime in the next most crime prone 10 per
cent of areas. Looking at the worst 10 per cent of areas against the best 10 per
cent, the worst 10 per cent suffer forty-three times as much crime as the least
victimised 10 per cent. Another way of saying this is that some 40 per cent of
all crime experienced happens in the 10 per cent most crime prone areas. Well
over half occurs in the 20 per cent most crime prone areas. Calls logged from
the public will also show a massive range of crime densities.
The 10 per cent of areas with most crime can get to be that way via one or
both of two different routes. First, increasing proportions of people living in the
area may become victims, so that perhaps 80 or 90 per cent of people in the
worst areas suffer some crime. Alternatively, the same proportion of people
could become victims of crime in the worst and best areas, but those victimised
in the worst areas would suffer crime more often. The old and unfunny joke is
that in England and Wales somebody is getting robbed every thirty minutes –
and she’s getting sick of it. Unfunny as it is, it shows that more people do not
necessarily have to fall victim to crime for the crime rate to rise.
Figure 9.2 shows the proportion of people victimised in each area decile.
Thus in decile 10 (the 10 per cent of areas with most crime) some 28 per cent
of people are victims of crime over the year. The proportion increases steadily to
230 Paul Wiles and Ken Pease
that figure from 3 per cent in the least crime-ridden areas. The point to stress,
however, is that even if you live in one of 10 per cent most crime prone areas,
you have a 72 per cent chance of not being a victim over a one-year period.
However, Figure 9.3 shows the number of crimes which people who are victims
each suffer. It will be seen that in the worst areas, each victim of property crime
suffers an average of nearly five.
The same pattern is even more marked for crimes of violence, where 15 per
cent of people in the worst areas suffer crimes against the person, but each of
those who do suffer crime has to endure six crimes, on average. Most people in
the worst areas do not suffer crime over the course of a year. Those who do,
suffer it several times each. Since areas which suffer much property crime are by
and large also those which suffer most personal crime, looking at all crime
combined yields an even more marked difference between areas in levels of
chronic victimisation.4
One should not rely on the precision of the numbers presented to measure
crime concentration. There are conventions in the British Crime Survey
concerning the maximum number of victimisation forms which a victim may
complete, the maximum number of events recordable as a series against a
chronic victim, and the like. Such conventions change the exact numbers
arrived at. Neither should one stereotype all crime victims as the innocent and
put upon. As yet unpublished research by the first author with Andrew Costello
Distributive justice and crime 231
Table 9.1 is calculated from Budd (1999) and represents the risk of domestic
burglary victimisation in relation to a national average of 1. It will be seen that
certain social groups suffer much more than their ‘fair’ share of burglary, with
young householders suffering some 2.7 times the national rate, the recently
moved some 1.75, and so on.
most crime-prone 2.5 per cent of OCUs account for some 17 per cent of crime.
The difference between the curves remains along their length. The smaller the
unit, the higher the degree of concentration.
Displacement
In the late 1980s, the geographer Robert Barr and one of the writers of this
chapter (Pease) became interested in the terms in which the debate about crime
displacement was being conducted. The debate centred upon whether displace-
ment happened, the extent to which it did so, and the limits on crime
prevention efficacy which that entailed. Absent from the literature was any
suggestion that some distributions of crime were to be preferred to others. Barr
and Pease (1990) expressed the view that:
The notion of benign displacement was introduced by Barr and Pease (1990).
Benign displacement is said to exist when the distribution of crime after deflec-
tion is judged to be fairer than its distribution beforehand. Malign displacement
is its opposite. There is a judgement to be made about the fair distribution of
unavoidable crime, a point which the lack of differentiation of the concept of
displacement obscures.
Barr and Pease’s argument has been extended by Barnes (1995). The impor-
tance of the argument lies simply in the recognition that the previous literature
had been written as though ‘a crime is a crime is a crime’, with no apparent
recognition that the way in which the crime burden is shared is matter of policy
concern. To speculate, the literature is as it is because the focus has been on the
administrative unit recording crime rather than the crime victim. Police
commanders can get into trouble for large numbers of crimes. How they are
distributed is not of central relevance. Crimes will be regarded as equal only
when their sole existence are as units to be totted up by the police for onward
transmission to the Home Office for inclusion in Criminal Statistics. It is not as
though crimes are treated that way by front-line police officers, where, for
example, particular effort may be given to preventing burglaries against the
elderly, or against those who may make the most vociferous complaints to the
Chief Constable.7 Although the literature on displacement is naive about crime
distributions, front-line police officers are not.
There are some social changes which may impact upon emerging patterns of
crime concentration. One dimension along which people may vary is that of
information-richness to information-poverty. Informed decisions taken by the
information-rich in relation to where to live, how to protect themselves and
their families, and so on, may well tend to concentrate crime victimisation yet
further.
So what?
By what means may concerns for the fair distribution of crime opportunities be
brought recognisably to bear upon crime control practice? What follows is a
speculative, certainly flawed, but hopefully useful attempt to make some of the
connections.
violence that citizen experience is most varied according to where they live.
By the Rawls’ difference principle, areas with the highest rates of violence
should be given some priority, since they define the most extreme variation
by area.
It is perhaps worth noting that standard scores (mean/SD) are commonplace
in the criminological literature, whereas the coefficient of variability
(SD/mean) is extremely rare. In microcosm, this eloquently states that crimi-
nology has neglected the measures in terms of which distributive justice is
always conceived.
Hazard integration
This approach has been most fully developed within criminology, as the length
of its exposition here suggests (see also Wiles and Pease 2000). Ironically, it will
find much less favour amongst philosophers of equity. Its central element is to
integrate the consideration and response to diverse externally-caused hazards.
The separation of crime and disorder as kinds of harm should be avoided. This
would require the repeal of the Crime and Disorder Act (1998) and its replace-
ment by an Act which did not distinguish between harms resulting from human
malice and other harms. Current arrangements will lead to, for example, inten-
sive action to reduce pub assaults while more people are being killed on the
roads. Harms should not be divided into criminal and other for the purposes of
prevention. The elevation of crime to a privileged position among harms risks
the ‘criminalisation of social policy’, and the cynical justification of programmes
which may be progressive in other ways by reference to their supposed crime
prevention potential.
Distributive justice and crime 237
Spheres of justice
Reducing harms to a common currency goes against the recent arguments of
communitarians. Different goods being incommensurable, fairness will be
achieved when status on one dimension is not associated with status on others.
Communities that now suffer high rates of crime are often also characterised by
poor housing, deprivation, exclusion, poor educational achievement, pollution
and the like. This is not coincidence. A wide range of social and physical vari-
ables contribute to and are contributed to by crime risk, both singly and in
interaction (see, for example, Tseloni et al. forthcoming). These variables
include affluence, region, area type, parity, household composition, land use and
physical attributes of a home, car or person. The establishment of causal routes
through which these allied ills manifest themselves is technically difficult and
probably pointless. Social variables may both drive and be driven by crime and
perceptions of crime, or be manifestations of other variables, overt or subtle. For
example, concentration of single parent households may be associated with
crime for many reasons, including the following:
The intriguing (even mind-blowing) question is: what would crime policy
look like if its single aim were to uncouple risks from the risks of other types of
disadvantage? How could it be monitored? It would mean that effort at crime
reduction would be concentrated on those who were most crime-prone. This
could most easily be achieved by a major emphasis on the prevention of repeat
victimisation, since repeat victims are disproportionately to be found in areas
and groups suffering most crime (see Trickett et al. 1995; Johnson et al. 1997;
Pease 1998). The emphasis solely on prior victims will lead the reader to ques-
tion, ‘And what else?’ The answer is nothing else. Why not prior victimisation
occasioning high trauma? Because repeats can escalate in trauma, from robbery
to murder, and because the sheer grind of chronic victimisation, even events
which may dispassionately be regarded as individually trivial, is itself traumatic
(see Shaw 2001). Preventing repeat crimes is the most elegant means of
applying Rawls’ difference principle. Not classifying victims further buys
simplicity of implementation.
Prior victims are disproportionately future victims. Any other means of
dispensing crime prevention help will be less efficient in identifying and
helping those at risk. Let us assume that help is dispensed by geographic area.
As noted above, crime is less concentrated the more aggregated an area or
238 Paul Wiles and Ken Pease
group. Thus an areal definition of areas needing crime reduction help will
exclude individuals at high risk and include those at low risk. Dispensing crime
reduction according to prior victimisation is the closest we have to a means of
reducing differences in crime suffering. Recent research (Everson 2000) also
suggests that it denies opportunities to those prolific offenders to whom we most
wish to deny opportunities.
Parallel attention to those who are disadvantaged in other respects will
reduce associations between harms. As stated earlier, this must not be restricted
to the intersecting set of those suffering both harms. When the key associations
approach zero, we have a distributively fair society within a set of independent
spheres of justice (see Walzer 1983), and hopefully the reconciliation of justices
of redistribution and recognition (Fraser 1997). Functionally, this approach and
the required reduction in range of experiences of crime within an area (see
‘Crime and Rawls’ Difference Principle’ above) will tend to the same result, if
the attempt to reduce best-worst ratios as indices of performance are applied
across forms of disadvantage.
Conclusion
Of the ideas presented above, the idea of best-worst ratios in crime as the basis
of performance measurement seems to have immediate promise. The recogni-
tion that statistics centring on variation are rare in criminology, whereas
statistics centring on central tendency are common, felt like an insight. The
crude calculations of OCU and force variability contained in this chapter show
that the technique is easy, the only difficult issue being the collection of the
most appropriate data. Application to more disaggregated data will make the
technique more useful and truer to the Rawls’ difference principle.
Notions of uncoupling measures of disadvantage, taken from Walzer (1983)
and consonant with the ideas of Fraser (1997; 2000), are intriguing in their
implications, and could with profit be elaborated. The details of how the distri-
bution of opportunities from the victim perspective translates into effects on
criminal careers will not be simple. Single offenders commit offences against
many victims, alone or with others. The impact of different tactics of reducing
crime opportunities will likely be different in limiting victim harm and offender
vulnerability to sanction. Past neglect of these issues makes the task a daunting
one, albeit worthwhile.
Notes
The opinions expressed in this chapter are not necessarily those of the Home Office.
References
Arneson, R. (1989) ‘Equality of Opportunity for Welfare’, Philosophical Studies, 56:
77–93.
Barnes, G. C. (1995) ‘Defining and Optimising Displacement’, in J. E. Eck and D. Weis-
burd (eds) Crime and Place, Monsey, NY: Criminal Justice Press.
Barr, R. and Pease, K. (1990) ‘Crime Placement, Displacement and Deflection’, in M.
Tonry and N. Morris (eds) Crime and Justice, volume 12, Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Budd, T. (1999) Burglary of Domestic Dwellings: Findings from the British Crime Survey,
Home Office Statistical Bulletin, 4/99, London: Home Office.
Cohen, G. A. (1989) ‘On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice’, Ethics 99: 906–44.
Dworkin, R. (1981a) ‘What is Equality? Part 1: Equality of Welfare’, Philosophy and Public
Affairs, 10: 185–246.
—— (1981b) ‘What is Equality? Part 2: Equality of Resources’, Philosophy and Public
Affairs, 10: 283–345.
Elster, J. (1989) Solomonic Judgements: Studies in the Limitations of Rationality, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
—— (1992) Local Justice: How Institutions Allocate Scarce Goods and Necessary Burdens,
New York: Sage.
Everson, S. (2001) Repeat Victims and Prolific Offenders, Ph.D. thesis, University of
Huddersfield.
Farrell, G., Ellingworth, D. and Pease, K. (1996) ‘High Crime Rates, Repeat Victimisa-
tion and Routine Activities’, in T. Bennett (ed.) Preventing Crime and Disorder,
Cambridge: Institute of Criminology.
Farrell, G., Tseloni, A., Wiersema, B. and Pease, K. (2001) ‘Victim Careers and “Career
Victims”? Towards a Research Agenda’, in G. Farrell and K. Pease (eds) Repeat
Victimisation, Monsey, NY: Willow Tree Press.
240 Paul Wiles and Ken Pease
Field, S. (1991) Trends in Crime and their Interpretation: A Study of Recorded Crime in Post-
war England and Wales, Home Office Research Study 119, London: HMSO.
Fraser, N. (1997) Justice Interruptus, London: Routledge.
—— (2000) ‘Rethinking Recognition’, New Left Review, 224: 107–19.
Hales, J. and Stratford, N. (1997) 1996 British Crime Survey (England and Wales), Tech-
nical Report, London: SCPR.
Hesseling, R. B. P. (1995) ‘Displacement: A Review of the Empirical Literature’, in R. V.
Clarke (ed.) Crime Prevention Studies 3, Monsey, NY: Criminal Justice Press.
Hood, R. (1992) Race and Sentencing, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hope, T. J. (1996) ‘Communities, Crime and Inequality in England and Wales’, in T.
Bennett (ed.) Preventing Crime and Disorder, Cambridge: Institute of Criminology.
Johnson, S. D., Bowers, K. and Hirschfield, A. (1997) ‘New Insights into the Spatial and
Temporal Distribution of Repeat Victimisation’, British Journal of Criminology, 37:
224–41.
Nussbaum, M. and Sen, A.(1993) The Quality of Life, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Pascal, B. (1658/1961) Pensées, Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Pease, K. (1998) Repeat Victimisation: Taking Stock, London: Home Office Policing and
Reducing Crime Unit.
Rawls, J. (1971) A Theory of Justice, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Roemer, J. E. (1996) Theories of Distributive Justice, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Univer-
sity Press.
Sen, A. (1980) ‘Equality of What?’, in S. McMurrin (ed.) Tanner Lectures on Human
Values,volume 1, Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press.
Shaw, M. (2001) ‘Time Heals All Wounds?’, in G. Farrell and K. Pease (eds) Repeat
Victimisation, Monsey, NY: Willow Tree Press.
Sherman, L. W., Gottfredson, D., MacKenzie, D., Eck, J., Reuter, P. and Bushway, S.
(1997) Preventing Crime: What Works, What Doesn’t and What’s Promising, Wash-
ington, DC: Office of Justice Programmes.
Skogan, W. (1991) ‘Redesigning the National Crime Victimisation Survey’, Public
Opinion Quarterly, 23: 1–24.
Trickett, A., Osborn, D. R. and Ellingworth, D. (1995) ‘Property Crime Victimisation:
The Roles of Individual and Area Influences’, International Review of Victimology, 3:
273–95.
Tseloni, A., Osborn, D. R., Trickett, A. and Pease, K. (forthcoming) ‘The Lifestyle and
Socio-economic Environment of Households Experiencing High Property Crime
Rates in England and Wales’, British Journal of Criminology, in press.
Von Hirsch, A. and Roberts, J. V. (1997) ‘Racial Disparity in Sentencing: Reflections on
the Hood Study’, Howard Journal, 36: 227–36.
Walzer, M. (1983) Spheres of Justice: A Defence of Pluralism and Equality, New York: Basic
Books.
Wiles, P. and Pease, K. (2000) ‘Crime Prevention and Community Safety: Tweedledum
and Tweedledee?’, in V. McLaren, S. Ballantyne and K. Pease (eds) Key Issues in
Community Safety and Crime Prevention, London: IPPR.
Wilkins, L. T. (1999) Did I Really Become a Criminologist?, unpublished manuscript.
Young, H. P. (1994) Equity, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Young I. M. (1990) Justice and the Politics of Difference, Princeton: Princeton University
Press.
—— (1999) ‘Unruly Categories: A Critique of Nancy Fraser’s Dual Systems Theory’,
New Left Review, 223: 147–60.
Index