Projective Geometry - Coxeter, H. S. M. (Harold Scott Macdonald), 1907-2003 - 1964 - New York, Blaisdell Pub. Co - Anna's Archive
Projective Geometry - Coxeter, H. S. M. (Harold Scott Macdonald), 1907-2003 - 1964 - New York, Blaisdell Pub. Co - Anna's Archive
EX LIB RIS
« V
Projective Geometry
A Blaisdell Book in the Pure and Applied Sciences
H. S. M. Coxeter
UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO
In Euclidean geometry, constructions are made with the ruler and com¬
pass. Projective geometry is simpler: its constructions require only the ruler.
We consider the straight line joining two points, and the point of intersection
of two lines, with the further simplification that two lines never fail to
meet!
In Euclidean geometry we compare figures by measuring them. In projective
geometry we never measure anything; instead, we relate one set of points
to another by a projectivity. Chapter 1 introduces the reader to this important
idea. Chapter 2 provides a logical foundation for the subject. The third and
fourth chapters describe the famous theorems of Desargues and Pappus.
The fifth and sixth make use of projectivities on a line and in a plane, re¬
spectively. In the next three we develop a self-contained account of von
Staudt’s approach to the theory of conics, made more “modern” by allowing
the field to be general (though not of characteristic 2) instead of real or
complex. This freedom has been exploited in Chapter 10, which deals with the
simplest finite geometry that is rich enough to illustrate all our theorems
nontrivially (for instance, Pascal’s theorem concerns six points on a conic,
and in PG{2, 5) these are the only points on the conic). In Chapters 11 and 12
we return to more familiar ground, showing the connections between pro¬
jective geometry, Euclidean geometry, and the popular subject of “analytic
geometry.”
The possibility of writing an easy book on projective geometry was fore¬
seen as long ago as 1917, when D. N. Lehmer [1,* Preface, p. v] wrote:
Vll
Vlll PREFACE
In this ideal course of Geometry, the fifth stage is occupied with the
elements of Projective Geometry . . .
This “fifth” stage has one notable advantage: its primitive concepts are so
simple that a self-contained account can be reasonably entertaining, whereas
the foundations of Euclidean geometry are inevitably tedious.
The present treatment owes much to the famous text-book of Veblen and
Young [1], which has the same title. To encourage truly geometric habits of
thought, we scrupulously avoid the use of coordinates and all metrical ideas
(Whitehead’s first four “stages”) except in Chapters 1, 11, 12, and a few of
the Exercises. In particular, the only mention of cross ratio is in three exer¬
cises at the end of Section 12.3.
I gratefully acknowledge the help of M. W. Al-Dhahir, W. L. Edge,
P. R. Halmos, S. Schuster and S. Trott, who constructively criticized the
manuscript, and of H. G. Forder and C. Garner, who read the proofs. I wish
also to express my thanks for permission to quote from Science: Sense and
Nonsense by J. L. Synge (Jonathan Cape, London).
H. S. M. COXETER
Toronto, Canada
February, 1963
Contents
CHAPTER 1 Introduction
2.1 Axioms 14
2.2 Simple consequences of the axioms 16
2.3 Perspective triangles 18
2.4 Quadrangular sets 20
2.5 Harmonic sets 22
CHAPTER 7 Polarities
chapter 11 Parallelism
chapter 12 Coordinates
References 158
Index 159
A Note to the Reader
Introduction
The plane geometry of the first six books of Euclid’s Elements may be
described as the geometry of lines and circles: its tools are the straight-edge
(or unmarked ruler) and the compasses. A remarkable discovery was made
independently by the Danish geometer Georg Mohr (1640-1697) and the
Italian Lorenzo Mascheroni (1750-1800). They proved that nothing is lost
by discarding the straight-edge and using the compasses alone. * For instance,
given four points A, B, C, D, we can still construct the point where the lines
AB and CD would meet if we had the means to draw them; but the actual
procedure is quite complicated. It is natural to ask how much remains if we
discard the compass instead, and use the straight-edge alone.f At a glance,
it looks as if nothing at all will remain: we cannot even carry out the construc¬
tion described in Euclid’s first proposition. Is it possible to develop a geometry
The motivation for this kind of geometry came from the fine arts. It was
in 1425 that the Italian architect Brunelleschi began to discuss the geometrical
PERSPECTIVE 3
the community as full members having the same privileges as ordinary points.
This emancipation of the subject was carried out by another German,
K. G. C. von Staudt (1798-1867). The last vestiges of dependence on ordinary
geometry were removed in 1871, when Felix Klein provided an algebraic
foundation for projective geometry in terms of “homogeneous coordinates,
which had been discovered independently by K. W. Feuerbach and A. F.
Mobius in 1827.
The determination of a point by two lines nicely balances the determina¬
tion of a line by two points. More generally, we shall find that every state¬
ment about points and lines (in a plane) can be replaced by a dual statement
about lines and points. The possibility of making such a replacement is
known as the “principle of duality.” Poncelet claimed this principle as his
own discovery; but its nature was more clearly understood by another French¬
man, J. D. Gergonne (1771-1859). Duality gives projective geometry a
peculiar charm, making it more symmetrical than ordinary (Euclidean)
geometry.
Besides being a thing of beauty in its own right, projective geometry is
useful as supplying a fresh approach to Euclidean geometry. This is especially
evident in the theory of conics, where a single projective theorem may yield
several Euclidean theorems by different choices of the line at infinity; e.g.,
if the line at infinity is a tangent or a secant, the conic is a parabola or a
hyperbola, respectively. Arthur Cayley (1821-1895) and Felix Klein (1849-
1925) noticed that projective geometry is equally powerful in its application
to non-Euclidean geometries. With characteristic enthusiam, the former said:
Metrical geometry is a part of descriptive geometry, and descriptive geometry is all
geometry.
(Cayley, in 1859, used the word “descriptive” where today we would say
“projective.”)
EXERCISES
2. How could a lampshade be tilted so that its circular rim would yield a
parabolic shadow on the wall?
1.3 Definitions
The word Space is repeated. We have Vish In Seven. . . . Well, what about it?
Didn’t we see and prove that a vicious circle is inevitable, so why be surprised that
we get one here? If that is your reaction, I shout with joy.. . .
Vish illustrates the important principle that any definition of a word must
inevitably involve other words, which require further definitions. The only
way to avoid a vicious circle is to regard certain primitive concepts as being so
simple and obvious that we agree to leave them undefined. Similarly, the proof
of any statement uses other statements; and since we must begin somewhere,
we agree to leave a few simple statements unproved. These primitive state¬
ments are called axioms.
In addition to the primitive concepts and axioms, we take for granted the
words of ordinary speech, the ideas of logical argument, and the principle of
one-to-one correspondence. The last is well illustrated by the example of cups
and saucers. Suppose we had about a hundred cups and about a hundred
saucers and wished to know whether the number of cups was actually equal
to the number of saucers. This could be done, without counting, by the simple
device of putting each cup on a saucer, that is, by establishing a one-to-one
correspondence between the cups and saucers.
EXERCISES
A, B, C. a, b, c.
Figure 1.4a
8 INTRODUCTION
EXERCISES
1.5 Projectivities
It is sometimes convenient to use the name range for the set of all points on
a line, and pencil for the set of all lines that lie in a plane and pass through a
point. Ranges and pencils are instances of one-dimensional forms. We shall
often have occasion to consider a one-to-one correspondence between two
one-dimensional forms. The simplest such correspondence between a range
and a pencil arises when corresponding members are incident. In this case it is
naturally understood that the line o on which the points of the range lie is not
incident with the point O through which the lines of the pencil pass. Thus
the range is a section of the pencil (namely, the section by the line o) and the
pencil projects the range (from the point O). As a notation for this elementary
correspondence we may write either
X 7\ x,
where A is a variable point of the range and x is the corresponding line of the
pencil (as in Figure 1.5a), or
ABC • * • a abc • • • ,
Since the statement X /\ x means that X and x are incident, we can just as
well write
x a X;
but now it is convenient to make a subtle distinction. The correspondence
X a x is directed “from X to x”: it transforms X into x; but the inverse
correspondence x a X transforms x into X.
On-1
EXERCISES
1.6 Perspectivities
X x X' or X% X'. — /
x x * or a x x .
,
For instance, in Figure 1.6a (where A, B, C are particular instances of the
variable point X, and a, b, c of the vari, ible line x), we have the perspectivities
Oi
ABC ^ A’B'C, abc x a b'c'.
Figure 1.6a
Figure 1.6d
Figure 1.6e
PROJECTIVITIES 13
sign A was adopted by the great American geometer Oswald Yeblen (1880—
1960).
EXERCISES
2.1 Axioms
Axiom 2.11 There exist a point and a line that are not incident.
Axiom 2.12 Every line is incident with at least three distinct points.
Axiom 2.13 Any two distinct points are incident with just one line.
Axiom 2.14 If A, B, C, D are four distinct points such that AB meets CD,
then AC meets BD. (See Figure 2.1a.)
Axiom 2.15 If ABC is a plane, there is at least one point not in the plane
ABC.
Axiom 2.16 Any two distinct planes have at least two common points.
Axiom 2.17 The three diagonal points of a complete quadrangle are never
collinear. (See Figure 1.4a.)
Figure 2.1a
The best possible advice to the reader is to set aside all his previously
acquired knowledge (such as trigonometry and analytic geometry) and use
only the axioms and their consequences. He may occasionally be tempted to
use the old methods to work out one of the exercises; but then he is likely to
be so engulfed in ugly calculations that he will return to the synthetic method
with renewed enthusiasm.
EXERCISES
1. Give detailed proofs of the following theorems, pointing out which axioms
are used:
(i) There exist at least four distinct points.
(ii) If a is a line, there exists a point not lying on a.
(iii) If A is a point, there exists a line not passing through A.
(iv) Every point lies on at least three lines.
2. Construct a projectivity having exactly two invariant points. [Hint: Use
Exercise 3 of Section 1.5.]
16 TRIANGLES AND QUADRANGLES
3. Draw an equilateral triangle ABC with its incircle DEF, medians AD, BE,
CF, and center G. Notice that the figure involves 7 points, 6 lines, and 1
circle. Consider a “geometry,” consisting entirely of 7 points and 7 lines,
derived from the figure by calling the circle a line (and ignoring the extra
intersections). Which one of the “two-dimensional” axioms (Axioms 2.11,
2.12, 2.13, 2.14, 2.17, 2.18) is denied? [Hint: Where are the diagonal points
of the quadrangles ABCG, AEFG, BCEF1]
Most readers will have no difficulty in accepting Axioms 2.11, 2.12, 2.13.
The first departure from Euclidean geometry appears in Axiom 2.14, which
rules out the possibility that AC and BD might fail to meet by being “parallel.”
This axiom, which resembles Pasch’s Axiom (12.27 of Reference 8, p. 178), is
Veblen’s ingenious device for declaring that any two coplanar lines have a
common point before defining a plane! (In fact, the line BD, whose inter¬
section with AC is asserted, must lie in the plane AEC, where E — AB • CD,
since B lies on AE, and D on EC.)
Given a triangle ABC, we can define a pencil of lines through C as consisting
of all the lines CX, where X belongs to the range of points on AB. The first
four axioms are all that we need in order to define the plane ABC as a certain
set of points and lines, namely, all the points on all the lines of the pencil, and
all the lines that join pairs of such points. We then find that the same plane is
determined when we replace C by another one of the points, and AB by one
of the lines not incident with this point.
Axiom 2.15 makes the geometry three-dimensional, and Axiom 2.16
prevents it from being four-dimensional. (In fact, four-dimensional geometry
would admit a pair of planes having only one common point!) It follows that
two distinct planes, a and (5, meet in a line, which we call the line a • /?.
In virtue of Axiom 2.17, the diagonal points of a quadrangle form a triangle.
This is called the diagonal triangle of the quadrangle. It will be found to play
an important role in some of the later developments. However (as we shall
see in the exercise at the end of Section 10.3), there are some interesting,
though peculiar, geometries in which the diagonal points of a quadrangle are
always collinear, so that Axiom 2.17 is denied.
The plausibility of Axiom 2.18 will appear in Section 3.5, where we shall
prove, on the basis of the remaining seven axioms, that a projectivity having
three invariant points leaves invariant, if not the whole line, so many of its
points that they have the “appearance” of filling the whole line.
As an indication of the way axioms lead to theorems, let us now state four
simple theorems and give their proofs in detail.
THE SIMPLEST THEOREMS 17
2.21 Any two distinct lines have at most one common point.
Proof. Suppose, if possible, that two given lines have two common
points A and B. Axiom 2.13 tells us that each line is determined by these
two points. Thus the two lines coincide, contradicting our assumption that
they are distinct.
2.22 Any two distinct coplanar lines have at least one common point.
Proof. Let E be a point coplanar with the two lines but not on either
of them. Let AC be one of the lines. Since the plane ACE is determined by
the pencil of lines through E that meet AC, the other one of the two given
lines may be taken to join two points on distinct lines of this pencil, say B
on EA, and D on EC, as in Figure 2.1a. According to Axiom 2.14, the two
lines AC and BD have a common point.
2.24 There exist four coplanar points of which no three are collinear.
Proof. By our first three axioms, there exist two distinct lines having
a comfnon point and each containing at least two other points, say lines
EA and EC containing also B and D, respectively, as in Figure 2.1a. The
four distinct points A, B, C, D have the desired property of noncollinearity.
For instance, if the three points A, B, C were collinear, E (on AB) would be
collinear with all of them, and EA would be the same line as EC, contra¬
dicting our assumption that these two lines are distinct.
EXERCISES
Figure 2.3a
corresponding lines meet in collinear points. For instance, the two triangles
PQR and P'Q'R' in Figure 2.3a are perspective since corresponding vertices
are joined by the three concurrent lines PP', QQ', RR', or since corre¬
sponding sides meet in the three collinear points
When Theorems 2.31 and 2.32 have been stated and proved, we shall see
that either kind of correspondence implies the other. Meanwhile, let us say
tentatively that two figures are perspective from a point O if pairs of corre¬
sponding points are joined by lines through O, and that two figures are
perspective from a line o if pairs of corresponding lines meet on o. (It is some¬
times convenient to call O the center, and o the axis. Whenever we speak of
perspective figures we assume that the points, and also the lines, are all
distinct; for example, in the case of a pair of triangles, we assume that there
are six distinct vertices and six distinct sides.) The desired identification will
follow for all more complicated figures as soon as we have established it for
triangles. Accordingly, we begin with the following theorem:
DESARGUES 19
2.31 If two triangles are perspective from a line they are perspective from
a point.
Proof. Let two triangles, PQR and P'Q'R', be perspective from a line
o. In other words, let o contain three points D, E, F, such that D lies on
both QR and Q'R', E on both RP and R'P', F on both PQ and P'Q'. We
wish to prove that the three lines PP', QQ', RR! all pass through one point
O, as in Figure 2.3a. We distinguish two cases, according as the given
triangles are in distinct planes or both in one plane.
(1) According to Axiom 2.14, since QR meets Q'R', QQ' meets RR'.
Similarly RR' meets PP', and PP' meets QQ'. Thus the three lines PP', QQ',
RR' all meet one another. If the planes PQR and P'Q'R' are distinct, the
three lines must be concurrent; for otherwise they would form a triangle,
and this triangle would lie in both planes.
(2) If PQR and P'Q'R' are in one plane, draw, in another plane through
o, three nonconcurrent lines through D, E, F, respectively, so as to form a
triangle PXQXRX, with QXRX through D, RXPX through E, and PXQX through
F. This triangle is perspective from o with both PQR and P'Q'R'. By the
result for noncoplanar triangles, the three lines PPX, QQX, RRX all pass
through one point S, and the three lines P'Pi, Q'Qi, R'RX all pass through
another point S'. (The points S and S' are distinct; for otherwise Px would
lie on PP' instead of being outside the original plane.) Since Px lies on both
PS and P'S', Axiom 2.14 tells us that SS' meets PP'. Similarly SS' meets
both QQ' and RR'. Hence, finally, the three lines PP', QQ', RR' all pass
through the point
O = PQR • SS1'.
The converse is
EXERCISES
2. If three triangles are all perspective from the same center, then* the three
axes are concurrent. [Hint: Let the three axes be DXEX, D2E2, D3E3. Apply
2.31 to the triangles D1D2D3 and E^E^.]
Figure 2.4a
Following Veblen and Young (Reference 19, p. 49), we use the symbol
Q(ABC, DEF)
we apply any permutation to ABC and the same permutation to DEF\ for
instance, Q{ABC, DEF) has the same meaning as Q(BAC, EDF), since the
quadrangle PQRS can equally well be calledQPRS. Similarly, the statement
Q(ABC, DEF) is equivalent to each of
Figure 2.4b
22 TRIANGLES AND QUADRANGLES
EXERCISES
1. A necessary and sufficient condition for three lines containing the vertices
of a triangle to be concurrent is that their sections A, B, C by a line g form,
with the sections D, E, F of the sides of the triangle, a quadrangular set.
Figure 2.5a
H (AB, CF),
which evidently has the same meaning as H(BA, CF) or H{AB, FC) or
H{BA, FC), namely that A and B are two of the three diagonal points of a
quadrangle while C and F lie, respectively, on the sides that pass through the
third diagonal point. We call Fthe harmonic conjugate of C with respect to A
and B. Of course also C is the harmonic conjugate of F. From Theorem 2.41
we see that F is uniquely determined by A, B, C. (We shall prove in Theorem
3.35 that the relation H(T5, CF) implies H(CF, AB).) For a simple construc¬
tion, draw a triangle QRS whose sides QR, QS, RS pass through A, B, C (as
in Figure 2.5a); then P = AS • BR and F = AB • PQ.
Axiom 2.17 implies that these harmonic conjugates C and F are distinct,
except in the degenerate case when they coincide with A or B. In other words,
HARMONIC SETS 23
2.51 If A, B, C are all distinct, the relation H(AB, CF) implies that F is
distinct from C.
It follows that there must be at least four points on every line; how many
more is not specified. We shall examine this question in Section 3.5.
EXERCISES
3.11 Any two distinct lines have at least one common point.
24
AXIOMS FOR THE PROJECTIVE PLANE 25
(This is derived from 2.22 by omitting the word “coplanar,” which is now
superfluous.) We shall develop such a theory out of the following seven
propositions:
2.11, 2.12, 2.13, 3.11, 2.17, 2.32, 2.18,
which will thus be seen to form a sufficient set of axioms for the projective
plane.
The two-dimensional principle of duality (i.e., the principle of duality in the
plane) asserts that every definition remains significant, and every theorem
remains true, when we interchange the words point and line (and consequently
also certain other pairs of words such as join and meet, collinear and concur¬
rent, vertex and side, and so forth). For instance, the dual of the point AB • CD
is the line (a • b)(c • d). (Since duality interchanges joining and meeting, it
requires not only the interchange of capital and small letters but also the
removal of any dots that are present and the insertion of dots where they are
absent.) The arrangement in Section 4.1 of definitions in “parallel columns”
shows at once that the dual of a quadrangle (with its three diagonal points)
is a quadrilateral (with its three diagonal lines). Still more simply, the dual of
a triangle (consisting of its vertices and sides) is again a triangle (consisting
of its sides and vertices); thus a triangle is an instance of a self-dual figure.
Axiom 2.11 is clearly self-dual. The dual of 2.12 is easily proved. The dual
of 2.13 consists of 2.21 and 3.11; therefore the dual of 3.11 is part of 2.13.
Similarly, the duals of 2.17 and 2.18 present no difficulty. The dual of 2.32
is its converse, 2.31 (which can be proved by applying 2.32 to the triangles
PP'E and QQ'D in Figure 2.3a). Thus all the axioms for the projective plane
imply their duals.
This remark suffices to establish the validity of the two-dimensional prin¬
ciple of duality. In fact, after using the axioms and their consequences in
proving a given theorem, we can immediately assert the dual theorem; for, a
proof of the dual theorem could be written down quite mechanically by
dualizing each step in the proof of the original theorem. (Of course, our proof
of 2.31 cannot be dualized in this sense, because it is three-dimensional; but
this objection is avoided by taking 2.32 as an axiom and observing that 2.31
can be deduced from it without either leaving the plane or appealing to the
principle of duality.)
One of the most attractive features of projective geometry is the symmetry
and economy with which it is endowed by the principle of duality: fifty
detailed proofs may suffice to establish as many as a hundred theorems.
So far, we have considered only the two-dimensional principle of duality.
But by returning to our original Axioms 2.11 through 2.18, we can just as
easily establish the three-dimensional principle of duality, in which points,
lines, and planes are interchanged with planes, lines, and points. For instance,
26 THE PRINCIPLE OF DUALITY
if lines a and b are coplanar, the dual of ab is a • b. However, for the sake of
brevity we shall assume, until the end of Chapter 9, that all the points and
lines considered are in one plane. (For a glimpse of the analogous three-dimen¬
sional developments, see Reference 8, p. 256.)
EXERCISES
Then the triads of points A-J52C%, A2B1C2, A2B2C1, A^B^x lie on lines, say
p, q, r, s, forming a quadrilateral pqrs whose three diagonal lines are the
sides
a = BC, b = CA, c — AB
of the triangle ABC. In other words, the quadrangle PQRS and the quadri¬
lateral pqrs have the same diagonal triangle. (Reference 19, pp. 45-46.)
The dual of (mc, nd) is (nd, mc). For instance, (43, 62) is a quadrangle and (62, 43)
is a quadrilateral.
In the case of a self-dual configuration, we have m = n, c = d, and the
symbol (nd, nd) is conveniently abbreviated to nd. For instance, 32 is a triangle.
When the triangles PQR and P' Q'R' of Figure 2.3a are regarded as lying
in distinct planes, we have altogether five planes
a • <5 • e, d • P ■ e, y 6 - s, p ■ 7 •£,... , p ■ y d, . . . , a • p • y.
When the whole figure is in one plane, we can use a variant of the same
notation by associating the letters a, p, y, d, e with the digits 1, 2, 3, 4, 5 so as
to call the ten lines
We now have a self-dual configuration 103: ten points and ten lines, with
three points on each line and three lines through each point. For instance,
the three points on the line 45 are 145, 245, 345, and the three lines through
the point 123 are 23, 31, 12. The rule for incidence is simply that the point ijk
lies on the line ij (and the order of the digits in a symbol is arbitrary: 31 could
just as well be called 13). The self-duality of the configuration can be verified
by interchanging the point and line whose symbols together use up all the
five digits without repetition.
EXERCISES
1. Copy Figure 2.3a, marking the lines with the two-digit symbols.
2. Draw the five lines 12, 23, 34, 45, 51 in one color, and the five lines 14, 42,
25, 53, 31 in another color, thus exhibiting the configuration as a pair of
simple pentagons, “mutually inscribed” in the sense that consecutive
sides of each pass through alternate vertices of the other. [J. T. Graves,
Phil. Mag. (3), 5 (1839), p. 132.]
3. Beginning afresh, draw the four lines 15, 25, 35, 45 in one color, and the
remaining six in another color, thus exhibiting the configuration as a
complete quadrilateral and a complete quadrangle, so situated that each
vertex of the former lies on a side of the latter.
In fact, the quadrilateral pqrs has a and b for two of its three diagonal lines
while c andf respectively, pass through the vertices that would be joined by
the third diagonal line.
Figure 3.3b, which is obtained by identifying the lines
p, q, r, s, a, b, c
of Figure 3.3a with the lines
PQ, AB, QR, RP, PS, QS, RS
of Figure 2.5a, shows how the harmonic set of points ABCF arises as a section
of the harmonic set of lines abcf. Since such a figure can be derived from any
harmonic set of points and any point S outside their line,
3.31 A harmonic set ofpoints is projected from any point outside the line by
a harmonic set of lines.
Dually,
3.32 Any section of a harmonic set of lines, by a line not passing through
the point of concurrence, is a harmonic set of points.
EXERCISES
1. Let ABC be the diagonal triangle of a quadrangle PQRS. How can PQR
be reconstructed if only ABC and S are given? [Hint: QR is the harmonic
conjugate of AS with respect to AB and AC.]
2. If PQR is a triangle and H(AAX, QR) and H(BBU RP), then P and Q are
harmonic conjugates with respect to
Comparing Figure 3.4a with Figure 2.5a, we see that these points D, E, F are
the intersections of pairs of corresponding sides of the two triangles PQR and
ABC, namely,
Since these two triangles are perspective from S, 2.32 tells us that D, E, Flie
on a line s. This line is what Poncelet called the trilinear polar of S.
Conversely, if we are given the triangle PQR and any line s, not through a
vertex, we can define A, B, C to be the harmonic conjugates of the points
D, E, Fin which s meets the sides QR, RP, PQ. By 2.31, the three lines PA,
QB, RC all pass through a point S, which is the trilinear pole of 5.
30 THE PRINCIPLE OF DUALITY
EXERCISES
2. Locate (In Figure 3.4a) the trilinear pole of s with respect to the triangle
ABC.
3. How should all the lines in this figure be named so as to make it obviously
self-dual?
4. In the spirit of Section 2.5, Exercise 5, what metrical property of the tri¬
angle PQR arises when we seek the trilinear polar of the line at infinity?
This result, which we have deduced from our first seven axioms, may reason¬
ably be regarded as making Axiom 2.18 plausible.
By Theorem 1.63 (with B and D interchanged), any four collinear points
A, B, C, D satisfy ABCD DCBA. If D belongs to K(ABC), A must belong to
R(DCB), which is the same as R(BCD). It follows that not only A, but every
point of R(ABC), belongs also to R(BCD). Hence, if D belongs to R(ABC),
R (ABC) = R (BCD).
By repeated applications of this result we see that, if K, L, M are any three
distinct points of R(ABC),
R (ABC) = R(BCK) = R (CKL) = R (KLM).
Hence
3.52 A harmonic net is equally well determined by any three distinct points
belonging to it.
We could, in fact, define a harmonic net to be the smallest set of more than
two collinear points which includes, with every three of its members, the
harmonic conjugate of each with respect to the other two.
If we begin to make a careful drawing of a harmonic net, we soon find that
this is an endless task: the harmonic net seems to include infinitely many
points between any two given points, thus raising the important question
whether it includes every point on the line. There is some advantage
in leaving this question open, that is, answering “Yes and No.” Projective
geometry, as we are developing it here, is not categorical: it is really
not just one geometry but many geometries, depending on the nature
of the set of all points on a line. In rational geometry and the simplest
finite geometries, all the points on a line form a single harmonic net, so that
Axiom 2.18 becomes superfluous. In real geometry, on the other hand, the
points on a line are arranged like the continuum of real numbers, among
which the rational numbers represent a typical harmonic net (Reference 7,
p. 179). Between any two rational numbers, no matter how close, we can find
infinitely many other rational numbers and also infinitely many irrational
numbers. Analogously, between any two points of a harmonic net on the
real line we can find infinitely many other members of the net and also
infinitely many points not belonging to the harmonic net. Axiom 2.18 (or,
alternatively, some statement about continuity) is needed to ensure the
invariance of these extra points.
When the points of a line in rational geometry, or the points of a harmonic
32 THE PRINCIPLE OF DUALITY
•net in real geometry, are represented by the rational numbers, the natural
numbers (that is, positive integers) represent a harmonic sequence ABCD . . . ,
which is derived from three collinear points A, B, M by the following special
procedure. With the help of two arbitrary points P and Q on another line
through M, as in Figure 3.5a, we construct in turn,
EXERCISES
The Golden Age of Greek geometry ended with the time of Apol¬
lonius of Perga. . . . The beginning of the Christian era sees quite a
different state of things. . . . Production was limited to elementary
textbooks of decidedly feeble quality. . . . The study of higher ge¬
ometry languished or was completely in abeyance until Pappus arose
to revive interest in the subject. . . . The great task which he set
himself was the re-establishment of geometry on its former high
plane of achievement.
Sir Thomas Heath (1861-1940)
(Reference 11, p. 355)
Given four distinct points A, B, C, X on one line, and three distinct points
A', B', C' on the same or another line, there are many possible ways in which
we may proceed to construct a point X' (on A'B') such that
ABCX a A'B'C'X'.
For instance, if the two lines are distinct, one way is indicated in Figure 4.1a
(which is Figure 1.6b in a revised notation):
ABCX a A'B'C’X'?
If not, there must be two distinct chains of perspectivities yielding, respec¬
tively,
ABCX a A'B'C'X' and ABCX a A’B'C’X",
where X" # X'. Proceeding backwards along the first chain and then forwards
along the second, we would have
A'B'C'X' a A’B’C'X",
contradicting Axiom 2.18. Thus, by reductio ad absurdum, we have proved
4.12 The Fundamental Theorem of Projective Geometry: A projec-
tivity is determined when three collinear points and the corresponding three
collinear points are given.
Of course, either of the sets of “three collinear points” (or both) can be
replaced by “three concurrent lines.” Thus each of the relations
ABC a A'B'C', ABC a abc, abc p ABC, abc p ab'c’
THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM 35
expresses a special property of eight points, or of four points and four lines,
or of eight lines, of such a nature that any seven of the eight will uniquely
determine the remaining one. We now have the proper background for
Theorem 1.63, which tells us that, if a projectivity interchanges A and B while
transforming C into D, it also transforms D into C, that is, it interchanges
C and D. 6
EXERCISES
4.21 Any two harmonic sets {of four collinear points or four concurrent
lines) are related by a unique projectivity.
Proof. If H{AB, CF) and V\{A'B', C'Fj, the projectivity ABC a A'B'C'
transforms F into a point F" such that, by 3.34, H(A'B', CF"). But the
harmonic conjugate of C' with respect to A’ and B’ is unique. Therefore
F" coincides with F'. The same reasoning can be used when either of the
harmonic sets consists of lines instead of points.
be two other points of the first range, A' and B' the corresponding points
of the second. The fundamental theorem tells us that the perspectivity
ABE ^ A'B'E,
where O = AA' • BB', is the same as the given projectivity ABE a A'B'E.
Figure 4.2a
EXERCISES
1. Any two harmonic nets, R(ABC) and R(A'B'C) (or any two harmonic
sequences, ABC. . . and ABC'...) are related by a projectivity.
2. Let the side QR of a quadrangle PQRS meet the side BC of its diagonal
triangle ABC in Ax, as in Exercise 2 of Section 3.1. Regarding ABPCSA1 as
a hexagon whose six vertices lie alternately on two lines, w'hat can be said
about the intersections of pairs of “opposite” sides of this hexagon?
4. If H(AB, CD) then ABCD j. BACD. (Compare Section 4.1, Exercise 3.)
The fundamental theorem 4.12 tells us that there is only one projectivity
ABC a ABC relating three distinct points on one line to three distinct
points on the same or any other line. The construction indicated in 4.11
(see Figure 4.1a) shows how, when the lines AB and A'B' are distinct, this
unique projectivity can be expressed as the product of two perspectivities
whose centers may be any pair of corresponding points (in reversed order) of
the two related ranges. It is natural to ask whether different choices of the
THE AXIS OF A PROJECTIVITY 37
two centers will yield different positions for the.line MN of the intermediate
range. A negative answer is provided by the following theorem:
4.31 Every projectivity relating ranges on two distinct lines determines
another special line, the “axis,” which contains the intersection of the cross¬
joins of any two pairs of corresponding points.
Proof. In the notation of 4.11, the perspectivities from A' and A
determine the axis MN, which contains the common point of the “cross¬
joins of the pair A A and any other pair; for instance, N is the common
point of the cross-joins (AB' and BAj of the two pairs A A' and BB'. What
remains to be proved is the uniqueness of this axis: that another choice of
the two pairs of corresponding points (such as BB' and CCj will yield
another crossing point” on the same axis. For this purpose, we seek a
new specification for the axis, independent of the particular pair AA'.
Let E be the common point of the two lines. Suppose first that E is
invariant, as in Figures 4.2a and 4.3a. Referring to Figure 4.1a, we observe
that, when X coincides with E, so also do Q and X'. The axis EN is inde¬
pendent of AA', since it can be described as the harmonic conjugate of EO
with respect to the given lines EB and EB'. On the other hand, if the common
point E is noninvariant, as in Figure 4.3b, it is still a point belonging to
both ranges. Referring to Figure 4.1a again, we observe that, when X
coincides with E, Q and X' both coincide with the corresponding point
E'. Hence the axis passes through E'. For a similar reason the axis also
passes through the point E0 of the first range for which the corresponding
point of the second is E. Hence the axis can be described as the join E0E'.
This completes the proof of 4.31, which Forder (Reference 10, p. 72) has
named “the criss-cross theorem.” The final remark can be expressed as
follows:
4.32 If AA'E is a triangle, the axis of the projectivity AE0E a A'EE' is
the line E0E'.
38 THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM AND PAPPUS’S THEOREM
EXERCISE
We are now ready to prove the earliest of all projective theorems (which was
originally proved by a laborious application of Euclid’s methods):
4.41 Pappus’s Theorem : If the six vertices of a plane hexagon lie alternately
on two lines, the three pairs of opposite sides meet in collinear points.
Proof. Let the hexagon be AB'CA'BC', as in Figure 4.4a (which
shows two of the many different ways in which it can be drawn). Since
alternate vertices are collinear, there is a projectivity ABC a A'B'C'. The
pairs of opposite sides, namely
* See Reference 8, p. 238; also A. Cronheim, Proc. Am. Math. Soc., 4 (1953), pp. 219—
221. The details are really not as formidable as they look, but Cronheim complicates them
by writing A + B for AB, and (A + B)(C + D) for AB ■ CD.
pappus 39
Figure 4.4a
We saw, in Section 3.2, that the figure for Desargues’s theorem is a self¬
dual configuration 103. Somewhat analogously, the figure for Pappus’s
theorem is a self-dual configuration 93: nine points and nine lines, with three
points on each line and three lines through each point. This fact becomes
evident as soon as we have made the notation more symmetrical by calling
the nine points
A3 = L, B3 — M, C3 — N
and the nine lines
EXERCISES
2. Given a triangle AXA2A3 and two points Bx, B2, locate a point B3 such that
the three lines AXBX, A2B3, A3B2 are concurrent while also the three lines
AxB3, A2B2, A3Bx are concurrent. Then also the three lines AXB2, A2BX, A3B3
are concurrent; in other words, if two triangles are doubly perspective, they
are triply perspective. (Reference 19, p. 100.)
4. State the dual of Pappus’s theorem and name the sides of the hexagon in
the notation of Figure 4.4b.
One-Dimensional Projectivities
Axiom 2.18 tells us that a projectivity relating two ranges on one line (that
is, a projective transformation of the line into itself) cannot have more than
two invariant points without being merely the identity, which relates each
point to itself. The projectivity is said to be elliptic, parabolic, or hyperbolic
according as the number of invariant points is 0, 1, or 2. We shall see that
both parabolic and hyperbolic projectivities always exist. In fact, Figure 5.1a
(which is essentially the same as Figure 2.4a) suggests a simple construction for
the hyperbolic or parabolic projectivity AEC a BDC which has a given
invariant point C. Here A, B, C, D, E are any five collinear points, and we
draw a quadrangle PQRS as if we were looking for the sixth point of a quad¬
rangular set. The given projectivity can be expressed as the product of two
perspeotivities
AEC £ SBC % BDC,
and it is easy to see what happens to any other point on the line.
41
42 ONE-DIMENSIONAL PROJECTIVITIES
AECC a BDCC,
5.11 The two statements AECF a BDCF and Q(A BC, DEF) are equiva¬
lent, not only when C and F are distinct but also when they coincide.
D A
This is remarkable because, when the quadrangular set is derived from the
quadrangle, the two triads in the symbol arise differently: the first from three
sides with a common vertex, and the second from three that form a triangle.
It is interesting that, whereas one way of matching two quadrangles (Figure
2.4b) uses only Desargues’s theorem, the other (Exercise 2, below) needs the
fundamental theorem.
Our use of the words elliptic, parabolic and hyperbolic arises from the
aspect of the projective plane as a Euclidean plane with an extra line at infinity.
In this aspect a conic is an ellipse, a parabola, or a hyperbola according as its
number of points at infinity is 0, 1, or 2, that is, according as it “goes off to
PARABOLIC PROJECTIVITIES 43
infinity” not at all, or in one direction (the direction of the axis of the
parabola) or in two directions (the directions of the asymptotes of the
hyperbola). The names of the conics themselves are due to Apollonius
(see Reference 13, p. 10).
EXERCISES
projectivity would take A to some different point B, and the second would
take B back to A. Thus the first would be ACC a BCC, the second would
be its inverse BCC a ACC, and the product would not be properly
hyperbolic but merely the identity.
Figure 5.2a
Thus the product of ACC a A'CC and A'CC a A"CC is ACC a A'CC,
and we can safely write out strings of parabolic relations such as
ABCC a A'B'CC a A"B"CC.
In particular, by “iterating” a parabolic projectivity ACC a A'CC we obtain
a sequence of points A, A', A", . . . such that
CCAA'A" ... a CCA'A" A"'
as in Figure 5.2a. Comparing this with Figure 3.5a, we see that A A’ A" ... is a
harmonic sequence.
We have seen that the statements
AECF a BDCF and Q(ABC, DEF)
are equivalent. Setting B = E and C = F, we deduce the equivalence of
ABCC a BDCC and H(BC, AD).
Hence, after a slight change of notation.
EXERCISE
5.3 Involutions
Desargues’s treatise of 1639, which included his famous theorem and many
other projective ideas, was not well received during his lifetime. This lack of
appreciation was possibly a result of his obscure style; he introduced about
seventy new terms, of which only involution has survived. According to his
definition, formulated in terms of the nonprojective concept of distance and
the arithmetic concept of multiplication, an “involution” is the relation
between pairs of points on a line whose distances from a fixed point have a
constant product (positive or negative). He might well have added “or a con¬
stant sum.” An equivalent definition, not using distances, was given by von
Staudt: An involution is aprojectivity of period two, that is, a projectivity which
interchanges pairs of points. It is remarkable that this relation
XX' a X'X
holds for all positions of X if it holds for any one position:
AA'X a A'AX',
where X is an arbitrary point on the line AA'. By Theorem 1.63, there is a
projectivity in which AA'XX' a A'AX'X. By the fundamental theorem
4.12, this projectivity, which interchanges X and X', is the same as the
given projectivity. Since X was arbitrarily chosen, the given projectivity is
an involution.
which shows that there is a projectivity in which AECF p DBFC. Since this
interchanges C and F, it is an involution, namely
5.33 The three pairs of opposite sides of a complete quadrangle meet any
line (inot through a vertex) in three pairs of an involution. Conversely, any
three collinear points, along with their mates in an involution, form a quad¬
rangular set.
It follows that the construction for F, when A, B, C, D, E are given (as in
the preamble to 2.41), may be regarded as a construction for the mate of C in
the involution (AD)(BE). (See Figure 2.4a or 5.1a.)
We have seen that CF is a pair of the involution (AD)(BE) if and only if
AECF a BDCF. We must get accustomed to using other letters in the same
context. For instance, MN is a pair of the involution (AB')(BA') if and only if
AA'MN a BB'MN. Since (AB')(BA') is the same as (AB')(A'B), it follows
that the two statements
AA’MN a BB'MN and ABMN p A’B’MN
are equivalent. (Notice that it is only the statements that are equivalent: the
two projectivities are, of course, distinct.)
If two involutions, (AA')(BB') and (AA^BBf, have a common pair MN,
we deduce
A’B'MN a BAMN p A^MN.
Hence
All these results remain valid when M and Ncoincide, so that we are dealing
with parabolic (instead of hyperbolic) projectivities. Thus M is an invariant
point of the involution (AB')(BA’) if and only if A A'MM p BB'MM, that is,
if and only if ABMM p A!B'MM; and if M is an invariant point of each of
the involutions (AA')(BB') and (AAAiBBf, it is also an invariant point of
(A'BJiB'AJ.
If two involutions have a common pair MN, their product is evidently
hyperbolic, with invariant points M and N. In fact, by watching their effect
on A, M,N in turn, we see that the product of (AB){MN) and (BC)(MN) is
AMN a CMN. More interestingly,
THE PRODUCT OF TWO INVOLUTIONS 47
EXERCISES
As we have seen, any involution that has an invariant point B (and a pair
of distinct corresponding points C and Cj may be expressed as BCC a BCC
or (.BB){CC’). Let A denote the harmonic conjugate of B with respect to C
and C. By 4.21, the two harmonic sets ABCC and ABC'C are related by a
unique projectivity ABCC' a ABC'C. The fundamental theorem identifies
this with the given involution. Hence
5.41 Any involution that has an invariant point B has another invariant
point A, which is the harmonic conjugate of B with respect to any pair of
distinct corresponding points.
Thus any involution that is not elliptic is hyperbolic: there are no “parabolic
involutions.” Moreover, any two distinct points A and B are the invariant
48 ONE-DIMENSIONAL PROJECTIVITIES
5.42 Any point is its own harmonic conjugate with respect to itself and any
other point.
EXERCISES
1. If ABCD a BACD then H{AB, CD). (Compare Section 4.2, Exercise 4.)
4. Given Q{ABC, DEF), let A', B', C', D', E', F' be the harmonic conjugates
of A, B, C, D, E, Fwith respect to two fixed points on the same line. Then
Q(A'B'C', D'E'Fj.
5. If ABCD a ABDE and H(CE, DDj, then H(AB, DDj. (S. Schuster.)
6. Let Xbe a variable point collinear with three distinct points A, B, C, and
let Y and X'be defined by H(AB, XY), H{BC, YXj. Then the projectivity
X a is parabolic. [Hint: When X is invariant, so that X' coincides
with it, Ytoo must coincide with it; for otherwise both A and C would be
the harmonic conjugate of B with respect to X and T. Therefore X must
be either A or B, and also either B or C; that is, X = B.]
7. If H{BC, AD) and H(CA, BE) and H(AB, CF), then Q{ABC, DEF).
[Hint: Apply 5.41 to the involution BCAD 7; ACBE. Deduce Y\{DE, CF).]
CHAPTER SIX
Two-Dimensional Projectivities
We shall find that the one-dimensional projectivity ABC a A'B'C' has two
different analogues in two dimensions: one relating points to points and lines
to lines, the other relating points to lines and lines to points. The names
collineation and correlation were introduced by Mdbius in 1827, but some
special collineations (such as translations, rotations, reflections, and dilata¬
tions) were considered much earlier. Another example is Poncelet’s “ho¬
mology”: the relation between the central projections of a plane figure
onto another plane from two different centers of perspective. We shall give
(in Section 6.2) a two-dimensional treatment of the same idea.
By a point-to-point transformation X -> X' we mean a rule for associating
every point X with every point X' so that there is exactly one X' for each X
and exactly one X for each X'. A line-to-line transformation x—>-x' is
defined similarly. A collineation is a point-to-point and line-to-line trans¬
formation that preserves the relation of incidence. Thus it transforms ranges
into ranges, pencils into pencils, quadrangles into quadrangles, and so on.
Clearly, it is a self-dual concept, the inverse of a collineation is a collineation,
and the product of two collineations is again a collineation.
49
50 TWO-DIMENSIONAL PROJECTIVITIES
Figure 6.1a
Proof. Let a and a' be the corresponding lines that carry the pro¬
jectively related ranges. We wish to establish the same kind of relationship
between any other pair of corresponding lines, say b and b' (Figure 6.1a).
Let Tbe a variable point on b, and O a fixed point on neither a nor b. Let
O Y meet a in X. The given collineation transforms O into a fixed point O'
(on neither a! nor bj, and O Y into a line O' Y' that meets a! in X'. Since X
is on the special line a, we have X a X'. Thus
O O'
YkXkX'kY':
6.12 The only projective collineation that leaves invariant 4 lines forming
a quadrilateral, or 4 points forming a quadrangle, is the identity.
Proof. Suppose the sides of a quadrilateral are 4 invariant lines.
Then the vertices (where the sides intersect in pairs) are 6 invariant points,
3 on each side. Since the relation between corresponding sides is projective,
every point on each side is invariant. Any other line contains invariant
points where it meets the sides and is consequently invariant. Thus the
collineation must be the identity. The dual argument gives the same result
when there is an invariant quadrangle.
PROJECTIVE COLLINEATIONS 51
6.13 Given any two complete quadrilaterals (or quadrangles), with their
four sides (or vertices) named in a corresponding order, there is just one pro¬
jective collineation that will transform the first into the second.
EXERCISE
Let PQRS -^P'Q'R'S' denote the projective collineation that relates two
given quadrangles PQRS and P' Q'R'S'; for instance, PQRS —*■ PQRS is
the identity. Describe the special collineations
(i) PQRS —► QPRS, (ii) PQRS -> QRPS, (iii) PQRS -* QRSP.
Hints:
(i) What happens to the lines PQ and RSI
(ii) What does Figure 3.4a tell us about the possibility of an invariant
line?
(iii) What happens to the lines PR, QS, and to the points QR • PS, PQ • RSI
6.22 A homology is determined when its center and axis and one pair of
corresponding points (collinear with the center) are given.
Proof. Let O be the center, o the axis, P and P' (collinear with O)
the given corresponding points. We proceed to set up a construction where¬
by each point R yields a definite corresponding point R'. If R coincides
with O or lies on o, it is, of course, invariant, that is, R' coincides with R.
If, as in Figure 2.3a, R is neither on o nor on OP, we have
R' = EP’ ■ OR, where E = o ■ PR.
Finally, if R is on OP, as in Figure 6.2b, we use an auxiliary pair of points
Q, Q' (of which the former is arbitrary while the latter is derived from it
the way we just now derived Rr from R) to obtain
R' = DQ' • OP, where D = o • QR.
54 TWO-DIMENSIONAL PROJECTIVITIES
Figure 6.2c
6.23 An elation is determined when its axis and one pair of corresponding
points are given.
Proof. Let o be the axis, P and P' the given pair. Since the collinea-
tion is known to be an elation, its center is o • PP'. We proceed as in the
proof of 6.22, using Figures 6.2a and 6.2c instead of 2.3a and 6.2b.
This elation, with center o ■ PP', is conveniently denoted by [o; P —► P'].
6.24 Any collineation that has one range of invariant points (but not more
than one) is perspective.
Proof. Since the identity is (trivially) a projectivity, 6.11 tells us that
any such collineation is projective. There cannot be more than one invariant
point outside the line o whose points are all invariant; for, two such would
form, with two arbitrary points on o, a quadrangle of the kind considered
in 6.12. If there is one invariant point O outside o, every line through O
meets o in another invariant point; that is, every line through O is invariant.
Any noninvariant point P lies on such a line and is therefore transformed
into another point P' on this line OP\ hence the collineation is a homology,
as in 6.22. If, on the other hand, all the invariant points lie on o, any two
distinct joins PP' and QQ' (of pairs of corresponding points) must meet o
in the same point O, and the collineation is an elation, as in 6.23.
Hence, also,
6.25 If a collineation has a range of invariant points, it has a pencil of
invariant lines.
EXERCISES
3. If, on a line through its center O, an elation transforms A into A', and
B into B', then Q(OAA', OB'B). (Reference 19, p. 78.) [Hint: Use 5.11.]
6. What kind of projective collineation will leave invariant two points and
two lines (the points not lying on the lines) ?
6.31 A harmonic homology is determined when its center and axis are
given.
For any point P, the corresponding point P' is simply the harmonic con¬
jugate of P with respect to O and o ■ OP. Thus a harmonic homology is of
period 2. Conversely,
quadrangle PP'QQ' into P'PQ'Q. The invariant lines PP' and QQ' meet in
an invariant point O, as in Figure 6.3a. Since the collineation interchanges
the pair of lines PQ, P'Q', and likewise the pair PQ', P' Q, the two points
are invariant. Moreover, the two invariant lines PP' and MN meet in a
third invariant point L on MN. By Axiom 2.18, every point on MN is
invariant. Thus the collineation is perspective (according to the definition
in Section 6.2). Since, by Axiom 2.17, its center O does not lie on its axis
MN, it is a homology. Finally, since H(PP', OL), it is a harmonic homology.
EXERCISES
2. Any elation with axis o may be expressed as the product of two harmonic
homologies having this same axis o.
5. What is the Euclidean name for a harmonic homology whose axis is the
line at infinity?
* Private communication.
PROJECTIVE CORRELATIONS 57
Figure 6.4a
58 TWO-DIMENSIONAL PROJECT1VITIES
6.42 A quadrangle and a quadrilateral, with the four vertices of the former
associated in a definite order with the four sides of the latter, are related by
just one projective correlation.
EXERCISE
Polarities
Chasles was the last important member of the great French school
of projective geometers. After his time primacy in this subject
passed across the Rhine, never to return.
/. L. Coolidge (Reference 4, p. 58)
a; two distinct points would both have the same polar. This is impossible,
since a polarity is a one-to-one correspondence between points and lines.
Dually, the lines x and CX are paired in the involution of conjugate lines
through C.
Such a triangle ABC, in which each vertex is the pole of the opposite side
(so that any two vertices are conjugate points, and any two sides are con¬
jugate lines), is called a self-polar triangle.
EXERCISES
(ABCXPp).
Thus any triangle ABC, any point P not on a side, and any linep not through
a vertex, determine a definite polarity (ABC)(Pp), in which the polar x of
an arbitrary point X can be constructed by incidences.
This construction could be carried out by the method of 6.42, as applied to
the correlation ABCP —> abcp. More elegantly, we could adapt the notation
of Figure 7.2a so that
Ap = a-p, Bv = b • p, Cp = c-p
are AP, BP, CP, the pairs of opposite sides of the quadrangle ABCP meet the
line p in pairs of conjugate points. Hence
EXERCISES
1. In the notation of Figure 2.4a, any correlation that relates the points
S, D, E, F to the respective lines g, SA, SB, SC is a polarity.
2. Consider a polarity (ABC)(Pp) in which P is on p. Find Q and q, not
incident, so that the same polarity can be described as (ABC){Qq).
From any given triangle we can derive a polar triangle by taking the polars
of the three vertices, or the poles of the three sides. M. Chasles observed that
a triangle and its polar triangle, if distinct, are perspective. In other words,
Figure 7.3a
This proof breaks down if Q lies on q. But in that case we permute the
names of P, Q, R (and correspondingly p, q, r), or call the first triangle pqr
and the second PQR, in such a way that the new Q and q are not incident. It
is evidently impossible for each triangle to be inscribed in the other.
EXERCISES
1. A triangle and its polar triangle (if distinct) are perspective from a line, and
therefore also from a point. The point is the pole of the line.
We are now ready to describe the “still simpler procedure” (Figure 7.4a)
which was promised in Section 7.2.
7-41 The polar of a point X (not on AP, BP, or p) in the polarity (.ABC)(Pp)
is the line XxX2 determined by
Ax — a • PX, Px—p- AX, Xx = AP-AxPx,
B2 = b • PX, P2=p- BX, X2 = BP- B2P2.
Proof.Applying 7.31 to the triangle PAX, we deduce that its sides
AX, XP, PA meet the polars p, a, x of its vertices in three collinear points,
66 POLARITIES
Figure 7.4a
the first two of which are Px and Ax. Hence x must meet PA in a point lying
on PXAX, namely, in the point PA • PXAX — Xx. That is, x passes through Xx.
Similarly (by applying 7.31 to the triangle PBX instead of PAX), x passes
through X2.
This construction fails when X lies on AP, for then A1P1 coincides with
AP, and Xx is no longer properly defined. However, since X2 can still be
constructed as above, the polar of X is now APX2 (where Av = a • p).
Similarly, when X is on BP, its polar is XxBv.
Finally, to locate the polar of a point X on p, we can apply the dual of the
above construction to locate the pole Y of a line y through X. This y may be
any line through Xexceptp or PX. (It is convenient to choose y — AX or, if
this happens to coincide with PX, to choose y = BX.) Then the desired polar
is x = P Y.
EXERCISES
EXERCISES
2. Let Xbe any point on none of the sides p, r, s of a given self-polar pentagon
PQRST. Then its polar is the line
EXERCISE
Figure 2.3a (or Figure 6.2b) shows the homology with center O and axis
o = DF that transforms P into P' (and consequently Q into Qj. This
homology may be expressed as the product of two polarities
where p is any line not passing through a vertex of the common self-polar
triangle ODF. To prove this, we merely have to observe that, the homology
and the product of polarities both transform the quadrangle ODFP into
ODFP'.
Unfortunately, this expression for a homology as the product of two polar¬
ities cannot in any simple way be adapted to an elation. Accordingly, it is
worthwhile to mention a subtler expression that applies equally well to either
kind of perspective collineation. Figure 7.7a shows the homology or elation
with center O and axis o — CP that transforms A into another point A' on the
line c = OA. Here C and P are arbitrary points on the axis o (which passes
through O if the collineation is an elation). Let p be an arbitrary line through
O, meeting b = CA and b' = CA' in Q and Q'. Let B be an arbitrary point on
c. We proceed to verify that the given perspective collineation is the product of
the two polarities
(.ABC)(Pp) and (A'BC)(Pp).
THE PRODUCT OF TWO POLARITIES 69
A’
Figure 7.7b
70 POLARITIES
does not lie on V nor on 1". Let l" meet / in B, l' in C. Of the two polarities
EXERCISES
The Conic
The study of conics is said to have begun in 430 b.c., when the Athenians,
suffering from a plague, appealed to the oracle at Delos and were told to
double the size of Apollo’s cubical altar. Attempts to follow this instruction
by placing an equal cube beside the original one, or by doubling the edge
length (and thus producing a cube of eight times the volume of the original
one), made the pestilence worse than ever. At last, Hippocrates of Chios
explained that what was needed was to multiply the edge length by the cube
root of 2. The first geometrical solution for this problem was given by
Archytas about 400 b.c. (Reference 2, p. 329). He used a twisted curve.
Menaechmus, about 340 b.c., found a far simpler solution by the use of
conics. For the next six or seven centuries, conics were investigated in great
detail, especially by Apollonius of Perga (262-200 B.c.), who coined the
names ellipse, parabola, and hyperbola. Interest in this subject was revived in
the seventeenth century (a.d.) when Kepler showed how a parabola is at once
a limiting case of an ellipse and of a hyperbola, and Blaise Pascal (1623-1662)
discovered a projective property of a circle which consequently holds just as
well for any kind of conic. We shall see how this characteristic property of a
71
72 THE CONIC
Figure 8.1a
the conic twice or not at all, that is, according as the involution of conjugate
points on it is hyperbolic or elliptic. The above remarks show that, of the lines
through any point P on the conic, one (namely p) is a tangent and all the
others are secants. Moreover, if P and Q are any two distinct points on the
conic, the line PQ is a secant.
Dually, a point not lying on the conic is said to be exterior or interior
according as it lies on two tangents or on none, that is, according as the
involution of conjugate lines through it is hyperbolic or elliptic. Thus an
exterior point H is the pole of a secant h, and an interior point E (if such a
point exists) is the pole of a nonsecant e. Of the points on a tangent p, one
(namely P) is on the conic, and all the others are exterior. If p and q are any
two distinct tangents, the point p • q (which is the pole of the secant PQ) is
exterior.
Figure 8.1b
Figure 8.1b may help to clarify these ideas, but we must take care not to be
unduly influenced by real geometry. For instance, it would be foolish to
waste any effort on trying to prove that every point on a nonsecant is exterior,
or that every line through an interior point is a secant; for in some geometries
these “obvious” propositions are false.
Conversely,
Dually,
8.13 Any two conjugate lines through an exterior point p • q are harmonic
conjugates with respect to the two tangents p, q; and any pair of harmonic
conjugates with respect to p and q is a pair of conjugate lines with respect to
the conic.
EXERCISES
2. The polar of any exterior point joins the points of contact of the two tan¬
gents that can be drawn through the point. Dually, the pole of a secant PQ
is the point of intersection of the tangents at P and Q.
7. In the spirit of Section 2.5, Exercise 5, what would be natural names for:
(i) a conic of which the line at infinity is a nonsecant,
(ii) a conic of which the line at infinity is a tangent,
(iii) a conic of which the line at infinity is a secant,
(iv) the pole of the line at infinity with respect to any conic,
(v) the tangents of a hyperbola through its center,
(vi) a line (other than a tangent) through the center of any conic,
(vii) conjugate lines through the center?
as in Figure 8.2a. The line BC meets the sides QR and PS in points Ax and
A2 such that H{QR, AAj) and H(P<S, AA2). By 8.12, both Ax and A2 are
conjugate to A. Thus the line BC, on which they lie, is the polar of A.
Similarly, CA is the polar of B, and AB of C.
Hence:
8.22 To construct the polar of a given point A, not on the conic, draw any
two secants QR and PS through A; then the polar joins the two points QS • RP
and RS • PQ.
8.23 To construct the tangent at a given point A on the conic, join A to the
pole of any secant through A.
These constructions serve to justify the statement that any conic determines
a hyperbolic polarity whose self-conjugate points are the points on the conic.
EXERCISES
1. Let A and B be two conjugate points with respect to a given conic. Let an
arbitrary line through A meet the conic in Q and R, while BQ and BR
meet the conic again in S and P, respectively. Then A, S, P are collinear.
6. There is one and only one conic through three given points and having
another given point as pole of a given line. (Reference 19, p. 137.) [Hint:
Let PQR be the given triangle, D and afthe point and line. Let DP meet d in
P'. Let S be the harmonic conjugate of P with respect to D and P'. Let ABC
be the diagonal triangle of the quadrangle PQRS. Consider the polarity
(ABC)(Dd).]
Figure 8.3a
We are now ready for one of the most significant properties of a conic:
8.32 Steiner’s Theorem: Let lines x and y join a variable point on a conic
to two fixed points on the same conic; then x a y.
Proof. The tangentsp and q, at the fixed points P.and Q, meet in D,
the pole of PQ (see Figure 8.3a). Let c be a fixed line through D (but not
through P or Q), meeting x in B, andy in A. By 8.31, BA is a pair of the
involution of conjugate points on c. Hence, when the point R — x • y
varies on the conic, we have
x A B A A A y,
as desired.
The following remarks make it natural for us to include the tangents p
and q as special positions for x and y. (Notice that the idea of “continuity,”
though intuitively helpful, is not assumed.) Writing d — PQ and Cx = c • d,
consider the possibility of using P or Q as a position for R. When R is P, y is d,
A is Cl5 B is the conjugate point D, and therefore x is p. Similarly, when R is
Q, x is d, B is Cl5 A is D, and y is q. In other words, when y is d, x is p; and
when x is d, y is q.
EXERCISES
TEAU a TABU.
If we are not given the conic, but only the points P, Q, R, D, we can still
construct C = PQ ■ RD and its harmonic conjugate Cx. Then c is the line
CXD, which meets QR and RP in A and B. The conic itself can be described
as the locus of self-conjugate points (and the envelope of self-conjugate lines)
in the polarity (ABC)(Pp), where p = PD. Since PD and QD are the tangents
at P and Q, our conclusion may be stated as follows:
8.41 A conic is determined when three points on it and the tangents at two
of them are given.
h in C2. The line c is fixed, since it joins D — p ■ q to Cl5 which is the harmonic
conjugate of C with respect to P and Q. In other words, the fixed point
C = d- h has the same polar for all the conics. Thus C2 = c • h is another
fixed point, and RS is always a pair of the hyperbolic involution (CC)(C2C2)
on h. Hence:
8.42 Of the conics that touch two given lines at given points, those which
meet a third line (not through either of the points) do so in pairs of an
involution.
EXERCISES
1. In Figure 8.4a, RCx is the tangent at R. [Hint: Use 8.23 with R for A.]
3. Given three tangents to a conic, and the points of contact of two of them,
construct another tangent.
* Private communication.
80 THE CONIC
EXERCISES
1. Given a triangle PQR and a point O, not on any side, what is the locus of
the trilinear pole of a variable line through 01 [Hint: In Figure 3.4a, let
PQR be fixed while DE varies in a pencil. Then A a D x E a R ]
2. Let P and Q be two fixed points on a tangent of a conic. If x is a variable
line through P, and X is the (variable) pole of x, what is the locus of
x • QX1 (S. Schuster.*)
3. Give an explicit determination of the locus in Exercise 2, by naming a
sufficient number of special points on it.
4. Let P, Q, R, P', Q' be five points, no three collinear, and let x be a variable
line through P. Define
N = PQ' • P'Q, M — RP' • x, L = Q'R • MN, R' = QL-x.
What is the locus of R' 1
* Private communication.
CHAPTER NINE
a YxY2YzY.
Hence
9.12 Any five lines, of which no three are concurrent, determine a unique
conic touching them.
We may regard XYZ as a variable triangle whose vertices run along fixed
lines p, q, d while the two sides YZ and ZX pass through fixed points A and B.
We have seen that the envelope of XY is a conic touching p at P, and q at Q.
More generally,
B A
X^Z^Y.
A CONIC ENVELOPE 83
Figure 9.Id
C — q ■ r, E = p • r, G = AB • r, I = AB ■ p, J = AB • q,
X — ZB • DE, Y — ZA • CD,
In Figure 9.Id, we see a hexagon ABCYXE whose six sides all touch a
conic. The three lines A Y, BX, CE, which join pairs of opposite vertices, are
naturally called diagonals of the hexagon. Theorem 9.14 tells us that, if the
diagonals of a hexagon are concurrent, the six sides all touch a cpnic.
Conversely, if all the sides of a hexagon touch a conic, five of them can be
identified with the lines DE, EA, AB, BC, CD. Since the given conic is the
only one that touches these fixed lines, the sixth side must coincide with one
of the lines XY for which BX • A Y lies on CE. We have thus proved
Figure 9.1e
EXERCISES
Figure 9.If
A CONIC LOCUS 85
9.21 Any five points, of which no three are collinear, determine a unique
conic through them.
9.22 If the sides of a variable triangle pass through three fixed non-
collinear points P, Q, R, while two vertices lie on fixed lines a and b‘not
concurrent with PQ, then the third vertex describes a conic.
Figure 9.2b
This enables us (as in Figure 9.2b, where the variable triangle is shaded) to
locate any number of points on the conic through five given points.
The dual of 9.15 is the still more famous
In Figure 9.2c, the hexagon is abcdef and the three collinear points are
a • d, b • e, c • f. We have obtained Pascal’s theorem by dualizing Brianchon’s.
Historically, this procedure was reversed: C. J. Brianchon (1760-1854)
obtained his theorem by dualizing Pascal’s, at a time when the principle of
duality was just beginning to be recognized. Pascal’s own proof (for a
hexagon inscribed in a circle) was seen and praised by G. W. Leibniz (1646-
1716) when he visited Paris, but afterwards it was lost. All that remains of
Pascal’s relevant work is a brief Essay pour les coniques (1640), in which the
theorem is stated as follows:
Si dans le plan MSQ du point M partent les deux droites MK, MV, & du point
86 THE CONIC, CONTINUED
S partent les deux droites SK, S V • • • & par les points K, V passe la circonference
d’un cercle coupante les droites MV, MK* SV, SK es pointes O, P, Q, N: je dis
que les droites MS, NO, PQ sont de mesme ordre.
EXERCISES
1. Given five points (no three collinear), construct the tangent at each point
to the conic through all of them.
2. Given a quadrangle PQRS and a line s through S (but not through any
other vertex), construct another point on the conic through P, Q, R that
touches s at S.
3. Given six points on a conic, in how many ways can they be regarded as the
vertices of a Pascal hexagon ?
5. Try to reconstruct Pascal’s lost proof (using only the methods that would
have been available in his time).
Desargues not only invented the word involution (in its geometrical sense)
but also showed how the pairs of points belonging to an involution on a line
arise from a “pencil”of conics through four points. This is his “involution
theorem,” which is even more remarkable than his “two triangle theorem.”
Proof. Let PQRS be the given quadrangle, and g the given line,
meeting the sides PS, QS, QR, PR in A, B, D, E, and any one of the conics
in T and U (see Figure 9.3a). By regarding S, R, T, U as four positions of a
variable point on this conic, we see from 8.32 that the four lines joining them
to P are projectively related to the four lines joining them to Q. Hence
AETU a BDTU.
AETU a DBUT.
EXERCISES
9.41 If two triangles have six distinct vertices, all lying on a conic, there is a
polarity for which both triangles are self-polar.
Figure 9.4a
TWO SELF-POLAR TRIANGLES 89
9.42 If two triangles, with no vertex of either on a side of the other, are
self-polar for a given polarity, their six vertices lie on a conic and their six
sides touch another conic.
EXERCISES
1. How many polarities can be expected to arise in the manner of 9.41 from
six given points on a conic?
2. If two triangles have six distinct vertices, all lying on a conic, their six
sides touch another conic.
3. If two conics are so situated that there is a triangle inscribed in one and
circumscribed about the other, then every secant of the former conic that is
a tangent of the latter can be used as a side of such an inscribed-circum-
scribed triangle.
Figure 9.5a
90 THE CONIC, CONTINUED
EXERCISES
The above words of Forder emphasize the fact that our primitive concepts
are defined solely by their properties as described in the axioms. This fact is
most readily appreciated when we abandon the “intuitive” idea that the
number of points is infinite. We shall find that all our theorems remain valid
(although the figures are somewhat misleading) when there are only 6 points
on each line, and 31 points in the plane.
In 1892, Fano described an ^-dimensional geometry in which the number of
points on each line is p + 1 for a fixed prime p. In 1906, O. Veblen and
W. H. Bussey gave this finite Projective Geometry the name PG(n,p) and
extended it to PG(n, q), where q — pk,p is prime, and k is any positive integer.
(For instance, q may be 5, 7, or 9, but cannot be 6.)
Without attempting to explain the necessity for restricting the possible
values of q to primes and their powers, we can deduce some numerical
results immediately. Since any range can be related to any other by a sequence
of perspectivities, the number of points on a line must be the same for all
lines. Let us agree to denote it by q + 1. By the two-dimensional principle of
91
92 A FINITE PROJECTIVE PLANE
duality, this is the same as the number of lines in a pencil (that is, lying in a
plane and passing through a point); by the three-dimensional principle of
duality, it is also the same as the number of planes through a line in three-
dimensional space. In a plane, any one point is joined to the remaining
points by a pencil which consists of q -f- 1 lines, each containing the one
point and q others. Hence the plane contains
q(q + 1) + l = q2 + q + l
points and (by duality) the same number of lines. In space, the q + 1 points
on one line are joined to the remaining points by q + 1 planes, each containing
the q + 1 points and q2 others. Hence the whole space contains
q\q + 1) + (q + 1) = q3 + q2 + q + 1
points and (by duality) the same number of planes.
The general formula for the number of points in PG(n, q) is
qn+qn-1 + ---+q + 1= -.
q — i
It was proved by J. Singer (Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 43 (1938), pp. 377-385)
that every geometry of this kind (with Desargues’s theorem taken as an
axiom if n = 2) can be represented by a combinatorial scheme such as the
one exhibited in Section 10.2 for the special case PG(2, 5).
EXERCISES
1. In PG(3, q) there are q + 1 points on each line, how many lines (or planes)
through each point? How many lines in the whole space? [Hint: Every
two of the <73 + q2 + q + 1 points determine a line, but each line is
determined equally well by any two of its q + 1 points.]
In accordance with the general formula, the finite projective plane PG(2, 5)
has 6 points on each line, 6 lines through each point,
s3 _ 1
52 + 5 + 1 =--- =31
5 — 1
PERFECT DIFFERENCE SETS 93
points altogether, and of course also 31 lines. The appropriate scheme uses
symbols P0, Px,. . P30 for the 31 points, and /0, lx,. . ., /30 for the 31 lines,
with a table (page 94) telling us which are the 6 points on each line and which
are the 6 lines through each point.
For good measure, this table gives every relation of incidence twice: each
column tells us which points lie on a line and also which lines pass through a
point; e.g., the last column says that the line /„ contains the six points
P0, Pi) P» P8 P12) > Pia
and that the point P0 belongs to the six lines
4> 4 4 12
’ > ^ > ll8-
Thus the notation exhibits a polarity Pr<-> lr. Marshall Hall [Cyclicprojective
planes, Duke Math. J. 14 (1947), pp. 1079-1090] has proved that such a
polarity always occurs. (Our lr is his m_r.) By regarding the subscripts as
residues modulo 31, so that r + 31 has the same significance as r itself, we
can condense the whole table into the simple statement that the point Pr and
line lg are incident if and only if
10.21 r + s = 0, 1, 3, 8, 12, or 18 (mod 31).
The “congruence” a = b (mod n) is a convenient abbreviation for the
statement that a and b leave the same remainder (or “residue”) when
divided by n. The residues 0, 1, 3, 8, 12, 18 (mod 31) are said to form a
“perfect difference set” because every possible residue except zero (namely,
1, 2, 3, . . ., 30) is uniquely expressible as the difference between two of these
special residues:
1 = 1-0, 2 = 3-1, 3 = 3 — 0, 4 = 12-8, •••,
13 = 0 — 18,. . ., 30 = 0 — 1.
The impossibility of a PG(2, 6) is related in a subtle manner to the
impossibility of solving Euler’s famous problem of the 36 officers [Reference
2, p. 190]. '
EXERCISES
0 1 3 9
0 0 1 3 9
1 12 0 2 8
3 10 11 0 6
9 4 5 7 0
o O CO 00 CN oo
o O CN r-
co
<N ON O VO o VO
CN cn T 1 1—11
co 00 ON O »o ON to
(N <N
r- OO O 00
CN <N CO T ’
CO
c >0 vo r- ON CO
<D CN <N CN 1"H
r2
'o VO lO vo OO CN vo CN
_c
CN CN CN *“
r- to
o
I—
r-
(N
to
<N CN
03
oo co vo O o
CN <N CN ’
t3 ON <N cn to o CO ON
CN CN CN CO
C
c3
o _ <N ON CN 00
r—1 CN CN CN CN
_ O CO OO r-
CN (N CN CN
CN ON O CN r- o vo
CN CN CN
C
a OO ON
t—< CN
vo
CN
O
CO
to
r- OO O to ON
CN CN CN
c3
-C 00
*o VO r- ON CO
T—1 CN CN
*-*
-3
o 00 CO
3 VO to vo
T“t CN CN
CN
t"- in r- CN vo
CN CN
fi T-"
<0
> oo co vo
T—■(
»-H
CN
»o
CN
O
'5b
of ON CN co «o O O
CN CN CO
o o CN ON CO ON
</a CN CN CN
(U
_3 O CO OO CN 00
CN ""H r-H CN CN
1"H
> _
CN ON O CN r-
(N CN CN
3
co 00 ON 1—H vo O vo
IZ) CN T"H CN CN
O
a. r- OO o to On to
<N CN
Q-,
o
»o vo f" ON 00
jy (N CN
3
3 vo to vo 00 CO r- CO
y—4
H CN
*■*
CN
r- Tf- to r- CN vo CN
CN T—» CN
OO co Tj- VO _ to
CN r~' CN
ON CN cn in o O
CN CN
O _ <N ON CO ON
co
^ =o
94
AXIOMS FOR THE PROJECTIVE PLANE 95
2. Set up an incidence table for PG(2, 3), assuming thatP,. and ls are incident
if and only if
r + s = 0, 1, 3, or 9 (mod 13).
The discussion in Section 3.1 indicates that the following seven axioms
suffice for the development of two-dimensional projective geometry:
Axiom 2.11 There exist a point and a line that are not incident.
Axiom 2.12 Every line is incident with at least three distinct points.
Axiom 2.13 Any two distinct points are incident with just one line.
Axiom 3.11 Any two distinct lines are incident with at least one point.
Axiom 2.17 The three diagonal points of a quadrangle are never collinear.
Axiom 2.32 If two triangles are perspective from a point, they are per¬
spective from a line.
D = P12, E = P8, F — P0 — A. Since there are only six points on the line,
the sequence is inevitably periodic: the five points
are repeated cyclically for ever. Instead of taking P and Q to be P5 and P30,
we could just as well have taken them to be any other pair of points on /13 or
lu or /16 or 4i or /25 (these being, with l0, the lines through P18); we would
still have obtained the same harmonic sequence.
EXERCISE
Set up an incidence table for PG(2, 2), assuming that Pr and ls are incident
if and only if
r + s = 0, 1, or 3 (mod 7).
Verify that this “geometry” satisfies all our two-dimensional axioms except
Axiom 2.17.
10.4 Involutions
EXERCISES
1. In PG(2, 3), how many projectivities are there on a line ? How many of
them are involutions ? How many of the involutions are elliptic ?
3. In PG(2, 3), the four points on a line form a harmonic set in every possible
order. (G. FanoX)
4. In PG(2, 5), any four distinct points on a line form a harmonic set in a
suitable order. In fact, H(AB, CD) if and only if the involution (AB)(CD) is
hyperbolic. In other words, each of the fifteen pairs of points on the line
induces a separation of the six into three mutually harmonic pairs. (W.L.
Edge, “31 -point geometry," Math. Gazette, 39 (1955), p. 114, section 3.)
* This problem, for q a prime, was solved more than a hundred years ago by J. A.
Serret, Corns d'algebre superieure. Tome 2, 3rd ed. (Gauthier-Villars: Paris, 1866), p. 355,
or 5th ed. (Paris, 1885), pp. 381-382.
t Giornale di Matematiche 30 (1892), p. 116.
98 A FINITE PROJECTIVE PLANE
collineation may transform P0 into any one of the 31 points, and P1 into any
one of the remaining 30. It may transform P2 int° any one of the 31 6 25
points not collinear with the first two. The number of points that lie on at
least one side of a given triangle is evidently 3 + (3 • 4) = 15; therefore the
number not on any side is 16. Hence PG(2, 5) admits altogether
31 • 30*25 • 16 = 372000
31 -25 = 775.
Apart from the identity, the two most obvious collineations are Pr —^► P5r
(of period 3, since 53 = 1 (mod 31)) and Pr-*Pr+1 (of period 31). The
criterion 6.11 assures us that they are projective. In fact, the corresponding
ranges of the former on P0Pi and P0P5 are related by the perspectivity
PqP\P^P%P\2^18 7\ P0P5P15P9P29P28
and the corresponding ranges of the latter on P0Pi and P4P2 are related by a
projectivity with axis P0P2:
A P0P2P20P11P17P7 A P1P2P4P97,i3JPi9-
EXERCISES
2. How many projective collineations exist in PG(2, 3)? How many of them
are of period 2?
10.6 Conics
The most obvious correlation is, of course, Pr -> lr. To verify that it is
projective, we may use 6.41 in the form
symbol (ABC)(Pp) with P not on p. When only one side is a secant, 2 of the 6
points are on this side and the remaining 4 are among the 16; therefore each
hyperbolic polarity (with ABC of the second type) is named 4 times with P on
p and 12 times with P not on p. Conversely, if P lies on p, ABC can only be of
the second type; therefore the number of such hyperbolic polarities (each
accounting for 4 of the 48 symbols) is 12. Since each hyperbolic polarity
(or conic) has 5 self-polar triangles of the first type and 15 of the second, the
number of hyperbolic polarities in which a given triangle ABC is of the first
type is one-third of 12, that is, 4. The total number of symbols (ABC)(Pp)
that denote hyperbolic polarities is thus
48 + 16 • 4 + 12 • 12 = 256.
Since we have accounted for all the available symbols,
There are no elliptic polaritu v in PG(2, 5).*
The total number of triangle s in PG(2, 5) can be found as follows. There are
31 choices for the first vertex, 30 for the second, and 31 — 6 = 25 for the
third; but the three vertices can be permuted in 3! = 6 ways. Hence the
number is
31 -30-25
-- = 31 • 125 = 3875.
6
We can easily deduce the number of conics. Each conic has 5 self-polar
triangles of the first type, and each triangle plays this role for 4 conics;
therefore the number of conics isf
31 -125-4
= 3100.
5
As an instance of 7.71, we observe that the collineation Pr->Pr+1 (or
lr -> lr_j) is the product of the polarities lr and Pr<-> lT_x, which may be
expressed as
(PzPbPzvliP Ji) and (P4P5P2 s)(P 3^2) •
EXERCISES
1. In PG(2, 5), express the collineation Pr —► P5r (or ls —► /5s+3) as the product
of two polarities.
2. Derive the number of conics in PG(2, 5) from the number of sets of 5
points, no 3 collinear.
* In other words, every polarity is hyperbolic. This is true not only in complex geometry
and in PG{2, 5) but in PG(2, q) for every q = pk. See P. Scherk, Can. Math. Bull., 2 (1959),
pp. 45-46, or Segre (Reference 15, pp. 266-268).
t Analogous reasoning shows that the number of conics in PG{2, q) is qh — q2. See B.
Segre, Le geometrie di Galois, Ann. Matematica (4), 48 (1959), pp. 1-96, especially p. 4.
ACCESSIBILITY WITH RESPECT TO A POLARITY 101
3. In PG(2, 5), how many conics can be drawn through the vertices of a
given triangle? [Hint: Use 9.21.] How many triangles can be inscribed in a
given conic? (These results provide another method for determining the
total number of conics.)
4. How many conics exist in PG(2, 3)? In what sense does 9.21 remain valid
when there are only 4 points on a conic?
5. Does a conic in PG(2, 3) admit a self-polar triangle all of whose sides are
nonsecants?
6. In any projective plane, let us say that a point Q is accessible from a point
P if it is the harmonic conjugate of P with respect to some pair of distinct
points which are conjugate (to each other) in a given polarity. Then P is
accessible from itself; if Q is accessible from P, P is accessible from Q;
if Q is accessible from R, and R from P, Q is accessible from P. In other
words, the relation of accessibility is reflexive, symmetric, and transitive.
Parallelism
The attentive reader must have noticed that most of the conics appearing
in our figures look like something that has been familiar ever since he first
saw the full moon: they look like circles. This observation raises the important
question: Is the circle a conicl We can answer Yes as soon as we have found a
characteristic property of a conic that is also a property of the familiar circle.
One way to do this is to give a Euclidean definition for the pole-and-polar
relation with respect to a circle, and carry the discussion far enough to find
that this relation satisfies the projective definition for a polarity. A quicker
way is to give a Euclidean proof for the Braikenridge-MacLaurin construc¬
tion (Figure 9.2b). More precisely, we select five points on a circle and prove
that the unique conic that can be drawn through these points coincides with
the circle. For convenience we shall take the five points A, P, B, Q, C
102
THE CIRCLE IS A CONIC 103
Figure 11.1a
By Euclid III.21 and 22, the locus of X is the circle APO. By the Braikenridge-
MacLaurin construction, the locus of X is the conic APBQC. Hence the
conic coincides with the circle.
EXERCISES
The time has come for us to investigate the connection between projective
space, as determined by our axioms, and affine space, that is, the ordinary
space of elementary solid geometry, in which two coplanar lines, or a line
and a plane, or two planes, are said to be parallel if they do not meet. Instead
104 PARALLELISM
these may be any two lines that meet; an axial pencil is determined by any two
of its planes, and these may be any two planes that meet; finally, a bundle
(like a flat pencil) is determined by any two of its lines.
EXERCISE
A range, a flat pencil, and an axial pencil are three kinds of one-dimensional
form. Which two are space-duals of each other? Which one is its own dual
(that is, which one is “self-dual”)?
11.3 How Two Coplanar Lines Determine a Flat Pencil and a Bundle
If (in ordinary space) we are given a point P, and two coplanar lines a and b
whose point of intersection O is inconveniently far away, how can we construct
the line through P of the pencil or bundle determined by a and b ? If O were
available we could simply draw OP, but can we still locate this line without
using O ? If P is not in the plane ab, we merely have to draw the planes Pa and
Pb; these meet in a line p through P, which is the desired line of the bundle
(see Figure 11.3a). In a single symbol, the member through P (outside the
plane ab) is the line
p — Pa - Pb.
On the other hand, if P is in the plane ab, we can use an auxiliary point Q
outside the plane, locate the member q through Q (which is the line OQ), and
consider (as in Figure 11.3b) the line of intersection of the planes ab and Pq.
In other words, the line through P (of the bundle or pencil) is now
p — ab • Pq where q — Qa • Qb.
This construction owes its importance to the fact that it remains valid when a
and b are parallel, so that O does not exist! The lines a, b, q,p, which originally
passed through O, are now all parallel.
A practical model for this new situation is easily made by dividing a
rectangular card into four unequal strips (of widths roughly proportional to
q b a q p
Figure 11.3c
EXERCISE
Two lines parallel to the same line are parallel to each other. Does this
remain true
(i) when the word “lines” is replaced by “planes,”
(ii) when the word “line” is replaced by “plane,”
(iii) when both substitutions are made simultaneously?
If we are given a point P, and two planes a and /3 whose line of intersection
is far away, how can we construct the member through P of the axial pencil
determined by a and /?? This can be done by means of two applications of
THE AXIAL PENCIL DETERMINED BY 2 PLANES 107
Figure 11.4a
EXERCISE
Can two lines be parallel to the same plane without being coplanar?
We have seen that a bundle can be derived from two of its lines, and an
axial pencil from two of its planes, by constructions that remain valid when
the two lines or planes are parallel.
108 PARALLELISM
Since an ordinary bundle consists of all the lines and planes through a
point, and an ordinary axial pencil consists of all the planes through a line,
any simple statement about points and lines can be “translated” into a
corresponding statement about bundles and axial pencils. For instance, the
statement
Any two distinct points lie on a line
becomes:
The common planes of any two distinct bundles form an axial pencil.
It is significant that the latter statement remains true when one of the
bundles is replaced by a bundle of parallels, and again when both are replaced
by bundles of parallels. In fact, the common planes of an ordinary bundle and
a bundle of parallels form the ordinary axial pencil whose axis is the common
line of the two bundles. (For instance, the bundle of lines and planes through
any point O shares with the bundle of vertical lines and planes the vertical
line through O and all the planes through this line.) Again, the common
planes of two bundles of parallels form a pencil of parallel planes. (For
instance, the bundle whose lines are horizontal in the north-south direction
and the bundle whose lines are horizontal in the east-west direction have in
common all the horizontal planes.)
EXERCISE
Translate the following statement into the language of pencils and bundles:
If two distinct lines have a common point they lie in a plane.
ideal points. On the other hand, since a bundle of parallels contains ordinary
axial pencils as well as pencils of parallel planes, an ideal point lies on some
ordinary lines as well as on some ideal lines. Since any ordinary line belongs to
just one bundle of parallels (consisting of all the lines and planes parallel to it),
it contains just one ideal point, which we call its point at infinity. Thus we
regard any two parallel lines as meeting in an ideal point: their common
point at infinity. Since any plane belongs to just one pencil of parallel planes
(consisting of all the planes parallel to it), it contains just one ideal line, which
we call its line at infinity. Thus we regard any two parallel planes as meeting in
an ideal line: their common line at infinity. In a given plane, each point on
the line at infinity is the “center”of a pencil of parallel lines.
Since any two pencils of parallel planes belong to a bundle of parallels,
Any two ideal lines meet in an ideal point.
It follows that, if a and b are any two ideal lines, every other ideal line
meets both a and b. This state of affairs resembles what happens in a plane.
For, if a and b are two ordinary intersecting lines, every point in the plane ab
lies on a line that meets both a and b. Accordingly, it is appropriate to regard
the set of all ideal points and ideal lines as forming an ideal plane: the plane
at infinity. This makes it possible to assert that any two intersecting (or
parallel) lines determine a plane through both of them. If one of the lines is
ordinary this is an ordinary plane; if both are ideal it is the plane at infinity.
Since each point (or line) at infinity is joined to an ordinary point O by an
ordinary line (or plane), the points and lines of the projective plane may
simply be regarded as a “new language” for the lines and planes (respectively)
through O. In other words,
The projective plane is faithfully represented by a bundle.
Historically, points at infinity, lines at infinity, and the plane at infinity
were first thought of by Kepler, Desargues, and Poncelet, respectively.
EXERCISE
Examine all the Axioms 2.11-2.18 for projective space, verifying that each
is satisfied in our “extended” space, that is, in the ordinary affine space plus
the plane at infinity with all its points and lines.
EXERCISE
Let P and Q be two distinct points in Euclidean space. What is the locus of
the point of intersection of a variable line through P and the perpendicular
plane through Q ?
* Melvin Hausner, “The Center of Mass and Affine Geometry,” Am. Math. Monthly,
69 (1962), p. 730.
CHAPTER TWELVE
Coordinates
12.2 Definitions
Setting aside all ideas of measurement, let us now build up the analytic
geometry of the projective plane in the manner proposed by Hardy, that is, as
consisting entirely of definitions and theorems, beginning with the definitions
of point, line, and incidence.
A point is the set of all triads equivalent to a given triad (xx, x2, x3). In
other words, a point is an ordered set of three numbers (xx, x2, x3), not all
zero, with the understanding that (2xx, Xx2, 2x3) is the same point for any
nonzero X. For instance, (2, 3, 6) is a point, and (——1) is another
way of writing the same point.
A line is the set of all triads equivalent to a given triad [Xx, X2, X3]. In
HOMOGENEOUS LINEAR EQUATIONS 113
other words, a line is defined in the same manner as a point, but with square
brackets instead of ordinary parentheses, and with capital letters to represent
the three numbers. Thus [3, 2, -2] is a line, and [-1, -f, f] is the same line.
(We shall find that the point (xls x2, x3) and the line [x1; x2, x3] (with the
same x s) are related by a polarity, but the apparently special role of this
polarity is a notational accident.)
The point (x) and line [X], meaning (xl5 x2, x3) and [Xlt X2, X3], are said to
be incident (the point lying on the line and the line passing through the point)
if and only if
{xJT} = 0
in the notation of (12.11). For instance, (2, 3, 6) lies on [3, 2, —2], It follows
that any discussion can be dualized by interchanging small and capital letters,
round and square brackets.
The three numbers x{ are called the coordinates (or “homogeneous
coordinates,” or “projective coordinates”) of the point (x). The three numbers
Xi are called the coordinates (or “line coordinates,” or “envelope coordi¬
nates,” or “tangential coordinates”) of the line [X].
If (x) is a variable point on a fixed line [X], we call {Tx} = 0 the equation
of the line [X], because it is a characteristic property of points on the line.
For instance, the line [3, 2, —2] has the equation
Dually, if [X] is a variable line through a fixed point (x), we call {x2f} = 0
(which is the same as {Tx} = 0) the equation of the point (x), because it is a
characteristic property of lines through the point. For instance, the point
(2, 3, 6) has the equation
2Xx + 3*2 + 6X3 = 0,
and the point (1, 0, 0) has the equation Xx — 0. Thus the coordinates of a
line or point are the coefficients in its equation (with zero for any missing
term).
The three points (1, 0, 0), (0, 1, 0), (0, 0, 1), or Xt — 0 (/ = 1, 2, 3), and
the three lines [1,0, 0], [0, 1, 0], [0, 0, 1], or x, = 0, are evidently the vertices
and sides of a triangle. We call this the triangle of reference (see Figure 12.2a).
The point (1, 1, 1) and line [1, 1, 1] are called the unit point and unit line. We
shall find, in Section 12.4, that there is nothing geometrically special about
this triangle and point and line, except that the point does not lie on a side,
the line does not pass through a vertex, and the point is the trilinear pole of
the line (see Section 3.4).
By eliminating Xx, X2> X3 from the equations
Figure 12.2 a
of three given points (x), (y), (z), we find the necessary and sufficient condition
(12.21) yi y2 y3 = o
If (y) and (z) are distinct points, X # 0. Hence the general point collinear
with (y) and (z) is {Juy1 + vzx, fiy2 + vz2, fxyz + vz3) or, briefly,
(,uy + vz)
where /j, and v are not both zero.
When v = 0, this is the point (y) itself. For any other position, since (vz) is
the same point as (z), we can allow the coordinates of (z) to absorb the v, and
the point collinear with (y) and (z) is simply
(my + z).
If we are concerned with only one such point, we may allow the ju to be
absorbed too; thus three distinct collinear points may be expressed as (y), (z),
LINEAR DEPENDENCE 115
Xi Xo X*
(12.22) Y1 Y3 0;
Z3
the general line concurrent with [ 7] and [Z] is [y Y + vZ]; and any particular
line concurrent with [ Y] and [Z], but distinct from them, may be expressed as
[Y + Z].
EXERCISES
1. Where does the unit line [1, 1, 1] meet the sides of the triangle of reference?
2. Copy Figure 12.2a (without the coordinate symbols) and add the lines
[0, 1, 1], [—1, 0, 1], [1, 1, 0]. Are these lines concurrent?
3. What line joins the points (1, 1, 1) and (1, —1, 0)? Where does it meet
[1,0, 0]?
4. The line joining (1, 0, 0) to (xx, x2, x3) is [0, x3, — x2]. Where does it
meet [1, 0, 0] ?
({Xz}y - {Zy}z).
7. Obtain coordinates for the various points and lines in Figure 3.4a, begin¬
ning with
A = (1,0,0), B = (0,1,0), C = (0,0,1),
Deduce the condition xxZx = x2X2 = x3X3 for the point (x) and line [Z]
to be trilinear pole and polar with respect to the triangle of reference.
8. Where is the harmonic conjugate of (xl5 x2, 0) with respect to (1, 0, 0) and
(0,1,0)?
116 COORDINATES
To show that this analytic geometry provides a model for the synthetic
geometry developed in earlier chapters, we must verify that Axioms 2.11,2.12,
2.13, 3.11, 2.17, 2.32, and 2.18 (page 95) are all satisfied.
The first four are easy. The point (1, 0, 0) and line [1, 0, 0] are certainly not
incident. A line [X] with X^Xa ^ 0 is incident with three points such as
" 72 73 73 71 7i 72 '
5
•^2 Z3 Z3 Z1 Zi z2 _
Y2 Y3 y, Y1 Y2
Z2 Z3 Z1 z2
To prove Axiom 2.17, we consider a quadrangle PQRS whose first three
vertices (p), (q), (r) satisfy
Pi P2 Pz
(12.31) <h ^2 ?3 ^0.
fi r2 r3
Since the side PS joins (p) to the diagonal point A — QR • PS, we may take A
(on QR, but distinct from Q and R) to be (q + r), and S (on PA, but distinct
from P and A) to be (p +
q + r), meaning
qi + rx q% + r2 q% + r3 Pi P2 Pz
(12.32) fi + Pi r2 + p2 rz + Pz = 2 qi qz qz 7^0.
Pi + qi Pz + q* Pz + qz ri rz
As for Axiom 2.32 (i.e., Desargues’s theorem), let the first triangle PQR
and the center of perspective O be (p)(q){r) and (u). There is no loss of
THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM 117
The point D = QR • Q'R', being collinear with (q) and (r) and also with
(q + u) and {r + «), can only be (q — r). Similarly, E is (r — p), and F is
(p — q)- These points D, E, F are collinear since
q1 ~ ri qz~ r2 q3 - r3
ri — Pi rz— p3 r3 — p3 = o
Pi ~ qi Pz q% Pz — qz
or, more simply, since
in [Z], [Y + Z].
From the information that P and p are incident in these three cases, can we
deduce that, when P is (juy + z),p is [pY + Z] with the same pi Yes! Since
showing that the line [pY + Z] is indeed incident with the point (juy + z).
Repeated application of this result shows that the relation
holds not only for an elementary correspondence but for any projectivity
from a range to a pencil; and of course we have also
This is the algebraic version of the Fundamental Theorem 4.12, from which
Axiom 2.18 can be deduced as a special case.
EXERCISES
2. Where is the harmonic conjugate of (yy + z) with respect to (y) and (z)?
Dualize this result.
5. Give an equation (or equations) for the general projectivity on the line
[0, 0, 1].
6. Under what circumstances will the projectivity described in Exercise 4 or 5
be:
(i) an involution, (ii) parabolic?
7. When four distinct collinear points are expressed in the form
00> 00> (y + z), (juy + z),
the number p is called the cross ratio of the four points. There is an analogous
definition for the cross ratio of four concurrent lines. Two such tetrads are
projectively related if and only if they have the same cross ratio.
8. For two points (y), (z) and two lines [ F], [Z], the expression
{yr}{zz}
{yZ}{zT}
CROSS RATIO 119
is equal to the cross ratio of the two given points with the points in which
their join meets the two lines.
9. The cross ratio of (a, 1, 0), (b, 1, 0), (c, 1, 0), (d, 1, 0) is
(a — c)(b — d)
(a — d)(b - c)
We have seen that the condition (12.21) makes the points (x), (y), (z)
collinear; conversely (12.31) makes (p), (<q), (r) noncollinear, so that they
form a triangle. This triangle enables us to describe the position of any point
by means of barycentric coordinates A, fx, v, which are the coefficients in the
expression (Xp + [xq -f vr). This is an obvious generalization of the expression
(p + <7 + r) used in the proof of Axiom 2.17 in Section 12.3. Points on a side
of the triangle can be included by allowing X/xv = 0, and when fx = v = 0
we have the point (p) itself.
When (p)(q)(r) and {p + ? + r) are the triangle of reference and unit point,
(Xp + p,q + vr) is (X, ju, v), and the barycentric coordinates are the same as
the ordinary coordinates.
The correspondence (x) ->■ (x'), where
(12.41)
transforms (X, fx, v) into the point (Xp -(- [xq + vr) which has these same
barycentric coordinates referred to (p)(q)(r) instead of (1, 0, 0)(0, 1, 0)(0, 0, 1).
Since we are assuming (12.31), so that the equations (12.41) can be solved
for the x’s in terms of the x,5s, this is a point-to-point correspondence as
described at the beginning of Section 6.1. Since the equation {X x } = 0
[see (12.11)] is equivalent to
it is a collineation. Since it transforms (0, [x, v) into (jxq + vr), the collineation
is projective (see 6.11). Since it transforms the quadrangle
by a suitable choice of the p's and ^’s and r’s, it is the general projective
collineation (see 6.13).
This collineation, which shifts the points (x) to new positions (*'), is the
active or alibi aspect of the linear homogeneous transformation (12.41).
There is also a passive or alias aspect: a coordinate transformation that gives
a new name to each point. In fact, we may regard {p){q)(r) as a new triangle of
reference, with respect to which the point that we have been calling (*') has
coordinates
Oi, *2, *3),
whereas its coordinates with respect to the original triangle are, of course,
(x l9 X 2, X 3).
(Reference 19, p. 187; Reference 17, pp. 68, 85). The preservation of incidence
is verified as follows:
Since our coordinates are homogeneous, there are many occasions when
INVARIANT POINTS OF A COLLINEATION 121
we can omit the p and a in (12.43), that is, set p = <7 = 1. However, it is
important to retain them when we are looking for invariant points or invariant
lines. The invariant points are naturally given by x\ — x, or
Any root p of this characteristic equation makes the three equations for the
x’s consistent, and then we can solve any two of them to obtain the coordinates
of an invariant point.
For instance, the collineation
has the characteristic equation (p — l)3 = 0. If a3 and a3 are not both zero,
the triple root p = 1 yields the range of invariant points (xx, x2, 0); there are
no others. By 6.24 and 6.26, this collineation is an elation with axis [0, 0, 1].
Since the equation a2x\ — axx 2 = 0 implies a2x3 — a3x2 = 0, there is an
invariant line (other than [0, 0, 1]) through the point (a1; a2, 0). Hence this
point is the center of the elation.
Comparing the two parts of (12.43), we see that the expression for the
homology (12.45) as a line-to-line transformation is
EXERCISES
12.5 Polarities
Since the product of two correlations (for example, a polarity and another
projective correlation) is a collineation, any given projective correlation can
be exhibited as the product of an arbitrary polarity and a suitable projective
collineation. The most convenient polarity for this purpose is the one that
transforms each point (or line) into the line (or point) that has the same
coordinates. (This correlation is obviously projective, and of period 2.)
Combining the general projective collineation (12.43) with the polarity that
interchanges X\ and x\, we obtain the general projective correlation in the
form
P i ^ilX i T" Ci2X2 d~“ G'3-U — ^ ^iixj 0*=1,2, 3),
(12.51)
- cljX i -)- c2jx 2 T~ c3jX 3 = 2 ci]X i 0= 1,2, 3),
where again the coefficients satisfy (12.44). Incidences are dualized in the
proper manner for a correlation, since
with the same alp for all i and j, so that, since the cu are not all zero,
_ a _ (a? /cr\2 . a
ca Cji ( I cij, I l -1, — zti-
p \p/ \p/ p
The lower sign is inadmissible, as that would make cH = — c{j and
where ci3- = cH and det (ci3) = A =£ 0. These equations give us the polar [X]
of a given point (x). Solving them, we obtain the pole (x) of a given line [A]
in the form
Axi = 'ZCiiXi (i = l, 2, 3),
(12.53) ci3-Xiy3- = 0,
(xy) = 0.
Letting (x) vary, we see that this is the equation of the polar of (y). Dually, the
condition for lines [X] and [ F] to be conjugate, or the equation of the pole of
[F], is
(12.54) [XY] = 0,
where [XY] = 22 CijXl Y3.
As a particular case of (xjy) = 0, the condition for (0, 1, 0) and (0, 0, 1) to
be conjugate is c23 = 0. Thus the triangle of reference is self-polar if and
only if
C23 = C31 = C12 = 0-
By choosing any self-polar triangle as triangle of reference, we reduce a given
polarity to its canonical form
Xi = CjjX; (^11^22^33 # 0)
124 COORDINATES
EXERCISES
2. Prove 7.13, using the polarity (12.52) and the line [0, 0, 1].
3. Prove 7.61 (Hesse’s theorem), using the quadrilateral [1, ±1, ±1], whose
pairs of opposite vertices are
5. Any two perspective triangles are polar triangles for some polarity.
(yy) = p\zz):
either (yy) and (zz) are both zero or their product is a nonzero square.
(In real geometry this means that (yy) and (zz) have the same sign. But in
complex geometry, since every complex number is a square, all non¬
self-conjugate points are mutually accessible.)
12.6 Conics
The condition for a point (x) to be self-conjugate for the polarity (12.52) is
(jo:) = , or
0
We can now clarify the statement (in Section 8.1) that in some geometries
every polarity is hyperbolic, whereas other geometries admit elliptic polarities
too. The polarity (12.52) is hyperbolic or elliptic according as the equation
(xx) = 0 does or does not have a solution (other than x1 — x2 = x3 = 0).
The distinction depends on the coordinate field. If this is the field of complex
numbers, every such equation can be solved; for example, the equation
*12 + X2 + *32 = 0
Since the condition for the conic (xx) = 0 to pass through (1, 0, 0) is
cn = 0, the most general conic circumscribing the triangle of reference is
(12.63) *1* ± *2 ± x3 =
126 COORDINATES
EXERCISES
6 . Given a conic (xx) = 0 and an exterior point (y) (see Section 8.1), describe,
both algebraically and geometrically, the locus of a variable point (x) such
that the line (x)(y) is self-conjugate. Dualize this result.
7. If the four tangents through two exterior points are all distinct, their
points of contact and the two exterior points all lie on a conic.
8. Given a conic (xx) = 0, let (z) be any exterior point. If (zz) does not
happen to be a square, divide all the coefficients ctj in (xx) by (zz). We now
have the same conic expressed in such a way that (zz) is a square (namely,
1). When the equation (xx) = 0 has been thus normalized, any point (y)
not on the conic is exterior or interior according as (yy) is or is not a square.
(In real geometry this means, according as (yy) is positive or negative. In
complex geometry we know already that there are no interior points be¬
cause there are no elliptic involutions.) Illustrate this criterion by applying
it to the conic (12.61).
9. In real geometry all interior points of a conic are mutually accessible, but
in rational geometry the number of classes of mutually accessible points is
infinite.
In PG(2, q), the number of coordinate symbols (xx, x2, x3), with q possible
values for each xi? is qz. From this number we subtract 1, since the symbol
(0, 0, 0) has no geometric meaning. Moreover, each point (x) is the same as
(Ax) for q values of A, namely all the nonzero elements of the field. In this
way we see again that the number of points in the plane is
= q*+q + l.
q — 1
For each point (x) there is, of course, a corresponding line [x]; so the number
of lines is the same.
When q is an odd prime (and not the square or higher power of such a
prime), the elements of the field are simply the residue-classes modulo q.
For instance, when q = 5, they may be denoted by the familiar symbols
0, 1,2, 3, 4,
with the usual rules for addition and multiplication except that
l+4 = 2 + 3 = 0, 2 + 4 — 3 + 3 —- 1,
3 + 4 = 2, 4 + 4 = 3,
2-3 = 4-4= 1, 3-4 = 2,
2-4 = 3, 3-3 = 4.
These rules are quite natural, provided we interpret the symbols as follows:
0 means the set of all multiples of 5, in other words, all integers whose final
digit is 0 or 5; 1 means the residue-class that includes all the positive integers
whose final digit is 1 or 6, and so on. In a more familiar notation, such equa¬
tions as
3 + 4 = 3- 4 = 2
are “congruences”
3 + 4 = 3- 4 = 2 (mod 5).
128 COORDINATES
Some rather subtle considerations, involving the field with 125 elements,
provide a systematic method for assigning coordinates to the 31 points Pr
and 31 lines ls of Section 10.2. The results are as follows
/'-V
©
p
/(> = [1,0, 0],
II
Pi = (0,1, 0), 4 = [0, i, 0],
A = (1, 0, 0), 4 = [4, 0, 1],
A = (0, 1, 1), 4 = [i,i,0],
A = 0, 1,0), 4 - [4, 1, 1],
A = (4, 1, 1), 4 = [1,3, 2],
A = ( 1,2, 1), 4 = [0, 2, 1],
A = (1, 0, 2), 4 = [1,0, i],
A = (0, 1, 4), 4 [1,4, 0],
=
bo
As = (2,1, 0), t—-
II
CO
4s = [2, 1, 0],
II
00
o'
cT
Ao = (i,o, l).
II
EXERCISES
6. What condition must the coordinate field satisfy if there exists a configura¬
tion 83 (in the notation of Section 3.2) consisting of points A, B, C, D, E,
F, G, H with the following triads collinear:
Deduce F = (1, 1, co -f- 1), G — (1, co + 1, co). Obtain an equation for a>
from the collinearity of FGA.]
In Section 11.2 we saw how to derive affine space from projective space by
specializing one plane, calling it “the plane at infinity,” and then omitting it.
The synthetic treatment required three dimensions, but the analytic treatment
can be carried out just as easily in two dimensions. Accordingly, let us con¬
sider the affine plane, that is, the ordinary plane of elementary geometry, in
which two lines are said to be parallel if they do not meet. We regard this as
part of the projective plane, namely, the projective plane minus one line:
“the line at infinity.” Two lines are said to be parallel if they meet on this
special line. We soon see that parallelism, so defined, has all its familiar
properties. The apparent inconsistency, of saying that parallel lines meet and
130 COORDINATES
yet do not meet, is resolved by regarding the affine plane as being derived from
the projective plane by omitting the special line (and all its points) while
retaining the consequent concept of parallelism. This modification of pro¬
jective geometry is called affine geometry.
Figure 12.8a
Oi, 1),
which can be shortened to (x1? x2). The two numbers xx and x2 are called the
affine coordinates of the point. In other words, if x3 =£ 0, the point (xx, x2, x3)
of the projective plane can be regarded as the point (xjx3, x2/x3) of the
affine plane; and the equation of any locus can be made into the corresponding
equation in affine coordinates by setting x3 = 1. In particular, the line [X]
has the equation
Xlx\ + ^2x2 + = 0,
and a pencil of parallel lines is obtained by fixing X1 and X2 (or, more pre¬
cisely, the ratio X1:X2) while allowing X3 to take various values.
Let us see what has happened to the triangle of reference. Its first two sides
have become the coordinate axes, namely the x2-axis x^ = 0 (along which x2
varies) and the xraxis x2 = 0 (along which xx varies). The third side, x3 = 0,
is the line at infinity. The first two vertices are the points at infinity on the axes:
(1, 0, 0) on the xraxis and (0, 1, 0) on the x2-axis. The third vertex is the
origin (0, 0), where the two axes meet. (See Figure 12.8a.)
The homology (12.45) becomes a transformation of affine coordinates
In either case [since both (12.47) and (12.48) involve X\ = X1 and X'2 = X2],
every line is transformed into a parallel line; in other words, directions are
preserved. The homology leaves the origin invariant and multiplies the
coordinates of every point by p; we call this a central dilatation. The elation,
leaving no (proper) point invariant, is a translation (or “parallel displace¬
ment”). These two affine transformations enable us to define relative dis¬
tances along one line, or along parallel lines (Reference 7, pp. 117-125); but
affine geometry provides no comparison for distances in different directions.
A conic is called a hyperbola, a parabola, or an ellipse, according as the line
at infinity is a secant, a tangent, or a nonsecant. (This agrees with the classical
definitions, since a hyperbola “goes off to infinity” in two directions, a
parabola in one direction, and an ellipse not at all.) The pole of the line at
infinity is called the center of the conic. In the case of a hyperbola, this is an
exterior point (see Section 8.1), and the two tangents that can be drawn from
it are the asymptotes, whose points of contact are at infinity. Thus
EXERCISES
Section 1.2
2. So that just one “ray” (from the lamp to some point on the rim) is parallel
to the wall.
3. (i) An ordinary point and a point at infinity are joined by just one line,
(ii) Each ordinary line contains just one point at infinity.
Section 1.3
Section 1.4
(2) = in(n ~
1)
Section 1.5
1. So that distinct points X will yield distinct lines x.
Section 1.6
1. In the notation of Figure 1.6e, ABC 7^ SRC 77 BAC.
p_ x
2. In the notation of Figure 3.3a, abc 77 src 77 bac.
3. Use the method of Figure 1.6b, taking A", B", C" to be three collinear
points on a, b, c, respectively.
4. Proceed as in Figure 1.6d with the names of the points B and D inter¬
changed.
Section 2.1
1. (i) Axioms 2.11 and 2.12 yield one point and three others.
(ii) If this statement were not true, all the points that exist would lie on a.
By Axiom 2.12, every line would contain two (in fact, three) of these
points. By Axiom 2.13, every line would coincide with a, that is, a
would be the only line, contradicting Axiom 2.11.
(iii) Let P and / be the point and line described in Axiom 2.11. If A is not
on /, / fulfills our requirement. If A is on /, Axiom 2.12 yields another
point B on /. By Axiom 2.13, a line is equally well determined by any
distinct two of its points. The line / = AB, not containing P, is
distinct from BP. Therefore BP is a line not passing through A.
(iv) Consider the point A. By Axiom 2.12, the line whose existence is
proved in (iii) contains three distinct points, each of which (by Axiom
2.13) can be joined to A by a line. The three lines so obtained are
distinct; for, if two of them, AB and AC, were coincident, the same
line could be called BC, contradicting the fact that BC does not pass
through A.
2. In the notation of Figure 5.1a,
Section 2.2
1. (i) By 2.24, there exists a quadrangle PQRS having 6 distinct sides
p = PQ, q ~ PS, r = RS, s = QR, u = QS, w = PR.
The first 4 of these 6 lines form a quadrilateral pqrs having 6 distinct
vertices
p = p-q> Q= P'S, R = r- s, S — q • r, U = q ■ s, W = p- r
[Reference 8, pp. 231-232],
ANSWERS TO EXERCISES 135
Section 2.3
1. We have O = PP' ■ QQ' \ R' may be anywhere on the line OR.
Section 2.4
1. If AP, BQ, CR are concurrent, as in Figure 2.4a, we have immediately
Q(ABC, DEF). Conversely, if Q(ABC, DEE) while the lines AP, BQ, CR
are not known to be concurrent, define S = AP ■ BQ, C' = AB ■ RS.
The quadrangle PQRS yields Q(ABC', DEF). By Theorem 2.14, C' = C.
Therefore CR passes through S.
Section 2.5
1. H(PQ, FG), H(RS, CG).
2. As in Figure 1.6e.
3. Of course, the concept of a point “inside” a triangle does not belong to
projective geometry. But what happens in the Euclidean plane is that the
line AB separates R from the other three vertices of the quadrangle.
4. Since F coincides with C, the four points reduce to three. Each of the three
is its own harmonic conjugate with respect to the other two!
Section 3.1
2. Certain pairs of triangles are perspective from points P, Q, R, S, and con¬
sequently also from lines p, q, r, s. For instance, ABC and SRQ are per¬
spective from P.
Section 3.2
4. No, not in the projective geometry that we have defined. A 73 would
consist of a quadrangle with collinear diagonal points, as in Exercise 3 of
Section 2.1.
Section 3.3
1. We construct, in turn, A2 = BC ■ AS, B2 = CA• BS, Cx — AB • A2B2,
P = AS • CCX, Q = BS • CCX, R = CS • AQ. (Compare Exercise 2 of
Section 3.1.)
2. The quadrangle BCB1C1 tells us that CCX meets AAX in the harmonic
conjugate of R (with respect to A and Ax), which is Q. Similarly, the quad¬
rangle CAC1A1 tells us that CCX meets BBX in the harmonic conjugate of
R, which is P. Finally, the quadrangle ABAXBX tells us that Q (on AAX) and
P (on BBX) are harmonic conjugates with respect to C and Cx.
Section 3.4
2. S.
Section 3.5
1. Yes, M is the harmonic conjugate of B with respect to A and C.
2. Yes, since H{B'M, A'C'), H{C'M, B'D'),_
3. The points of the sequence are evenly spaced along the line (so that the
segments AB, BC, . . . , are all congruent).
Section 4.1
Section 4.2
1. Any point K of the harmonic net R(ABC) (or of the harmonic sequence
ABC . . .) is derived from ABC by a finite sequence of harmonic construc¬
tions, each of which is carried over by the projectivity ABC a A'B'C'.
Hence K is transformed into a corresponding point K' of the harmonic net
R(A'B'C') (or of the harmonic sequence A’B’C’. . .).
are collinear, since H(7?S', CC2), H(/?i?, PD), and RSC a RBP.
4. Use 4.21.
Section 4.3
Every projectivity relating pencils through two distinct points determines
another special point, the “center,” which lies on the join of the cross¬
intersections of any two pairs of corresponding lines. If aa’e is a triangle,
the center of the projectivity ae0e a a’ee’ is the point e0 ■ e'.
Section 4.4
1. Ciy by Cy 02 ^2 C2 fifg 63 Cg
A3 Ay A% A2 A3 Ay Ay A2 A3
By B.} B2 B3 B2 By B2 By B^
C2 C3 C2 Cy Cy Cy C3 C3 C3
4. If the six sides of a plane hexagon pass alternately through two points, the
three diagonals are concurrent. One such hexagon is axb2c1a2b1c2.
5. No. The hexagon ABPCSA1 is very special, as APS 77 AXBC and APS 7:
AXCB.
6. Suppose A1B1C2 is inscribed in A2B2C3, as in Figure 4.4b. Any point Cx on
A1B1 determines two further points
7. 8 = A, 0 = B, 1 = C, 2 = A', 3 = B', 4 = C\ 5 = L, 6 = M, 7 = N.
This notation has the advantage that the incidences are maintained when
we replace each number x by either 2x or x + 3 and reduce modulo 9.
Applying the former transformation to the given triads of collinear points,
we obtain the whole set of nine triads:
Section 5.1
3. The line joining the centers of the two perspectivities would inevitably
yield an invariant point (such as Fin Figure 5.1a, or C in Figure 5.1b).
Section 5.2
Section 5.3
1. This is merely 5.34 in a more symmetrical notation. The remarks about
Desargues at the beginning of Section 5.3 suggest an analogous theorem
concerning six numbers a, b, c, d, e,f (which we may think of as distances
of the points from an arbitrary “origin”):
2. The product leaves both M and N invariant, and transforms A into A'.
AA'A" a A'A"A'",
where the three points on either side are all distinct. (Conceivably A'"
coincides with A, and then the second involution, like the first, is expressed
in terms of one of its invariant points.)
Section 5.4
1. The given statement says that C and D are the invariant points of an
involution that interchanges A and B.
3. The involution (MM)(NN) has the effect AB’MN a BA'MN, which shows
that MN is a pair of the involution (AA')(BB').
6. The hint shows that the projectivity X a X' has only one invariant point,
namely B.
140 ANSWERS TO EXERCISES
Section 6.1
(i) This is a collineation of period 2, transforming the side PQ into itself
according to the hyperbolic involution (PQ){UU), where U = PQ • RS.
On the opposite side RS, every point is invariant.
(ii) This is a collineation of period 3, transforming the trilinear polar of S
into itself according to the projectivity DEF a EFD.
(iii) This is a collineation of period 4, leaving invariant the point PR • QS
and the line (£>/? • PS){PQ • RS).
Section 6.2
1. The center is PP' • QQ' and the axis joins D to PQ • P'Q'.
4. Clearly, each point on the axis o is invariant. If any other point A were
invariant too, the first elation would take A to some different point A', and
the second would take A' back to A: the two elations would be [o; A A']
and [o; A'-+A], whose product is the identity. Apart from this trivial
case, the product can only be an elation (not a homology). In fact,
[o-A-+B][o-B->C)= [o-A^C].
Alternatively, the dual result can be proved as follows: If two elations have
the same center O, they induce parabolic projectivities on any given line
through O. By 5.21, their product, inducing another parabolic projectivity
on this line, must itself be an elation (if it is not merely the identity).
5. Let A and B be the centers of two such elations, a and ft, which transform
P into P and P&. If A and B are distinct, and P is any point not on the
axis AB, the point AP? ■ BPa is both P^ and P^; therefore xft = ftx. If
A and B coincide, let y be an elation having a different center (but the
same axis), so that a commutes with both y and fty. Then afty = ftyx =
ft<x.y; therefore xft = ftx.
ANSWERS TO EXERCISES 141
Section 6.3
1. An elation. In fact, since the product is evidently a perspective collineation
having the same axis, we merely have to eliminate the possibility of a
homology. For this purpose we apply, to the line joining the two centers,
Exercise 6 of Section 5.4, which tells us that the product of two hyperbolic
involutions with a common invariant point is a parabolic projectivity.
2. In the notation of Figure 6.2a, the elation [o; P -> P'] may be expressed as
the product of harmonic homologies with centers P and Ox, Ox being the
harmonic conjugate of O with respect to P and P'. Knowing, from Exercise
1, that this product is some kind of elation, we merely have to observe that
the first homology leaves P invariant and the second takes P to P'.
3. The identity. In fact, choosing four points P, Q, R, S, on the first two sides
of the given triangle ABC, in such a way that H(BC, PQ) and H(CA, RS),
we find PQRS —*■ PQSR-+ QPSR —> PQRS.
4. Let Ox, 02, ox, o2 be the centers and axes of two harmonic homologies
whose product is a homology with center O and axis o. By Exercise 1,
0l ^ o2 (for, if ox and o2 were the same, the product would be an elation,
not a homology). Dually, Ox ^ 02. Any point P on o, being invariant
for the product, is interchanged with the same point P' by both the
harmonic homologies. Hence Ox and 02 are collinear with P and P .
Since P is arbitrary on o, it follows that o = 0X02. Dually, O — ox% o2.
Both the harmonic homologies induce on o an involution P a P whose
invariant points are Ox and o • ox, also 02 and o • o2. But Ox 7^ 02.
Therefore Ox = o • o2 and 02 = o • ox. Finally, by applying Exercise 3 to
the triangle 0X020, we see that the product of the harmonic homologies
with centers Ox, 02 and axes ox, o2 is the harmonic homology with center
O and axis o.
142 ANSWERS TO EXERCISES
Section 6.4
Each diagonal point of the quadrangle is determined by two opposite sides,
and these are transformed into two opposite vertices of the quadrilateral.
Section 7.1
1. A self-conjugate line contains its pole. By 7.11, it cannot contain any other
self-conjugate point.
2. Y = x ■ b.
4. r • BC and s ■ BC.
Section 7.2
1. Such a correlation induces on g the involution DEF a ABC. Thus we can
apply 7.21 to the triangle SAD (or SBE, or SCF).
2. Since P andp are self-conjugate, 7.11 shows that Q may be any other point
on p (but not on a side of the triangle ABC). For instance, we may take
Section 7.3
1. The pole of the line (p ■ QR)(q • RP) is the point P(q • r) • Q(r • p).
Section 7.4
1. (a ■ p)[A(p • x) ■ P{a ■ x)] • (b ■ p)[B{p ■ x) ■ P(b • *)].
Section 7.5
1. Each vertex is the pole of the opposite side.
Section 7.6
Apply the dual of Hesse’s theorem to the quadrangle RSUV, in which RS = p
is conjugate to UV(through P) and RV — t is conjugate to SU (through T).
Section 7.7
1. Yes. In the notation of Section 6.1, Exercise (iii), the projective collineation
PQRS —>■ QRSP interchanges PQ ■ RS and QR • SP.
2. The projective collineation ABCP —> ABCP' (where neither P nor P' is on
a side of the triangle ABC) is the product of the two polarities
Section 8.1
1. Every point on any line is conjugate to the pole of the line.
4. Yes. If an interior point exists, its polar exists and is neither a tangent nor
a secant.
6. Consider the vertices on the side r of the circumscribed triangle pqr. Apply
8.13 to the conjugate lines (p • q) R and (p • q)(r • PQ).
8. The line CD, joining the midpoint of the chord PQ to the pole of the line
PQ, is a diameter. Its two intersections with the parabola are the center
(at infinity) and S.
Section 8.2
1. By 8.21, QR meets SP in a point conjugate to B. But the only such point on
QR is A.
144 ANSWERS TO EXERCISES
2. Let AP meet the conic again in S. Then the diagonal triangle of the quad¬
rangle PQRS has the desired properties.
Section 8.3
1. If a triangle is circumscribed about a conic, any point conjugate to one
vertex is joined to the other two vertices by conjugate lines.
Let a variable tangent of a conic meet two fixed tangents in X and Y;
then X a Y.
Section 8.4
2. Any line h through R determines C, Cj, c, C2, and finally 5, the harmonic
conjugate of R with respect to C and C2. Accordingly, we construct c by
joining D to P(q • h) • Q(p ■ h). Then S' is the point where h meets either of
the lines
P(c ■ QR), Q(C ■ PR).
3. Dualizing Exercise 2, let p, q, r be the given tangents, P and Q the points of
contact of p and q, and H any point on r. Let PQ meet (p • QH)(q ■ PH) in
C. Then another tangent ^ joins H to either of the points
P ’ c(q ■ r), q • C(p • r).
4. Let P, Q, R be three points on the first conic, and P', Q’, R’ (orp', q, /) the
corresponding points (or tangents) of the second. Let D be the pole of PQ
for the first conic, D' the pole of P'Q' for the second (and d’ the polar of
p’ ■ q). In view of Exercises 2 and 3, we merely have to relate the quadrangle
PQRD by a projective collineation (or correlation) to the quadrangle
P'Q'R' D' (or to the quadrilateral p'q'r'd').
ANSWERS TO EXERCISES 145
Section 8.5
1. Let 5 = DE be the variable line through O. After using the hint, we observe
that, by 8.51 with x = PA and y — QB, the locus of S — x • y is a conic
through P, Q, R.
3. The line joins the points of contact of the remaining tangents from P and Q.
Section 9.1
1. AB,p, q are three tangents; P, Q are the points of contact of the last two.
Each point Z on PQ yields another tangent XY.
2. If EA, AB, BC, CD, DE are the five tangents, the point of contact of the
last lies on the line B(AD • CE).
Section 9.2
1. Dualizing Exercise 2 of Section 9.1, we see that the tangent at P to the conic
PQRST joins P to the point
RS-(TP- QR)(ST • PQ).
2. An arbitrary line through P, say z, meets the conic again where it meets the
line
S[(PQ ■ s)(RS - z) - QR].
3. 45! = 60.
angles shows that the quadrilateral Axy is directly similar to Cy'x', and Pyz
to Qz'y'. Therefore
and
Hence the quadrilateral Rxz is directly similar to Rz'x, and the diagonal
MR of the former is along the same line as the diagonal RN of the latter.
(See also H. G. Forder, Higher Course Geometry, Cambridge University
Press, 1949, p. 13.)
Section 9.3
1. The desired point lies on the line
Section 9.4
2. This follows from 9.41 along with the latter half of 9.42.
3. Let PQR (Figure 9.4a) be the given triangle, and ST any secant of the
former conic that is a tangent of the latter. Let the remaining tangents
from S and T meet in U. By the dual of Exercise 2, U lies on the conic
PQRST.
4. PQRS and PQRT are two quadrangles inscribed in the conic PQRST. By
8.21, their diagonal triangles, ABC and A'B'C', are self-polar. By 9.42, the
six vertices of these two triangles lie on a conic.
Section 9.5
Section 10.1
1. q2 + q + 1; {q2 + 1 ){q2 + q + 1).
2. q\q + 1 )(q2 + q + l)/6.
3. n = q2, q d = q + 1.
Section 10.2
2. r 12 11 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 0
s 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 0
2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 0 1
4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 0 1 2 3
10 11 12 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9
Section 10.3
r 6 5 4 3 2 1 0
1 2 3 4 5 6 0
s 2 3 4 5 6 0 1
4 5 6 0 1 2 3
The diagonal points of the quadrangle P2P4P5P6 are the three points on
Section 10.4
1. 24; 9; 3. If ^4, B, C, D are the four points on a line, the three elliptic
involutions are
(BC)(AD), (CA)(BD), (.AB)(CD).
Section 10.5
1. 4 4s+3- In fac4 if r + 5 = 0, 1, 3, 8, 12, or 18 (mod 31),
5r + (5s + 3) = 5(r + s) + 3 = 3, 8, 18, 12, 1 or 0.
2. 13 • 12 • 9 • 4 = 5616; 13 • 9 - 117.
3- q + 1; q + 2.
Section 10.6
1. Since this collineation has period 3, Figure 7.7b must be modified so that
1"' = / and therefore C = B", C' = B. Choosing A = P10 and / = /2, we
obtain the polarities
(^10^2 ^4 (^19 4 3
) . ), (P19P2 P )(.P 4
26 lo )-
16 • 6 3875 • 16
= 16; = 20; = 3100.
3! 20
4. 234. In PG(2, 3), any 5 points include 3 that are collinear; thus 9.21 holds
vacuously. In Section 9.5 we saw that any 5 points, no 4 collinear, deter¬
mine a conic (possibly degenerate). This result remains significant in
PG(2, 3), but the conic is necessarily degenerate.
5. Yes. The polarity Pr^ lr determines the conic P0P7PaPn which, regarded
as a quadrangle, has the diagonal triangle P4P10P12. The sides of this tri¬
angle (namely, /4, lw, l12) are nonsecants: the points on them are just all
the points in the plane except those that form the conic.
7. Let Q be accessible from P; that is, let H(CCls PQ), where CQ is a suitable
pair of conjugate points. The harmonic homology with center C and axis
the polar c (through C\) interchanges P and Q while transforming the conic
into itself (by Exercise 4 of Section 8.2). Since any tangent through P or Q
is transformed into a tangent through Q or P, two mutually accessible
points are always of the same type: both on the conic, or both exterior, or
both interior. By 8.11, any two points on the conic are mutually accessible.
By Exercise 1 of Section 8.1, any two exterior points on a tangent are
mutually accessible. Let P and Q be any two exterior points whose join is
not a tangent, and let either of the tangents from P meet either of the tan¬
gents from Q in R. Since R is accessible from both P and Q, Exercise 6
shows thatP and Q are accessible from each other. Thus the three answers
are:
(i) all the points on the conic,
(ii) all the exterior points,
(iii) a set of interior points (possibly all, as we shall see in Section 12.6,
Exercise 9, and Section 12.7, Exercise 7).
8. (i) On a given line through P, there are (q + l)/2 points accessible from P:
one for each pair of conjugate points on the line. (Two such pairs could
not both yield the same point Q ; for then the involution of pairs of
conjugate points could be described as (PP)(QQ), whereas we know
that it is elliptic.)
(ii) On each of the q -f- 1 lines through P, there are (q + l)/2 points
accessible from P, namely P itself and (q — l)/2 others. Hence the
total number of points accessible from P is
1 + {q + m - 1 )/2 = (.q2 + 1)12.
9. We use reductio ad absurdum. Suppose, if possible, that an elliptic polarity
exists. By Exercise 6, accessibility is an “equivalence relation” (G. Birkholf
and S. MacLane, A Survey of Modern Algebra, 2nd ed., Macmillan, New
York, 1953, pp. 155-156). Therefore the q2 + q + 1 points in PG{2, q) can
be distributed into a certain number of classes, each consisting of (q2 + l)/2
mutually accessible points. Dividing q2 + q + 1 by (q2 + l)/2 (and
remembering that q is an odd number, greater than 1), we obtain the
quotient 2 and a remainder q, which is absurd.
Section 11.1
1. X coincides with P.
2. See Exercise 5 of Section 9.2.
Section 11.2
The range and the axial pencil; the flat pencil.
150 ANSWERS TO EXERCISES
Section 11.3
(i) No. (ii) No. (iii) Yes.
Section 11.4
Yes.
Section 11.5
If two axial pencils belong to a bundle, they have a common plane.
Section 11.6
(2.14) If AB and CD are either intersecting or parallel, then AC and BD are
either intersecting or parallel.
(2.16) If two planes are parallel, their common points form a line at infinity.
Section 11.7
The sphere on PQ as diameter.
Section 12.1
When the triad (x1; x2, x3) is interpreted as a point in affine space, represented
by Cartesian coordinates, the equivalent triads all lie on a line through the
origin, and the equation {Xx} = 0 represents a plane through the origin.
When we pass from affine space to the projective plane, it is thus natural
to use xl5 x2, x3 as homogeneous coordinates for a point, and to regard
{Xx} = 0 as the equation for a line.
Section 12.2
1. (0, 1,-1), (-1,0, 1), (1, —1, 0).
2. Yes, they all pass through (1, —1, 1).
3. [1,1,-2]; (0,2,1).
Section 12.3
1. In the notation of Figure 2.5a, we may take
A = (y\ B = (z), C = (y + z), R = (*), Q = (x + y).
Then S, on both BQ and CR, must be (x + y + z); P, on both BR and
AS, must be (x + z); and F, on both AB and PQ, must be (y — z).
2. In Exercise 1, write py for y. The point (jxy — z) is, of course, the same as
(~PY + z). The harmonic conjugate of [juY + Z\ with respect to [F] and
[Z] is [—pY + Z].
Since py' + z' = ju(a.y + yz) + fiy + dz = (a(i + (i)y + (y/u + S)z,
x\ _ axj + /?x2
5. (a^ M
x'2 yx1 + <5x2
or px'-L = axj + /5x2, px'2 = yxx + dx2 (p # 0).
8. Since [F] passes through (y + z), and [Z] through (py + z), we have
{ Yy} + { Yz} = 0, p{Zy] + {Zz} = 0,
and the given expression reduces at once to p.
152 ANSWERS TO EXERCISES
9. Taking (y), (z), [Y], [Z] to be (a, 1, 0), (b, 1, 0), [1, —c, 0], [1, — d, 0],
we have
{yY}{zZ} __ Qa — c)(b — d)
{yZ}{zY} (a — d)(b — c)
Section 12.4
1. (i) x\ = pxv x'2 = qx2, x'3 = rx3.
(ii) x\ = —xx + x2 + x3, x\ = xx — x2 + x3, x'3 = x1 + x2 — x3.
(iii) x'i = x3, x'2 = xv x'3 = x2.
(iv) x' = x3, x'2 = —xx + x3, x'3 = —x2 + x3.
2. pXi 2^ijX j
or, solving the former set of equations in terms of Cih the cofactor of ci}
in the determinant 12.44,
Pxj —
3. Corresponding sides of the two triangles meet in the three points
which are collinear by the criterion 12.21 or, still more simply, by addition.
4. The lines AyBx and A3B2 meet in Cx = (1, 1, 1). Therefore B3 is (1, q, 1) for
a suitable value of q. The three lines A3BX, AXB3, A2B2, having equations
all pass through the same point C2 if pqr = 1. The three lines A3B3, A2Blt
AxB2, having equations
all pass through the same point C3 if qpr = 1. These two conditions agree,
sincepq = qp. (The connection between Pappus’s theorem and the commu¬
tative law of multiplication is one of the many important discoveries of
David Hilbert, 1862-1943.)
Section 12.5
1. If the correlation 12.51 transforms (1,0,0) into [1,0,0], (0, 1,0) into
[0, 1, 0], and (0, 0, 1) into [0, 0, 1], we must have ctj — 0 whenever i j.
Therefore ci3- = cH, and the correlation is a polarity.
2. Setting [X] = [7] = [0, 0, 1] in 12.54, we see that the condition for this
line to be self-conjugate is C33 = 0, or
C11C22 C122 — 0.
ANSWERS TO EXERCISES 153
C11 — c22-
Similarly, if (0, ±1, 1) are conjugate, c22 = c33. Hence cn = c33, and this
makes (±1,0, 1) conjugate.
4. The polars [cu, c21, c31], [c12, c22, c32), [c13, c23, c33] of the vertices meet the
respectively opposite sides [1, 0, 0], [0, 1, 0], [0, 0, 1] in the collinear points
6. The point (y) is accessible from (z) if and only if there exists a number p
such that the harmonic conjugates (y ± pz) are conjugate for the polarity.
Replacing x andy in the expression (xy) byy + pz andy — pz, we see that
the desired condition for conjugacy is
Section 12.6
1. When (xx) = 2{pc2x3 + x3xx + xxx2), the condition for conjugacy (xy) = 0
becomes (x2y3 + y2x3) + (x3yx + y3Xi) + (xxy2 + yiX2) = 0. Setting
x3 = y3 = 0, we see that, on the secant [0, 0, 1 ], (xl5 x2, 0) is conjugate
to (xl5 —x2, 0) (see Exercise 8 of Section 12.2).
154 ANSWERS TO EXERCISES
c22x2 + 2c3ix3xi = 0
passes through (1, 1, 1) if c22 = — 2c31, and we are left with the equation
x22 = x3xv
3. The point of intersection (1, —/x, /u2) traces the conic x22 = XgX^
5. Let PQR be the triangle of reference, and O the unit point (1,1, 1). The
point (Aq, x2, x3) whose locus we seek is the trilinear pole of the line
[jxq-1, x2-1, x3-1], which passes through O if
(xx)(yy) - (xy)2 = o,
which is the combined equation of the two tangents that pass through (y).
Dually, if [T] is a secant PQ of the conic [XX] = 0,
[XX][YY] - [XY]2 = 0
7. Let (y) and (z) be the two exterior points, so that the points of contact are
the intersections of the original conic (xx) = 0 with the polars (xy) = 0
and (xz) = 0. The conic
(xx)(yz) - (xy)(xz) = 0
evidently passes through all these six points. Dually, two secants [ Y], [Z],
and the tangents at their four “ends,” all touch the conic
[XX][YZ] - [XY][XZ] = 0.
ANSWERS TO EXERCISES 155
8. By Exercise 7(ii) at the end of Chapter 10, a point (y) is exterior if and only
if it is accessible from (z). By Exercise 6 of Section 12.5, this condition
means that (yy), like (zz), is a nonzero square.
The conic 12.61 has tangents xx = x3 and x2 = x3, meeting in the point
(1,1, 1), for which (zz) = 1. Therefore (y) is exterior or interior according
as yy2 + yy2 — y>32 is a nonzero square or a nonsquare.
9. In the field of real numbers, the product of any two negative numbers is
positive. But in the field of rational numbers, the product of two non¬
squares is not necessarily a square. To obtain an infinity of mutually
inaccessible points, we can take (xx) = xx2 + x22 — x32 and choose
points (y) for which the values of (yy) run through the sequence of primes.
Section 12.7
1. (0, 0, 1), (0, 1, 0), (0, 1, 1), (0, 1, 4), (0, 2, 1), (0, 1, 2).
2. [4, 0, 1], [1, 4, 0], [1, 3, 1], [1, 1, 3], [3, 1, 1], [0, 1, 4],
X\ = 3T2,
II
1
w«
x 2 — Ay x3,
II
<M
4.
(1,0,0) — [-1,0, 1], [l,0,0]->(0, 0, 1),
(0,1,0) ->[0,1,0], [0,1,0] -(0,1,0),
(0, 0, 1)-[1,0, 0], [0, 0, 1] —> (1, o, 1),
(1, 1,1) -[0,1, 1], [1, 1, 1]-(1, 1,2);
X1 *3
II
= —
%2 — -^2,
*
II
X3 — xy, *3 = + X..
5. (i) (1, 0, 2), (0, 2, 1), (2, 1, 0), (2, 0, 1), (0, 1, 2), (1, 2, 0).
(ii) (0, 1, 1), (0, 1, 4), (4, 0, 1), (2, 1, 0), (1, 2, 0), (1, 0, 1).
(iii) (0, 0, 1), (1, 0, 0), (1, 1, 1), (2, 1, 3), (3, 1, 2), (1, 4, 1).
(iv) (0, 0, 1), (0, 1, 0), (1, 0, 0), (1, 2, 1), (2, 1, 1), (1, 1, 2).
(v) (0, 1, 1), (1, 1, 0), (4, 1, 1), (1, 1, 4), (1, 4, 1), (1, 0, 1).
6. The field must admit an element whose square is —3; for instance, such a
configuration exists in the complex plane but not in the real plane, in
PG(2,pk) if and only if p is a prime congruent to 1 or 3 modulo 6.
Following the hint, we obtain F = CD • EH, G = BH • DE. The colline-
arity of EGA makes
CO2 + CD + 1 = 0.
The joins of “opposite” points all pass through (—to, 1, 1). In the case of
PG{2, 3), we have co = 1, and the (94, 123) uses up all the points except
Section 12.8
1. (i) x\ = —xlt x'2 — —x2 (as in 12.81 with ^ = — 1).
(ii) x\ — 2ax — xv x'2 = la2 — x2.
159
160 INDEX
The author received his B.A. and Ph.D. degrees from the University of
Cambridge and an LL.D. degree in 1957 from the University of Alberta.
He has been visiting professor at the University of Notre Dame and Columbia
University. Professor Coxeter is a life member of the London Mathematical
Society and was once first vice-president of the Mathematical Association of
America. His areas of specialization are in ^-dimensional crystallography
and in connections between geometry and the theory of groups.
f £ 2^’^
RESERX t
N0 23 7C
OE 7 TO
3 ns? DDD3D317 1
mm ^