System of Transcendental Idealism
System of Transcendental Idealism
TRANSCENDENTAL
IDEALISM
(1800)
EW. J. SCHELLING
translated by Peter Healh
with an introduction by Michael Vater
System of Transcendental Idealism
(1800)
by F.W. J. Schelling
P.L.H.
CONTENTS
Introduction [by Michael Vater] xi
Glossary xxxvii
Foreword 1
Introduction
1. Concept of Transcendental Philosophy 5
2. Corollaries [on 'I am* and 'there is] 7
3. Preliminary Division of Transcendental Philosophy 10
4. The Organ of Transcendental Philosophy 13
PART ONE
On the Principle of Transcendental Idealism
Section I: On the Necessity and Character of a
Supreme Principle of Knowledge 15
[Supreme Principle of Knowledge:
Self-Consciousness]
[In the Supreme Principle of Knowledge,
Content and Form condition each other]
Section II: Deduction of the Principle Itself 21
Elucidations 24
[The Self is one with the Act of
Self-Thinking]
[The Self is Intellectual Intuition]
[The Self is Identity of Being and
Producing]
General Observations 31
[Self and Object; and Individual;
and Thing-in-Itself]
PART TWO
General Deduction of Transcendenta 1 Idealism
Introductory 34
[According to Fichte's Wissenschaftslehre]
PART THREE
System of Theoretical Philosophy according to the
Principles of Transcendental Idealism
Introductory 42
[On the *Self for us' and the *Self itself]
I Deduction of the Absolute Synthesis Contained
in the Act of Self-Consciousness 43
[Positing and Counter-Positing as Original
Syntheses]
II Deduction of the Middle Terms of the
Absolute Synthesis
Introductory 47
[Philosophy as Repetition of the Original
Series of Acts]
Contents
PARTFOUR
System of Practical Philosophy According to the
Principles of Transcendental Idealism
[First Proposition: Absolute Abstraction = Self
Determination of the Intelligence = Willing] 155
Corollaries [On the Relationship of Theore
tical and Practical Philosophy] 156
[Second Proposition: The Act of Self-Deter
mination explicable only by the Action of
an Intelligence external to it] 161
Additional Remarks
1. [Operations of Other Intelligences
on an Object] 171
2. [Only through Intelligences outside me
does the World become Objective for me] 173
E Problem: To explain how Willing again
becomes objective for the Self
Solution
I [Third Proposition: Willing is necessarily
directed upon an External Object] 175
A [Transition from the Ideal to the
Objective: Time] 177
B [Change only of the Contingent Deter
minations of Things] 179
[Acting and Intuiting originally one]
[The truly Objective: The Activity at
X Contents
PART FIVE
Essentials of Teleology according to the
Principles of Transcendental Idealism
[Nature] 215
II [Art] 217
PART SIX
Deduction of a Universal Organ of Philosophy, or:
Essentials of the Philosophy of Art according
to the Principles of Transcendental Idealism
1. Deduction of the Art-Product as such 219
2. Character of the Art-Product 225
3. Corollaries [Relation of Art to
Philosophy] 229
General Observation on the Whole System 233
[Review]
INTRODUCTION
indeed restricts our freedom, through a process in which the self sees
itself develop through a necessary but not consciously observed act of
self-positing,* (S. W.» X, 97). This process, unnamed in 1800, is now
given the name dialectic~Schelling insinuates that credit for the dis
covery of *^Ae dialectic" is popularly misplaced.
In this dialectic or clarificatory process the positing and self-ex
panding activity of the self and the limitation of that activity are seen
to be both and equally the selfs activity. The self is primordially both
activity and limitation; inside the process it consciously makes itself to
be both, i.e., the self itself makes itself to be both subject and object, fi
nite and inHnite. The self is doubled in that it appears to itself; it loses
the abstract simplicity of the Fichtean self-positing (I = I); it ceases to
be in4tself and becomes fbr-itself. As Schelling explains it in 1827, in
side the dialectical process, which is the system, the self returns from
limitation to its original freedom and for the first time becomes for it
self (or in the System's language, consciously) what it already was in
itself, namely pure freedom or activity. Schelling further remarks
that this one process makes up the whole mechanism of the system.
What in a preceding moment is posited in consciousness (i.e., is admit
ted as real) only for the philosopher, is in the succeeding moment
raised in the self itself; in the end the objective self (the self itself, the
subject of experience) is raised to the standpoint of philosophizing con
sciousness and the two coincide (S.W., X, 98).
That this was indeed Schellings method and intent is evident
from a reading of the System, though often the *method* seems a
clumsy didactic device and hardly the simple mirroring of a process
inside consciousness. The claim that this dialectical procedure is
his method rather than Fichte's is plainly extravagant,4 although
the System's main advantage over the Science of Knowledge is the
adoption of this one method over the three or four that Fichte
variously employs.5 It is, at least in
general form, the same method that Hegel was to take up and perfect
in the Phenomenology of Spirit, and not the method alone, but the or
dering of the strata of experience determined by it. It seems difficult,
if not impossible, to understand the order of experiential levels in the
Phenomenology from HegeFs transitions alone, without the pattern of
materials inherited from Fichte and Schelling before one's eyes. The
pattern of the System indicates the road that Hegel was to follow, viz.
from theory to praxis, from the individual consciousness to the objec
tive social order, and from a world-embedded consciousness to a philo
sophically reflective one. But it shows, too, the Kantian and Fichtean
systems which lie at its origin. Here is the System% basic structure:
(1) A general consideration of self-consciousness, dialectic and
the methodology of the system—Parts I and II, Part III in part; pages
1-47.
(2) A theoretical philosophy: the deduction of cognitive phe
nomena ranging from rudimentary (and properly unconscious) presen
tation up to the categories generally necessary to secure objectivity for
experience-Part HI, pages 47-154.
(3) A (sketchily outlined) philosophy of nature, contained within
the theoretical philosophy, in which cognitive phenomena are seen of
necessity to involve a reflection and validation in an objective intuited
order, viz. nature—Part III, First Epoch (conclusion) and Second Ep
och; pages 83-129.
(4) A transcendental analysis of cognitive and judgmental facul
ties, again contained within the theoretical philosophy. Here the pre
vious stages of the selfs activity, viz. as productive intuition and as
matter organized in nature, are seen to be equally grounded in free re
flection or self-relation, the activity which in practical philosophy
emerges on its own as will—Part III, pages 129-54.
(5) A practical philosophy which advances from the perceptual
and volitional solipsism implicit in the theoretical standpoint to a de
duction of the rational human community as guarantor both of the ob
jectivity of the world of experience and the ideality (value) of the moral
order—Part IV, pages 155-93.
(6) A philosophy of history contained within the practical
philosophy and evidencing the objectivity of will, much as the
philosophy of nature does in the
and genetic-i.e., once the category of feeling is introduced, we watch the ac
tual growth of consciousness. Ironically, Fichte was to criticize the System for
a lack of dialectical rigor (Letter of the Summer of 1801, Fichte-Schelling
Briefu)echselt ed. W. Schulz [Frankfurt a. M., 1968], p. 126).
Introduction xv
9The one notable departure from his lifelong allegiance to the practical
and spirit-centered orientation of the Fichtean outlook is the System of Iden
tity of 1801-1806 which is prefigured in the System s concluding sections on
history and art. It seeks a model of being not in man's activity but in a quan
tified and formalistic approach to physical being.
Introduction xix
z^See "On the Form of the Sensible and Intelligible Worlds and Their
Principles" (1770), paragraph 10.
xxviii System of Transcendental Idealism
260f Human Freedom, tr. J. Gutmann (Chicago, 1936), p. 24; S. W., VII,
350.
XXX System of Transcendental Idealism
Science, art and philosophy remain sundered, and so the goal of fash*
ioning one comprehensive metascience is not accomplished. But the
solution Schelling envisages to this scandal of plurality is not to reduce
and simplify. The System has accomplished all that a general and ab
stractive approach can do. What is needful now, says Schelling, is a
turn to the concrete, the fabrication of a “new mythology/*31 the inte
gration of the particularistic 'knowing* of the arts with the conceptual
generality of the sciences—a task not to be accomplished in thought
alone, or by the philosopher in isolation, but one to be worked out by a
unew race, personifying, as it were, one single poet," an accomplish
ment of history, not of thought alone (p. 233)产
M.G.V.
31A myth or its subject, the god or hero, plays the role of a concrete uni
versal for Schelling. Concepts indicate with empty generality, but symbolic
forms with absolute specificity. A myth is its meaning, and all science aspires
to that exactitude. See The Philosophy of Art, S. W., V, 407-11.
32The remark has political overtones. The *new mythology* might well
be the ideology of the Republican polity. Compare Schiller's Letters on the
Aesthetic Education of Man.
GLOSSARY
That a system which completely alters and even overthrows the whole
view of things prevailing, not merely in common life, but also in the
greater part of the sciences, should encounter, despite the rigorous
demonstration of its principles, a continuing opposition even among
those in a position to feel or really to discern the force of its argu
ments, is a circumstance that can be due only to an incapacity for ab
stracting from the multitude of individual problems, which, on such an
altered view, the busy imagination at once conjures up from the whole
wealth of experience, so that the judgment is in consequence dis
tracted and disturbed. We cannot deny the strength of the arguments,
nor do we know of anything certain and assured to put in place of the
principles; but we are afraid of the supposedly monstrous conse
quences that are foreseen to follow from them, and despair of resolving
all those difTiculties which the principles, in their application, must in
evitably encounter. Nevertheless one may legitimately demand of
anyone who takes any part whatever in philosophical enquiries, that
he be capable of this abstraction, and know how to grasp the principles
in the highest degree of generality, wherein details disappear entirely,
and wherein, if it be only the highest, the solution of all possible prob
lems is assuredly also contained in advance; and it is therefore natural
that in first setting up the system, all enquiries descending into detail
should be set aside, and only the first thing needful be done, namely to
bring the principles into the open, and to put them beyond all doubt.
And by this, indeed, such a system finds the surest touchstone of its
truth, that it not only provides a ready solution to problems hitherto
insoluble, but actually generates entirely new problems, never before
considered, and by a general shattering of received opinion gives rise
to a new sort of truth. But this is precisely characteristic of transcen
dental idealism, that as soon as it is once admitted, it puts us under
the necessity of generating knowledge afresh, as it were, of once more
putting to the test what has long since passed as established truth,
and, assuming that it stands the test, of at least compelling it to
emerge therefrom in a wholly novel shape and form.
Now the purpose of the present work is simply this, to enlarge
transcendental idealism into what it really should be, namely a
system of all knowledge. The aim, then, is to provide proof of the
system, not merely in general, but in actual fact, that is, through
the real extension of its principles to all possible problems in regard
to the main objects of knowledge, whether these
2 System of Transcendental Idealism [III, 330-31]
have already been raised earlier, but not resolved, or have only now
been rendered possible and have newly come into existence through
the system itself. It follows accordingly that this work must treat of
topics and questions that have simply never been agitated or artic
ulated among a great many of those who now presume nonetheless
to have an opinion in philosophical matters; inasmuch as they still
halt at the first rudiments of the system, and cannot get beyond them,
either because of an initial incapacity even to understand what the
first principles of all knowledge require, or because of prejudice, or
for whatever other reason. Now although the enquiry does of course
revert to elementary first principles, the above class of persons has
little to hope for from the present work, since in regard to basic enqui
ries nothing can be found herein that has not already been said long
since, either in the writings of the originator of the Science of Knowl
edge, or in those of the present author; save that in the present
treatment, the exposition in regard to certain points may perhaps
have achieved a greater clarity than it previously possessed—though
even this can never, at any rate, make up for a fundamental want of
understanding. The means, furthermore, whereby the author has
sought to achieve his aim of setting forth idealism in its full extent,
consist in presenting every part of philosophy in a single continuum,
and the whole of philosophy as what in fact it is, namely a progressive
history of self-consciousness, for which what is laid down in experience
serves merely, so to speak, as a memorial and a document. In order
to trace this history with precision and completeness, it was chiefly a
matter, not only of separating exactly the individual stages thereof,
and within these again the individual moments, but also of presenting
them in a sequence, whereby one can be certain, thanks to the very
method employed in its discovery, that no necessary intervening step
has been omitted; the result being to confer upon the whole an inter
nal coherence which time cannot touch, and which in all subsequent
development remains, as it were, the unalterable framework, to
which everything must be related. The author's chief motive for
devoting particular care to the depiction of this coherence, which is
really a graduated sequence of intuitions, whereby the self raises
itself to the highest power of consciousness, was the parallelism of
nature with intelligence; to this he has long since been led, and to
depict it completely, neither transcendental philosophy nor the phi
losophy of nature is adequate by itself; both sciences together are
alone able to do it, though on that very account the two must forever
be opposed to one another, and can never merge into one. The
conclusive proof of the perfectly equal reality of
[331-32] Foreword 3
the two sciences from a theoretical standpoint, which the author has
hitherto merely asserted, is thus to be sought in transcendental phi
losophy, and especially in that presentation of it which is contained in
the present work; and the latter must therefore be considered as a nec
essary counterpart to his writings on the philosophy of nature. For in
this work it will become apparent, that the same powers of intuition
which reside in the self can also be exhibited up to a certain point in
nature; and, since the boundary in question is itself that of theoretical
and practical philosophy, that it is therefore indifferent, from a purely
theoretical standpoint, whether objective or subjective be made pri
mary, since this is a matter that practical philosophy (though it has no
voice at all in this connection) is alone able to decide; whence it will
also appear that even idealism has no purely theoretical basis, and to
that extent, if theoretical evidence alone be accepted, can never have
the evidential cogency of which natural science is capable, whose basis
and proof alike are theoretical through and through. Readers ac
quainted with the philosophy of nature will, indeed, conclude from
these observations, that there is a reason, lying pretty deep in the sub
ject itself, why the author has opposed this science to transcendental
philosophy and completely separated it therefrom, whereas, to be sure,
if our whole enterprise were merely that of explaining nature, we
should never have been driven into idealism.
But now as to the deductions which are effected in the present
work from the primary objects of nature, from matter as such and its
general functions, from the organism, etc., there are certainly idealis
tic, though not on that account teleological derivations (albeit many re
gard them as equivalent), which are as little capable of giving satisfac
tion in idealism as in any other system. For supposing I prove, for ex
ample, that it is necessary for the sake of freedom, or for practical pur
poses, that there should be matter having such and such properties, or
that the intellect intuit its dealings with the external world as medi
ated through an organism, this demonstration continues to leave un
answered for me the question as to how and by what mechanism the
intellect actually intuits precisely that which is necessary for this pur
pose. On the contrary, all proofs that the idealist offers for the exist
ence of determinate external things must be derived from the primor
dial mechanism of intuition itself, that is, by a genuine construction of
objects. Since the proofs are idealistic, the merely teleological applica
tion of them would not in fact advance true knowledge a single step,
since notoriously the teleological explanation of an object can teach
4 System of Transcendental Idealism [333-34]
§2 Corollaries
In the course of the foregoing, we have not only deduced the concept of
transcendental philosophy, but have also furnished the reader with a
glimpse into the entire system of philosophy; this, as we see, is consti
tuted of two basic sciences which, though opposed to each other in
principle and direction, mutually seek and supplement one another.
Here we shall not set forth the entire system of philosophy, but only
one of the basic sciences, and the derived concept thereof will thus
first receive a more exact characterization.1
1. If the subjective—the first and only ground of all reality— is
for transcendental philosophy the sole principle of explanation for ev
erything else (§1), then it necessarily begins with a general doubt as to
the reality of the objective.
Just as the nature-philosopher, directed solely upon the objec
tive, has nothing he more dearly wishes to prevent than an admixture
of the subjective into knowledge, so the transcendental philosopher, by
contrast, wishes nothing more dearly than to avoid an admixture
as much as art does on the productive capacity, and the difference be
tween them rests merely on the different direction taken by the pro
ductive force. For whereas in art the production is directed outwards,
so as to reflect the unknown by means of products, philosophical pro
duction is directed immediately inwards, so as to reflect it in intellec
tual intuition. The proper sense by which this type of philosophy must
be apprehended is thus the aesthetic sense, and that is why the phi
losophy of art is the true organon of philosophy (§3).
From ordinary reality there are only two ways out—poetry,
which transports us into an ideal world, and philosophy, which makes
the real world vanish before our eyes. —It is not apparent why the gift
for philosophy should be any more widely spread than that for poetry,
especially among that class of persons in whom, either through
memory-work (than which nothing is more immediately fatal to pro
ductivity), or through dead speculation, destructive of all imagination,
the aesthetic organ has been totally lost.
4. It is needless to linger over the commonplaces about a native
sense of truth, since we are wholly indifferent to its conclusions,
though one might ask what other conviction could still be sacred to
one who takes for granted the most certain of all (that there are things
outside us). —Let us rather take one more look at the so-called claims
of the common understanding.
In matters of philosophy the common understanding has no
claims whatever, save that to which every object of enquiry is entitled,
namely to be completely accounted for.
Thus it is no concern of ours to prove the truth of what it takes
to be true; we merely have to lay bare the inevitability of its delusions.
—It is agreed that the objective world belongs only to the necessary
limitations which make self-consciousness (the I am) possible; for the
common understanding it is sufficient if from this opinion itself the ne
cessity of its own view is again derived.
For this purpose it is necessary, not only that the inner work
ings of our mental activity be thrown open, the mechanism of neces
sary presentation unveiled, but also that it be shown by what peculiar
ity of our nature it is ordained, that what has reality merely in our in
tuition is reflected to us as something present outside us.
Just as natural science brings forth idealism out of realism, in
that it spiritualizes natural laws into laws of mind, or appends the for
mal to the material (§1), so transcendental philosophy brings forth re
alism out of idealism, in that it materializes the latus of mind into laws
of nature, or annexes the material to the formal.
PART ONE
Elucidations
is how geometry proceeds, in that it sets out, not from theorems, but
from postulates. In that the most primary construction therein is pos
tulated, and the pupil himself left to bring it forth, it is dependent
from the start upon self-construction. —So too with transcendental
philosophy. Unless the transcendental mode of thinking is already
brought with ust we are bound to find it unintelligible. It is therefore
necessary to transfer oneself freely from the outset into that way of
thinking, and this comes about by means of the free act whereby the
principle originates. If transcendental philosophy presupposes its ob
jects not at all, it can least of all presuppose its primary object, the
principle} this it can only postulate as something to be freely con
structed, and just as the principle is a construction of its own, so too
are all its other concepts, and the whole science is concerned only with
its own free construction.
If the principle of philosophy is a postulate, the object of this
postulate will be the most primary construction for inner sense, i.e” for
the self, not insofar as it is determined in this particular fashion or
that, but qua self as such, as the producing of itself. Now in and
through this original construction something determinate does indeed
come about, just as it does through every determinate act of mind.
But the product is in no sense external to the construction, it exists at
all only in being constructed, and has no more existence in abstraction
from the construction than does the geometer's line. —And this line
also is nothing existent, for the line on the blackboard is by no means
the line itself, and is only recognized as linear by relating it to the
original intuition of the line itself.
What the self is, is for that reason no more demonstrable than
what the line is; one can only describe the action whereby it comes
about. —If the line could be demonstrated, it would not need to be pos
tulated. And so it is with that transcendental line, the act of produc
ing, which in transcendental philosophy must initially be intuited, and
from which ail other constructions of the science first come into being.
What the self is, we experience only by bringing it forth, for no
where but in the self is the identity of being and producing fundamen
tal. (Cf. my general review of philosophical literature in the new
Philosophical Journal^ No. 10).1
i) That which arises for us through the original act of intellectual in
tuition can be formulated in a basic proposition, which may be termed
the first basic proposition of philosophy. Now by intellectual intuition
there arises for us the self, insofar as it is its own product, at once pro
ducing and produced. This identity between the self as producing and
the self as produced is expressed in the proposition, self = self; since it
equates opposites to itself, this is by no means an identical proposition,
but a synthetic one.
Thus the proposition self = self converts the proposition A = A
into a synthetic proposition, and we have found the point at which
identical knowledge springs immediately from synthetic, and synthetic
from identical. But this point also contains (Section 1) the principle of
all knowledge. Hence that principle must be expressed in the proposi
tion self = self, since this very proposition is the only one there can 6e
that is simultaneously both identical and synthetic.
Mere reflection upon the proposition A =A could have led us to
the same point. —To be sure, A = A appears identical, but it might
very well also have synthetic meaning, if the one A, say, were opposed
to the other. One would thus have to substitute in place of A a concept
expressing a fundamental duality within the identity and vice versa.
A concept of this sort, is that of an object that is at once opposed
to, and the same as, itself. But the only such object is one that is at
once cause and effect of itself, producer and product, subject and ob
ject. —The concept of an original identity in duality, and vice versa^ is
thus to be found only in the concept of a subject-object^ and only in
self-consciousness does such a concept originally manifest itself.
Natural science proceeds arbitrarily from nature, as the simul
taneously productive and produced, in order to derive from that con
cept the particular. The identity in question is an immediate object of
knowledge only in immediate self-consciousness; in that highest power
of self-objectification, to which the transcendental philosopher raises
himself at the outset—not arbitrarily, but through freedom} and the
fundamental duality in nature is itself ultimately explicable only inas
much as nature is taken to be an intelligence.
k) The proposition self = se/f fulfills at the same time the second
requirement imposed upon the principle of knowledge, that it should
simultaneously ground both the form and the content of knowledge.
For the supreme formal principle, A = A, is indeed only possible
through the act expressed in the proposition self ~ self—through the
act of thinking that becomes an object to itself and is identical with
itself. Thus, so far from the self = seZ/*falling under the principle of
identity, it is rather the latter that is conditioned by the former.
For did not self 二 self, then nor could A = A, since
[373-74] Self and Individual 31
General Observations
Introductory
indeed, to the most obstinate dogmatist, that the world consists only in
presentations; but full conviction only comes upon a complete exhibition
of the mechanism of its emergence from the inner principle of mental
activity. For nobody, surely, who has once seen how the objective world,
with all its determinations, develops out of pure self-consciousness with
out any affection from outside, will still find need for another world
independent of this; which is approximately the view taken in misinter
pretations of the Leibnizian theory of preestablished harmony? But
before this mechanism is itself derived, the question arises, how we come
to assume such a mechanism in any case. In deriving it, we consider the
self as an utterly blind activity. We know that the self is originally mere
activity; but how do we come to posit it as blind activity? This determi
nation must first be appended to the concept of activity. One might
make appeal here to the feeling of compulsion in our theoretical knowl
edge, and then argue as follows: since the self is originally mere activ
ity, the compulsion in question is to be construed merely as blind (me
chanical) activity; but this, as an appeal to fact, is not permitted in a
science such as our own. On the contrary, the existence of this compul
sion must first be deduced from the nature of the self as such. Moreover,
the question as to the ground of this compulsion presupposes an original
free activity, united with the tied activity in question. And so in fact it
is. Freedom is the one principle on which everything is supported, and
what we behold in the objective world is not anything present outside us,
but merely the inner limitation of our own free activity. Being as such is
merely the expression of an impeded freedom. It is our free activity,
therefore, that is fettered in knowledge. But then again we should have
no conception of an activity restricted, if there were not at the same time
an unrestricted activity within us. This necessary coexistence of a free
but limited, and an illimitable activity in one and the same identical
subject must, if it exists at all, be necessary, and the deduction of this
necessity appertains to that higher philosophy which is both theoretical
and practical at once.
If, therefore, the system of philosophy itself divides into theoreti
cal and practical, there must be a general proof that already in its origin,
and in virtue of its concept, the self cannot be a restricted (albeit free)
activity without being at the same time an unrestricted one and vice
versa. This proof must itself precede both theoretical and practical phi
losophy.
That this proof, of the simultaneous necessary coexistence of both
According to such a view, each single monad does indeed produce the
world from out of itself, yet the world still exists concurrently, independent of
the presentations; whereas on Leibniz's own view the world, insofar as it is
real, itself again consists merely of monads, so that in the last resort all reality
rests solely on powers of presentation after all.
36 System of Transcendental Idealism [380-81]
explain how it may also become ideal, that is, it certainly explains the
fact that the self is limited as such, but not its knowledge of that limi
tation, or its being limited for itself.
cc). But now the boundaty must be at once real and ideal. Real, that
is, independent of the self, since otherwise the latter is not genuinely
bounded; ideals dependent on the self, since otherwise the self does not
posit or intuit itself as limited. Both claims, that the boundary is real,
and also that it is merely ideal, are to be deduced from self-conscious
ness. Self-consciousness says that the self is limited for itself; in order
that it be limited, the boundary must be independent of the activity so
confined; in order that it be limited for itself, the boundary must de
pend on the self. The conflict between these claims is therefore soluble
only through an opposition obtaining in selSconsciousness itself. That
the boundary is dependent on the self means that the latter contains
another activity besides the one limited, which the boundary must be
independent of. So besides that infinitely outreaching activity which
we wish to call real, since it alone is really limitable, there must be an
other in the self, which we may term the ideal activity. The boundary
is real for the infinitely outreaching, or—since this very activity is to
be limited in self-consciousness—for the objective activity of the self,
and ideal, therefore, for an opposing, nonobjective, intrinsically illimit
able activity, which must now be more exactly described.
dd). Apart from these two activities, one of which we simply postulate
from the outset as necessary to explain the boundedness of the self, no
other factors of selfconsciousness are given. The second, ideal or non
objective, activity must therefore be such that through it are given si
multaneously the grounds both of the limitation of the objective activ
ity, and of the knowledge that it is so limited. Now since the ideal ac
tivity is originally posited merely as the intuitant (subjective) of the
other, so as to explain thereby the limitation of the self as self, to be in
tuited and to be limited must, for the latter, objective, activity, be one
and the same. This must find its explanation in the basic character of
the self. The latter activity, if it is to be activity of a self, must simul*
taneously be limited and intuited as limited, for in this very identity of
being intuited and of being lies the nature of the self. In that the real
activity is limited, it must also be intuited, and in that it is intuited, it
must also be limited; and both must be absolutely one.
ee). Both activities, the real and the ideal, mutually
[386-87] General Deduction, after Fichte 41
presuppose each other. The real, originally striving into infinity, but
to be limited for the sake of self-consciousness, is nothing without the
ideal, for which, in its limitation, it is infinite (by dd). Conversely, the
ideal activity is nothing without the to-be-intuited, the limitable, and,
on that very account, the real.
From this reciprocal presupposition of the two activities, for the
sake of self-consciousness, the entire mechanism of the self will have
to be derived.
fl). Just as the two activities reciprocally presuppose each other, so
also do idealism and realism. If I reflect merely upon the ideal activity,
there arises for me idealism, or the claim that the boundary is posited
solely by the self. If I reflect merely upon the real activity, there
arises for me realism, or the claim that the boundary is independent of
the self. If I reflect upon the two together, a third view arises from
both, which may be termed ideal-realism^ or what we have hitherto
designated by the name of transcendental idealism.
gg). In theoretical philosophy we explain the ideality of the boundary
(or how the limitation, originally existing only for free action, becomes
limitation for knowledge); practical philosophy has to explain the real
ity of the boundary (or how the limitation, which is initially a purely
subjective one, becomes objective). Theoretical philosophy is therefore
idealism, practical philosophy realism, and only the two together con
stitute the complete system of transcendental idealism.
Just as idealism and realism mutually presuppose each other, so
also do theoretical and practical philosophy; and in the self as such
there is initial union and combination of what we must hereafter sepa
rate, for the sake of the system now to be established.
PART THREE
System of Theoretical Philosophy according to the
Principles of Transcendental Idealism
Introductory
2. In accordance with the foregoing, the enquiry will divide into two
parts. First we shall derive the absolute synthesis contained in the act
of self-consciousness, and afterwards must seek out the mediating ele
ments of the synthesis in question.
to be limited, are one and the same. Only that which is limited me-
ward, so to speak, comes to consciousness: the limiting activity falls
outside all consciousness, just because it is the cause of all limitation.
The fact of limitation must appear as independent of me, since I can
discern only my own limitedness, never the activity whereby it is pos
ited.
4. This distinction between limiting and delimited activity being ac
cepted, neither of the two, the limiting or the limited activity, is what
we call the self. For the self exists only in self-consciousness, but
through neither of these two, taken in isolation, does the self of self
consciousness arise for us.
a) The limiting activity does not come to consciousness, or be
come an object, and is therefore the activity of the pure subject. But
the self of self-consciousness is not the pure subject, but subject and
object together.
b) The limited activity is merely that which becomes an object,
the purely objective element in self-consciousness. But the self of self
consciousness is neither pure subject nor pure object, but both of these
at once.
Thus neither through the limiting nor the limited activities, by
themselves, do we arrive at self-consciousness. There is} accordingly,
a third activity, compounded of these two, whereby the self of self-con
sciousness is engendered.
5. It is this third activity, oscillating between the limited and the lim
iting, whereby the self is first engendered; and, since the producing
and the being of the self are one, it is nothing other than the self of
self-consciousness itself.
The self is thus itself a compound activity, and self-conscious
ness itself a synthetic act.
6. To define this third, synthetic activity more closely, we must first
do the same for the conflict of opposing activities from which it is born.
a) This conflict is a conflict of activities originally opposed, not
so much in subject as in direction, for both are activities of one and
the same self The origin of these two directions is this. —The self has
an urge to produce the infinite, and this tendency must be thought of
as directed outwards (as centrifugal), but it is not distinguishable as
such without an activity regressively directed inwards to the self as
center. The outgoing, by nature infinite activity is the objective in
the self; the self-reverting activity is nothing else but the striving to
intuit oneself in that infinitude. Through this action as such, the
inner and the outer are divided within the self, and with their
separation is posited a conflict in the self that only the necessity of
self-consciousness can explain. Why the self should
[392-93] Deduction of Absolute Synthesis 45
that wavers between them, and this third activity is again not possible
unless both opposites are themselves activities of the self.
This advance from thesis to antithesis, and from thence to syn
thesis, is therefore originally founded in the mechanism of the mind,
and so far as it is purely formal (as in scientific method, for example),
is abstracted from this original, material sequence established in tran
scendental philosophy.
Introductory
Solution
from what can and cannot be posited; it seems contingent. The posi
tive element in the real activity appears as that from which one cannot
abstract. The limit, for that very reason, can appear only as some
thing found, i.e., foreign to the self and opposed to its nature.
The self is the absolute ground of all positing. For something to
be opposed to the self means, therefore, that something is posited
which is not posited through the self. The intuitant must therefore
find in the intuited something (the limitation) which is not posited
through the self as intuitant.
(Here for the first time we may perceive very clearly the differ
ence between the philosopher's standpoint and that of his object. We,
who philosophize, know that the limitation of the objective has its sole
ground in the intuitant or subjective. The intuiting self as such does
not and cannot know this, as now becomes clear. Intuiting and limit
ing are originally one. But the self cannot simultaneously intuit and
intuit itself as intuiting, and so cannot intuit itself as limiting either.
It is therefore necessary that the intuitant, which seeks only itself in
the objective, should find the negative element therein to be something
not posited by itself. If the philosopher likewise maintains this to be
the case (as in dogmatism), this is because he continually coalesces
with his object and shares with it the same point of view.)
The negative element is encountered as not posited by the sel£
and is for this very reason that which can in principle only be found
(and which is subsequently transformed into the merely empirical).
That the self finds its limitation to be something not of its own
positing, amounts to saying that the self finds it posited by something
opposed to itself, namely, the not-self. Thus the self cannot intuit itself
as limited, without intuiting this limitation as an affection on the part
of a not-self.
The philosopher who remains fixed at this standpoint can offer
no other explanation for sensation (for it is self-evident that self-intu
ition in limitation, as so far derived, is none other than what in ordi
nary parlance is called sensation), save that it comes about through
affection by a thing-in-itself. Since sensation gives rise only to the
determinacy among presentations, he will also be explainingjust
this as due to the said affection. For that in presentation the self
merely takes,几,and is pure receptivity, he cannot maintain, owing
to the spontaneity involved therein, and indeed because even in
the things themselves (as presented), there emerges the unmistakable
trace of an activity of the self. The influence in question will
therefore originate, not from things as we present them
[404-5] Sensation 55
to an object as its cause is a much later step, whose grounds can again
be shown to lie in the self itself.
Now if the self always senses only its own suspended activity,
the sensed is nothing distinct from the self; the latter is merely sens
ing itself, a fact to which ordinary philosophical parlance has already
given expression, in that it speaks of the sensed as something purely
subjective.
Additional Remarks
The act by which the self limits itself is none other than that of
self-consciousness, and to this we must confine ourselves, as the basis
for explanation of all limitation, if only because it is utterly inconceiv
able how any affection from without can transform itself into a presen
tation or into knowledge. Supposing, even, that an object were to act
upon the self as if upon an object, such an affection could still only
bring forth something homogeneous in every case, ie, again an objec
tive determinacy merely. For the law of causality holds only between
things of the same sort (things of the same world), and does not extend
from one world to the other. So how a primordial being can transform
itself into knowledge, would be conceivable only if it could be shown
that even presentation was itself a kind of being; and in fact this is the
explanation offered by materialism, a system that would have to be
congenial to the philosopher if only it actually performed what it
promises. However, as materialism stands so far, it is altogether unin
telligible, and as rendered intelligible, it no longer differs, in fact, from
transcendental idealism. —To explain thinking as a material phenom
enon is possible only by turning matter itself into a phantom, the mere
modification of an intelligence, whose common functions are thought
and matter. Materialism itself thereby reverts to the intelligent as
that which is primary. To be sure, it is no less out of the question to
explain being from knowing by treating the former as the effect of the
latter; between the two there can be no causal relation whatsoever,
and the twain can never meet, unless they are originally one, as they
are in the self. Being (matter), regarded as productive, is a knowing,
and knowing regarded as a product is a being. If knowing is produc
tive as such, it must be productive through and through, not in part
merely; nothing can enter into knowing from without, for everything
that exists is identical with knowing and there is nothing outside it. If
one factor in presentation resides in the self, the other must do like
wise, for in the object both are inseparable. Supposing, for example,
that only stuff pertains to things, then before it reaches the self this
stuff must be without form, at least in the transition from thing to pre
sentation, which is assuredly inconceivable.
But now if the original limitation is posited through the self
as such, how does the latter come to sense it, that is, envisage it as
something opposed to itself? Everything real about cognition
attaches to sensation, and a philosophy that cannot explain
sensation is already, on that very account, an abortive one. For
the truth of all cognition undoubtedly rests on the feeling of
compulsion which accompanies it. Being (objectivity)
58 System of Transcendental Idealism [408-9]
Explanation
with sensation (that between self and thing-in-itselD is for this reason
again posited, not for the self itself, but only for us in the self.
This phase of self-consciousness will hereafter be called that of
original sensation. It is that wherein the self intuits itself in the origi
nal limitation, without being aware of this intuition, or the latter itself
again becoming an object for the self. In this phase the self is entirely
rooted upon the sensed, and, as it were, lost therein.
More precisely, then, the problem is this: how does the self,
which was hitherto purely sensed, become both sensing and sensed at
once?
From the original act of self-consciousness, only the fact of limi
tation could be deduced. Were the self to be limited for itself it would
have to intuit itself as such; this intuition, which reconciles the unlim
ited self with the limited, was the act of sensation, though for reasons
given, all that remains of this in consciousness is the mere vestige of a
passivity. This act of sensing must therefore itself in turn be made
into an object, and it has to be shown how this, too, enters conscious
ness. It is easy to foresee that we shall be able to solve this problem
only through a new act.
This is fully in accordance with the progress of the synthetic
method —Two opposites a and b (subject and object) are united by the
actx, butx contains a new opposition, c and d (sensing and sensed),
and so the actx itself again becomes an object; it is itself explicable
only through a new act = z, which perhaps again contains an opposi
tion, and so on.
Solution
I
The self senses when it finds in itself something opposed to it, namely,
since the self is mere activity, a real negation of activity, or state of be
ing afiected. But to be that which senses, for itself, the (ideal) self
must posit in itself that passivity which till now has been present only
in the real; and this can undoubtedly occur only through activity.
We are here at the very point around which empiricism has
constantly circulated without being able to explain it. For the
external impression explains to me only the passivity of sensation;
at most it explains a return action upon the impinging object, as it
might be after the fashion of an elastic body repelling another that
strikes it, or a mirror reflecting the light that falls
62 System of Transcendental Idealism [413-14]
upon it; but it does not explain the return action, the reversion of the
self upon itself, or how the latter relates the external impression to it
self as self, or intuitant. The object never reverts into itself, and re
lates no impression to itself; for that very reason it is without sensa
tion.
Thus the self cannot possess sensation> for itself, without being
intrinsically active. Now the self that is active here cannot be the lim
ited self, but only the illimitable. But this ideal self is unlimited only
in contrast to the objective, now limited, activity, and thus only insofar
as it overleaps the boundary. If we reflect upon what happens in every
sensation, we shall find that in each there must be something that
knows about the impression, but is yet independent thereof and goes
out beyond it; for even the judgment that the impression proceeds
from an object presupposes an activity which does not attach to the im
pression, but is directed, rather, to something beyond the impression.
The self does not sense, therefore, unless it contains an activity that
goes out beyond the limit. It is by means of this that the self, to have
sensation for itself has to take up the alien element into itself (g〃a
ideal); but this alien element is itself again within the self, for it is the
latter*s suspended activity. For the sake of what follows, the relation
ship of these two activities must now be more exactly determined. The
unlimited activity is originally ideal, like every activity of the self, in
cluding therefore the real as well, but is in opposition to the real only
insofar as it overleaps the boundary. The limited activity is real inso
far as there is reflection upon the fact that it is limited, but ideal inso
far as we reflect that it is in principle the same as the ideal; it is real
or ideal, depending on how it is regarded. It is evident, moreover, that
the ideal is distinguishable as intrinsically ideal only in contrast to the
real, and vice versa, as can be confirmed by the simplest experiment;
the way, for example, that a fictitious object is distinguishable as such
only in contrast to the real, and conversely, that every real object is
distinguishable as such only in contrast to a fictitious one imported
into the judgment. Taking this for granted, the following conclusions
can be drawn.
1. That the self should have sensation for itself, means
that it should actively take up the opposite into itself. But this
opposite is nothing else but the limit or checking-point, and the
latter resides only in the real activity, which is distinguishable
from the ideal only by the limit. That the self should appropriate
the opposite to itself means, therefore, that it should take this up
into its ideal activity. Now this is not
[414-15] Producing Derived 63
possible, unless the limit falls within the ideal activity, and this, too,
would have to come about by way of an activity of the self itself. (As
now becomes increasingly clear, the whole of theoretical philosophy
has this problem only to solve, namely how the restriction becomes
ideal, or how the ideal (intuitant) activity also comes to be limited. It
was evident in advance, that the disturbed equilibrium (above, A.2) be
tween ideal and real activity would have to be restored as surely as
the self is a self. How it is to be restored is our sole remaining prob
lem.) —But the limit falls only upon the line of the real activity, and
conversely, just that activity of the self is the real one, on which the
limit falls. Apart from the limit, moreover, the ideal and real activities
are originally indistinguishable, for it is only the limit which marks
the point of separation between them. Thus the activity is only ideal,
i.e., only to be distinguished as ideal, beyond the boundary, or insofar
as it oversteps the limit.
That the limit shall fall within the ideal activity therefore means
that the limit is to fall beyond the limit, which is a manifest contradic
tion. This contradiction must be resolved.
2. The ideal self could go about to abolish the limit, and in that
it did so, the limit would also necessarily fall upon the line of the ideal
activity; but the limit is not to be done away with; it is to be taken up
qua limit, that is, unabolished, into the ideal activity.
Alternatively, the ideal self could limit itself, and thus engender
a limit. —But this, too, would provide no explanation of what has to be
explained. For in that case the limit posited in the ideal self would not
be identical with that posited in the real, which it is supposed to be.
Even if we were willing to assume that the hitherto purely ideal self
should become an object to itself, and thereby limited, we should still
have failed to advance a single step thereby, and would indeed have
been thrown back to the first stage of our enquiry, where the hitherto
purely ideal self first separates and, as it were, decomposes itself into a
subjective and an objective.
There is therefore nothing for it but to find a mean between
abolishing and engendering. Such a mean is determining. That which
I am to determine must be present independently of myself. But in
that I determine it, it again becomes, through that very determination,
a thing dependent on myself. Moreover, in that I determine an inde
terminate, I abolish it as indeterminate and engender it as determi
nate.
So the ideal activity will have to determine the limit.
64 System of Transcendental Idealism [415-16]
II
We see now, indeed, from this whole discussion, that the proposed so
lution to the problem is assuredly the right one; but this solution itself
is not yet comprehensible, and we may doubtless still be in want of
certain middle terms thereof
The solution discloses, at all events, that the ideal self cannot be
passive without already being previously active, and hence that a
mere impression upon the ideal (intuitant) self can in no case account
for sensation; but it also appears that the ideal self in turn cannot be
active, in the manner defined, without already being passive; it ap
pears, in a word, that activity and passivity mutually presuppose one
another within this act.
66 System of Transcendental Idealism [418-19]
conditioned by each other. The genesis of this third activity thus ex
plains for us, at the same time, the origin of that circle, which we saw
ourselves to have fallen into with the self (I.).
The genesis of this activity is, however, as follows. In the first
act (that of self-consciousness), the self is \ntuited-as-suchf and in
being intuited is thereby limited. In the second act it is intuited, not
as such, but determinately, as limited} yet it cannot be intuited as
limited, unless the ideal activity oversteps the boundary. Hence there
arises in the self an opposition between two activities which, as activi
ties of one and the same self, are automatically united in a third, in
which there has necessarily to be a mutual conditioning of aflected-
ness and activity, or in which the self is ideal only insofar as it is si
multaneously real, and vice versa; and by this, then, the self as sens
ing becomes an object to itself.
3. In this third activity the self is vacillating between the activ
ity that has passed the limit and that which is still confined. Through
this vacillation of the self, they acquire a reciprocal relation to each
other, and become fixated as opposites.
It may be asked:
a) what the ideal activity becomes fixated as? So far as it is fix
ated at all, it ceases to be pure activity. It becomes in the same action
opposed to the activity confined within the limit, and is thus appre
hended as an activity fixated but set in opposition to the real self. So
far as it is apprehended as fixated, it acquires an ideal substrate; so
far as it is apprehended as an activity opposed to the real self, it itself
becomes—but only in this opposition—a real activity; it becomes the
activity of something really opposed to the real self. But this real op
ponent to the real self is nothing other than the thing-in-itself.
Thus the ideal activity, having passed the limit and now become
an object, at this point disappears as such from consciousness and is
transformed into the thing-in-itself.
The following observation is easily made. The sole ground of
the original limitation is, by the foregoing, the selfs intuitant or
ideal activity; but this latter is here reflected, as ground of limitation,
to the self itself, though not indeed as an activity thereof, for the
self is now simply real; rather, as something opposed to the self.
The thing-in-itself is therefore nothing else but the shadow of the
ideal activity, now over the boundary, which is thrown back to the
self by intuition, and is to that extent itself a product of the self.
The dogmatist, who regards the thing-in-itself as real, is in the
same position as that now currently occupied
[422-23] Productive Intuition Derived 69
by the self. The thing-in-itself arises for it through an action; the out
come remains behind, but not the action that gave rise to it. Thus the
self is originally ignorant of the fact that this opposite is its own prod
uct, and must remain in the same ignorance so long as it stays en
closed in the magic circle which self-consciousness describes about the
self; only the philosopher, in breaking out of the circle, can penetrate
behind the illusion.
The deduction has now progressed to the point at which some
thing outside the self is for the first time present to the self as such.
In the current action the self is directed for the first time to something
beyond the limit, and this latter is now nothing but the common point
of contact between the self and its opposite. In the original sensation,
only the limit was disclosed; here, something beyond the limit,
whereby the self explains the limit to itself It is to be expected that
the limit also will thereby acquire an altered significance, as will soon
appear. The original sensation, in which the self was merely the
sensed, is transformed into an intuition, in which the self for the first
time becomes for itself that which senses, but for that very reason
ceases to be the sensed. For the self that intuits itself as sensing, the
sensed is the (previously sensing) ideal activity which has crossed the
boundary, but is now no longer intuited as an activity of the self. The
original limitant of the real is the self itself, but it cannot enter con
sciousness as a limiting factor without transforming itself into the
thing-in-itself. The third activity, here deduced, is that in which the
limited and the limitant are simultaneously separated and gathered
together.
It still remains to enquire
b) what becomes in this action of the real or restricted activity?
The ideal activity has transformed itself into the thing-in-itself,
and so the real will transform itself through the same action into the
opposite of the thing-in-itself, namely the self-in-itself. The self, which
was hitherto always both subject and object at once, is now for the first
time something in itself; the originally subjective aspect of the self has
been carried over the boundary, and is there intuited as the thing-in-
itself; what remains within the boundary is the purely objective aspect
of the self.
Thus the deduction now stands at the point where the self and
its opposite separate, not just for the philosopher merely, but for the
self itself. The origin duality of self-consciousness is now as it were
divided between the self and the thing-in-itself. From the present
action of the self there is left over, therefore,
70 System of Transcendental Idealism [423-24]
not a mere passivity, but two opposites really opposed to each other, on
which the determinacy of sensation depends; and thereby the problem
of how the self comes to have sensation for itself is first completely
solved. A problem that until now no philosophy could answer, and
least of all empiricism. In passing, when the latter vainly endeavors
to explain the passage of the impression from the purely passive self
into the thinking and active one, the difficulty of the task is one that
he actually shares with the idealist. For wherever the passivity may
come from, whether from an impression of the thing outside us, or
from the primordial mechanism of the mind itself, it is still always pas
sivity, and the transition to be explained is the same. The marvel of
productive intuition resolves this difficulty, and without this there is
no solving it at all. For it is manifest that the self cannot intuit itself
as sensing, without intuiting itself as opposed to itself, and simulta
neously in limitant and delimited activity—in that mutual determina
tion of activeness and passiveness which arises in the manner indi
cated; save only that this opposition in the self itself, which only the
philosopher perceives, appears to his object, the self, as an opposition
between itself and something outside it.
4. The product of the oscillation between real and ideal activity
is the self-in-itself on the one hand, and the thing-in-itself on the
other, and both are the factors of the intuition now to be derived. We
must first ask how these two are determined by the action already in
ferred.
a) That the self is determined by this action as a pure objective,
has just been proved. But it only becomes so in the reciprocal relation*
ship in which it now stands with the thing-in-itself. For were the
limitant still within it, it would be determined merely through appear
ing so to itself, whereas it now is determined in itself and as it were in
dependently of itself; exactly as is demanded by the dogmatist, who in
fact only elevates himself to this point of view.
(It is not a matter of which self is active in this process, for this
self is ideal in its limitation, and conversely, limited in its ideality, nei
ther subject nor object alone, since it embraces within itself the whole
(complete) self; save only that what belongs to the subject appears as
thing-in-itself, and what belongs to the object, as self-in-itself.)
b) The thing is, to start with, wholly and solely determined
as the absolute opposite to the self. But now the self is determined
as activity, and so the thing is likewise determined merely as a coun
terpart to the activity of the self. But all setting in opposition
[424-25] Productive Intuition Derived 71
of it is not yet possible here, and can be given only in the sequel.
5. That oscillation, whose residues are the self and thing-in-it-
self as opposites, cannot persist, for by this opposition a contradiction
is posited in the self itself (that self which oscillates between the two).
But the self is absolute identity. As certainly, therefore, as self = self
there arises automatically and necessarily a third activity, in which
the two opposites are brought into a relative equilibrium.
All activity of the self proceeds from a contradiction therein.
For since the self is absolute identity, it requires no ground determin
ing it to activity other than a duality in itself, and the persistence of
all mental activity depends upon the continuance, i.e., the constant re-
emergence, of this contradiction.
Here indeed, the contradiction appears as an opposition between
the self and something outside it, but is by derivation a contradiction
between ideal and real activity. If the self is to intuit (or sense) itself
in its original confinement, it must simultaneously press on out be
yond the confinement. Restriction, necessity, compulsion—these are
all felt only in opposition to an unconfined activity. Nor is anything
actual in the absence of imagination. —Thus already with sensation
itself a contradiction is posited in the self. It is at once confined and
pressing out over the boundary.
This contradiction cannot be got rid of, but nor again can it per
sist. Hence it can be unified only by means of a third activity.
This third activity is essentially intuitant, for it is the ideal self
that is here thought of as becoming limited.
But this intuition is an intuiting of intuition, for it is an intuit
ing of sensation. —Sensing is already itself an intuiting, but an intuit
ing of the first order (hence the simplicity of all sensations, the
impossibility of defining them, for all definition is synthetic). The in
tuiting now derived is thus an intuiting of the second order, or, what
comes to the same, a productive intuition.
Introductory
Descartes the physicist said: give me matter and motion, and
from that I will fashion you the universe. The transcendental
philosopher says: give me a nature made up of opposed activities,
of which one reaches out into
[427-28] Theory of Productive Intuition 73
the infinite, while the other tries to intuit itself in this infinitude, and
from that I will bring forth for you the intelligence, with the whole
system of its presentations. Every other science presupposes the intel
ligence as already complete; the philosopher observes it in its genesis,
and brings it into being, so to speak, before his eyes.
The self is but the ground upon which the intelligence, with all
its determinations, is delineated. The original act of self-consciousness
explains to us only how the self is restricted in regard to its objective
activity, or in its original striving; but not how it is confined in its sub
jective activity, or in knowing. It is productive intuition which first
transfers the original limit into the ideal activity, and is the selfs first
step towards intelligence.
The necessity of productive intuition, here systematically de
duced from the entire mechanism of the self, has got to be derived, as
a general condition of knowing as such, directly from the concept
thereof; for if all knowing borrows its reality from an immediate cogni
tion, it is this alone that is to be met within intuition; whereas con
cepts, in fact, are merely shadows of reality, projected through a repro
ductive power, the understanding, which itself presupposes a higher
power, having no original outside itself, and which produces from
within itself by a primordial force. Hence an improper idealism, a sys
tem, that is, which turns all knowledge into illusion, would have to be
one which eliminated all immediacy in our cognition, eg, by positing
external originals independent of our presentations; whereas a system
which seeks the origin of things in an activity of the mind that is ideal
and real at once, would have, precisely because it is the most perfect
idealism, to be at the same time the most perfect realism. For if the
most perfect realism is that which recognizes things in themselves and
immediately, it is possible only in an order which perceives in things
its own reality merely, confined by its own activity. For such an order,
as the indwelling soul of things, would permeate them as its own im
mediate organism and―just as the master has the most perfect knowl
edge of his work-would fathom their inner mechanism from the first.
As against this, the attempt may be made to explain the evi
dence of sensory intuition upon the hypothesis that there is something
or other in our intuition which arrives there through a check or im
pression. For a start, however, a check upon the percipient will not
convey to him the object itself, but only the effect thereof. But now in
intuition it is not the mere effect of an object, but the object itse/f that
is immediately present. Now as to how the object is annexed to the
74 System of Transcendental Idealism [428-29]
direction, are both positive forces, and opposed only relatively to one
another* so that it is completely arbitrary which of the two, A or B, is
taken to be negative. Suppose, on the other hand, that the cause of
gravity lies in no way outside the point from which force A proceeds;
in that case the two forces A and B will have a common source, where
upon it is at once evident that one of the two is necessarily and by ori
gin negative, and such that if A, the positive, is a force operating
through contact, the negative must be such that it also acts at a dis
tance. The first case is an example of a purely relative opposition, the
second of an absolute one. Which of the two is adopted is admittedly a
matter of indifference for calculation, but not for natural philosophy.)
Thus if two activities have one and the same subject, the self, it
is self-evident that they must be absolutely opposed to each other; and
conversely, if both are absolutely opposed to each other, that they are
activities of one and the same subject.
If the two activities were divided between different subjects, as
might here seem to be the case, since we have posited one as an activ
ity of the self, the other as an activity of the thing, then the selfs ten
dency to reach out to infinity could indeed be restricted by an activity
(of the thing-in-itself) coming in the opposite direction. In that case,
however, the thing-in-itself would have to be outside the self. But the
thing-in-itself is only outside the real (practical) self; by the magic of
intuition both are united, and posited as activities, not relatively but
absolutely opposed, within one identical subject.
4. The opposed activities that are to be the condition of intuition
are now more exactly determined, and for both we have found charac
terizations independent of their directions. The first, that of the self,
may be recognized by its positive nature, the second by the fact that it
can be thought of solely as the limitant of a positive activity. We now
proceed to apply these definitions to the question raised above.
In the common outcome arising from the opposition of the two
activities, the traces of both must be apparent, and since we know
their nature, the product also must admit of characterization in terms
of them.
Since the latter is a product of opposed activities, it must, for
that very reason, be finite.
Since, moreover, it is the common product of opposites, neither
activity can eliminate the other; both together must emerge in the
product, not indeed as identical, but as what they are, namely opposed
activities, maintaining a mutual equilibrium.
To the extent that they preserve a balance between them,
the two will not cease, indeed, to be activities, but they will not
appear as such. —Let us recall once more
82 System of Transcendental Idealism [439-40]
Deduction of Matter
1. The two activities, which maintain equilibrium in the prod
uct, can appear only as fixed, static activities, that is, as forces.
The first of these forces will be by nature positive, so that if un
restricted by any opposing force it would expand out to infinity. —That
matter possesses such an infinite expansive force will be given only a
transcendental proof. As surely as the first of the two activities from
which the product is constructed tends, by its nature, to strive into the
infinite, so surely must the first factor of the product be also an infi
nite expansive force.
Left to itself, this latter force, which is concentrated in the prod
uct, would now expand ad infinitum. That it is actually retained in a
finite product, is explicable only through an opposing, negative, re
straining force, which must likewise display itself as the counterpart
in the common product to the limiting activity of the self.
Thus if the self could reflect at this present stage upon its con
struction, it would find the latter to be a composite of two forces main
taining an equilibrium, of which one on its own would produce the in
finitely large, while the other in its unrestricted form would reduce
the product to the infinitely small. —However, at its present stage the
self is not yet reflective.
2. Till now we have had regard only to the opposite natures of
the two activities and of the forces corresponding to them; but upon
their opposite natures their opposite directions also depend. We can
therefore raise the question, how two forces come to be distinguished
even in their mere directions, a problem that will lead us to a closer
determination of the product, and will open the road to a new enquiry;
for it is undoubtedly a query of great importance, to ask how forces
that are thought of as operating from one and the same point can act
in opposite directions.
The first of the two activities was assumed to be headed
originally towards the positive infinite. But in infinity there are no
directions. For direction is determination, yet determination =
negation. The positive activity will therefore have to appear in the
product as an activity intrinsically quite lacking in direction, and
for that very reason headed in all directions. It must be noted once
more, however, that this omnidirectional activity is in fact only
distinguished as such from the standpoint of reflection, for in the
moment of production the activity is nowhere distinguished from its
direction, and how the self makes this distinction on its own account
will be the topic of a special enquiry. The question now
84 System of Transcendental Idealism [442-43]
Corollaries
save the line above constructed, since the direction of the positive force
is so far determined by the negative that it can perforce go only to
wards the one point at which the boundary falls. The opposite will
happen, therefore, as soon as the two forces are parted from each
other. Let C be the point at which both forces are united. If we sup
pose this point stationary, then round about it is a countless set of
points to which it could move, if it were capable of purely mechanical
motion. But now at this point there is a force which can move in all
these directions at once, namely the expansive force, originally
directionless, and thus capable of all directions. This force will thus be
able to pursue all these directions at once, but in every single line that
it describes will nevertheless be unalterably capable of following just
this one direction, so long as the negative force is not separated there
from; it will thus also operate in all directions only in the pure dimen
sion of length. As soon as the two forces are completely distinct, the
opposite will happen. For no sooner does point C shift (in the direction
CA, for example) than already, at the next position it occupies, it is
surrounded by innumerable points, to all of which it can move. The
expansive force, now wholly given over to its tendency to spread in all
directions, will therefore again throw out lines in all directions from
every point along line CA; these will form angles with CA and thus the
dimension of length will be supplemented by that of breadth. The
same, however, also holds of all the lines which point C, still supposed
stationary, radiates in the other directions, so that none of these lines
will now continue to represent mere length.
Now that this stage of construction will be represented in nature
by electricity, is evident from the fact that, unlike magnetism, the lat
ter does not act in merely linear fashion, seeking and guided by
length, but adds to the pure length of magnetism the dimension of
breadth, in that it spreads over the whole surface of a body to which it
is conveyed; yet no more acts in depth than does magnetism, since, as
we know, it seeks merely length and breadth.
c) As surely as the two now completely separated forces are
originally forces of one and the same point, so surely must their cleav
age occasion a striving in both for a return to unity. But this can
come about only by means of a third force, which can intervene
among the two opposed forces and in which these may interpenetrate.
This mutual interpenetration of the two forces by means of a third
first endows the product with impenetrability, and by this property
adds to the two earlier dimensions a third, namely thickness.
[448-50] Chemical Process and Galvanism 89
There will doubtless be no reader who in the course of our enquiry has
not made the following observation.
In the first epoch of self-consciousness we could distinguish
three acts, and these seem to reappear in the three forces of matter
and in the three stages of its construction. These three stages of con
struction give us three dimensions of matter, and these latter, three
levels in the dynamic process. It is very natural to hit upon the idea
that it is always just one and the same trinity that recurs among these
various forms. To develop this idea and gain a complete grasp of the
connection so far merely surmised, a comparison of the three acts of
the self with the three stages in the construction of matter will not be
devoid of usefulness.
Transcendental philosophy is nothing else but a constant raising
of the self to a higher power; its whole method consists in leading the
self from one level of self-intuition to another, until it is posited with
all the determinations that are contained in the free and conscious act
of self-consciousness.
The first act, from which the whole history of intelligence sets
forth, is the act of self-consciousness insofar as it is not free but still
unconscious. The same act, which the philosopher postulates from the
very outset, when thought without consciousness, yields the first act of
our object, the self.
In this act the self is for us, indeed, but not for itself, both sub
ject and object at once; it presents, as it were, that point we noted in
the construction of matter, at which the two activities, the originally
unlimited and the limitant, are still united.
The result of this act is again for us only, not for the self itself, a
limitation of the objective activity by the subjective. But the limiting
activity, as itself illimitable and acting at a distance, must necessarily
be thought of as striving out beyond the point of limitation.
In this first act, therefore, exactly the same determinations are
contained as those which also distinguish the first stage in the con
struction of matter.
In this act there really does occur a common construction out
of the self as object and as subject, but this construction does not
exist for the self itself. Hence we were driven on to a second act,
which is a self-intuiting of the self in this state of limitation. Since
the self cannot be aware of its limitation as having been posited by it
self, this intuiting is merely a finding, or sensing. Since, therefore,
the self is not conscious in this act of its own activity, whereby it is
limited, there is at once and immediately
[451-52] Mind and Matter 91
posited along with sensation—not for the self, but certainly for us—the
contrast between self and thing-in-itself.
Stated in other terms, this amounts to saying that in this second
act there is a separation—not for the self, but for us—of the two activi
ties originally united therein into two entirely different and mutually
external activities, namely into that of the self on the one hand, and
that of the thing on the other. The activities, which are originally
those of an identical subject, are divided between different subjects.
Hence it becomes clear that the second stage we assume in the
construction of matter, namely the stage where the two forces become
forces of different subjects, is exactly the same for physics as this sec
ond act of intelligence is for transcendental philosophy. It is also now
evident that already with the first and second acts a start has been
made with the construction of matter, or that the self, without know
ing it, is already from the first act onwards engaged, as it were, upon
the construction of matter.
A further remark, which shows us more closely yet the identity
of the dynamic and the transcendental, and affords us a glimpse of the
far-reaching interconnections stemming from the present point, is as
follows. This second act is the act of sensation. Now what, then, is it
that becomes an object to us through sensation? Nothing else but qual
ity. But all quality is simply electricity, a proposition that is demon
strated in natural philosophy. But electricity is precisely that
whereby we designate in nature this second stage in construction.
One might therefore say that what sensation is in the realm of intelli
gence, electricity is in nature.
The identity of the third act with the third stage of the construc
tion of matter really requires no proof. Thus it is obvious that in con
structing matter the self is in truth constructing itself. The third act
is that by means of which the self as sensing becomes an object to it
self. But this is incapable of derivation unless the two activities, so far
completely separated, are exhibited in one and the same identical
product. This product, namely matter, is thus a complete construction
of the self, though not for the self itself, which is still identical with
matter. If the self in the first act is intuited only as object, and in the
second only as subject, it now becomes objectified in the third act as
both at once—for the philosopher, of course, not for itself. For itself it
is objectified in this act as a subject only. That it appears merely as
matter is necessary, since in this act it admittedly is a subject-object,
but without intuiting itself as such.
92 System of Transcendental Idealism [452-54]
The concept of the self that the philosopher starts from is that of a
subject-object which is conscious of itself as such. Matter is not so con
scious, and through it, therefore, the self, likewise, does not become
objectified as a self. But now transcendental philosophy is completed
only when the self becomes an object to itselfjust as it does to the phi
losopher. Hence also the circuit of this science cannot be closed with
the present epoch.
The result of the comparison so far instituted is that the three
stages in the construction of matter really do correspond to the three
acts in the intelligence. So if these three phases of nature are actually
three stages in the history of self-consciousness, it is evident enough
that really all forces of the universe ultimately relate back to presents
tive forces, a principle underlying the idealism of Leibniz, which, prop
erly understood, does not in fact differ from transcendental idealism.
When Leibniz calls matter the sleeping state of monads, or when
Hemsterhuis speaks of it as congealed mind, there lies in these state
ments a meaning very easy to discern from the principles now put for
ward. Matter is indeed nothing else but mind viewed in an equilib
rium of its activities. There is no need to demonstrate at length how,
by means of this elimination of all dualism, or all real opposition be
tween mind and matter, whereby the latter is regarded merely as
mind in a condition of dullness, or the former, conversely, as matter
merely in becoming, a term is set to a host of bewildering enquiries
concerning the relationship of the two.
There is equally little need of any further discussion to show
that this view leads to far more elevated notions of the nature and dig
nity of matter than any others; for example, atomism, which con
structs matter out of atoms, without considering that we advance not a
step thereby towards its true nature, since the atoms themselves are
just matter.
The construction of matter deduced a priori provides the basis
for a general theory of natural phenomena, in which there is hope of
being able to dispense with all the hypotheses and fictions which an
atomistic physics will never cease to require. Before even the
atomistic physicist actually arrives at the explanation of a natural
phenomenon, he is obliged to make a mass of assumptions, e.g” con
cerning materials to which he assigns, quite arbitrarily and without
the smallest evidence, a multitude of properties, simply because he can
use just these and no others for his explanation. But once it is estab*
lished that the ultimate causes of natural phenomena can never be in
vestigated by the aid of experience, there is nothing for it but either to
[454] Mind and Matter 93
The first epoch closes with the selfs elevation to intelligence. The two
activities, wholly separated and located in quite different spheres, are,
by the third that intervenes upon them, again posited in one and the
same product. By this intervention in both of a third activity, the ac
tivity of the thing again also becomes an activity of the self, which, by
that very fact, is itself elevated into an intelligence.
But the self, in its intuitive capacity, is also completely fettered
and bound in its producing, and cannot be both intuitant and intuited
at once. The production is thus totally blind and unconscious. In ac
cordance with the now familiar method of transcendental philosophy,
the question now arises, therefore, how the self, which has so far been
intuitant and intelligent only for us, becomes this also for itself, or in
tuits itself as such. But now no ground whatever can be thought of,
which would determine the self to intuit itself as productive, unless in
the production itself there lies a ground whereby the ideal activity of
the self that is involved in producing is driven back upon itself, and is
thereby led to transcend the product. The question as to how the self
recognizes itself as productive is thus the same as asking how it is able
to tear itself free from its production and to transcend the latter.
Before embarking upon the solution of this problem itself, the
following remark will serve to give a preliminary idea of the content of
the next epoch.
The whole topic of our enquiry is simply the elucidation of self
consciousness. All acts of the self that we have so far derived, or will
derive henceforth, are but the intermediate stages through which
our object attains to self-consciousness. Self-consciousness itself is a
determinate act, and so all these intermediaries must also be determi
nate acts. But through every determinate act a determinate product
arises for the self. Now the selfs concern was not with the product,
but with itself. It seeks to intuit, not the product, but itself in the
product. Now it would, however, be possible, and is, as we shall soon
see, actually necessary, that in the very act of striving to intuit itself
in production the condition of a new product should arise for the self;
and so on indefinitely, were it not for the addition of a new and hith
erto unknown limitation, such that there is no
[455-56] Inner and Outer Intuition 95
seeing how the self, having once launched into production, should ever
again emerge from it, since the condition of all producing, and the
mechanism thereof, is constantly reinstated.
Hence, in trying to explain how the self gets clear of production,
we shall in fact involve our object in a whole series of productions. We
shall thus be able to resolve the main problem of this epoch only in a
very indirect fashion, and only so long as there will arise for our ob
ject, instead of what we sought, something entirely different, until we
finally break out of this circle, as it were, by an act of reflection occur
ring with absolute spontaneity. Between this point of absolute reflec
tion and the present point of consciousness there lies as an intermedi
ate stage the whole multiplicity of the objective world, its products and
phenomena.
Since our whole philosophy proceeds from the standpoint of in
tuition, not that of reflection, occupied, for instance, by Kant and his
philosophy, we shall also derive the now incipient series of acts of the
intelligence as acts, and not, say, as concepts of acts, or as categories.
For how these acts attain to reflection is the problem for a later epoch
of self-consciousness.
Solution
I
After the self has once become productive, we must renounce the idea
that it should intuit itself as a simple activity. But that it should in
tuit itself as producing, cannot be conceived unless directly through
production there should arise for it a further ideal activity, whereby it
intuits itself therein.
Thus it will meanwhile be assumed as a hypothesis merely, that
the self has an intuition of itself in its producing, in order thereby to
find the conditions of such an intuition. If these conditions are actu
ally to be found in consciousness, we shall thereupon conclude that
such an intuition does indeed take place, and will try to discover its
outcome.
The first thing we can establish in this matter is the
following: if the self is to intuit itself as
96 System of Transcendental Idealism [456-58]
merge into one. Outer sense begins at the point where inner sense
leaves ofE What appears to us as the object of outer sense is merely a
boundary point of inner sense, and hence both of them, outer and in
ner, are also in origin identical, for outer sense is merely inner sense
subjected to a limit. Outer sense is necessarily also inner, though by
contrast, inner is not necessarily also outer. All intuition is in prin
ciple intellectual, and hence the objective world is merely the intellec
tual world appearing under restrictions.
The outcome of the whole enquiry consists in the following. If
the self is to intuit itself as producing, inner and outer sense must
firstly part company therein, and secondly there must be a relation of
each to the other. The question at once arises, therefore, as to what
the relating factor of the two intuitions will be.
The relating factor is necessarily something common to both.
But now inner intuition had nothing in common with outer intuition
as such, though conversely, outer intuition certainly had something in
common with inner, for outer sense is also inner sense. Thus the re
lating factor of outer and inner sense is itself once more inner sense.
Here we first begin to grasp how the self may be able to arrive
at opposing outer and inner sense to itself, and at relating them to one
another. For this in fact would never happen, if the relating factor, in
ner sense, were not itself incorporated in outer intuition, as the sole
active and constructive principle therein; for if outer sense is inner
sense under limitation, we are obliged, in contrast, to posit inner
sense, as such, as originally illimitable. Inner sense is thus nothing
else but the illimitable tendency of the self, posited therein from the
very outset, to self-intuition; and at this point is distinguished only for
the first time as inner sense, and thus as the same activity which, in
the foregoing act, was immediately limited by its overstepping of the
boundary.
If the self is to recognize itself in outer intuition as
intuitant, it must needs relate outer intuition to the now reinstated
ideal intuition, which now appears, however, as inner intuition. But
the self is itself nothing other than this ideal intuition, for the simul
taneously ideal and real intuition is something quite different; hence
the relating element, and that to which it relates, will in this act be
one and the same. Now outer intuition could indeed be related to
inner, for the two are different and yet again there is a ground of
identity between them. But the self cannot relate outer intuition to
inner, qua inner, for it cannot in one and the same act relate outer
intuition to itself, and in doing so, simultaneously reflect
[460-61] Inner and Outer Intuition 99
again upon itself as the ground of relation. Thus it could not relate
outer intuition to inner, qua inner, for, according to presumption, it
would itself be nothing else but inner intuition; and were it to acknow
ledge inner intuition as such, it would have again to be something
other than this.
In the foregoing act, the self was a producer, but producer and
produced lapsed into one; the self and its object were one and the
same. We now seek an act in which the self shall recognize itself as
producing. If this were possible, no trace at all of an intuited would
evince itself in consciousness. But productive intuition, if it were rec
ognized, would be recognized as such only in contrast to inner intu
ition. But now inner intuition itself would not be acknowledged as in
ner, precisely because the self in this act would be nothing else but in
ner intuition, and hence even outer intuition could not be acknowl
edged as such, and since it can be recognized only as outer intuition, it
could not be acknowledged as intuition at all. There would accord
ingly be nothing left of this whole act in consciousness, save on the one
side the intuited (detached from the intuition) and on the other the
self as ideal activity, though this latter is now inner sense.
In empirical consciousness there is no trace whatever of an
outer intuition, qua act, nor should there be; it is, however, most im
portant to enquire how in such a consciousness the object and an inner
sense as yet unlimited and wholly free, for example, in the projecting
of schemata, etc., can coexist together. —The thing-in-itself likewise
makes no more appearance in consciousness than does the act of outer
intuition; repressed from consciousness by the sensory object, it is sim
ply an ideal explanatory ground of consciousness, and, like the acts of
the intelligence itself lies, for intelligence, beyond consciousness. As
ground of explanation, the thing-in-itself needs only a philosophy that
stands a few steps higher than empirical consciousness. Empiricism
will never ascend to this level. By the thing-in-itself, which he intro
duced into philosophy, Kant has at least provided the first impulse
which could carry philosophy beyond ordinary consciousness, and has
at least shown that the ground of the object that appears in conscious
ness cannot itself again lie in consciousness; but he never even consid
ered clearly, let alone explained, that this ground of explanation lying
beyond consciousness is in the end no more than our own ideal activ
ity, merely hypostatized into the thing-in-itself.
100 System of Transcendental Idealism [462-63]
in the real and objective sel£ The selfs passivity was limited by the
very fact that its ground was posited in a thing-in-itself^ which itself
was necessarily a limited affair. But that which is boundary for the
thing-in-itself (the ideal activity), is boundary of the passivity of the
real self, not its activity, for this is already restricted by the thing-in-
itself as such.
As to what the boundary of the thing may be, that question now
answers itself. Self and thing are so opposed, that what is passivity in
the one is activity in the other. So if the boundary limits the passivity
of the sel£ it necessarily sets a limit to the activity of the thing, and
only to that extent is it the common boundary of them both.
Thus the boundary, too, can only be recognized as such if it is
recognized as bounding the activity of the thing. The question arises,
how we are to conceive of this.
The boundary is to set limit to the activity of the thing, and it is
to be contingent, not only to the self merely, but equally so to the
thing. If it is contingent to the thing, the latter must originally, and in
and for itself, be unlimited activity. Hence the fact that the things ac
tivity is limited must be inexplicable from its own nature, and hence
explicable only from a ground external to it.
Where are we to look for this ground? In the self? But from our
present standpoint, this explanation will simply not do any longer.
That the self should unconsciously be the cause once more of this limi
tation of the thing (the ideal activity) and thereby of its own passiv
ity―that is, as will soon appear, of its own particular limitation—is
something of which the self itself can know nothing. So the ground of
limitation of the things activity, and hence indirectly of the limited
passivity of the self, can be sought by the self itself nowhere but in
something that now lies wholly outside consciousness> but yet inter
venes in the present phase of consciousness. As surely, therefore, as
the self must acknowledge the boundary as a boundary, so surely must
it also overstep the boundary, and seek its ground in something that
now no longer falls within consciousness. This unknown, which we
shall meanwhile describe as A, therefore lies necessarily beyond the
producing of the present object, which we may designate as A Thus
while the self was producing B, A must already have existed. So in the
present phase of consciousness, nothing can any longer be changed in
A; it is, so to speak, out of the hands of the self, for it lies beyond the
current act of the latter, and is unalterably determined for the sel£
Once A is posited, B too must be posited just so and no otherwise as it
is now in fact posited.
102 System of Transcendental Idealism [464-65]
fact, return. The common boundary of self and object, the ground of
the second limitation, forms the boundary between the present stage
and a past one. The feeling of being thus driven back to a stage that it
cannot in reality return to is the feeling of the present. Thus at the
first stage of its consciousness the self already finds itself trapped in a
present. For it cannot oppose the object to itself without feeling itself
restricted and committed, as it were, to a single point. This feeling is
no other than that which we describe as self-awareness. All conscious
ness begins with it, and by it the self first posits itself over against the
object.
In self-awareness, inner sense, that is, sensation combined with
consciousness, becomes an object to itself. It is for that very reason en
tirely different from sensation, into which there necessarily enters
something different from the self In the previous act, the self was in
ner sense, but without being so for itself.
But now hoiut then, does the self become an object to itself as in
ner sense? Simply and solely through the fact that time arises for it
(not time insofar as it is already externally intuited, but time as a
mere point, a mere limit). In that the self opposes to itself the object,
there arises for it the feeling of self-awareness, that is, it becomes an
object to itself as pure intensity, as activity which can extend itself
only in one dimension, but is at present concentrated at a single point;
but in fact this unidimensionally extensible activity, when it becomes
an object to itself, is time. Time is not something that flows indepen
dently of the self; the self itself is time conceived of in activity.
Now since in this act the self opposes to itself the object, the lat
ter will have to appear to it as the negation of all intensity, that is, will
have to appear to it as pure extensity.
Thus the self cannot oppose the object to itself without inner and
outer intuition not only separating themselves within the self, but also
becoming, as such, objects.
But now the intuition whereby inner sense becomes an object to
itself is time (though we are speaking here of pure time, i.e., time in its
total independence of space); the intuition whereby outer sense be
comes an object to itself is space* Hence the self cannot oppose the ob
ject to itself without on the one hand inner sense becoming an object to
it, through time, and on the other, outer sense becoming an object,
through space.
Ill
In the first construction of the object, inner and outer sense were
involved together. The object appears as
104 System of Transcendental Idealism [467-68]
pure extensity only when outer sense becomes objectified to the self,
because it is in fact inner sense itself to which outer sense is objecti
fied; hence the two can no longer be united, which was not so, how
ever, in the original construction. Thus the object is neither merely
inner nor merely outer sense, but both of them at once, in such a way
that each is reciprocally restricted by the other.
Hence, to determine the object more accurately than hitherto as
the union of both forms of intuition, we must distinguish still more
strictly than has yet been done the opposing members of the synthesis.
So what, then, is inner sense, and what is outer—both consid
ered in their unrestricted form?
Inner sense is nothing else but the selfs activity driven back
into itself. If we consider inner sense as absolutely unrestricted by
outer, the self will be in its highest state of feeling, its whole illimit
able activity concentrated, as it were, upon a single point. If, on the
contrary, we consider outer sense as unrestricted by inner, it will be
the absolute negation of all intensity, the self will be wholly dissolved,
there will be no resistance therein.
Inner sense, considered in its unrestrictedness, will thus be rep
resented by the point, the absolute boundary, or by the image of time
in its independence of space. For time, considered in and for itself is
merely the absolute boundary, and hence the first synthesis of time
with space, which so far, however, has not yet been derived at all, can
be expressed only by the line, or by the expanded point.
The opposite of the point, or absolute extensity, is the negation
of all intensity, uiz., infinite spacet likewise the dissolved self.
Hence, in the object itself, that is, in producing, space and time
can only arise together and unseparated from each other. Both are
opposed to each other, precisely because they mutually restrict each
other. Both, for themselves, are equally infinite, though in opposing
senses. Time becomes finite only through space, space only through
time. That one becomes finite through the other means that one is de
termined and measured through the other. Hence the most basic mea
sure of time is the space traversed by a uniformly moving body
therein, and the most basic measure of space is the time that a uni
formly moving body requires in order to traverse it. Both therefore
show themselves as absolutely inseparable.
But now space is nothing else but objectified outer sense,
and time nothing else but objectified inner sense, so what holds
of space and time is also true of outer and inner sense. The object
is outer sense determined
[468-69] Space and Time 105
by inner. Extensity is thus not merely spatial size in the object, but
extensity determined by intensity, in a word, what we call force. For
the intensity of a force can only be measured by the space in which it
can diffuse itself without becoming equal to zero. Just as, conversely,
this space is again determined by the size of that force for inner sense.
So what corresponds in the object to inner sense is intensity, and what
corresponds to outer, extensity. But intensity and extensity are mutu
ally determined by each other. The object is nothing else but fixated,
merely present time, and yet time is fixed simply and solely by the
space that is occupied, and the occupancy of space is determined sim
ply and solely by the amount of time, which is not itself in space but is
extensione prior. So that which determines the occupancy of space has
a mere existence in time, and that which, conversely, fixes time has a
mere existence in space. But now that in the object which has mere
existence in time, is precisely that whereby the object belongs to inner
sense, and the magnitude of the object for inner sense is determined
solely by the common boundary of inner and outer sense, which
boundary appears as absolutely contingent. Hence that in the object
which corresponds to inner sense, or has magnitude merely in time,
will appear as the absolutely contingent or accidental; while that, on
the other hand, which corresponds in the object to outer sense, or has
magnitude in space, will appear as the necessary or the substantial.
Hence, just as the object is extensity and intensity at once, so likewise
is it also substance and accident at once; both are inseparable therein,
and only through both together is the object completed.
That which is substance in the object has only magnitude in
space, and that which is accident, magnitude only in time. Time is
fixed through the occupancy of space, and space occupied in determi
nate fashion through magnitude in time.
If now, armed with this result, we return to the question from
which this enquiry began, the outcome is as follows. —The self was
obliged to oppose the object to itself in order to recognize it as an ob
ject, But in this opposition, outer and inner sense became objects for
the self, that is, for us, as philosophers, space and time could be distin
guished in the self, and substance and accident in the object. —That
substance and accident were distinguishable therefore rested simply
on the fact that the one has only being in time ascribed to it, and the
other only being in space. Only through the accidents of intuition is
the self restricted to time as such, for substance, since it only has be
ing in space, also has a being wholly independent of time, and leaves
the intelligence wholly unrestricted in regard to time.
106 System of Transcendental Idealism [469-71]
Since, then, in this manner, and through the act of the self de
duced in the foregoing, space and time have become, for the philoso
pher, distinguishable in the self, and substance and accident in the ob~
jectt we now ask} according to our established method, how space and
time, and thereby substance and accident, also become distinguishable
for the self itself!
Time is merely inner sense becoming an object to itself, and
space is outer sense becoming an object thereto. Thus if both are
again to become objects, this can only take place through a higher,
that is, a productive, intuition. Both are intuitions of the self, which
can only again become objects to the self inasmuch as they emerge out
of the self. Now what do we mean by “out of the self? The self at the
present juncture is simply inner sense. So what is out of the self is
that which exists only for outer sense. Space and time alike can thus
become objects to the self only through production, that is, since the
self has stopped producing (being now merely inner sense), only
through the fact that it now starts producing again. —But now in this
producing space and time, no less than inner and outer sense, are syn
thetically united. Hence even by this second producing we should
have gained nothing: we should again stand towards it precisely as
we stood with the first, unless, say, this second producing were op
posed to the first, so that by means of this opposition to the first it im
mediately became an object to the self. —But that the second produc
ing should be opposed to the first is conceivable only if the first is in
some sense restrictive of the second. —Hence, that the self as such
should start producing again can in no case have its ground in the first
producing, for this is merely the restricting factor of the second, and
presupposes something to be restricted, or a material for restriction;
the ground must lie, rather, in the intrinsic infinitude of the self.
The first producing cannot therefore be the ground of a transi
tion from present producing to a subsequent one on the part of the self
as such, but only of the fact that the succeeding object is produced
with this particular degree of limitation. In a word, only the acciden
tal features in the second producing can be determined by the first.
We designate the first producing as B, and the second as C. Now ifB
contains only the ground of the accidental in C, it can only be some
thing accidental in B whereby that in C is determined. For that C is
limited byB in this particular manner is possible only ifB itself is lim
ited in a particular way, that is, by virtue merely of that which is acci
dental inB itself.
To facilitate the enquiry, and so that its goal
[471-72] Causality 107
will be seen right away, let it be observed that we are approaching the
deduction of the causal relation. Since this is in fact a point from
whence it is easier than in many other cases to discern the manner in
which categories are deduced in transcendental idealism, we may be
permitted to prefix a general remark about our procedure.
We deduce the causal relation as the necessary condition under
which alone the self can recognize the present object as an object. If
the presentation in intelligence as such were static, if time remained
fixed, the intelligence would not only contain no manifold of presenta
tions (as would, of course, be the case), but even the present object
would not be recognized as present either.
The succession in the causal relation is a necessary one. From
the very outset there can be no thought of an arbitrary succession
among presentations. The choice which occurs, for example, in con
struing the individual parts of a whole as those of an organism or an
artifact, is itself ultimately grounded in a causal relation. Whatever
part of the former I start from, I shall always be driven back from one
to another, and from this one to that, because in an organism every
thing is reciprocally cause and effect. Admittedly, this is not the case
with an artifact, for here no part is cause of another, but each in fact
presupposes the other in the productive understanding of the maker.
So is it everywhere, where otherwise the succession of presentations
appears arbitrary, for example, in construing the individual parts in
inorganic nature, in which there is likewise a general interplay of all
the parts.
All categories are modes of action, whereby objects themselves
first come about for us. There is no object for the intelligence in the
absence of a causal relation, and the relation is for that very reason
inseparable from objects. If we judge that A is the cause of J3, this is to
say that the succession occurring between them is not only present in
my thoughts t but lies in the objects themselves. Neither A nor B could
exist at all, if they were not in this relation. Here, therefore, we have
not only succession as such, but a succession that is the condition of
the objects themselves. Now what, then, in idealism, can be under
stood by this contrast between that which exists in thought merely,
and that which exists in the objects themselves? That the succession
is objective, means, for the idealist, that its ground lies, not in my free
and conscious thinking, but in my unconscious act of producing. That
the ground of this succession does not lie in us means that we are not
conscious of this succession before it takes place; its occurrence and
108 System of Transcendental Idealism [472-73]
the awareness thereof are one and the same. The succession must
come before us as inseparable from the appearances, just as the ap
pearances present themselves as inseparable from the succession. For
experience, therefore, the result is the same, whether the succession
be linked to the things, or the things to the succession. The judgment
of common sense is merely that both are absolutely inseparable. It is
thus in fact completely illogical to attribute the succession to an act of
the intelligence, while the objects, by contrast, are held to arise inde
pendently thereof. At least we should proclaim both, the succession no
less than the objects, to be equally independent of our presentations.
Let us revert to the connection. We now have two objects, B and
C. And what, in fact, was B? It was substance and accident insepara
bly united. So far as it is substance, it is nothing else but fixated time
itself, for by the fact that time is fixed for us, substance arises for us,
and vice versa. So if there is also a sequence in time, substance itself
must again be that which persists through time. And substance, ac
cordingly, can neither come to be nor pass away. It cannot come into
being, for if we posit something as doing so, a moment must have pre
ceded in which it did not yet exist; but that moment must itself have
been fixed, and so in it there must have been something that persisted.
Hence, what now comes into being is only a determination of the per
manent, not the permanent itself, which is always the same. Equally
little can substance disappear, for if something disappears, a perma
nent of some kind must remain behind, whereby the moment of disap
pearance is fixed. Hence that which disappeared was not the perma
nent itself, but merely a determination thereof.
If therefore, no object can engender or abolish the substance of
another, it will in fact be only the accidental in the subsequent object
that can be determined by the preceding one, and conversely, it will be
only the accidental in the later object whereby the accidental in the
first is determined.
Now in that B determines something accidental in C, substance
and accident are separated in the object; substance persists, while the
accidents change—space abides, while time passes, and so both become
objects to the self in separation. But by this very fact the self also
finds itself translated into a new condition, namely into that of an in
voluntary succession of presentations, and it is to this state that our
reflection must now turn.
<(The accidental inB contains the ground of an accidental
in C.M —This, however, is known only to us, who contemplate
the self. But now the intelligence
[473-75] Causality as Succession 109
itself must also recognize the accidental in B as the ground for that in
C; yet this is not possible unless both B and C are opposed in one and
the same act, and again related to one another. That they are both op
posed is obvious, for B is repressed from consciousness by C and re
treats into time past; B is the cause, C the effect, B the restricting fac
tor, C the restricted. But how both can be related to each other is not
intelligible, since the self is now nothing else but a succession of pri
mary presentations, of which one represses another. (On the same
grounds whereby the self is driven from B to C, it will also be driven
from C to Dt and so on.) Now it was indeed established that only acci
dents can come and go, not substances. But then what is substance? It
is itself no more than the fixation of time. Hence even substances can
not endure (for the self, needless to say, since the question how sub
stances may somehow persist for themselves is wholly without mean
ing); for time is now not fixated at all, but in flux (again, not in itself,
but only for the self), and so substances cannot be fixated, since the self
itself is not fixed, being now nothing save this succession itself.
This state of the intelligence, in which it is just a succession of
presentations, is in fact a merely intermediate condition, assumed
therein only by the philosopher, since it necessarily passes through this
state into the following*
Assuredly, substances must endure, if an opposition between C
and B is to be possible. It is, however, impossible for the succession to
be fixed unless it be through the very fact that opposing directions en
ter into it. The succession has but one direction. This one direction,
abstracted from the succession, is what constitutes time, which, out
wardly intuited, has but one dimension.
But opposing directions could enter into the succession only if the
self, while it is driven from B to C, is simultaneously driven back again
uponB; for then the opposing directions will cancel one another, the
succession will be fixated, and thereby also the substances. But now
the self can undoubtedly be driven back from C to B only in a manner
similar to that whereby it was driven from B to C. Exactly, that is, as
B contained the ground of a determination in C, so must C, in turn,
contain the ground of a determination in R But now this determina
tion in B cannot have existed before C did, for the accidental in C is
supposed} after all, to contain the ground of it; C, however, arises for
the self as this particular determinate only at the present moment. C
as a substance may, indeed, have already existed previously, but of this
the self knows nothing just now; C arises for it absolutely in arising
110 System of Transcendental Idealism [475-76]
far been given whereby the producing itself should again be limited,
the intelligence is repeatedly carried away in the stream of succession.
So how it arrives at accepting a simultaneity of aZZ substances in the
world, that is, a universal reciprocity, is not yet explained thereby.
Along with reciprocity, the concept of coexistence is also simulta
neously derived. All simultaneity occurs only through an act of the
intelligence, and coexistence is merely the condition of the primordial
succession of our presentations. Substances are nothing distinct from
coexistence. That they are fixated as substances means that coexist
ence is posited, and conversely, coexistence is nothing else but a
mutual fixating of substances by one another. If now this act of the
intelligence is reproduced ideally, that is, with consciousness, there
arises for me thereby space, as the mere form of coexistence or simul
taneity. In general, it is first through the category of reciprocity that
space becomes the form of coexistence; under the category of substance
it emerges only as the form of extensity. Thus space itself is nothing
else but an act of the intelligence. We can define space as time sus
pended, and time, by contrast, as space in flux. In space, regarded on
its own account, everything is merely concurrent, just as in time,
rendered objective, everything is sequential. Hence both, space and
time, can become objects only in succession as such, since in the latter
space is static, while time flows. Synthetically united, both space and
time, rendered objective, are manifested in reciprocity. Simultaneity
is, in fact, this union; adjacency in space is transformed, once the
determination of time is added, into a simultaneity. And so too, once
the determination of space is added, with successiveness in time.—
Time alone has a fundamental direction, though the point which gives
it direction lies in the infinite; but precisely because it has this basic
direction, only one direction is in fact distinguished therein. Space
originally has no direction, for in it all directions mutually cancel one
another; as the ideal substrate of all succession it is itself absolute
rest, absolute want of intensity, and to that extent nothing. —What
has hitherto made philosophers doubtful in regard to space is simply
that it possesses all the predicates of nothing, and yet cannot be
regarded as nothing. Precisely because space originally has no direc
tion, every direction is contained in it, when once direction has en
tered into it at all. But now in virtue merely of the causal relation
there is but one direction; I can only go from A to B, and not back
again from B to A, and it is not until we introduce the category of
reciprocity that all directions become equally possible.
112 System of Transcendental Idealism [477-78]
between the absolute and the finite intelligence, and serves at the
same time as a new proof that, without knowing it, we have already
displaced the self and its producing into the second or determinate
form of limitation. The more exact working-out of this relationship is
as follows.
That a universe, ie, a universal interplay of substances, exists
at all, is necessary, if the self as such is originally restricted. In virtue
of this original restrictedness, or, what comes to the same, in virtue
of the original conflict of self-consciousness, the universe arises for
the self, not gradually, but through one absolute synthesis. But this
original or primary restrictedness, which assuredly can be explained
from self-consciousness, does not explain for me the particular re
strictedness which can no longer be explained from self-consciousness,
and to that extent is therefore not explicable at all. The particular,
or, as we shall also call it in future, the secondary restrictedness, is
precisely that by virtue of which the intelligence, at the very outset
of empirical consciousness, must appear to itself as in a present, as
held fast in a particular moment of the time series. Now what
emerges in this series of the second restrictedness is all posited al
ready through the first, only with this difference, that by the latter
everything is posited at once, and the absolute synthesis arises for
the self, not by an assemblage out of parts, but as a whole; nor does
it arise in time, for all time is first posited through that synthesis,
whereas in empirical consciousness the whole in question can only be
engendered through a gradual synthesis of parts, and so only through
successive presentations. Now insofar as the intelligence is not in
time, but is eternal, it is nothing else but that absolute synthesis itself,
and to that extent has neither begun, nor can it cease, to produce; but
insofar as the intelligence is limited, it can also appear only as inter
vening upon the successive series at a particular point. Not indeed,
as if the infinite intelligence were different from the finite, and as
though there existed an infinite intelligence outside, as it were, the fi
nite one. For if I take away the particular restrictedness of the finite
intelligence, it is the absolute intelligence itself If I posit this
restrictedness, the absolute intelligence is by that very fact suspended
as absolute, and is now a merely finite one. Nor is the relationship to
be pictured as though the absolute synthesis and this incursion upon
a particular point in its evolution were two different acts; rather it is
that in one and the same original act there arises at once for the
intelligence both the universe, and the particular point of
116 System of Transcendental Idealism [482-83]
rv
In the succession above described, the intelligence has to do,
not with the succession, for the latter is wholly involuntary, but
rather with itself. It seeks
[489-90] Deduction of the Organic 121
itself, but in so doing actually flees from itself. Once it has been dis
placed into this succession, it can no longer intuit itself otherwise than
as active in the succession. But now we have already deduced a self
intuition of the intelligence within the succession, by way, that is, of
reciprocity. But hitherto we have been able to make reciprocity intelli
gible only as a relative, not as an absolute synthesis or intuition of the
whole succession of presentations. It is now utterly beyond concep
tion, how the whole succession can become an object unless a limiting
of the succession is to take place.
Here, therefore, we see ourselves driven into a third phase of
limitation, which thrusts the intelligence into a sphere still narrower
than any of the preceding, but one we must put up with, if only in or
der to postulate. The first restriction of the self was that it became an
intelligence at all; the second, that it had to start out from a present
moment, or could intervene only at a particular point in the succes
sion. Though from that point at least, the series could proceed to in
finity. But now if this infinitude is not in turn restricted, there is ab
solutely no seeing how the intelligence may step out from its own pro
ducing and intuit itself as productive. Hitherto, the intelligence and
the succession itself have been one; now it must oppose the succession
to itself, in order to intuit itself therein. The succession, however,
runs only to change among the accidents, whereas the intuiting of the
succession requires that the substantial element therein be intuited as
persisting. But the substantial element in this infinite succession is
nothing else save the absolute synthesis itself, which did not come to
be, but is eternal. The intelligence, though, has no intuition of the ab
solute synthesis, that is, of the universe, unless the latter become fi
nite to it. The intelligence, therefore, is also unable to intuit the suc
cession unless the universe comes to be limited for it in intuition.
But now the intelligence can no more cease to produce than it
can cease to be an intelligence. Hence this succession of presentations
will not be capable of limitation for it, unless it be again an infinite
succession within this limitation. To make this clear at once, there
is in the external world a constant sequence of changes, which do
not, however, lose themselves in the infinite, but are restricted to a
specific circle, into which they constantly revert. This sequence of
changes is thus at once both finite and infinite; finite, because it
never oversteps a certain limit; infinite, because it constantly
returns back into itself. The circular line is the original synthesis
of finitude and infinity, into which even the straight line must
122 System of Transcendental Idealism [490-91]
and even touch, that is, receptivity for the immediately present, is
scarcely operative. —What we call sensation in animals does not refer,
say, to a power of acquiring presentations through impressions from
without, but merely to their relationship with the universe, which may
be broader or more confined. But the view we have to take of animals
as such may be gathered from this, that through them there is desig
nated in nature that stage of consciousness at which our deduction
presently stands. —If we move upwards in the scale of organization,
we find that the senses gradually develop in that order in which, by
means of them, the world of the organizations is enlarged.1 The sense
of hearing, for example, appears far earlier, since by means of it the
world of the organism is extended only to a very short distance. The
godlike sense of vision is much later to emerge, since by means of it
the world is expanded to an extent which even the imagination is un
able to encompass. Leibniz betrays so great a reverence for light that
for this reason alone he attributes higher presentations to animals,
that they are receptive to light-impressions. Although even where this
sense, with its associated structures, appears, it remains always un
certain how far the sense itself extends, and whether even for the
highest organizations the light is not simply light.
3. Organization as such is succession hampered and, as it were,
coagulated in its course, But now the intelligence was to intuit, not
merely the succession of its presentations as such, but itself, and
itself as active in the succession. If it is to become an object to itself
as active in the succession (externally, of course, for the intelligence
is now merely outwardly intuitant), it must intuit the succession as
sustained by an inner principle of activity. But now the internal suc
cession, outwardly intuited, is motion. Hence the intelligence will be
able to intuit itself only in an object that has an internal principle of
motion within itself. But an object such as this is said to be alive.
Hence the intelligence must intuit itself, not merely qua organization
as such, but as a living organization. But now it appears from this
very deduction of life, that the latter must be common to all organic
nature, and hence that there can be no distinction between living and
nonliving organizations in nature itself Since the intelligence is to
intuit itself as active in the successions throughout the whole of or
ganic nature, every organization must also possess life in the wider
sense of the word, that is, must have an inner principle of
motion within itself. The life in question may well be more or less re
stricted; the question, therefore: whence this distinction? reduces itself
to the previous one: whence the graduated sequence in organic na
ture?
But this scale of organization merely refers to different stages in
the evolution of the universe. Precisely as the intelligence, by means
of the succession, constantly tries to depict the absolute synthesis, so
likewise will organic nature constantly appear as struggling towards
universal organism and at war against an inorganic nature. The
bounds of the succession in the presentations of the intelligence will
also be the bounds of organization. But now there must be an absolute
boundary to the intuiting of the intelligence; this boundary, for us, is
light. For although it extends our sphere of intuition almost into the
immeasurable, the light-boundary cannot be the boundary of the uni
verse, and it is no mere hypothesis that beyond the world of light there
shines with a radiance unknown to us a world which no longer falls
within the sphere of our intuition. —So now if the intelligence intuits
the evolution of the universe, so far as this falls within its intuition, in
terms of an organization) it will intuit this latter as identical with its
own self. For it is the intelligence itself, which through all the laby
rinths and convolutions of organic nature seeks to reflect back itself as
productive. But in none of the subordinate organizations is the world
of the intelligence depicted to the full. Only on attaining to the most
perfect organization, into which its entire world contracts, will it rec
ognize this organization as identical with itself. Hence the intelligence
will appear to itself, not merely qua organic as such, but as standing
at the summit of organization. It can regard the other organizations
only as intermediate stages, throughout which the most perfect gradu
ally extricates itself from the fetters of matter, or by way of which it
becomes completely an object to itself. Hence also it will not concede
to the other organizations a like dignity with its own.
The limit of its world, or what comes to the same, the limit of the
succession of its presentations, is also, for the intelligence, the limit of
organization. Hence, what we have called the third restrictedness
consists in the fact that the intelligence must appear to itself as an or
ganic individual. Through the necessity of intuiting itself as an or
ganic individual its world, for it, becomes wholly limited, and con
versely, through the fact that the succession of its presentations is a
limited one, it itself becomes an organic individual.
4. The basic character of organization is that,
126 System of Transcendental Idealism [495-96]
V
From the relationship, now wholly deduced, of the intelligence to the
organism, it is evident that in the present stage of consciousness the
intelligence is absorbed in its organism, which it intuits as wholly
identical with itself, and so once more fails to attain to intuition of it
self.
But now at the same time, owing to the fact that
130 System of Transcendental Idealism [500-1]
its whole world is drawn together, for the intelligence, in the organ
ism, the circle of production is closed for it. So the last act whereby
complete consciousness is posited in the intelligence (and to find this
was our only task; everything else which occurred in solving this prob
lem arose for us only incidentally, as it were, and with no more inten
tion than for the intelligence itself), must fall altogether outside the
sphere of producing; that is, the intelligence itself must break away
entirely from producing if consciousness is to come about, which can
undoubtedly occur once more only through a series of acts. Now be
fore we are able to derive these acts themselves, it is necessary to have
at least a general acquaintance with the sphere covering those acts
which are opposed to producing. For that such acts must be opposed
to producing is already to be inferred from the fact that they are to set
limits thereto.
We ask, therefore, whether perchance in the foregoing se
quence, any act opposed to producing has emerged for us? —In deduc
ing the series of productions whereby the self gradually arrived at in
tuiting itself as productive, we certainly found no activity whereby the
intelligence divorced itself utterly from producing, though the positing
of every derived product in the intelligence's own consciousness could
indeed be explained only through a constant reflecting of the intelli
gence upon the produced; save only that through every act of reflec
tion the condition of a new producing arose for us. In order to explain
the progressive sequence in producing, we therefore had to posit an
activity in our object, whereby it strives on beyond every individual
act of producing, though the very effect of its so doing is to involve it
repeatedly in new productions. We can therefore know in advance
that the series of acts we have now postulated belongs in the sphere of
reflection as such.
But producing is now at an end for the intelligence, so that it
cannot return into that sphere by any new act of reflection. The re
flecting that we shall now deduce must therefore be entirely different
from that which constantly ran parallel to the act of producing; and if,
indeed, as is perfectly possible, it should be necessarily accompanied
by a producing, this producing, in opposition to the necessary sort will
be a free one. And conversely, if the reflection that accompanied pro
duction without consciousness was a necessary one, so much the more
will that which we now seek be a free one. By means of it the intelli
gence will set limits, not simply to its own individual producing, but to
producing absolutely and as such.
The contrast between producing and reflecting will become
most apparent in that what we have hitherto
[501-3] Self and Thing-in-itself 131
in its passivity. Through the opposition between ideal and real activ
ity as such the first restrictedness is posited; while through the mea
sure or limit of this opposition, which, no sooner is it recognized as
opposition, as happens, in fact, in productive intuition, than it must
necessarily be a determinate opposition, the second restrictedness is
posited.
Thus without knowing it, the self, immediately on becoming pro
ductive, was subjected to the second form of restriction, that is, even
its ideal activity became limited. For the intrinsically illimitable self
this second restrictedness must necessarily be absolutely contingent.
That it is absolutely contingent means that it has its ground in an ab
solutely free action of the self itself. The objective self is bounded in
this particular fashion, because the ideal self has acted in just this par
ticular way. But that it should have acted thus itself presupposes al
ready a determinacy in the latter. Hence this second limit must ap
pear to the self as at once dependent on, and independent of, its activ
ity. This contradiction is soluble only on the assumption that this sec
ond restrictedness is merely a present one, and thus must have its
ground in a past act of the self. Insofar as we reflect on the fact that
the boundary is a present one, it is independent of the self; insofar as
we reflect on the fact that it exists at all, it is posited through an act of
the self itself. This restrictedness of the ideal activity can thus appear
to the self only as a restrictedness of the present; thus immediately
through the fact that the self comes to have sensitivity with conscious
ness, time arises for it as an absolute limit, whereby it becomes an ob
ject to itself as having sensation with consciousness, that is, as inner
sense. But now in the preceding act (that of producing) the self was
not merely inner sense, but—though this is admittedly visible only to
the philosopher―both inner and outer sense at once, for it has at once
both ideal and real activity. Hence it cannot become an object to itself
as inner sense without outer sense simultaneously becoming an object
to it, and if the former is intuited as an absolute boundary, the latter
can be intuited only as activity infinite in all directions.
As an immediate result, therefore, of the bounding of the ideal
activity in production, inner sense becomes an object to the self
through time in its independence from space, and outer sense an ob
ject through space in its independence from time; both, therefore, en
ter consciousness, not as intuitions, of which the self cannot become
conscious, but merely as items intuited.
But now time and space themselves must again become
objects for the self, which constitutes the second
[504] Categories and Production 133
In the series of synthetic acts that have so far been derived, we have
encountered none whereby the self might have arrived directly at a
consciousness of its own activity. But now since the circle of synthetic
acts is closed and totally exhausted by the foregoing deductions, the
act or series of acts, whereby consciousness of the derived is posited in
the self itself, cannot be synthetic, but only analytic in nature. The
standpoint of reflection is therefore identical with that of analysist and
from it, accordingly, no act can be found in the self which has not al
ready been posited synthetically therein. But how the self itself at
tains to the standpoint of reflection is something that has neither been
explained until now, nor is perhaps explicable at all in theoretical phi
losophy. In discovering that act whereby reflection is posited in the
sel£ the synthetic thread will again be united, and from that point on
will undoubtedly extend into the infinite.
Since the intelligence, so long as it is intuitant, is one with the
intuited and in no way distinct therefrom, it will be unable to arrive at
any intuition of itself through the products until it has separated itself
from the products; and since in itself it is nothing else but the determi
nate mode of action whereby the object arises, it will be able to arrive
at itself only by separating its acting as such from that which arises
for it in this acting, or, what comes to the same, from the items pvo-
duced.
Till now we have been quite unable to tell whether such a sepa
ration in the intelligence is possible at all, or whether it occurs; assum
ing that it does, the question is, what will the intelligence contain?
This separating of the act from the product is referred to in ordi
nary usage as abstraction, which therefore appears as the first condi
tion of reflection. So long as the intelligence is nothing distinct from
its acting, no consciousness thereof is possible. Through abstraction it
self it becomes something different from its producing, which latter,
for that very reason, however, can now no longer appear as an acting,
but only as a product.
But now the intelligence> i.e., this acting, and the object are
originally one. The object is this particular one, because the intelli
gence has produced precisely thus and not otherwise. The object on
the one hand, and the acting of the intelligence on the
[506-7] Objects External to the Self 135
other, since they both exhaust each other and are alike in all respects,
will thus again coincide in one and the same consciousness. —That
which arises for us, when we separate the acting as such from the out
come, is called the concept. The question as to how our concepts con
form to objects has therefore no meaning from a transcendental view
point, inasmuch as this question presupposes an original difference be
tween the two. In the absence of consciousness, the object and its con
cept, and conversely, concept and object, are one and the same, and
the separation of the two first occurs with the emergence of conscious
ness. A philosophy which starts from consciousness will therefore
never be able to explain this conformity, nor is it explicable at all with
out an original identity, whose principle necessarily lies beyond con
sciousness.
In producing as such, where the object still has no existence
whatever as an object, the act itself is identical with what arises
therein. This state of the self can be elucidated by reference to similar
cases, where no external object as such makes entry into con
sciousness, although the self does not cease to produce or intuit. In
sleep, for example, the original producing is not suspended; it is a state
of free reflection, simultaneously interrupted by the consciousness of
individuality. Object and intuition are completely lost in each other,
and for that very reason neither one nor the other exists in the intelli
gence for itself. The intelligence, were it not everything solely for it
self, would in this state be intuitant for an intelligence outside itself,
but it is not so for itself, and therefore is not so at all. Such is the state
of our object, as so far derived.
So long as the act of producing does not become an object to us,
uncontaminated by and separated from the product, everything exists
only within us, and without this separation we should indeed believe
that we intuited everything purely in ourselves. For that we must
intuit objects in space still does not explain the fact that we intuit
them outside ourselves, since we could also intuit space purely within
us, and originally we do indeed intuit it purely in ourselves. The
intelligence is present where it intuits; how, then, does it now come to
intuit objects outside itself? There is no seeing why the whole of the
external world does not appear to us in the manner of our organism,
in which we believe ourselves to be immediately present wherever we
have sensation. Just as, even after external things have detached
themselves from us, we do not as a rule intuit our organism as in any
way outside us, unless it is distinguished from us by a special abstrac
tion, so also we could not view objects as distinct from us
136 System of Transcendental Idealism [507-8]
object wants only the specific region of space wherein the latter is lo
cated. The schema, by contrast, is not a presentation determinate in
all its aspects, but merely an intuition of the rule whereby a specific
object can be brought forth. It is an intuition, and so not a concept, for
it is that which links the concept with the object. But nor is it an intu
ition of the object itself, being merely an intuition of the rule whereby
such an object can be brought forth.
The nature of the schema can be explained most clearly from the
example of the craftsman, who has to fashion an object of specific form
in accordance with a concept. What can be conveyed to him, in effect,
is the concept of the object, but it is utterly inconceivable that, without
any external pattern, the form associated with the concept should
gradually emerge under his hands, if he did not have an inner,
though sensorily intuited rule, which guides him in the making. This
rule is the schema, which contains nothing in any way individual, and
is equally little to be identified with a general concept, whereby an art
ist could create nothing. Following this schema, he will first bring
forth merely a raw sketch of the whole, proceeding from thence to the
fashioning of the individual parts, until gradually, in his inner intu
ition, the schema approximates to the image, which again accompanies
him, until simultaneously with the fully emergent determination of
the image, the work of art itself is also brought to completion.
In the commonest exercise of the understanding, the schema fig
ures as the general link whereby we recognize any object as of a cer
tain sort. If, as soon as I see a triangle, of whatever kind you please, I
judge in the same moment that this figure is a triangle, that presup
poses the intuition of a triangle as such, which is neither obtuse nor
acute nor right-angled, and would be no more possible by means of a
mere concept of a triangle than by means of a mere image thereof; for
since the latter is necessarily a determinate thing, the congruence of
the actual with the merely imagined triangle, if it were to occur, would
be purely fortuitous, which is insufficient for the formation of a judg
ment.
We may infer from this very necessity of a schematism, that the
whole mechanism of language will rest upon it. Suppose, for example,
that a man wholly unacquainted with technical concepts knows only
certain specimens or particular strains of a given animal; neverthe
less, as soon as he sees an individual of a strain as yet unknown to
him within this species, he will still judge that it belongs to that type;
he cannot do this by means of a general concept, for whence,
138 System of Transcendental Idealism [510-11]
mode of action whereby the particular object arises, but the mode of
action whereby the object as such comes into being.
intuiting. In the original intuition both are united. Hence if, by the
higher abstraction, which in contrast to empirical abstraction we wish
to call transcendental, everything conceptual is to be removed from in
tuition, the latter becomes, as it were, free, for all restrictedness enters
it only through the concept. Divested of the latter, intuiting therefore
becomes an undetermined act, completely and in every respect.
If intuition becomes wholly indeterminate, absolutely without
concepts, nothing else remains of it save the general intuiting itself,
which, if it is itself intuited once more, is space.
Space is conceptless intuiting, and thus in no way a concept that
might have been first abstracted, say, from the relationships of things;
for although space arises for me through abstraction, it is still no ab
stract concept either in the sense that categories are, or in the sense
that empirical or specific concepts are; for if there was a specific con
cept of space, there would have to be many spaces, instead of which
there is but one infinite space, which is presupposed by every limita
tion in space, that is, by every individual space. Since space is merely
an intuiting throughout, it is necessarily also an intuiting into the infi
nite, such that even the smallest part of space is still itself an intuit
ing, that is, a space and not, say, a mere boundary; and this alone is
the basis for the infinite divisibility of space. Geometry, although it
draws all its proofs solely from intuition, and yet does so no less gener
ally than from concepts, ultimately owes its existence entirely to this
property of space; and this is so generally admitted, that no further
demonstration of it is needed here.
b) What becomes of the concept when everything intuitive is removed
from it?
In that, by transcendental abstraction, the original schematism
is done away with, it follows that if conceptless intuition arises at one
extreme, an intuitionless concept must come about at the other. If the
categories, as deduced in the preceding epoch, are determinate intu
ition-forms of the intelligence, then if they are divested of intuition,
pure determinacy alone must remain behind. It is this that is desig
nated by the logical concept. Hence, if a philosopher begins by adopt
ing merely the standpoint of reflection or analysis, he will also be able
to deduce the categories as no more than purely formal concepts, and
thus to deduce them simply from logic. But apart from the fact that
the different functions of judgment in logic are themselves in need of
a further derivation, and that so far from transcendental philosophy
being abstracted from logic, the latter has to be abstracted
[514-15] Categories 141
from the former, it is in any case a pure deception to believe that the
categories, once separated from the schematism of intuition, continue
to remain as real concepts; for, divested of intuition, they are purely
logical concepts, connected with intuition, yet no longer concepts
proper, but true forms of intuition. The inadequacy of such a deriva
tion will betray itself through still other deficiencies, e.g., that it can
not uncover the mechanism of the categories, the special any more
than the general, though it is evident enough. Thus it is certainly a
striking feature of the so-called dynamic categories, that each of them
has its correlate, whereas with the so-called mathematical categories
this is not the case. Yet this peculiarity is very easily accounted for,
once we know that in the dynamic categories inner and outer sense
are still unseparated, whereas of the mathematical categories one be
longs only to inner, and the other only to outer sense. Again, the oc
currence, throughout and in every class, of three categories, of which
the first pair are opposed, while the third is a synthesis of the two,
shows that the general mechanism of the categories rests upon a
higher opposition, no longer perceived from the standpoint of reflec
tion, and therefore requiring the existence of a higher viewpoint, lying
further back. Since, moreover, this opposition runs through all the
categories, and it is one type that underlies them all, there is undoubt
edly also but one category, and since from the original mechanism of
intuition we could derive only the single category of relation, it is to
be expected that this one category will be primary, which a closer in
spection does indeed confirm. If it can be shown that prior to reflec
tion, or beyond it, the object is in no wise determined by the math
ematical categories, it being in fact only the subject that is so deter
mined, whether it be as intuiting or as feeling, just as, for example,
the object is one, not indeed in itself, but only in relation to the simul
taneously intuitant and reflecting subject; and if it can be shown, in
contrast, that already in the first intuition, and without a supervening
reflection, the object must be determined as substance and accident:
Then it surely follows from that, that the mathematical categories are
as such subordinated to the dynamic, or that the latter precede the
former; and hence, for this very reason, the mathematical categories
can only present separately what the dynamic present as united,
namely that the categories arising merely from the viewpoint of reflec
tion, so long as here too there has been no preceding opposition of
outer and inner sense, as happens in the categories of modality, also
belong merely to inner sense or to outer, and so can likewise
142 System of Transcendental Idealism [515-16]
Ill
second category, for only through the second (deduced by us as the in
tuition of the first) does that which in the first is inner sense become
time for the self. Hence the first category as such is intuitable only
through the second, as has been shown at the proper juncture; the
ground of this, which appears here, is that only through the second do
we add the transcendental schema of time.
Substance is intuitable as such only by being intuited as persist
ing in time, but it cannot be intuited as persistent unless time, which
has so far designated only the absolute boundary, flows (extends itself
in one dimension), which in feet comes about only through the succes
sion of the causal sequence. But conversely, too, that any succession
occurs in time is intuitable only in contrast to something that persists
therein, or, since time arrested in its flow = space, that persists in
space, and this in fact is substance. Hence these two categories are
possible only mutually through one another, that is, they are possible
only in a third, which is reciprocity.
From this deduction the following two propositions can be ab
stracted as a matter of course, whereby the mechanism of all the other
categories becomes intelligible:
1. The opposition obtaining between the first two categories is
the same as that originally obtaining between space and time;
2. The second category in each class is necessary only because it
appends the transcendental schema to the first.—
Not for the purpose of anticipating something as yet underived,
but in order to clarify these two propositions by further employment,
we set forth their application to the so-called mathematical categories,
although these have not yet been deduced as such.
We have already pointed out that these are not categories of in
tuition, in that they arise solely from the standpoint of reflection. But
concurrently with reflection, the unity of outer and inner sense is at
once abolished, and the one basic category of relation thereby divided
into two opposites, of which the first designates only that in the object
which pertains to outer sense, while the other expresses only that in
the object which belongs to outwardly intuited inner sense.
If then, to begin with the first, we remove everything intuitive
from the category of unity, which stands first in the class of quantity,
we are left only with logical unity. If this is to be combined with intu
ition, the determination of time must be added. But now quantity com
bined with time is number. Hence only by way of the second category
(that of plurality) does the determination of time come to be appended.
For only with a given plurality does numbering begin. Where there is
[521-23] Transcendental Schematism 147
only one, I do not number. Only through multiplicity does unity be
come a number. (That time and plurality first enter together is also
apparent from the fact that only through the second category of rela
tion, namely that whereby time first arises for the self in outer intu
ition, is a multiplicity of objects determined. Even in the arbitrary suc
cession of presentations, a multiplicity of objects only arises for me in
that I apprehend them one after another, i.e., apprehend them simply
and solely in time. In the number series, only through multiplicity
does 1 become a unity, that is, an expression of finitude as such. This
can be shown as follows. If 1 is a finite number, there must be a pos
sible divisor for it, but 1/1 = 1, hence 1 is divisible only by 2, 3, etc.,
that is, by plurality as such; without this it is 1/0, i.e., the infinite.)
But just as unity is unintuitable without plurality, so plurality is
unintuitable without unity, and so both mutually presuppose one an
other, that is, both are possible only through a third that is common to
them.
The same mechanism now appears in the categories of quality.
If I remove from reality the intuition of space, which is effected by
transcendental abstraction, nothing remains for me save the mere
logical concept of position as such. If I again combine this concept
with the intuition of space, I obtain the filling of space; but there is no
intuiting of this without some degree that is, without having a magni
tude in time. But the degree, that is, the determination by time, is
first added only through the second category, that of negation. So
again the second is necessary here simply because the first only be
comes intuitable by means of it, or because it appends to the latter the
transcendental schema.
This may perhaps be clarified as follows. If I think the real in
objects to myself as unrestricted, it will spread out to infinity, and
since intensity, as shown, stands in converse relation to extensity,
nothing remains save infinite extensity devoid of all intensity, namely
absolute space. If, on the other hand, we think of negation as the un
restricted, nothing remains save infinite intensity without extensity,
that is, a point, or inner sense insofar as it is merely inner sense. So if
I take the second category away from the first, I am left with absolute
space; if I take the first away from the second, I am left with absolute
time (i.e., time merely as inner sense).
Now in the original intuition neither concept, nor space, nor
time arises for us alone and separately, but rather all are given at
once. Just as our object the self conjoins these three determinations
unconsciously, and of itself, to the object, so likewise have we fared
in the deduction of productive intuition. Through
148 System of Transcendental Idealism [523-24]
IV
The final enquiry which must conclude the whole of theoretical phi
losophy is undoubtedly that concerning the distinction between a
priori and a posteriori concepts, which can hardly be made clear, in
deed, in any other way but by exhibiting their origin in the intelli
gence itself. The peculiarity of transcendental idealism in regard to its
doctrine is precisely this, that it can also demonstrate the so-called a
priori concepts in respect of their origin; a thing that is only possible,
indeed, in that it transports itself into a region lying beyond ordinary
consciousness. A philosophy that confines itself to the latter, on the
other hand, is able, in fact, to discover these concepts only as present
and, so to speak, lying there, and thereby involves itself in the in
soluble difficulties by which the defenders of these concepts have long
since been confronted.
In that we project the origin of the so-called a priori concepts be
yond consciousness, where we also locate the origin of the objective
world, we maintain upon the same evidence, and with equal right,
that our knowledge is originally empirical through and through, and
also through and through a priori.
All our knowledge is originally empirical, precisely because con
cept and object arise for us unseparated and simultaneously. For were
we originally to have a knowledge a priori〉there would first have to
152 System of Transcendental Idealism [528-29]
arise for us the concept of the object, and then the object itself in con
formity thereto, which alone would permit a genuine a priori insight
into the object. Conversely, all that knowledge is called empirical
which arises for me wholly without my concurrence, as happens, for
example, in a physical experiment whose result I cannot know before
hand. But now all knowledge of objects originally comes to us in a
manner so far independent of us, that only after it is there do we de
vise a concept thereof, but cannot give out this concept as itself again
furnished by the wholly involuntary intuition. All knowledge is thus
originally purely empirical.
But precisely because our whole knowledge is originally through
and through empirical, it is through and through a priori. For were it
not wholly our own production, our knowledge would either be all
given to us from without, which is impossible, since if so there would
be nothing necessary and universal in our knowledge; or there would
be nothing left but to suppose that some of it comes to us from outside,
while the rest emerges from ourselves. Hence our knowledge can only
be empirical through and through in that it comes wholly and solely
from ourselves, i.e.t is through and through a priori.
Insofar, that is, as the self produces everything from itself, to
that extent everything—not just this concept or that, or merely the
form of thought, even, but the whole of our knowledge, one and indi
visible—is a priori.
But insofar as we are not aware of this producing, to that extent
there is nothing a priori in us, and everything, in fact, is a posteriori
To become aware of our knowledge as a priori in character, we have to
become aware of the act of producing as such, in abstraction from the
product. But in course of this very operation, we lose from the con
cept, in the manner deduced above, everything material (all intuition),
and nothing save the purely formal can remain behind. To that extent
we do indeed have concepts a priori, and purely formal ones at that,
but these concepts also exist only insofar as we conceive, insofar as we
abstract in that particular fashion, and emerge, therefore, not auto
matically, but by a special exercise of freedom.
Hence there are a priori concepts without there having to be
innate concepts. It is not concepts that are innate in us, but our own
nature and the whole of its mechanism. This nature is a specific one,
and acts in a specific manner, though quite unawares, for it is itself
nothing else but this acting: the concept of this acting is not in it, for
otherwise it would have had originally to be something distinct there
from, and if the concept entered it, it would first do so by way
[529-30] A Priori and A Posteriori 153
Corollaries
self becomes an object to itself qua self, the question remains as to how
this act may be related to that original act of self-consciousness, which
is likewise a self-determining, although it does not bring about the
same result.
By what has preceded we are already supplied with a mark of
distinction between the two. The first act contained only the simple
opposition between determinant and determinate, which corresponded
to that between intuitant and intuited. In the present act we no
longer have this simple opposition; instead, the determinant and de
terminate are collectively confronted by an intuitant, and both to
gether, the intuited and intuitant of the first act, are here the intuited.
The ground of this distinction was as follows. In that first act
the self as such first came to be, for it is nothing else but that which
becomes an object to itself; hence in the self there was as yet no ideal
activity, which could simultaneously reflect upon what was emerging.
In the present act the self already exists, and it is a question only of its
becoming an object to itself as that which it already is. Objectively re
garded, indeed, this second act of self-determination is therefore just
the same, in fact, as the first and original one, save with this differ
ence only, that in the present act the whole of the first becomes an ob
ject to the self, whereas in the first act itself only the objective element
therein did so.
Here, no doubt, is also the most suitable place to review simulta
neously the oft-repeated question, by what common principle do theo
retical and practical philosophy hang together?
It is autonomy which is commonly placed at the summit only of
practical philosophy, and which, enlarged into the principle of the
whole of philosophy, turns out, on elaboration, to be transcendental
idealism. The difference between the primordial autonomy, and that
which is dealt with in practical philosophy, is simply this: by means of
the former the self is absolutely self-determinant, but without being so
for itself—the self both gives itself the law and realizes it in one and
the same act, wherefore it also fails to distinguish itself as legislative,
and discerns the laws in its products, merely, as if in a mirror. By
contrast, in practical philosophy the self as ideal is opposed, not to the
real, but to the simultaneously ideal and real, yet for that very reason
is no longer ideal, but idealizing. But for the same reason, since the
simultaneously ideal and real, that is, the producing self, is opposed to
an idealizing one, the former, in practical philosophy, is no longer
intuitant, that is, devoid of consciousness, but is consciously produc
tive, or realizing.
158 System of Transcendental Idealism [536-37]
it, must coexist, as though the one were determined by the other.
Such a relationship is conceivable only through a preestablished
harmony. The act outside the intelligence comes about entirely on its
own; the intelligence contains only the negative condition thereof^ that
is, if it had behaved in a certain fashion, this act would not have taken
place; but by merely not acting it still does not become the direct or
positive ground of the act, for by the mere fact of its not acting, this act
would still not have occurred unless there had been something else
outside the intelligence which contained the ground of that act. Con
versely, the idea or concept of the act arrives in the intelligence en
tirely on its own, as though there were nothing outside the latter; and
yet it could not occur therein unless the act took place really and inde
pendently of the intelligence; and hence this act likewise is again only
the indirect ground of a presentation in the intelligence. This indirect
reciprocity is what we understand by a preestablished harmony.
But such a harmony is conceivable only between subjects of
equal reality, and hence this act must have proceeded from a subject
endowed with just the same reality as the intelligence itself; that is, it
must have proceeded from another, external intelligence, and thus by
the contradiction noted above we find ourselves led on to a new prin
ciple.
Second Proposition. The act of self-determination, or the free ac
tion of the intelligence upon itself, can be explained only by the deter
minate action of an intelligence external to 让.
Proof. This is contained in the deduction just effected, and rests
solely upon the two propositions, that self-determination must be at
once explicable, and yet not explicable by a producing on the part of
the intelligence. So instead of dwelling any further on the proof, let us
pass on at once to the problems which we see to emerge from this doc
trine and from the proof adduced for it.
First, then, we see at all events that a determinate action of an
extraneous intelligence is the necessary condition of the act of self-de
termination, and thereby of consciousness; but we do not see howt and
in what manner such an external act could be even the indirect
ground of a free self-determination in ourselves.
Second. We do not perceive how there can be any external in
fluence at all upon the intelligence, and so also do not see how the in
fluence of another intelligence upon it may be possible. By now, in
deed, this difficulty has already been met by our deduction, in
162 System of Transcendental Idealism [542*43]
have derived, so surely are there also other intelligences with the
same determinations, for they are conditions of the consciousness of
the first, and vice versa.
But now different intelligences can have in common only the
first and second forms of restriction, and the third only in a general
sense; for the latter is precisely that by virtue of which the intelligence
exists as a specific individual. Hence it seems that, precisely through
this third restrictedness, insofar as it is a particular one, all commu
nity between intelligences is done away with. However, even through
this restriction of individuality, a preestablished harmony can again
be conditioned, if we do but suppose it to be the opposite of the previ
ous one. For whereas the latter, which occurs in regard to their objec
tive presentations, serves to posit something common among intelli
gences, the third restrictedness, by contrast, serves to posit in every
individual something which, precisely for that reason, is negated by all
the others, and which they cannot therefore intuit as their own action,
but only as other than theirs, that is, as the action of an intelligence
outside them.
The claim, therefore, is that immediately through the individual
restrictedness of every intelligence, immediately through the negation
of a certain activity therein, this activity is posited for it as the activity
of an intelligence outside it, which thus constitutes a preestablished
harmony of a negative kind.
To demonstrate such a thesis, two propositions must therefore
be proved,
1. That what is not my activity must be intuited by me, simply
because it is not mine, and without the need of any direct influence
upon me from without, as the activity of an intelligence outside me;
2. That immediately through the positing of my individuality,
without further restriction from outside, a negation of activity is pos
ited in me.
Now so far as the first proposition is concerned, we must observe
that we are speaking only of conscious or free acts; now the intelli
gence is admittedly confined in its freedom by the objective world, as
has already been shown in general above, but within this restriction
it is again unrestricted, so that its activity can, for example, be di
rected toward any object it pleases; now if we suppose that it begins
to act, its activity will necessarily have to be directed toward some
particular object, in such a way as to leave all other objects free and,
as it were, undisturbed: but now there is no seeing how its originally
quite indeterminate activity should restrict itself in this fashion, un
less the direction towards these other objects were
166 System of Transcendental Idealism [545-47]
somehow made impossible for it, which, so far as we have seen hith
erto, is possible only through intelligences outside it. It is thus a con
dition of self-consciousness that I intuit in general an activity of
intelligences outside me (the enquiry as yet being still an entirely gen
eral one), because it is a condition of self-consciousness that my activ
ity be directed upon a specific object. But this very direction of my ac
tivity is something that is already posited and predetermined by the
synthesis of my individuality. By the same synthesis, therefore, other
intelligences, whereby I intuit myself as restricted in my free action,
and hence also specific actions of these intelligences, are likewise al
ready posited for me, without the need of any further special influ
ence, on their part, upon myself.
We forbear to show the application of this solution to particular
cases, or to meet at once the objections that we can anticipate, in order
first merely to clarify the solution itself by means of examples.
The following may serve by way of elucidation. Among the origi
nal drives of the intelligence there is also a drive for knowledge, and
knowledge is one of the objects upon which its activity may be di
rected. Let us suppose this happens, which in fact will be so only if
the immediate objects of activity are all already preoccupied, so that
the activity of the intelligence is already restricted by that very fact;
but in itself this object is again infinite, and so here too it will again
have to be confined: if we suppose, therefore, that the intelligence di
rects its activity upon a specific object of cognition, it will either dis
cover or acquire the knowledge of that object, that is, it will arrive at
this kind of cognition through alien influence. Now what serves to
posit this alien influence here? Merely a negation in the intelligence
itself; for either its individual restrictedness renders it wholly incap
able of discovery, or the discovery has already been made, and if so,
this too is again posited by the synthesis of its individuality, to which
it also appertains that the intelligence has first begun to exist at this
particular period of time. Hence it is only through negations of its
own activity that the intelligence is exposed, and as it were opened, to
alien influence as such.
But now arises a new question, the most important of this en
quiry: how then, by pure negation, can anything positive be posited,
in such a way that I am obliged to intuit what is not my activity, sim
ply because it is not mine, as the activity of an intelligence outside me?
The answer is as follows: to will at all, I must will something determi
nate, but this I could never do if I could will everything; hence, by
[547-48] Activity of an Outside Intelligence 167
other rational beings upon the intelligence, and therewith freedom, the
power of reflecting upon the object, of becoming conscious of oneself,
and the whole sequence of free and conscious acts. The third
restrictedness, or that of individuality, is thus the synthetic point or
pivot of theoretical and practical philosophy, and only now have we re
ally arrived in the territory of the latter, and the synthetic enquiry be
gins afresh.
Since the restrictedness of individuality, and hence that of free
dom, was originally posited only in that the intelligence was obliged to
intuit itself as an organic individual, we simultaneously perceive here
the reason why—involuntarily, and through a sort of universal in
stinct—the contingent features of the organism, the particular shape
and build of the noblest organs especially, have been regarded as the
visible expression, and at least as affording the presumption, of talent
and of character itself.
Additional Remarhs
In the course of the investigation that has just been going on, we have
deliberately left undiscussed a number of subsidiary questions, which,
now that the main enquiry is concluded, require to be given an an
swer,
1. We claimed that by the operation of other intelligences upon
an object the unconscious direction of the free activity upon it could be
rendered impossible. It was already presupposed in this claim that, in
and for itself, the object is incapable of raising the activity directed
upon it to the level of consciousness; not, indeed, as if the object be
haves with absolute passivity in response to my acting, a thing that,
though the contrary thereof has not yet been proved, was certainly not
presupposed either. It is merely that for itself and without the prior
operation of an intelligence, the object is not capable of reflecting the
free activity as such within itself. What, then, is added to the object by
the operation of an intelligence, which the object does not possess in
and for itself?
In answering this question, the preceding discussion at least
supplies us with a datum.
Willing does not depend, as producing does, upon the simple
opposition between ideal and real activity, but upon a twofold opposi
tion between the ideal on the one side and the ideal and real on the
other. In willing, the intelligence is both idealizing and realizing at
the same time. If it were merely realizing, indeed, then since all
realization contains an ideal activity as well as the real, it would
give expression to a concept in the object. Since it is not simply
realizing, however, but besides that and independently
172 System of Transcendental Idealism [553-54]
any object, namely an intuition external to it, which, since it can never
become a thing intuited, is for it the first absolutely objective item en
tirely independent of itself. Now the object which pushes reflection to
ward something beyond any object, posits counter to free operation an
invisible ideal resistance, whereby, on that very account, it is not the
objective, producing activity that is reflected in ourselves, but an activ
ity at once ideal and productive. So where it is merely force, now ob
jective and appearing as physical in character, which encounters resis
tance, there can only be nature present; but where conscious activity,
that is, this ideal activity of the third order, is reflected in oneself
there is necessarily something invisible present, additional to the ob
ject, which makes a blind direction of activity upon the object utterly
impossible.
Now it cannot, indeed, be suggested, that through the influence
thus exerted by an intelligence upon the object, my freedom in regard
to the latter is absolutely taken away. All we are saying is that the in
visible resistance which I encounter in such an object compels me to a
decision, that is, to a restriction of myself; or that the activity of an
other rational being, insofar as it is fixated or made manifest in ob
jects, serves to determine me to self-determination; and this question,
how I am able to will something determinate, was all that we had to
explain.
2. Only by the fact that there are intelligences outside me, does
the world as such become objective to me.
It has just been shown that only operations of intelligences upon
the world of sense compel me to accept something as absolutely objec
tive. We are not now speaking of this, but rather of the fact that the
whole essentiality of objects only becomes real for me, in that the intel
ligences are outside me. Nor are we referring to anything that might
first be evolved through habituation or upbringing, but rather to the
fact that already from the start the notion of objects outside me simply
cannot arise, save through intelligences external to me. For
a) that the notion of an outside me, as such, could arise only
through the operation of intelligences, either upon myself, or upon
sensory objects whereon they set their stamp, is already apparent from
the fact that objects in and for themselves are not outside me; for
where objects are, there am I also, and even the space in which I intuit
them is originally only in myself. The sole original outside me is an in
tuition outside me, and this is the point at which the idealism we start
with is first transformed into realism.
b) I am, however, under a special necessity of
174 System of Transcendental Idealism [555-57]
Solution
I
Third Proposition. Willing, at the outset, is necessarily directed upon
an external object.
Proof. By the free act of self-determination, the self as it were
destroys everything material in its presenting, in that it makes itself
wholly free in regard to the objective; and only by this, in fact, does
willing become willing. But the self could not become aware of this act
as such, if willing did not once more become an object to it. This how
ever, is possible only in that an object of intuition becomes the visible
expression of its willing. But eveiy object of intuition is a particular
one, and must therefore be this particular one only because and insofar
as the self has willed in this particular manner. Only so would the self
become its own cause of the matter of its presenting.
But moreover the action whereby the object becomes this par
ticular one must not be absolutely identical with the object itself^ for
otherwise the action would be a blind producing, a mere intuiting. The
action as such and the object must therefore remain distinguishable.
But now the action conceived as such, is a concept. But that concept
and object remain distinguishable is possible only in that the object ex
ists independently of this action, that is, in that the object is an exter
nal one. Conversely, the object, on that very account, becomes an ex
ternal one for me only through willing, for willing is willing only inso
far as it is directed upon something independent of it.
And here already we have light upon what is still more fully ex
plained in the sequel, namely why the self can in no way appear to it
self as bringing forth an object as though it were a substance, and why,
on the contrary, all bringing forth in willing appears only as a forming
or shaping of the object.
Our proof has now shown, indeed, that willing as such can be
come objective to the self only through being directed upon an external
object; but it is not yet explained from whence this direction itself can
come.
In regard to this question, it is already presupposed that
productive intuition persists inasmuch as
176 System of Transcendental Idealism [558-59]
there first arises for the self the opposition between the object as the
idealizing activity demands it, and the object as it actually is according
to constrained thought; but this opposition at once engenders the drive
to transform the object as it is into the object as it ought to be. We en
title the activity that arises here a drive, because on the one hand it is
free, and yet on the other it springs immediately and without any
reflection from a feeling, both of which factors together make up the
concept of a drive. For that state of the self as it wavers between ideal
and object is a state of feeling, since it is a state of being restricted for
itself. But in every feeling a contradiction is felt, and nothing what
ever can be felt save an inner contradiction within ourselves. Now
through every contradiction the condition for activity is immediately
given; the activity springs forth as soon as its condition is but given,
without any further reflection, and if it is at the same time a free ac
tivity, which production, for example, is not, is for that very reason,
and to that extent only, a drive.
Direction upon an external object therefore finds expression
through a driveand this drive emerges directly from the contradiction
between the idealizing and the intuiting self, and is directly bent upon
restoring the lost identity of the self. As necessarily as self-conscious
ness is to continue, so this drive must have causality (for we still go on
deducing all the acts of the self as conditions of self-consciousness,
since through the objective world alone self-consciousness is not com
pleted, but only brought to the point at which it can begin, though
from there onwards it can be carried forward only through free acts).
The question, then, is merely, how this drive can have causality?
Here a transition is obviously postulated from the (purely) ideal
into the objective (at once both ideal and real). We first attempt to es
tablish the negative conditions for such a transition, and will subse
quently go on to the positive conditions, or those under which it actu
ally takes place.
A
a) By freedom the ideal self is immediately opened to infinity, as
surely as it is cast into confinement by the mere objective world; but
it cannot make infinity an object to itself without delimiting it; con
versely, infinity cannot be limited absolutely, but only for purposes of
action, in such a way that ig say, the ideal is realized, the Idea can be
extended further, and so on indefinitely. Thus the ideal always holds
178 System of Transcendental Idealism [562-63]
only for the present moment of action, whereas the Idea itself, which
ever becomes infinite again in reflecting upon the action, can be real
ized only in a progressus ad infinitum. That freedom is at every mo
ment limited and yet at every moment again becomes infinite, in re
spect of its striving, is what alone makes possible the consciousness of
freedom, that is, the continuance of self-consciousness itself. For it is
freedom which sustains the continuity of self-consciousness. If I re
flect upon the producing of time in my action, it becomes for me, in
deed, a magnitude interrupted and put together out of moments. But
in action itself, time is always continuous for me; and the more I act,
and the less I reflect, the more continuous it is. The drive in question
can therefore have no causality save in time, which represents the
first determination of our transition. But now since time can be
thought of objectively only as proceeding via a succession of presenta
tions, in which the later are conditioned by those that precede, there
must equally be such a succession present in our free producing, save
only that the presentations are related to each other, not as cause and
effect, but as means and end—seeing that every conscious action con
tains a concept of the concept, that is, the concept of an end; and these
two concepts will be related to those of cause and effect just as a con
cept of the concept is related to simple concepts as such. Hence we
may perceive it to be a condition of the consciousness of freedom, that
my realization of any end is not attainable directly, but only through a
number of intermediate steps.
b) It was established that action should not go over absolutely
into the object, for otherwise it would be an intuition; yet the object
has always to remain an external object, separate, that is, from my ac
tion; how is this conceivable?
According to a), the drive can have causality only in time. But
the object is that which is in opposition to freedom; yet it now has to
be determined through freedom, and we therefore have a contradiction
here. Let the object contain a determination = a; freedom now de
mands the opposite determination = -a. This is no contradiction for
freedom, but it is so for intuition. For the latter, the contradiction
can be removed only through the common intermediary, time. If I
could bring forth -a in the absence of all time, the transition would
be unthinkable; a and -a would coexist. In the succeeding instant
there must therefore be something which does not now exist, and
only so is a consciousness of freedom possible. But now no succession
can be perceived in time without something that persists. The
transition from a to -a in my presentations destroys
[562-63] Substance and Change 179
B
For purposes of this enquiry we return to the first requirement. By
means of a free action, something is to be determined in the objective
world.
180 System of Transcendental Idealism [563-64]
which we must look for the ground of that identity we have postulated,
between the freely active and the objectively intuitant self.
But if we wish to arrive at complete clarity on this matter, we
must repeat the reminder, that everything we have so far deduced has
had reference only to appearance, or was merely a condition under
which the self was to appear to itself, and so did not have the same re・
ality as the self itself. What we are just now trying to explain, namely
how the se】£ insofar as it acts, can determine something in the sel£ in
sofar as it knows—this whole opposition between acting and intuiting
self—undoubtedly also belongs only to the appearance of the self, and
not to the self proper. The self must appear to itself as though some
thing were determined, by its action, within its intuition, or, since it is
not conscious of this, within the external world. If this be presup
posed, the following explanation will be intelligible enough.
We set up an opposition between the free-acting and the objec
tively intuitant self. But now this opposition does not occur objec
tively, that is, in the self-in-itself, for the self which acts is itself the
intuitant self, only here become at the same time intuited, objective,
and thereby active. If the self which intuits (with its simultaneously
ideal and real activity) were not here at the same time the intuited,
the acting would still continue to appear as an intuiting; and con
versely, that the intuiting appears as an acting has its ground merely
in this, that the self here is not merely intuitant, but intuited as
intuitant. The intuitant intuited is simply the self which acts. There
can thus be no thought of any mediation between that which acts and
that which outwardly intuits, nor of any, either, between the free-
acting self and the external world. On the contrary, it would be
utterly unintelligible how an outer intuition could be determined by
an action of the self, if action and intuition were not originally one.
My action, in that I fashion an object, for example, must at the same
time be an intuiting, and conversely, my intuiting in this case must
at the same time be an action; only the self is unable to perceive this
identity, since the objectively intuiting for the self here is not the
intuitant but the intuited, so that for the self this identity between
the agent and the intuitant is abolished. The change which comes
about, through free action, in the external world, must take place
entirely according to the laws of productive intuition, and as though
freedom had no part in it at all. Productive intuition acts, as it were,
entirely in isolation, and produces according to its characteristic
laws whatever now results. That this producing
182 System of Transcendental Idealism [566-67]
does not appear as an intuiting to the self has its ground solely in this,
that here the concept (the ideal activity) is opposed to the object (the
objective activity), whereas in intuition subjective and objective activ
ity are both one. But that the concept here precedes the object is
again only due to appearance. But if the concept precedes the object
only for appearance, and not objectively or really so, then free action
as such also belongs only to appearance, and the sole objective factor is
the intuitant.
Just as one may say, therefore, that in that I thought I was intu
iting, I was in fact acting, so one may equally say here that in that I
think I act upon the external world, I am in fact intuiting; and every
thing that emerges in action, apart from intuiting, properly belongs
only to the appearance of the sole objective feature, namely intuiting,
and conversely, if we separate from acting everything that belongs
only to appearance, nothing remains save the intuiting.
The result thus far derived, and, as we think, sufficiently dem
onstrated, we now seek to explain and clarify from still other points of
view.
When the transcendental idealist maintains that there is no
transition from the objective into the subjective, and that both are
originally one, the objective being merely a subjective that has become
an object, there is admittedly a major question that he has to answer:
how then, conversely, is it possible to have a transition from the sub
jective into the objective, such as we are obliged to assume when we
act? If in every action a concept freely evolved by ourselves is to pass
over into a nature existing independently of us, although really this
nature enjoys no such independent existence, how can the transition
be conceived of?
Undoubtedly by this alone, that through this very act we in fact
first make the world become objective to us. We act freely, and the
world comes to exist independently of us—these two propositions must
be synthetically united.
Now if the world is nothing else but our own intuiting, it un
doubtedly becomes objective to us when our intuiting does so. But
now we are presently maintaining that our intuiting first becomes
objective to us through action, and that what we call an act is nothing
but the appearance of our intuiting. If this be accepted, then our
prop)osition: “that which appears to us as an act upon the external
world is, from the idealist viewpoint, nothing else but a prolonged
intuiting/* will no longer seem repellent. Thus, for example, if some
change in the external world is brought about by an act, this change,
regarded in itself, is an intuition like any other. Hence the intuiting
[567-68] Objective and Subjective 183
itself is here the objective factor which underlies the appearance; the
element thereof which belongs to appearance is the act upon the sup
posedly independent world of sense; so objectively here there is no
transition from the subjective into the objective, any more than there
was a transition from the objective into the subjective. It is only that I
cannot appear to myself as intuitant without intuiting a subjective as
passing over into the objective. The whole enquiry on this point can be
traced back to the general principle of transcendental idealism,
namely that in my knowing the subjective can never be determined by
the objective. In acting, an object is necessarily thought of as deter
mined by a causality exercised by myself in accordance with a concept.
Now how do I arrive at this necessary thought? If I also assume
herein without explanation, that the object is immediately determined
by my act, in such wise that it is related thereto as effect to agency,
how then is this also determined for my presentation, why am I
obliged also to intuit the object precisely as I had determined it by my
action? My action here is in this case the object, for acting is the oppo
site of intuiting or knowing. But now by means of this acting, this
objective, something is to be determined in my knowing, in my intuit
ing. According to the principle just enunciated, this is impossible. By
action, my knowledge thereof cannot be determined, for on the con
trary, rather, every action, like everything objective, must originally
be already a knowing, an intuiting. This is so clear and obvious, that
no difficulty can be found anywhere else, save perhaps in the manner
in which we are to think for purposes of appearance, of this transfor
mation of what is objectively an intuiting into an act. Reflection here
must address itself to three things:
a) to the objective, the intuiting
b) to the subjective, which is also an intuiting, but an intuiting
of the intuiting. —To distinguish it from the former objective intuiting,
we call this latter the ideal intuiting.
c) to the appeat'ance of the objective. But now it has already
been shown that this objective, the intuiting, cannot appear unless the
concept of an intuition (ideal) precedes the intuition itself But if the
concept of intuition precedes the intuition itself, so that the latter is
determined by the former, intuiting is a producing in accordance with
a concept, that is, a free act. But now admittedly the concept precedes
the intuition itself only to ensure objectification of the intuition, and
thus the action also is merely the appearance of the intuiting, and that
which is objective therein is the producing as such, in abstraction from
the concept which precedes it.
184 System of Transcendental Idealism [568-70]
same reality as the latter), follows from the fact that it only becomes an
act through the process of becoming objective. From this point, indeed,
a new light can in fact be cast backward upon theoretical idealism. If
the objective world is a mere appearance, so too is the objective element
in our acting, and conversely, only if the world has reality, does the ob
jective element in action also possess reality. It is therefore one and
the same reality which we perceive in the objective world, and in our
action upon the world of the senses. This conjoint status, and indeed
mutual conditioning of objective action and the world*s reality, outside
and through each other, is a consequence wholly peculiar to transcen
dental idealism, and unattainable through any other system.
So now how far, in fact, is the self active in the external world?
It acts only in virtue of that identity of being and appearance which is
already expressed in self-consciousness. —The self exists only in that it
appears to itself; its knowing is a form of being. The proposition I = I
says nothing else but that I, who know^ am the same who amt my
knowing and my being mutually exhaust each other, the subject of con
sciousness and the subject of activity are one. In consequence of this
identity, therefore, my knowing and free action are also identical with
free action as such; in other words, the proposition *1 intuit myself as
acting objectively* = the proposition *1 am objectively active*.
II
Now if what appears as an action, as has just been derived and demon
strated, is in itself an intuition merely, it follows that all action must
be constantly confined by the laws of intuition, that nothing that is im
possible according to natural laws can be intuited as coming about
through free action. And this is a new proof of the identity in question.
But now a transition from the subjective into the objective, such as
actually takes place, for appearance at least, is itself a contradiction of
natural laws. That which is to be intuited as operating upon the real,
must itself appear as real. Hence I cannot intuit myself as operating
upon the object immediately, but only as doing so by means of matter,
though in that I act I must intuit this latter as identical with myselfl
Matter, as the immediate organ of free, outwardly directed activity, is
the organic body, which must therefore appear as free and apparently
capable of voluntary movements. That drive which has causality in
my action must appear objectively as a natural inclination, which
even without any freedom would operate and bring forth for
186 System of Transcendental Idealism [571-72]
Thus this objectifying of the ideal activity can be accounted for only as
the result of a demand. The ideal activity, directed solely upon pure
self-determining, must become an object to the self through a demand,
which demand, indeed, can be no other than this: the self shall will
nothing else put pure self-determining itself, fbr by this demand the
pure activity, directed solely upon self-determining as such, is held be
fore it as an object. This demand, however, is itself nothing other than
the categorical imperative, or moral law, which Kant expresses as fol
lows: thou shalt will only what all intelligences are able to will. But
that which all intelligences are able to will is simply pure self-deter
mining itself pure conformity to law. Through the moral law, there
fore, pure self-determining (the purely objective element in all willing,
insofar as it is simply objective, i.e., not itself again intuitant, or di
rected upon anything external or empirical) becomes an object to the
sel£ Only to that extent, too, is the moral law a topic of transcenden
tal philosophy, for even the moral law is merely deduced as a condition
of self-consciousness. This law originally applies to me, not insofar as
I am this particular intelligence, for indeed it strikes down everything
that belongs to individuality and completely destroys it; it applies to
me, rather, as an intelligence in general, to that which has as its im
mediate object the purely objective, the eternal in me; not, however, to
this objective element itself, insofar as it is directed to a contingent
distinct from and independent of the self, and on that very account the
moral law is also the sole condition under which the intelligence be
comes aware of its own consciousness.
2. Reflection must now address itself to the objective activity,
directed upon something external, lying outside the compass of willing
itself, and enquire how this becomes an object to the sel£
This question, however, has already been largely answered in
what has preceded, and so here we can merely attempt to set forth the
answer in a new perspective.
The objective activity, directed upon something distinct from
willing and present outside it, is to be opposed in consciousness to that
ideal activity which is directed upon that selfsame objective activity,
simply as such and insofar as it is a pure self-determining.
But now this ideal activity could become an object to the self
only by means of a demand. So if the opposition is to be perfect, the
objective activity must become objective by itself〉without a de
mand, and its becoming objective must be presupposed. That
whereby it becomes objective to the self as an activity directed
upon something external, to which it is related
[575-76] Natural Inclination and Happiness 189
alone the absolute act of will can again become an object to the self it
self But now this opposition is precisely what turns the absolute will
into choice, so that choice is the appearance we were seeking of the ab
solute will—not the original willing itself, but the absolute act of free
dom become objectified, with which all consciousness begins.
That a freedom of the will exists is something the ordinary
consciousness can be persuaded of only through the act of choice, that
is, by the fact that in every willing we are aware of a choice between
opposites. But now it is argued that choice is not the absolute will it
self, for this, as demonstrated earlier, is directed only to pure self-de
termining as such; it is, rather, the appearance of the absolute will.
So if freedom = choice, then freedom too is not the absolute will itself
but merely the appearance thereof. Thus of the will absolutely re
garded it cannot be said that it is either free or not free, since the ab
solute cannot be thought of as acting from a law that was not already
prescribed to it by the inner necessity of its own nature. Since, in the
absolute act of will, the self has as its object only self-determining as
such, no deviation from this is possible for the will in its absolute
sense; if it can be called free at all, it is thus absolutely free, since that
which is a command for the will that appears is, for the absolute will,
a law that proceeds from the necessity of its own nature. But if the
absolute is to appear to itself, it must figure to itself as dependent in
its objective upon something else, something alien to it. This depen
dence, however, does not belong to the absolute itself, but merely to its
appearance. This alien factor, on which the absolute will is dependent
for purposes of appearance, is the natural inclination, in contrast to
which alone the law of the pure will is transformed into an imperative.
In its absolute sense, however, the will has originally no other object
save pure self-determining, that is, itself. So nor can there be any obli
gation or law for it, demanding that it be an object to itself. Hence the
moral law, and freedom, insofar as it consists in choice, are themselves
merely conditions for the appearance of that absolute will, which is
constitutive of all consciousness, and to that extent also a condition of
the consciousness that becomes an object to itself
Now by this result, without actually meaning to, we have
simultaneously resolved that notable problem which, so far from
having been settled, has so far scarcely been properly understood —I
mean the problem of transcendental freedom. In this problem it is
not a question whether the self is absolute, but whether, insofar as
it is not absolute, insofar as it is empirical, the
[577-78] Absolute and Empirical Freewill 191
self is free. But now it appears indeed from our solution, that just pre
cisely insofar as the will is empiricalt or appears, so to that extent it
can be called free in the transcendental sense. For insofar as it is ab
solute, the will itself transcends freedom, and so far from being sub
jected to any law, is in fact the source of all law. But insofar as the ab
solute will appears, it can only do so, in order to appear as absolute, in
the form of choice. This phenomenon of choice can therefore no longer
be explained objectively, for it is not anything objective, having reality
per se, but is rather the absolute subjective, the intuition of the abso
lute will itself, whereby the latter becomes, ad infinitum^ an object to
itself But this very appearance of the absolute will is in fact true free
dom, or what is commonly understood by the term freedom. Now
since, in free action, the self intuits itself ad infinitum as absolute will
and in its highest power is itself nothing else but this intuition of the
absolute will, the aforementioned appearance of choice is likewise as
certain and indubitable as the self itself. ―Conversely, also, the phe
nomenon of choice can be thought of only as an absolute will, though a
will that appears under the confines of finitude, and is thus an ever
recurring revelation of the absolute will within us. It should be noted,
however, that if we had sought to infer backwards from the phenom
enon of choice to that which lies at the root of it, we should assuredly
have had difficulty in ever hitting upon the correct explanation of it,
though Kant, in his Doctrine of Law, has at least pointed to the con
trast between the absolute will and the faculty of choice, even if he
does not yet give the true relationship of the one to the other. And
this, then, is a new proof of the superiority of a method which presup
poses no phenomenon as given, but first becomes acquainted with each
of them through its grounds, as though it were totally unknown.
And now by this we also resolve all the doubts which could be
drawn, say, from the common assumption that the will is free, con
cerning the claim put forward earlier, that the objective self which
appears to engage in action is in itself merely intuitant. For it is not
that merely objective self, operating quite mechanically in both action
and intuition, and in all free action the determinate^ to which the
predicate of freedom is ascribed; it is rather that self which wavers
between subjective and objective factors of willing, determining one
by the other—viz. the self-determinant of the second order■―to which
alone freedom is and can be attributed, in that the objective self,
which in regard to freedom is merely the determined, still continues,
in and for itself or regardless of the determinant, to remain
192 System of Transcendental Idealism [578-80]
Additional Remarks
namely choice. This cannot be the case. The holiest ought not to be
entrusted to chance. It must be made impossible, through the con
straint of an unbreakable law, that in the interaction of all the free
dom of the individual should be abolished. Now this constraint can
not, to be sure, be directed immediately against freedom, since no ra
tional being can be constrained, but only determined to constrain him
self; nor can this constraint be directed against the pure will, which
has no other object save what is common to all rational beings, namely
self>determining as such; it can be directed only against the self-inter
ested drive emanating from the individual and returning back to him
again. But against this drive there is nothing which can be used as a
sanction or a weapon except itself. The external world would have, as
it were, to be so organized that it compels this drive, in that it over
steps its boundaries, to act against itself, and opposes to it something
on which the free being can exert his will, insofar, that is, as he is a
rational being, though not insofar as he is a natural one; whereby the
agent is thrown into contradiction with himself, and at least made
mindful of the fact that he is divided within himself.
In and for itself the objective world cannot contain the ground
of such a contradiction within itself, for it behaves with complete indif
ference toward the operations of free beings as such; the ground of this
contradiction of the self-interested drive can therefore be lodged in it
only by the rational being.
A second and higher nature must, as it were, be set up over the
first, governed by a natural law quite different, however, from that
which prevails in visible nature, namely a natural law on behalf of
freedom. As inexorably, and with the same iron necessity whereby ef
fect follows cause in sensible nature, an attack upon the freedom of an
other must be succeeded, in this second nature, by an instantaneous
counter to the self-interested drive. A law of nature such as that just
depicted is to be found in the rule of law, and the second nature in
which its authority prevails is the legal system, which is thereby de
duced as a condition of the continuance of consciousness.
It will be evident from this deduction that law is no branch
of morality, nor in any sense a practical science, but rather a
purely theoretical one, which stands to freedom precisely as
mechanics does to motion, in that it merely sets forth the natural
mechanism under which free beings as such can be thought of as
interacting; a mechanism, indeed, which can undoubtedly itself be
set up only through freedom, and to which nature contributes
nothing. For nature, as the poet says, is
196 System of Transcendental Idealism [583-85]
without feeling, and God, as the gospel tells us, permits His sun to
shine on the just and the unjust alike. From the very fact, however,
that the legal system has to be considered merely as a supplement to
visible nature, it follows that the legal order is not a moral one, but a
purely natural order, which freedom has no more power over than it
has over sensible nature. It is no wonder, therefore, that all attempts
to transform it into a moral order present themselves as detestable
through their own perversity, and through that most dreadful kind of
despotism which is their immediate consequence. For although the le
gal system performs the same office, materially speaking, that we ex
pect, in fact, from Providence, and is altogether the best theodicy that
man is able to contrive, it still does not do this in form, or does not do
it qua Providence, that is, with judgment and forethought. It has to be
viewed as a machine primed in advance for certain possibilities, and
operating automatically, ie, entirely blindly, as soon as these cases
are presented; and although this machine is constructed and primed
by the hands of men, it is obliged, once the hand of the artificer is
withdrawn, to operate like visible nature according to its own laws,
and independently, as though it existed on its own. Thus, while a le
gal system becomes the more deserving of respect to the extent that it
approximates to an order of nature, a regime governed, not by law but
by the will of the judge and by a despotism which operates the law as a
providence looking into the heart of things, in that it constantly inter
feres with the natural course of the legal process, presents the most
unworthy and revolting spectacle that can exist for anyone imbued
with feeling for the holiness of the law.
But now if the legal system is a necessary condition for the free
dom existing in the external world, it is undoubtedly an important
question, how such a freedom can be thought of even as existing, since
the will of the individual can do absolutely nothing in this regard, and
presupposes as its necessary supplement something independent of it,
namely the will of everyone else.
It is to be supposed that even the first emergence of a legal
order was not left to chance, but rather to a natural compulsion
which, occasioned by the general resort to force, drove men to bring
such an order into being without their own knowledge of the fact,
and in such a way that its earliest workings affected them unawares.
But now it is also easy to see that an order brought about by need
could have no inherent stability, partly because what is fashioned
out of need is also devised only for immediate requirements, and
partly because the mechanism of such a system directs its
[585-86] Emergence of Legal Order 197
III
The emergence of the universal constitution cannot be consigned to
mere chance, and is accordingly to be anticipated only from the free
play of forces that we discern in history. The question arises, there
fore, as to whether a series of circumstances without plan or purpose
can deserve the name of history at all, and whether in the mere con
cept of history there is not already contained also the concept of a ne
cessity which choice itself is compelled to serve.
Here it is primarily a question of our ascertaining the concept of
history.
Not everything that happens is on that account an object of his
tory; natural circumstances, for example, owe their historical charac
ter, if they attain it, merely to the influence which they have had upon
human actions; still less by far, however, do we regard as a historical
object that which takes place according to a known rule, periodically
recurs, or is in general a consequence that can be calculated a priori.
If we wanted to speak of a history of nature in the true sense of the
word, we should have to picture nature as though, apparently free in
its productions, it had gradually brought forth the whole multiplicity
thereof through constant departures from a primordial original; which
would then be a history, not of natural objects (which is properly the
description of nature), but of generative nature itself. Now how would
we view nature in a history of this sort? We would view her, so to
speak, as ordering and managing in various ways with one and the
same sum or proportion offerees, which she could never exceed; we
should thus regard her, to be sure, as acting freely in this creation,
but not on that account as working in utter lawlessness. Nature
would thus become an object of history, on the one hand, through the
appearance of freedom in her productions, since in fact we would be
unable to determine a priori the directions of her productive activity,
although there would be no doubt at all that these directions had their
specific law; but she would also be an object, on the other hand,
through the confinement and conformity to law inherent in her, owing
to the proportion of the forces at her command; whence it is therefore
apparent that history comes about neither with absolute lawfulness
nor with absolute freedom either, but exists only where a single ideal
is realized under an infinity of deviations, in such a way that, not the
particular detail indeed, but assuredly the whole, is in conformity
thereto.
But now such a successive realizing of an ideal, where only
the progress as a whole, as it might be
200 System of Transcendental Idealism [588-90]
A
The first question which can justifiably be asked of a philosophy of his
tory is, no doubt, how a history is conceivable at all, since if everything
that exists is posited for each of us only through his own conscious
ness, the whole of past history can likewise be posited for each through
his consciousness alone. Now we do in fact also maintain that no indi
vidual consciousness could be posited, with all the determinations it is
posited with, and which necessarily belong to it, unless the whole of
history had gone before; and if we needed to do the trick, this could
very easily be shown by means of examples. Thus past history admit
tedly belongs merely to appearance, just as does the individuality of
consciousness itself; it is therefore no more, but also no less real for
each of us than his own individuality is. This particular individuality
presupposes this particular period, of such and such a character, such
and such a degree of culture, etc.; but such a period is impossible with
out the whole of past history. Historiography, which otherwise has no
object save that of explaining the present state of the world, could thus
equally set out from the current situation and infer to past history,
and it would be no uninteresting endeavor to see how the whole of the
past could be derived from this in a strictly necessary manner.
Now it might be objected to this account that past history is not
posited with each individual consciousness, nor is the whole of the
past posited with any, but only the main happenings thereof, which
are indeed recognizable as such only through the fact that they have
extended their influence up to the present time, and so far as the indi
viduality of each single person; but to this we reply, in the first place,
that a history exists only for those upon whom the past has operated,
and even for these, only to the extent that it has worked upon them;
and secondly, that all that has ever been in history is also truly con*
nected, or will be, with the individual consciousness of each, not
immediately, maybe, but certainly by means of innumerable linkages,
of such a kind that if one could point them out it would also become
obvious that the whole of the past was necessary in order to put this
consciousness together. But now it is admittedly certain that, just
as the great majority of men in every age have never had any exist
ence in the world wherein history properly belongs, so also is this
true of a multitude of happenings. For just as
202 System of Transcendental Idealism [591-92]
B
That the concept of history embodies the notion of an infinite
tendency to progress、has been sufficiently shown above. But it
cannot, indeed, be straightway concluded from this that the human
race is infinitely perfectible. For those who deny it could equally
well maintain that man is no more possessed of a history than the
animal, being confined, on the contrary, to an eternal circuit of ac
tions, in which, like Ixion upon his wheel, he revolves unceasingly,
and despite continuous oscillations and at times even seeming devia
tions from the line of curvature, still constantly finds
[592-94] Progress, Freedom and Necessity 203
himself back at the point from which he started. There is all the less
expectation, moreover, of arriving at a sensible answer to this ques
tion, in that those who purport to resolve it, either for or against, find
themselves in the greatest perplexity as to the standard whereby
progress is to be measured. Some address themselves to the moral ad
vances of mankind, of which we should certainly be glad to possess the
yardstick; others, to progress in the arts and sciences, although, seen
from the historical (practical) standpoint, this represents a regress, or
at best a movement against the course of history, on which point we
could appeal to history itself, and to the judgment and example of
those nations (such as the Romans), who may be termed classical in
the historical sense. But if the sole object of histoiy is the gradual re
alization of the rule of law, there remains to us, even as a historical
measure of man's progress, only the gradual approximation to this
goal, whose final attainment, however, can neither be inferred from
experience, so far as it has hitherto unfolded, nor be theoretically dem
onstrated a priori, but will be only an eternal article of faith to man as
he acts and works.
C
We now pass on, however, to the primary characteristic of history,
namely that it should exhibit a union of freedom and necessity, and be
possible through this union alone.
But now it is just this union of freedom and lawfulness in action
which we have already deduced to be necessary, from an entirely di&
ferent point of view, as following simply from the concept of history it
self
The universal rule of law is a condition of freedom, since without
it there is no guarantee of the latter. For freedom that is not guaran
teed by a universal order of nature exists only precariously, and—as in
the majority of our contemporary states—is a plant that flourishes
only parasitically, tolerated in general by way of a necessary inconsis
tency, but in such wise that the individual is never certain of his free
dom. That is not how it should be. Freedom should not be a favor
granted, or a good that may be enjoyed only as a forbidden fruit. It
must be guaranteed by an order that is as open and unalterable as
that of nature.
But now this order can in fact be realized only through freedom,
and its establishment is entrusted wholly and solely to freedom.
This is a contradiction. That which is the first condition of outward
freedom is, for that very reason, no less necessary than freedom
itself. And it is likewise to be realized only through
204 System of Transcendental Idealism [594-95]
freedom, that is, its emergence is consigned to chance. How can this
contradiction be reconciled?
The only way of resolving it is that in freedom itself there
should again be necessity; but how, then, can such a resolution be con
ceived of?
We arrive here at the supreme problem of transcendental phi
losophy, which has admittedly been set forth above (II), but has not
been resolved.
Freedom is to be necessity, and necessity freedom. But now in
contrast to freedom, necessity is nothing else but the unconscious.
That which exists in me without consciousness is involuntaiy; that
which exists with consciousness is in me through my willing.
To say that necessity is again to be present in freedom,
amounts, therefore, to saying that through freedom itself, and in that
I believe myself to act freely, something I do not intend is to come
about unconsciously, ie, without my consent; or, to put it otherwise,
the conscious, or that freely determining activity which we deduced
earlier on, is to be confronted with an unconscious, whereby out of the
most uninhibited expression of freedom there arises unawares some
thing wholly involuntary, and perhaps even contrary to the agent's
will, which he himself could never have realized through his willing.
This statement, however paradoxical it may seem, is yet nothing other
than a mere transcendental expression of the generally accepted and
assumed relationship between freedom and a hidden necessity, at
times called fate and at times providence, though neither of these
terms expresses any clear idea; a relationship whereby men through
their own free action, and yet against their will, must become cause of
something which they never wanted, or by which, conversely, some
thing must go astray or come to naught which they have sought for
freely and with the exertion of all their powers.
Such intervention of a hidden necessity into human freedom is
presupposed, not only, say, in tragedy, whose whole existence rests
on that presumption, but even in normal doing and acting. Without
such a presumption one can will nothing aright; without it, the dispo
sition to act quite regardless of consequences, as duty eiijoins us, could
never inspire a man's mind. For if no sacrifice is possible without the
conviction that the species we belong to can never cease to progress,
how is this conviction itself possible, if it is wholly and solely based
upon freedom? There must be something here that is higher than hu
man freedom, and on which alone we can reckon with assurance in
doing and acting; something without which a man could never
venture to undertake an act fraught with major consequences, since
even the most perfect calculation thereof can be so completely
[595-96] Moral Order as Communal Endeavor 205
can be neither subject nor object, nor both at once, but only the abso
lute identity, in which is no duality at all, and which, precisely because
duality is the condition of all consciousness, can never attain thereto.
This eternal unknown, which, like the everlasting sun in the realm of
spirits, conceals itself behind its own unclouded light, and though
never becoming an object, impresses its identity upon all free actions,
is simultaneously the same for all intelligences, the invisible root of
which all intelligences are but powers, and the eternal mediator be
tween the self-determining subjective within us, and the olyective or
intuitant; at once the ground of lawfulness in freedom, and of freedom
in the lawfulness of the object.
But now it is easy to see that this absolutely identical principle,
which is already divided in the first act of consciousness, and by this
separation generates the entire system of finitude, cannot, in fact,
have any predicates whatever; for it is the absolutely simple, and thus
can have no predicates drawn either from intelligence or free agency,
and hence, too, can never be an object of knowledge, being an object
only that is eternally presupposed in action, that is, an object of belief.
But now if this absolute is the true ground of harmony between
objective and subjective in the free action, not only of the individual,
but of the entire species, we shall be likeliest to find traces of this eter
nal and unalterable identity in the lawfulness which runs, like the
weaving of an unknown hand, through the free play of choice in his
tory.
Now if our reflection be directed merely to the unconscious or
objective aspect in all action, we are obliged to suppose all free acts,
and thus the whole of history, to be absolutely predetermined, not by a
conscious foreordaining, but by a wholly blind one, finding expression
in the obscure concept of destiny; and this is the system of fatalism. If
reflection be directed solely to the subjective in its arbitrary determin
ing, we arrive at a system of absolute lawlessness, the true system of
irreligion and atheism^ namely the claim that in all doing and acting
there is neither law nor necessity anywhere. But if reflection be el
evated to that absolute which is the common ground of the harmony
between freedom and intelligence, we reach the system of providence,
that is, religion in the only true sense of the word.
But now if this absolute, which can everywhere only reveal it
self, had actually and fully revealed itself in history, or were ever to do
so, it would at once make an end of the appearance of freedom. This
perfect revelation would come about if free action were to coincide
210 System of Transcendental Idealism [601-3]
Problem: To explain how the self itself can become conscious of the
original harmony between subjective and objective
Solution
I
1. All action can be understood only through an original unification of
freedom and necessity.1 The proof is that every action, alike of the in
dividual and of the entire species,must be conceived of, qua action, as
'and nature, insofar as it is this, provides for us the first answer to the
question, how or by what means this absolute harmony of necessity and free
dom, postulated for the sake of making action possible, can again itself be
come objective to us.
PART FIVE
through a single absolute harmony, which has divided itself, for the
sake of appearing, into conscious and unconscious activity.
2the speculative and original proof
^or nature is there presented as purposive in the sense that the inten
tion to create is insisted on. The point, however, is that the highest degree of
purposiveness appears precisely where intention and purpose are absent.
216 System of Transcendental Idealism [608-9]
to us, says Kant; the interpretation of its cipher yields us the appear
ance of freedom in ourselves. In the natural product we still find side
by side what in free action has been separated for purposes of appear
ance. Every plant is entirely what it should be; what is free therein is
necessary, and what is necessary is free. Man is forever a broken frag
ment, for either his action is necessary, and then not free, or free, and
then not necessary and according to law. The complete appearance of
freedom and necessity unified in the external world therefore yields
me organic nature only,1 and this could already have been inferred be
forehand from the place that nature occupies, in theoretical philoso
phy, in the series of productions; seeing that, according to our distinc
tions, nature itself is already a producing become objective, and to that
extent therefore approximates to free action, but is nevertheless an
unconscious intuiting of producing, and hence to that extent is itself
again a blind producing.
Now this contradiction, whereby one and the same product is at
once a blind product, and yet is purposive, is utterly inexplicable in
any system except that of transcendental idealism, inasmuch as every
other denies either the purposiveness of the products, or the mechan
ism involved in bringing them about, and so must do away with this
same coexistence. One possibility is to suppose that matter shapes
itself automatically into purposive products, whereby it at least be
comes intelligible how matter and the concept of purpose interfuse
in the products; and then one either ascribes absolute reality to mat
ter, as happens in hylozoism, a nonsensical system, inasmuch as it
supposes matter itself to be intelligent; or else not, in which case
matter must be thought of as merely the mode of intuition of an intel
ligent being, so that the concept of purpose and the object thereupon
merge, in fact, not in matter, but in the intuition of that intelligence,
whereby hylozoism itself then leads back once more to transcendental
idealism. The other possibility is to suppose matter to be absolutely
inert, and to have the purposiveness in its products brought about by
an intelligence outside it, in such a way that the concept of this
purposiveness must have preceded production itself; but then there
is no seeing how concept and object can have been everlastingly
interfused, or how—in a word—the product can be a work, not of arti
fice, but of nature. For the difference between artifact and natural
product resides precisely in this, that in the former the concept is im
pressed only upon the surface of the object, while in
the latter it has gone over into the object itself and is utterly insepa
rable therefrom. But now this absolute identity of the purposive con
cept with the object itself is attributable only to a type of production in
which conscious and unconscious activity are united; but this in turn
is possible only within an intelligence. But now it is readily intelli
gible how a creative intelligence should be able to present a world to
itself, yet not how it could do so to others outside itself. So here once
more we find ourselves driven back upon transcendental idealism.
The purposiveness of nature, alike in the large and in individual
products, can be grasped only through an intuition in which the con
cept of the concept and the object itself are originally and inseparably
united; for then indeed the product will have to appear as purposive,
since the production itself was already determined by that principle
which separates, for the sake of consciousness, into the free and the
nonfree; and yet again the concept of purpose cannot be thought to
have preceded production, since both, in this intuition, were still in
separable. Now that all teleological modes of explanation, eg, those
which have the purposive concept that corresponds to the conscious
activity taking precedence over the object that corresponds to the un
conscious activity, in fact do away with all true explanation of nature,
and thereby themselves become pernicious to knowledge in its full
ness, is so palpably self-evident from what has gone before, that even
by way of examples it requires no further elucidation.
II
Nature, in its blind and mechanical purposiveness, admittedly repre
sents to me an original identity of the conscious and unconscious ac
tivities, but [for all that,] it does not present this identity to me as one
whose ultimate ground resides in the self itself. The transcendental
philosopher assuredly recognizes that the principle of this [harmony]
is that ultimate in ourselves1 which already undergoes division in the
primary act of selfconsciousness, and on which the whole of conscious
ness, with all its determinations, is founded; but the self itself is not
aware of this. Now the aim of our whole science was in fact precisely
this, of explaining how the ultimate ground of the harmony between
subjective and objective becomes an object to the self itself.
An intuition must therefore be exhibitable in the intelligence
itself, whereby in one and the same
appearance the self is at once conscious and unconscious for itselft and
it is by means of such an intuition that we first bring forth the intelli
gence, as it were, entirely out of itself; by such an intuition, therefore,
that we also first resolve the entire [the supreme] problem of transcen
dental philosophy (that of explaining the congruence between subjec
tive and objective).
By the first specification, namely that conscious and uncon
scious activity become objective in one and the same intuition, this in
tuition is distinguished from that which we were able to deduce1 in
practical philosophy, where the intelligence was conscious only for in
ner intuition, but for outer remained unconscious.
By the second specification, namely that in one and the same in
tuition the self become simultaneously conscious for itself, and uncon
scious, the intuition here postulated is distinguished from that which
we have in the case of natural products, where we certainly recognize
this identity, but not as an identity whose principle lies in the self it
self. Every organism is a monogram2 of that original identity, but in
order to recognize itself in that reflected image, the self must already
have recognized itself directly in the identity in question.
We have only to analyze the features of this intuition we have
now deduced, in order to discover the intuition itself; and, to judge
beforehand, it can be no other than the intuition of art.
'That which lies, for the free act, in an infinite progress, is to be, in the
current engendering, a thing present, is to become actual, objective, in some
thing finite.
[614-15] Deduction of the Art Product 221
xAt that point the free activity has wholly gone over into the olyective,
the necessary aspect. Hence production is free at the outset, whereas the
product appears as an absolute identity of the free activity with the necessary
one.
2[This paragraph canceled in the author's copy. - Tr.]
3For it (the intelligence) is itself the producer; but at the same time
this identity has wholly broken loose therefrom, and become totally objective
to the intelligence, i.e., totally objective to itself,
4the primordial self.
222 System of Transcendental Idealism [613-14]
will appear to the intelligence as something lying above the latter, and
which, in contrast to freedom, brings an element of the unintended to
that which was begun with consciousness and intention.
This unchanging identity, which can never attain to conscious
ness, and merely radiates back from the product, is for the producer
precisely what destiny is for the agent, namely a dark unknown force
which supplies the element of completeness or objectivity to the piece
work of freedom; and as that power is called destiny, which through
our free action realizes, without our knowledge and even against our
will, goals that we did not envisage^ so likewise that incomprehensible
agency which supplies objectivity to the conscious, without the coopera
tion of freedom, and to some extent in opposition to freedom (wherein is
eternally dispersed what in this production is united), is denominated
by means of the obscure concept oigenius.
The product we postulate is none other than the product of ge
nius, or, since genius is possible only in the arts, the product of art.
The deduction is concluded, and our next task is simply to show
by thoroughgoing analysis that all the features of the production we
have postulated come together in the aesthetic.
The fact that all aesthetic production rests upon a conflict of ac
tivities can be justifiably inferred already from the testimony of all art
ists, that they are involuntarily driven to create their works, and that
in producing them they merely satisfy an irresistible urge of their own
nature; for if every urge proceeds from a contradiction in such wise
that, given the contradiction, free activity becomes involuntary, the ar
tistic urge also must proceed from such a feeling of inner contradiction.
But since this contradiction sets in motion the whole man with all his
forces, it is undoubtedly one which strikes at the ultimate in him, the
root of his whole being.1 It is as if, in the exceptional man (which art
ists above all are, in the highest sense of the word), that unalterable
identity, on which all existence is founded, had laid aside the veil
wherewith it shrouds itself in others, and, just as it is directly aflected
by things, so also works directly back upon everything. Thus it can
only be the contradiction between conscious and unconscious in the
free act which sets the artistic urge in motion; just as,conversely, it can
be given to art alone to pacify our endless striving, and likewise to re
solve the final and uttermost contradiction within us. Just as aesthetic
Attributes ... to a bounty freely granted by his own nature, and thus
to a coincidence of the unconscious with the conscious activity [Author*s copy].
2from the standpoint of mere reflection.
224 System of Transcendental Idealism [618-19]
inborn through the free bounty of nature; and this is what we may
call, in a word, the element ofpoetry in art.
It is self-evident from this, however, that it would be utterly fu
tile to ask which of the two constituents should have preference over
the other, since each of them, in fact, is valueless without the other,
and it is only in conjunction that they bring forth the highest. For al
though what is not attained by practice, but is born in us, is commonly
regarded as the nobler, the gods have in fact tied the very exercise of
that innate power so closely to a man% serious application, his indus
try and thought, that even where it is inborn, poetry without art en
genders, as it were, only dead products, which can give no pleasure to
any man's mind, and repel all judgment and even intuition, owing to
the wholly blind force which operates therein. It is, on the contrary,
far more to be expected that art without poetry should be able to
achieve something, than poetry without art; partly because it is not
easy for a man to be by nature wholly without poetry, though many
are wholly without art; and partly because a persistent study of the
thoughts of great masters is able in some degree to make up for the
initial want of objective power. All that can ever arise from this, how
ever, is merely a semblance of poetry, which, by its superficiality and
by many other indications, eg, the high value it attaches to the mere
mechanics of art, the poverty of form in which it operates, etc., is eas
ily distinguishable in contrast to the unfathomable depth which the
true artist, though he labors with the greatest diligence, involuntarily
imparts to his work, and which neither he nor anyone else is wholly
able to penetrate.
But now it is also self-evident that just as poetry and art are
each individually incapable of engendering perfection, so a divided ex
istence of both is equally inadequate to the task? It is therefore clear
that, since the identity of the two can only be innate, and is utterly im
possible and unattainable through freedom, perfection is possible only
through genius, which, for that very reason, is for the aesthetic what
the self is for philosophy, namely the supreme absolute reality, which
never itself becomes objective, but is the cause of everything that is so.
Neither has priority over the other. It is, indeed, simply the equipoise
of the two (art and poetry) which is reflected in the work of art.
[619-20] Artistic Production 225
of art. There are, admittedly, sublime works of art, and beauty and
sublimity in a certain respect are opposed to each other, in that a land
scape, for example, can be beautiful without therefore being sublime,
and vice versa. However, the opposition between beauty and sublimity
is one which occurs only in regard to the object, not in regard to the
subject of intuition. For the difference between the beautiful and the
sublime work of art consists simply in this, that where beauty is
present, the infinite contradiction is eliminated in the object itself;
whereas when sublimity is present, the conflict is not reconciled in the
object itself, but merely uplifted to a point at which it is involuntarily
eliminated in the intuition; and this, then, is much as if it were to be
eliminated in the object.1 It can also be shown very easily that sublim
ity rests upon the same contradiction as that on which beauty rests.
For whenever an object is spoken of as sublime, a magnitude is admit
ted by the unconscious activity which it is impossible to accept into the
conscious one: whereupon the self is thrown into a conflict with itself
which can end only in an aesthetic intuition, whereby both activities
are brought into unexpected harmony; save only that the intuition}
which here lies not in the artist, but in the intuiting subject himself, is
a wholly involuntary one, in that the sublime (quite unlike the merely
strange, which similarly confronts the imagination with a contradic
tion, though one that is not worth the trouble of resolving) sets all the
forces of the mind in motion, in order to resolve a contradiction which
threatens our whole intellectual existence.
Now that the characteristics of the work of art have been de
rived, its difference from all other products has simultaneously been
brought to light.
For the art-product differs from the organic product of
nature primarily in these respects: [a) that the organic being still
exhibits unseparated what the aesthetic production displays after
separation, though united; b)] that the organic production does not
proceed from consciousness, or therefore from the infinite contradic
tion, which is the condition of aesthetic production. Hence [if beauty
is essentially the resolution of an infinite conflict] the organic product
of nature will likewise not necessarily be beautiful^ and if it is so,
its beauty will appear as altogether
"his passage replaced in the author's copy by the following: For al
though there are sublime works of art, and sublimity is customarily con
trasted with beauty, there is actually no true objective opposition between
beauty and sublimity; the truly and absolutely beautiful is invariably also
sublime, and the sublime (if it truly is so) is beautiful as well.
[622-23] Art and Science 227
of genius, but because this same problem whose solution can be found
by genius, is also soluble mechanically. Such, for example, is the
Newtonian system of gravitation, which could have been a discovery of
genius, and in its first discoverer, Kepler, really was so, but could
equally also have been a wholly scientific discoveiy, which it actually
became in the hands of Newton. Only what art brings forth is simply
and solely possible through genius, since in every task that art has dis
charged, an infinite contradiction is reconciled. What science brings
forth, can be brought forth through genius, but it is not necessarily en
gendered through this. It therefore is and remains problematic in sci
ence, fe., one can, indeed, always say definitely where it is not
present, but never where it is. There are but few indications which al
low us to infer genius in the sciences; (that one has to infer it is al
ready evidence of the peculiarity of the matter). It is, for example, as
suredly not present, where a whole, such as a system, arises piecemeal
and as though by putting together. One would thus have to suppose,
conversely, that genius is present, where the idea of the whole has
manifestly preceded the individual parts. For since the idea of the
whole cannot in fact become clear save through its development in the
individual parts, while those parts, on the other hand, are possible
only through the idea of the whole, there seema to be a contradiction
here which is possible only through an act of genius, i.e., an unex
pected concurrence of the unconscious with the conscious activity. An
other ground for the presumption of genius in the sciences would be if
someone were to say and maintain things whose meaning he could not
possibly have understood entirely, either owing to the period at which
he lived, or by reason of his other utterances; so that he has thus as
serted something apparently with consciousness, which he could in
fact only have asserted unconsciously. It could, however be readily
shown in a number of ways, that even these grounds for the presump
tion may be delusive in the extreme.
Genius is thus marked off from everything that consists in mere
talent or skill by the fact that through it a contradiction is resolved,
which is soluble absolutely and otherwise by nothing else. In all pro
ducing, even of the most ordinary and commonplace sort, an uncon
scious activity operates along with the conscious one; but only a pro
ducing whose condition was an infinite opposition of the two activities
is an aesthetic producing, and one that is only possible through genius.
Art and Philosophy 229
§3 Corollaries
Now that we have deduced the nature and character of the art-product
as completely as was necessary for purposes of the present enquiry,
there is nothing more we need do except to set forth the relation which
the philosophy of art bears to the whole system of philosophy.
1. The whole of philosophy starts, and must start, from a prin
ciple which, qua absolutely identical, is utterly nonobjective. But now
how is this absolutely nonobjective to be called up to consciousness and
understood—a thing needful, if it is the condition for understanding
the whole of philosophy? That it can no more be apprehended through
concepts than it is capable of being set forth by means of them, stands
in no need of proof Nothing remains, therefore, but for it to be set
forth in an immediate intuition, though this is itself in turn inconceiv
able, and, since its object is to be something utterly nonobjective,
seems, indeed, to be self-contradictory. But now were such an intu
ition in fact to exist, having as its object the absolutely identical, in it
self neither subjective nor objective, and were we, in respect of this in
tuition, which can only be an intellectual one, to appeal to immediate
experience, then how, in that case, could even this intuition be in turn
posited objectively? How, that is, can it be established beyond doubt,
that such an intuition does not rest upon a purely subjective decep
tion, if it possesses no objectivity that is universal and acknowledged
by all men? This universally acknowledged and altogether incontest
able objectivity of intellectual intuition is art itself. For the aesthetic
intuition simply is the intellectual intuition become objective.1
叮he preceding is replaced in the author's copy by: The whole of phi
losophy starts, and must start, from a principle which, as the absolute prin
ciple! is also at the same time the absolutely identical. An absolutely simple
and identical cannot be grasped or communicated through description, nor
through concepts at all. It can only be intuited. Such an intuition is the or
gan of all philosophy. —But this intuition, which is an intellectual rather
than a sensory one, and has as its object neither the objective nor the subjec
tive, but the absolutely identical, in itself neither sulyective nor objective, is
itself merely an internal one, which cannot in turn become objective for itself:
it can become objective only through a second intuition. This second intuition
is the aesthetic.
230 System of Transcendental Idealism [625-26]
one and the same activity. But this very fact, that where the condi
tions of emergence are otherwise entirely similar, the one takes itfi ori
gin from outside consciousness, the other from within it, constitutes
the eternal difference between them which can never be removed.
To be sure, then, the real world evolves entirely from the same
original opposition as must also give rise to the world of art, which has
equally to be viewed as one great whole, and which in all its individual
products depicts only the one infinite. But outside consciousness this
opposition is only infinite inasmuch as an infinity is exhibited by the
objective world as a whole, and never by any individual object;
whereas for art this opposition is an infinite one in regard to every
single object, and infinity is exhibited in every one of its products. For
if aesthetic production proceeds from freedom, and if it is precisely for
freedom that this opposition of conscious and unconscious activities is
an absolute one, there is properly speaking but one absolute work of
art, which may indeed exist in altogether different versions, yet is still
only one, even though it should not yet exist in its most ultimate form.
It can be no objection to this view, that if so, the very liberal use now
made of the predicate *work of art* will no longer do. Nothing is a
work of art which does not exhibit an infinite, either directly, or at
least by reflection. Are we to call works of art, for example, even such
compositions as by nature depict only the individual and subjective?
In that case we shall have to bestow this title also upon every epigram,
which preserves merely a momentary sensation or current impression;
though indeed the great masters who have practiced in such genres
were seeking to bring forth objectivity itself only through the totality
of their creations, and used them simply as a means to depict a whole
infinite life, and to project it back from a many-faceted mirror.
2. If aesthetic intuition is merely transcendental1 intuition be
come objective, it is self-evident that art is at once the only true and
eternal organ and document of philosophy, which ever and again con
tinues to speak to us of what philosophy cannot depict in external
form, namely the unconscious element in acting and producing, and its
original identity with the conscious. Art is paramount to the philoso
pher, precisely because it opens to him, as it were, the holy of holies,
where burns in eternal and original unity, as if in a single flame, that
which in nature and history is rent asunder, and in life and action, no
less than in thought, must forever fly apart. The view of nature,
which the philosopher frames artificially, is for art the original
mythology is itself to arise, which shall be the creation, not of some in
dividual author, but of a new race, personifying, as it were, one single
poet—that is a problem whose solution can be looked for only in the
future destinies of the world, and in the course of history to come.
phase, whereby all these intuitions acquire for it the same meaning as
they have for the self. But what this final phase may be, will appear
from what follows.
If the self were to continue to be purely objective, self-intuition
could go on rising to higher powers ad infinitum, but the process
would merely lengthen the series of products in nature without ever
giving rise to consciousness. The latter is possible only if that purely
objective element in the self becomes objective to the self itself. But
the ground of this cannot lie in the self itself. For the self is absolutely
identical with this purely objective element. The ground can therefore
lie only outside a self which, by progressive limitation, has gradually
been restricted into an intelligence, and even to the point of individ
uality. But outside the individual, i.e., independent of him, there is
only the intelligence itself. But [according to the mechanism deduced]
the intelligence itself where it exists, must restrict itself into individu
ality. Hence the ground we are looking for outside the individual can
only lie in another individual.
The absolutely objective can only become an object to the self it
self through the influence of other rational beings. But the intention
of such influence must already have been present in these beings.
Hence, freedom is always presupposed in nature (nature does not en
gender it), and where it is not already there from the first, it cannot
arise. It therefore becomes evident here, that although up to this
point nature is entirely similar to the intelligence, and traverses with
it the same sequence of powers, freedom, if it exists (though that it
does so, cannot be theoretically demonstrated), must be superior
(naiuraprior) to nature.
From this point onwards, therefore, we begin a new sequence of
acts, which are not possible through nature, and in fact leave it be
hind.
The absolutely objective, or the law-governed nature of intuit
ing, becomes an object to the self itself. But intuiting becomes an ob
ject to the intuitant only through willing. The objective factor in will
ing is intuiting as such, or the pure lawfulness of nature; the subjec
tive factor, an ideal activity directed upon this lawfulness as such.
The act in which this occurs is the absolute act of will.
The absolute act of will itself in turn becomes an object to the
self, in that the objective element in willing, directed to something ex
ternal, becomes an object to the self in the form of a natural urge,
while the subjective, directed to lawfulness as such, is objectified in
the form of absolute will, Le.t as a categorical imperative. But this,
too, is impossible without an activity superior to them both. This
236 System of Transcendental Idealism [633-34]
Beauty, 225-7
Being, 16-19, 32, 35, 40, 57-8, 153, 185
Berkeley, G., 153
Breadth, 88
Death, 128
Demand, 163,188,190
Descartes, R., xv, 72
Despotism, 196
Destiny, see Fate
Determination, 10-11, 36, 59-60, 63-4, 70-1, 83, 96, 100,
108-10,117-18,139-40, 145-6,150,164-7,179,183,
189, 208 see also Predetermination, Self-determination
Determinism, xixt xxxi-ii
Dialecticv xiii-v
Dimensions, 86, 126
Dogmatism, 17-18, 35, 37, 43, 54, 58, 68, 70, 74
Drive, 166, 170, 177-8,185-6,194-5
Index 241
Duty, 204-5
Education, 170
Electricity, 87-8, 91, 126
Empiricism, 61, 65, 70, 99, 122, 127
Ethics, xxxi, 189
Experience, xiv, xxv, 10, 92-3, 108, 136, 197
Extensity (and Intensity), 103-5, 111, 145,147
Facticity, xxv, 34
Fatalism, xxx, 209
Fate, 116,169, 204-5, 211-12, 222-3
Fichte, J.G., xi-xvii, xix-xxiii, xxv, xxvii-viii, xxxii, xxxiv, 28
Force, 79-81, 83-92,105,114,173» 197,199
Form (and Content), 20-1, 49-50, 122
Freedom, xi-xiii, xvii-xx, xxx, xxxii, 3, 24, 26-8, 30, 33,
35, 42, 47, 49, 65, 75, 102, 112,116-19, 128-32,140,
150,152,156-9,162-200, 203-25, 231, 235-6
Freud, S., xxxiii
Happiness, 189,194
Harmony, Pre-established, xv, xviii, xxxi, 4, 11-12, 35,
129,154,161-5, 168, 174,180,192, 207-15, 217, 221,
223-6
242 System of Transcendental Idealism
Hearing, 123-4
Hegel, G.W.F., xv, xvii, xxxiv
Heidegger, M., xix> xxii, xxxiii
Hemsterhuis, F., 92
History, xv, xix-xx, xxiii, xxvi, xxx-i, xxxv, 4, 34,
198-203, 206-13, 231
Philosophy of, xiv, xvii, xix, 201
Hylozoism, 216
Kant, I., xi, xv-viii, xxi-iv, xxvii, xxxiv, 31, 85, 95,
99. 112. 176. 188. 191. 193. 216
Kepler, J., 228
Kielmeyer, 124
Knowledge, xxiii, xxx, xxxiv, 1-2, 5-7, 9-10. 15-23, 26-7,
30, 57, 73-4, 93,113,133,151-4,166,183-5
Science of, xi, xiii, xviii, xix, xxi, xxiii, xxv,
xxviii, xxxiv, 2, 16, 19, 21, 31, 34
Language, 137-8
Law, xii, xxxi, 6,14,128,157,169,185-6,189-92,195,
198-203, 20743, 216
Moral, 188-90,194 see also System
Leibniz, G.W. von, 35, 92,120,124, 129,154
Length, 86-9
Life, 124-7
244 System of Tra nscende nta 1 Idealism
Light, 75,124-5,127,153
Limitation (of Activity), xxvi, xxix, 16, 35-44, 47-73,
76-87, 90, 94, 97-102,106,115-18,121,123,125,
130*3,140-2,149-50,163-74,177-9, 232, 235
Locke, J.)154
Logic, 20-1, 24,140
Pain, 186
Passivity, 37, 60-1, 64-7, 70-1, 78-9,100-1, 131-2,168,
171,194
Past, 117-19, 132, 201
Phenomenology (Hegel), xiv, xxiv, xxxiv
Philosophy, 7,14,18-19, 28, 49-50, 75, 80, 224, 229-33
Moral, 155
Practical, xv, xxiii, xxvi, 4, 11, 129, 149, 155, 157,
218
Theoretical, 50, 63, 134, 216
Theoretical and Practical, xii-iv, xvii-xx, 6,11, 33-5,
41» 50, 149,151,157-8,171, 201
Transcendental, see Idealism
246 System of Transcendental Idealism
Real and Ideal (Activity), 40-3, 46, 49-52, 62・3, 67, 70-2,
98, 102, 131-2,149-50,157-8, 163,171-2,177,180-7,
232
Realism, xxvi, 14, 41, 58, 73, 116, 173 see also Dogmatism
Reason, xvi-vii, xx-xxi, xxv, xxxv, 6, 8, 117-18, 176, 192,
197, 200, 236
Practical, xvii
Reciprocity, 110-14,121, 126, 133,142, 146,150
Reflection, xiv, 6,13, 24, 48, 83, 95,130-1, 134-5,140-6,
150-1,157,171-3,176-9, 183, 188, 192, 209, 234
Reinhold, K.L., 28
Religion, xx, 209
Reproduction, 102
Index 247
Scepticism, 8, 15, 21
Schematism, xvi, 99, 136-8,140-50, 176
Schiller, F., xxxvi
Schopenhauer, A.,xxxiii, xxxv
Science, Natural, 3, 5-6,14,17, 30, 52, 81, 91, 227-8
Secondary Qualities, 179
Self, xii, xvii-viii, xxvii, xxx, xxxiv, 3, 5, 7, 25-57,
61-85, 90-119,127,13i・5, 138,146-9,152-8,162-3
174-81,184-94, 212-13, 217-20, 224, 230-5 see also
Intelligence, Intuition
Self-Consciousness, xiv, xxvii-xxx,*-xxiii-v, 2, 14-18, 25,
302 36-51, 56-61, 68-9, 73, 90, 94・5,115,122,131,
148,157-9,167,171,177-8,185, 188, 217, 233-4
History of, xxxiv, 2, 50, 90-2, 116, 236
Self-Determination, 155-62, 167, 173, 175, 187-95
Self-in-itself, 69-70, 75,181
Self-Interest, 189, 195
Sensation, 54-76, 91, 100, 103, 123-6, 132, 135, 149-50, 156, 234
Sense-object, 100, 173
Sensibility, 126
Sight, 25,123-4
Simultaneity, 111, 114
Sleep, 135
Soul, 153-4
Space, 28, 32, 58, 84, 103-8, 111, 120, 132, 135-7, 140-7,
150,164,173
Species, 200, 202, 205-9. 212
Spinoza, B., xix, xxxiii, 17
Spirit, xxxiv-v, 74, 128,169, 210, 232
248 System of Transcendental Idealism
Unconscious, xxvi, xxvii-xxxii, 58, 75, 77, 79, 90, 94, 100-1,
107,129,151,159, 170-1, 204-28, 231, 234, 236
Understanding, 73» 107,137,145,176
Unity (and Plurality), 146-7
Universe, 114-25, 142, 174 see also World
ISBN O-aiaT-lHSd-E
University Press of Virginia
Charlottesville and London
www. upress.virginia. edu