Lori Gruen - Ethics and Animals, An Introduction-61-92
Lori Gruen - Ethics and Animals, An Introduction-61-92
Crocodiles are animals who inhabit human nightmares and with good reason.
Crocodiles hide below the surface and wait until just the right moment to
spring out, toothy mouths ajar, to attack. They are ideal metaphors for the
subconscious. They are also truly frightening predators. The late ecofeminist
philosopher Val Plumwood had a near fatal encounter with a crocodile and
described her terror after enduring a crocodile “death roll.” Her description
of the attack is horrifying:
As I pulled the canoe out into the main current, the rain and wind started up
again. I had not gone more than five or ten minutes down the channel when,
rounding a bend, I saw in midstream what looked like a floating stick – one I
did not recall passing on my way up. As the current moved me toward it, the
stick developed eyes. A crocodile! . . . Although I was paddling to miss the
crocodile, our paths were strangely convergent. I knew it would be close, but I
was totally unprepared for the great blow when it struck the canoe. Again it
struck, again and again, now from behind, shuddering the flimsy craft. As I
paddled furiously, the blows continued. The unheard of was happening; the
canoe was under attack! For the first time, it came to me fully that I was prey.
I realized I had to get out of the canoe or risk being capsized.
The bank now presented a high, steep face of slippery mud. The only
obvious avenue of escape was a paperbark tree near the muddy bank wall. I
made the split-second decision to leap into its lower branches and climb to
safety. I steered to the tree and stood up to jump. At the same instant, the
crocodile rushed up alongside the canoe, and its beautiful, flecked golden
eyes looked straight into mine. . . . The golden eyes glinted with interest. I
tensed for the jump and leapt. Before my foot even tripped the first branch, I
had a blurred, incredulous vision of great toothed jaws bursting from the
water. Then I was seized between the legs in a red-hot pincer grip and whirled
into the suffocating wet darkness.
44
The natural and the normative 45
Few of those who have experienced the crocodile’s death roll have lived to
describe it. It is, essentially, an experience beyond words of total terror. The
crocodile’s breathing and heart metabolism are not suited to prolonged
struggle, so the roll is an intense burst of power designed to overcome the
victim’s resistance quickly. The crocodile then holds the feebly struggling
prey underwater until it drowns. The roll was a centrifuge of boiling
blackness that lasted for an eternity, beyond endurance, but when I seemed
all but finished, the rolling suddenly stopped. My feet touched bottom, my
head broke the surface, and, coughing, I sucked at air, amazed to be alive. The
crocodile still had me in its pincer grip between the legs. I had just begun to
weep for the prospects of my mangled body when the crocodile pitched me
suddenly into a second death roll.
When the whirling terror stopped again I surfaced again, still in the
crocodile’s grip next to a stout branch of a large sandpaper fig growing in the
water. I grabbed the branch, vowing to let the crocodile tear me apart rather
than throw me again into that spinning, suffocating hell. For the first time I
realized that the crocodile was growling, as if angry. I braced myself for
another roll, but then its jaws simply relaxed; I was free.1
point, the hippo puts the impala’s head into her mouth in what looks to be
an effort to revive him. Hippopotamuses are herbivores, so the impala would
not have been a meal for the hippo. On this particular occasion, the hippo’s
efforts to resuscitate the impala fail as the impala’s injuries from the crocodile
attack are too severe. After the impala dies, the hippo wanders away. Almost
instantly the crocodile climbs onto the bank to retrieve the carcass and drags
the dead impala back to the water to eat it.
There is no way of knowing why the hippo did what she did or how often
hippopotamuses exhibit this type of seemingly caring or altruistic behavior
in the wild. We do know that, just as crocodiles are predictable predators,
hippopotamuses are capable of building cross-species relationships.3
These stories, while remarkable in their own right, also raise interesting
questions for us to try to answer. Did the crocodile choose to attack Val Plum-
wood? Did the croc let Plumwood go on purpose? Did the hippo purposely try
to help the impala because she recognized the impala was in mortal danger,
like the dolphins protecting the swimmers discussed in the last chapter, or
was it an instinctual response? If it was instinctual, why did it happen on
this occasion, but not on others? Does it make sense to say that what the
hippopotamus did in trying to save the impala was good, virtuous, or right?
Was what the crocodile did to Plumwood or to the impala wrong? These are
questions about the natural and the normative, the topics of this chapter.
The concept of the “natural” is a fraught one; it can mean many different
things in different contexts. Too often we think we understand what a claim
about what is natural means, but just a little bit of pushing reveals that we may
not be particularly clear. Normativity, as we briefly discussed in Chapter 1,
also has multiple connotations. It sometimes means what is typical, normal,
or expected; it sometimes means what is good; and it sometimes refers to a
combination of what is expected and what is good in the form of a prescription
for action.
In this chapter we’ll explore what is meant by “natural” and what is meant
by “normative” in the context of evaluating the grounds of our ethical obliga-
tions to other animals. We will begin with a very common skeptical response
to the central idea of this book – that we are in ethical relation with other ani-
mals and that our attitudes, decisions, and actions have ethical consequences
for all of us, humans as well as non-humans. When initially presented with
the idea that other animals matter from a moral point of view, skeptics think,
and some even say, “Animals kill, torment, and use other animals, and since
they do it, and since we too are animals, why shouldn’t we?” Since it is natural
for a crocodile to kill and eat an impala, it makes sense to think it is natural
for humans to kill and eat crocodiles or, more generally, to do what serves us
best, even if that means disregarding the interests and needs of other animals.
The idea that nature is distinct from culture can also be seen as self-
defeating. If there were an imperative to “get back to nature,” it would result
from human conceptual and ethical reflection, which, according to the dualis-
tic conception under consideration, is unnatural. This conception of nature,
as William Cronin has so forcefully argued in “Getting Back to the Wrong
Nature: Why We Need to End our Love Affair with Wilderness,” rests on a
profound misunderstanding. Cronin writes, “Viewing nature and ourselves
in such stark, absolute terms leaves us little hope of discovering what an
ethical, sustainable, honorable human place in nature might actually look
like.”4 There is no way to value what is natural, because according to this
understanding of what it means to be natural, the very process of valuing
ends up devaluing nature.
So understanding nature as distinct from culture isn’t particularly sen-
sible. Another proposal for understanding what it means to be doing what
is “natural” is to think of natural behavior as synonymous with instinctual
behavior. The idea here is that when the crocodile attacks the impala the
croc is acting on instinct, and the skeptic’s claim, if we understand natu-
ral to mean instinctual, is that it is instinctual for us to use other animals
to serve our ends. But what exactly is instinct? The notion of “instinct” has
been subject to almost as much conceptual challenge as has “nature,” and
it may be that replacing “natural” with “instinctual” will not be particularly
illuminating. Historically, there were debates among psychologists and ethol-
ogists about what instincts were. Some saw instincts as automatic reactions
to specific stimuli; others saw them as adaptable motivations that underlie
behavior; and still others saw instincts as heritable systems “of co-ordination
within the nervous system as a whole, which when activated find expres-
sion in behaviour culminating in a fixed action pattern.”5 Sometimes the
term “instinctual” has been used interchangeably with the term “innate.”
Yet, here again, we may be exchanging one slippery term for another as there
is a tremendous debate about what constitutes “innateness.”
Commenting on innateness, ethologist Patrick Bateson identifies at least
six meanings for the term: “present at birth; a behavioral difference caused
by a genetic difference; adapted over the course of evolution; unchang-
ing throughout development; shared by all members of a species; and not
To call something biological (or genetic, natural, or innate) is clearly not just
to make a bare scientific statement. It is also to pronounce on the relevance of
experience and the conditions of life . . . The same is true for the contrasting
terms: cultural, acquired, environmental. If something is biological, it is
reasoned, it is physical, preprogrammed and controlled from the inside;
while learning is an accident of personal history, a product of mind, not body.
This echo of an ancient dualism should raise suspicions . . . the traditional
nature–nurture categories are incoherent. I suggest . . . we free ourselves from
the whole set of interlaced conceptual habits that keeps these disputes going.8
All this debate about the meaning of the terms natural, instinctual, or innate
doesn’t erase the possibility that there is something meaningful that the skep-
tic is trying to say. There are some behaviors that seem to be typical to a species.
As we briefly discussed in the last chapter and will return to in Chapter 5,
accurately interpreting the behavior of other animals is an important part
of understanding what their interests are and how our actions may impact
their abilities to satisfy those interests. Recognizing species-typical behaviors,
then, is an important part of understanding other animals. So, to return to
our skeptic’s claim, perhaps what he means when he says that it is natural
for humans to use other animals to serve our ends is that it is part of our
species-typical behavioral repertoire, much as it is for the crocodile. Using
other species for food, clothing, protection, or even entertainment is some-
thing that we, as a species, evolved to do. As a couple of skeptics put it, “it is
an evolutionary necessity to regard one’s own kind as more important than
other species.”9 That we evolved to want to further our own species’ interests,
at the expense of members of other species, if need be, may very well be what
the skeptic means when he says it is natural for us to use other animals.
There are two issues raised by this particular version of the skeptic’s chal-
lenge. First is the issue of understanding what it means to say that a species
evolved to perform certain behaviors or to have certain attitudes. Second,
even if there were a way to establish that performing certain behaviors or
having certain attitudes was natural or a product of evolutionary forces, we
need to ask whether having a preference for one’s own species, what has been
called “speciesism,” is justified. In other words, does the natural justify the
normative?
You probably won’t be surprised, at this point in the discussion, to learn that
there are multiple and contested meanings of the concept of “species” and
that whether a particular population of organisms is classified as a species may
change, even quickly, so particular individuals who are currently members of
one species may later become members of a new species.10 Conversely, individ-
uals who were once members of different species may be classified as a single
species. Our understanding of species relies on various sorts of judgments
based on the reasons we need the classification and how such a classification
will help to organize particular inquiries and practices. Species categoriza-
tions are not, strictly speaking, fixed by nature but rather are constructed by
us to understand the natural world. Without going further into the fascinat-
ing debate about the species concept here, let us posit that “species,” as well as
“species-typical behaviors,” are not simply biologically or naturally given and
are not necessarily immutable, although they are based, in part, on evolved
biological properties, some of which may be intrinsic and others relational.
Given that species is not a biologically determinate classification, species are
not, in evolutionary terms, what natural selection operates on – rather it is
populations or groups, if that.11 If species is a relatively arbitrary unit in evo-
lutionary terms, it does not make sense to suggest, as the skeptic has, that a
preference for members of one’s own species is a product of evolution.
In addition, both empirical and historical examinations show that it simply
is not the case that members of the same lineage, species, or population do
prefer or protect their own. Ethological studies have established that members
of the same species, conspecifics, often compete fiercely with one another to
survive, and in some cases will kill their own kind. Some animals even kill
their own siblings. Great egret chicks are known to peck their youngest sibling
to death and then push him out of the nest.12 Many mammals, from rats to
primates, practice infanticide on conspecifics. Most individuals appear to be
concerned with their own survival, and possibly the survival of their offspring
or other members of their immediate group, not the survival of their species
as a whole. This is also the case among humans. The history of our own
kind is full of examples of mass murders, wars, and genocides. Humans, like
other social animals, are particularly adept at identifying in-groups and out-
groups and granting respect and protection to those in their own group, and
exhibiting contempt and disregard for others, no matter if they are members
of our species or others.
But nature isn’t always red in tooth and claw. There are less frequent, but
regularly documented cases in which members of one species help or protect
11 There are debates about units of selection (e.g., whether genes, cells, organisms, and/or
populations ultimately evolve) among biologists and philosophers. For a philosophically
rich discussion, see Godfrey-Smith 2009. There are some, most notably David Sloan Wilson
and Eliott Sober, who argue that selection can be understood to operate on groups, and
the late Steven Jay Gould, who argued for species selection. See, for a start, Wilson 1993
and Lieberman & Vrba 2005.
12 My colleague Barry Chernoff told me about the case of siblicide among armadillos who
are actually genetically identical twins. So when one armadillo kills her sibling she is, in
a sense, killing herself. He also mentioned that male fish, who look after the young, on
occasion will be forced to kill the mother as she is threatening to kill and eat her young.
52 Ethics and Animals
members of another species – as was the case with the dolphins discussed at
the beginning of the last chapter and the hippopotamus discussed earlier. The
struggle for survival may pit one animal against another, but it also involves
animals cooperating against obstacles and hardships in their environments.
Sometimes this will bring members of different species together for mutual
advantage.
The capacity to identify and favor those within one’s own group, and to
deny resources to or attack those who are outsiders, undoubtedly conferred
some evolutionary advantage on those who exercised this capacity. Yet the fact
that a capacity is evolutionarily advantageous does not have a direct bearing
on whether or not we humans (or other animals), here and now, are ethically
justified in continuing to invoke that capacity. At certain points in our history,
some humans may have experienced greater reproductive success relative
to other humans because the males raped and impregnated the females.
That this practice generated an evolutionary advantage to the group that
practiced rape doesn’t justify rape. The moral permissibility of exercising a
particular capacity, or engaging in a particular action, is not determined by
the evolutionary history or the success of the use of the capacity. As the late
Stephen Jay Gould wrote, “nature favors none and offers no guidelines. The
facts of nature cannot provide moral guidance in any case.”13
One of the capacities that humans have, and perhaps other animals, as
well, is the ability to make decisions about what behavior to engage in and
what course of action to follow. We may make bad choices – eat or drink too
much, have unsafe sex, smoke cigarettes, destroy our environments – but we
are not always destined to act on our bad choice. We can change our behavior.
Appeals to nature do not ethically justify various actions, including the use of
other animals, as we’ll see. Much of what is thought to be natural behavior is,
in fact, conventional behavior, behavior that we can, and should, hold up to
normative scrutiny and ask whether there are reasons to refrain from doing
certain things that we thought, before reflection, were permissible.
There are many human behaviors that feel utterly natural, but, as we have
just seen, it is sometimes difficult to explicate what lies behind that feeling.
Throughout human history, in-groups have often justified discriminatory and
violent behaviors toward out-groups by appeals to what is natural. The history
of genocides, too horrible to recount here, contain multiple examples of
attitudes and rhetoric in which those being destroyed are likened to animals,
a comparison that justifies their destruction.
In the 1970s, Richard Ryder suggested that the species boundary was
being used to identify who is “in” and who is “out,” and he coined the term
“speciesism” to denote this type of prejudice. Shortly thereafter, Peter Singer
popularized the term as being comparable to racism and sexism. He argued
that movements to end oppression often begin by uncovering a basic idea
and set of practices that seem natural and inevitable that, when subjected to
careful scrutiny, turn out to be unjustifiably discriminatory.
When we consider the reasons that people have given for denying equality
to non-whites, to women, and to gay men, lesbians, and transgendered peo-
ple, we often see that the prejudice is naturalized. One need only recall the
debates over gay marriage to illuminate how this is so. Much of the popu-
lar and legal rhetoric employed by opponents of recognizing gay marriage
was infused with claims about the “unnaturalness” of gay and lesbian rela-
tionships and arguments that socially endorsing such behavior by allowing
gay people to marry would legitimize this unnatural behavior. Attempts to
disguise animus against non-heterosexual people by naturalizing heterosex-
uality, though often politically successful, do not withstand the demands for
equal respect. Similarly, Ryder and Singer argue that invoking species mem-
bership in order to deny the moral claims of those who are not members of
the “in” species amounts to unjustified prejudice.
Discrimination on the basis of skin color, gender, sexual orientation, or
being able-bodied is thought to be prejudicial, because these are not charac-
teristics that matter when it comes to making moral claims or demanding
moral attention. That one is a woman or in a wheelchair should not bear
on whether an individual’s interests matter from an ethical point of view.
Species membership, it has been argued, is also morally irrelevant when it
comes to determining who can make moral claims. If an individual’s life can
14 Singer 1990: 9
54 Ethics and Animals
go better or worse for her, by her own lights; if she has interests and desires,
the satisfaction of which will contribute to her well-being; and my behavior
can impact her life for better or worse, then my failing to consider how my
actions affect that individual would be morally irresponsible. If a child runs
out into the street, and I purposely fail to stop my car because the child was
Asian or a boy or wore leg-braces, I would rightly be judged a monster. Simi-
larly, if I fail to stop my car and purposely run over a cat, I will not be excused
by saying, “it was only a cat.” These are individuals who have interests in not
being run over by cars, and when I fail to consider these interests I put my very
capacity to act morally in question. My interests in getting to my destination
faster, or not being bothered to stop, do not obviously outweigh the interests
of those who inadvertently cross my path.
Sexism and racism involve actions and attitudes (either conscious or not)
that elevate the interests of one’s own gender or race over the interests of
another gender or race, merely because the sexist favors his gender and the
racist favors his race, over others. Similarly, speciesism involves actions and
attitudes that elevate human interests above the interests of any other species,
because humans favor humans over others and think of humans as superior.
Speciesist actions and attitudes are prejudicial, because there is no prima facie
reason for preferring the interests of beings like me, or of those belonging
to my group, to the interests of those who are different. I happen to have
been born a human female in the US, but I could have been born a male in
Australia or a chimpanzee in Africa. It is just a bit of luck that I was born
me, and it is no more interesting from a moral point of view, than the fact
that I have five fingers on each hand, including opposable thumbs. I’m happy
I have the hands I do. But, having hands like mine doesn’t give me more of a
claim to moral attention than those who don’t have hands like mine, and it
doesn’t justify my devaluing the interests of those who have different sorts of
hands. Species membership is a morally irrelevant characteristic, and, given
our discussion above, classification of the species to which I belong seems even
less important, given that it is a matter of convention, rather than something
irrevocably or naturally fixed.
Of course, that I am a human and not a chimpanzee has implications for
how I am treated. If I were a chimpanzee, my particular interests would be dif-
ferent. I would undoubtedly want to live a quite different, more active sort of
life. Ideally, I would want to be in a tropical forest with lots of fresh fruits and
vegetation and other chimpanzees. A chimpanzee’s interests in living a good
The natural and the normative 55
life for her are no less morally important than my human interests simply
because they are not human interests. Difference does not justify disregard.
Attending to the specific interests of other individuals whose interests
matter from a moral point of view will require attending to both the biological
and the social facts about those individuals. Although some of the morally
relevant facts might be gleaned from species membership, many of them
won’t be so apparent. That an individual is a human may not tell us everything
we need to know about how to treat that individual, and the same will be true
of members of other species. For example, we hold some humans accountable
for their actions in a way that we forgive others for the same actions. A
paradigm example is children – when a toddler hurts the dog or another
child, we don’t think the toddler has done something morally wrong. Even if
the toddler were to cause the death of another, say by picking up a loaded gun
and shooting his sister, we would certainly find that tragic, but we wouldn’t
say that the child was a monster in the way that we might the adult who
purposely runs over a cat. This is because a toddler has not yet developed
the skills necessary to understand right from wrong and to make a decision
about how to act based on that understanding. A human child, much like
the crocodile, is acting without reflecting. Both lack the capacity to reflect on
their actions and, thus, cannot decide to act differently. Because they cannot
decide to do otherwise, we do not hold them ethically responsible for their
actions. In philosophical parlance, the human child and the crocodile are not
persons.
16 Until fairly recently it made sense to say that humans develop in a woman’s body, but
given the fluidity of gender and the fact that some people who were born with female
reproductive organs identify as men and some of those men have given birth to children, it
is more accurate to say that humans, at least until technology becomes more advanced,
develop in uterine environments, whether those belong to individuals identifying as
“women,” “men,” or some other gender category.
17 For example, as the result of developments in reproductive technologies, including
cloning, surrogate mothers can be a different species from the developing infant.
The natural and the normative 57
every rational being exists as an end in himself and not merely as a means to
be arbitrarily used by this or that will . . . Beings whose existence depends not
on our will but on nature have, nevertheless, if they are not rational beings,
only a relative value as means and are therefore called things. On the other
hand, rational beings are called persons inasmuch as their nature already
marks them out as ends in themselves.18
In his Lectures on Anthropology Kant wrote, “The fact that the human being can
have the representation ‘I’ raises him infinitely above all the other beings on
earth. By this he is a person . . . that is, a being altogether different in rank
and dignity from things, such as irrational animals, with which one may deal
and dispose at one’s discretion.”19 Similarly, John Locke defined a person as
a “thinking intelligent being that has reason and reflection and can consider
itself as itself, the same thinking thing, in different times and places.”20 In
more contemporary language, we might say that a Lockean person is some-
one who has certain psychological capacities – cognition, self-awareness, and
episodic memory. While Locke’s view of personhood is primarily aimed at
identifying what capacities are needed in order to classify an individual as a
person, Kant’s view of personhood has stronger normative implications. Only
persons seem to matter morally on Kant’s view.
For Kant, it appears that non-rational beings who do not have a self-
conception – non-persons – are mere things. But some humans lack ratio-
nality and do not have a self-conception. Fetuses, newborns, and probably
even toddlers don’t yet have the concept of themselves as themselves, distinct
from others, and thus wouldn’t be considered persons, even though they
are humans. The same is true of a human in a permanent vegetative state.
The distinction between humans and persons has become a central one in
the bioethics literature. Whether we have duties to humans before they are
persons (at the beginning of life) and what sorts of obligations we have to
humans when they are no longer persons (after significant brain injuries or
at the end of life) are some of the most pressing questions for health care
providers and policymakers. Kant’s view would not allow us to recognize that
there are important ethical questions to address here. Similarly, Kant’s view
would have us deny most, but maybe not all, other animals moral concern.
This seems highly counterintuitive.21
argues in this way and suggests that all beings that potentially have a rational nature, or
who virtually have it, or who have had it, or who have part of it, or who have the necessary
conditions of it, what he calls “the infrastructure of rational nature,” should be directly
morally considerable. Insofar as a being stands in this relation to rational nature, they are
the kinds of beings that can be wronged. The third way has been proposed by Christine
Korsgaard (2004), who argues that though only persons can make moral demands on other
persons, what we demand is that our animal natures be respected. I discuss Korsgaard’s
view in the next section.
22 See Broom, et al. 2009 for pigs and Reiss & Marino 2001 for dolphins.
60 Ethics and Animals
to avoid searching for worms after a longer interval during which the worms
had decayed.”23 Clayton’s observations suggest that the birds “form integrated
memories about what happened where and when, rather than encoding the
information separately. Furthermore, the jays can also remember whether
another individual was present at the time of caching, and if so, who was
watching when.”24 If jays have a self-conception, then they might count as
persons.
So there are human persons and non-human persons, human non-persons
and non-human non-persons. Of course, more empirical work and further
conceptual refinement of the definition of personhood will help us to figure
out what sorts of beings, with what sorts of capacities, fall into what category,
and thus, what specific moral claims and responsibilities they will, in fact,
have. Even before we have definitive answers about “where to draw the lines,”
as it were, we can still explore what general ethical obligations or attitudes
we should have to those who are not persons but who still deserve our moral
attention.
23 Clayton & Dickinson 1998: 272–4. See also Clayton, et al. 2003.
24 Clayton, et al. 2007: R190.
The natural and the normative 61
wrong in the way that killing a person who does have an explicit desire to
continue to exist would be, other things being equal. Similarly, persons are
autonomous, and, thus, denying them their freedom would be ethically prob-
lematic. In the case of many non-persons who lack autonomy, denying them
freedom may actually be the right thing to do from an ethical perspective.
We will talk about the issues of killing and liberty in greater depth in the
chapters ahead.
For now, it is important to see that the scope of ethical attention extends
over a broad range of beings, all of whom have valuable capacities and inter-
ests as we discussed in the last chapter: they are alive and have bodies that
experience pleasures and pains and can suffer from violence, neglect, or
abuse; they have emotions, desires, likes, and dislikes; and they are engaged
in the world in a variety of ways, some which are enriching and some which
are debilitating. If you are a being whose life can go better or worse, then you
are a proper object of moral attention. A subset of attention-worthy beings
has additional capabilities and interests as well as obligations and responsi-
bilities. Moral agents not only have interests in living lives that are good for
them by their own lights, full of enriching experiences, pleasurable activities,
and satisfying projects, but they also have ethical obligations that arise, in
part, because they have the capacity to reason about their actions and alter
their behaviors accordingly. Moral agents can form intentions about their
actions; are causally responsible for actions and can be blamed or praised for
them; are able to make judgments about rightness and wrongness, both of
their own conduct and of the conduct of other agents; and can construct and
follow norms or moral principles.
The moral universe, as it were, thus can be said to have two levels: a level
that contains moral agents, actors who are responsible for doing the right
thing; and a level that contains moral patients, those to whom right or wrong
actions are directed, but who may or may not be moral agents themselves.
Someone who lacks the capacities of personhood will always be at the level of
a moral patient. But the levels are not exclusive. In certain contexts, persons
can be moral patients too – for example, when they are the ones acted upon
by moral agents, when they are benefited or harmed by others, or when
they temporarily lose their capacities for reason and reflection. Similarly,
upon changes in the abilities of a moral patient, our understanding of those
abilities, or changes in the context in which moral agency is expressed, moral
patients may turn out to be moral agents some of the time.
62 Ethics and Animals
25 She uses the term “human” when she is describing what we are calling “persons.”
The natural and the normative 63
What moral agents construct as valuable and normatively binding is not only
our rational or autonomous capacities, but the needs and desires we have as
living, embodied beings. Insofar as these needs and desires are valuable for
agents, the ability to experience similar needs and desires in patients should
also be valued. As a result, moral agents have duties to moral patients.
The two-level view of the moral universe – one that recognizes the moral
claims of agents and patients as springing from the same source, and the
duties and responsibilities of agents that emerge as a result of their status
as persons – appears in competing ethical theories. These theories will differ
when it comes to determining how to adjudicate conflicts of values and what
particularly constitutes right action. As we’ll see when discussing specific
issues, such as experimentation on other animals and conflicts that arise in
26 Korsgaard 2007: 9.
64 Ethics and Animals
assessing various strategies for addressing threats to wild animals, there will
be a good deal of substantive disagreement among these theories. Nonethe-
less, it is reassuring to note that there is an emerging common vision that
humans and other animals populate the moral universe.
Despite this apparent common ground about how and why we recognize our
moral obligations to other animals, there have been complex, often passion-
ate, debates about the characterization I have been making about the sphere
of moral concern. In particular, there has been reluctance from some quarters
to accept the distinction between humans and persons. Those who support
the distinction often use it to make the case for greater ethical regard and
better treatment for other animals, and they sometimes invoke what has been
called the “Argument from Marginal Cases,” or the AMC, for short. The AMC
goes something like this:
While proponents of the AMC generally use the argument to ground claims
that we should expand the sphere of those who deserve ethical attention, the
conclusion has led some to worry that the argument will diminish the respect
we have for humans who are not persons. And this worry is not unwarranted.
As Eva Kittay has noted:
Personhood in the past has also been used less capaciously to exclude specific
humans: women, slaves, Jews, certain racial groups, the disabled – those who,
for one reason or another, were believed unworthy or incapable of rationality
and self-governance. As current disputes over the moral personhood of fetuses
and very premature neonates attest, personhood has been, and continues to
be, a contested category.
What endows these controversies with urgency are the real-life stakes, for
personhood marks the moral threshold above which equal respect for the
intrinsic value of an individual’s life is required and the requirements of
justice are operative and below which only relative interest has moral
weight.27
and the dangers associated with comparing some humans with animals. Let’s
consider each of these responses in turn.28
Social relations
The ability to decide between eating pizza or stir-fried veggies, to enjoy the
warmth of the sun on a crisp spring day, to laugh when being tickled, to
enjoy a Beethoven piano concerto is based on the possession of intrinsic prop-
erties particular to individuals with certain types of perceptual and cognitive
capacities. As we have been discussing the occupants of the moral universe in
this chapter and the last, we have explored a range of such capacities. One of
the reasons that philosophers tend to examine intrinsic capacities in deter-
mining who matters from an ethical point of view is that by focusing on the
capacities an individual possesses, extrinsic considerations such as popular-
ity, usefulness to others, political expediency, and social prejudice can be set
aside. If I am the sort of being whose life can go well if I have the company of
good friends and enough chocolate, I should not be denied the opportunity
to spend time with friends and eat chocolate just because I am Jewish or a
woman. Belonging to a politically marginalized or unpopular group is not a
morally relevant social fact about me. No one should be denied the possibility
of exercising their capacities and satisfying their interests simply because of
inegalitarian social conventions or discriminatory traditions. These sorts of
relational properties have a long history of being used to exclude members of
“out” groups, and appeals to such relational properties have led to ethically
unacceptable practices and policies. It is interesting, then, that recently some
philosophers have challenged the AMC, because it is focused on intrinsic prop-
erties rather than relational ones. These philosophers argue that some social
relations must be taken into account.
Of course, to be able to exercise the deliberative capacities I just mentioned
– to have access to pizza or pizza-making ingredients, to be able to listen to
Beethoven, and to be with friends – presupposes that the individuals who are
in a position to exercise their capacities are embedded in social relations. We
wouldn’t know what pizza or Beethoven or friendship was without our human
28 It is quite interesting that these arguments are raised in particular against those who
argue for extending concern for sentient beings (philosophers like Peter Singer and Jeff
McMahan, who are consequentialists) when it seems that the worries would be just as
troubling for Kantians.
The natural and the normative 67
not properly toileted and decently dressed in clean clothes, her hair combed,
her face and nose wiped, and so forth. These demands have only partially to
do with matters of health and hygiene. They are, more fundamentally,
matters of making the body fit for human society for presentation to others.
Human beings need to live with other humans, but cannot do so if those
When proponents of the AMC make the situation for those in 1 equivalent
to the situation for those in 2, they are denying the very sensibility of this
scenario.
One response might simply be to say that humans with severe Alzheimer’s, or
those who are severely cognitively impaired, and non-human animals, who
are not persons or moral agents, will command different sorts of treatment
depending on the kinds of reasoned justifications that moral agents can
make for that differential treatment and, as Anderson says, the types or
relationships with moral patients those agents have. Nonetheless, there is no
reason to invoke a hierarchy of moral status, where human moral patients
are higher than non-human moral patients in virtue of their species-based
connection to human moral agents. One can imagine that if one treated a
dog like a horse, some human moral agent might object in a similar vein.31
That the AMC equates the moral status of individuals in 1 with individuals in
2 does not mean that their treatment should now be identical or that there is
nothing troubling or objectionable about treating a human like a dog, a dog
like a horse, a chimpanzee like a human child.
In addition, consider the fact that different living options are available
for parents with Alzheimer’s. Adult children will often go to great lengths
30 Ibid.: 282.
31 Some object to greyhound racing on just these grounds, but I have in mind people riding
on dogs.
The natural and the normative 69
to see that their ailing parents get the very best possible care, perhaps quite
expensive care, even when their parent is completely unaware that they are
being cared for in such an elaborate way. It is not for the parent’s sake that
this care is offered, but for the sake of the family and their peace of mind.
Some families don’t care for their ailing parents in these ways – because they
can’t afford such care; because they would rather spend what funds they have
on the members of the family who are persons and can directly appreciate
the benefit from such funds; or because they don’t see it as their moral
responsibility (perhaps the parent was abusive to the children who are now
estranged from her). We don’t force families to provide top-of-the-line care for
their parents who are not persons. (Indeed, we don’t have moral expectations
that families provide top-of-the-line care for members who are persons.) A
decent society would surely care for these individuals in ways that attend
to their basic needs. The specific social relations will determine how moral
agents come to understand their moral obligations to moral patients. A family
who has their mother with Alzheimer’s in a top-of-the-line facility might find
the state-run care “undignified”; they might even think that the state-run
facility “treats people like animals.” But this judgment could be the result of
snobbery or speciesism, and we should not draw moral conclusions from such
judgments. These judgments, in themselves, don’t show that human non-
persons, by virtue of their social relations with other, sometimes judgmental,
persons are due more consideration than non-human non-persons.
Kittay has also argued against the AMC on similar grounds. As the mother
of a severely cognitively impaired daughter, named Sesha, Kittay is vividly
attuned to the role of social relations in understanding our moral commit-
ments to others. When we think of the individuals in 1, she wants us always to
think of them as “someone’s child . . . That social relationship [entails] a series
of appropriate emotional and moral responses . . . It is morally (and emotion-
ally) appropriate to care for one’s child for the child’s own sake. It is the
practices that define parenthood, and not simply the intrinsic properties of
the product of the pregnancy.”32 The intrinsic properties account leads to the
conclusion that we may disregard individuals like Sesha and accept “treating
her like an animal” just as consistently as it would require greater moral
attention for people like Sesha and other animals. Kittay argues that we can
avoid this risk by rejecting the intrinsic properties account for determining
Here, Kittay is suggesting that partiality to one’s own group, the “in” group,
needn’t be thought of as necessarily prejudicial. She is urging us to think
of speciesism – favoring one’s own species over members of other species –
as on par with favoring one’s own family. Insofar as we think it is ethically
permissible to grant greater weight to the interests and desires of members of
our own family, so is it permissible to grant greater weight to the interests and
desires of members of our own species. Kittay is essentially denying premise
4 of the AMC.
There are a number of possible responses to this view. It might be suggested
that ultimately we aren’t morally justified in caring more about our own
children and family members than the children and family members of our
neighbors and colleagues; it is just a function of the way we have arranged our
social relations and institutions that we are psychologically oriented toward
favoring our own family members and, practically, it works out well if every
family takes care of their own. There are, in fact, different cultural practices
and alternative family arrangements in which caring for one’s own family
members more than for other people is not thought to be justifiable. Favoring
one’s own family and how we understand who counts as a family member are
arguably artifacts of our particular social and cultural practices. And cultural
practices are often the very sorts of practices that should be held up to ethical
interrogation, because they tend to make certain kinds of prejudices seem
natural, as I noted earlier. Even within our own culture, there are limits
beyond which favoring one’s own family members become questionable. We
33 Ibid.: 151–2.
The natural and the normative 71
cannot go to any lengths to further the interests of our own children over
the interests of other people’s children. It would be quite objectionable, for
example, if you were driving your child and a neighbor’s child to school, for
you to use both seatbelts to double-strap your child in while leaving your
neighbor’s child without a seatbelt. In addition to being limited, partiality to
one’s own family members is not thought to be ethically required. We don’t
think that the parent who sends her children to public school and sends
the money she would have spent sending them to private school to support
education in the developing world is doing something unethical; indeed,
many would find that admirable. So, partiality to family looks more like a
contingent feature of our social relations and not a principle for organizing
our ethical obligations.
Families come in many forms. These days, families often include children
from other marriages and various genetic parents, adopted children, the chil-
dren of adopted children, girlfriends or boyfriends who have been rejected
by their families of birth, orphaned cousins, etc. One might also argue that it
is possible to think of “families” as including more than just humans. Many
people have come to identify other animals as part of their family or inti-
mate social units. Donna Haraway has written expansively about “compan-
ion species” who are not simply “pets” but other beings with whom we are in
significant, life-altering relationships. She describes her own transformation
as a result of working with her dog. Haraway says, ‘‘my over-the-top love for
Cayenne has required my body to build a bigger heart with more depths and
tones for tenderness. Maybe that is what makes me need to be honest; maybe
this kind of love makes one need to see what is really happening because
the loved one deserves it. There is nothing like the unconditional love that
people ascribe to their dogs!’’34 George Pitcher describes the relationship he
and his partner had with their two adopted dogs in distinctly familiar terms.
He describes:
their complete and unwavering devotion to us. They showed this constantly,
in countless ways . . . We loved them with all our hearts . . . and they loved us,
too, completely, no holds barred. Such love is perhaps the best thing life has
to offer, and we shall always be grateful for having had such an abundance
of it to receive and to give for so long a time . . . They were our surrogate
children . . . Naturally the love of one’s dog cannot be as deep and rich as the
love of one’s child, but it can be in some ways just as intense. For example,
our concern for the welfare of Lupa and Remus was, I believe, as strong as a
devoted father’s for his child’s.35
Taking offense
Kittay has simply denied the possibility that other animals can be members
of our families in the relevant way; indeed, she finds the idea offensive. She
has lived with and loved dogs, but to compare her feelings for her dog with
those for her daughter is, it seems, unthinkable for her. She writes:
How can I begin to tell you what it feels like to read texts in which one’s
child is compared, in all seriousness and with philosophical authority, to a
dog, pig, rat, and most flatteringly a chimp; how corrosive these comparisons
are, how they mock those relationships that affirm who we are and why we
care? I am no stranger to a beloved animal. I have had dogs I have loved, dogs I
have mourned for. But as dog lovers who become parents can tell you, much
as we adore our hounds, there is no comparison between the feelings for a
beloved child of normal capacities and those for a beloved canine. And I can
tell you that there is also no comparison when that child has intellectual
disabilities.37
35 Pitcher 1995: 158–9, 162, and 163, as quoted in McMahan 2005: 364.
36 Prince-Hughes 2004: 3. 37 Kittay 2009: 610.
The natural and the normative 73
38 Ibid.: 613.
39 As Mary Midgley 1983: 119 puts it: “One sort of love does not need to block another,
because love, like compassion, is not a rare fluid to be economized, but a capacity which
grows by use.”
74 Ethics and Animals
cognitively impaired, have interests that deserve our moral attention. But
that does not ensure that their interests will always win out when there are
conflicts of interests, just as is the case when conflicts between persons occur
and everyone’s interests cannot be simultaneously satisfied. Greater knowl-
edge of the specific kinds of interests that different moral patients have will
enhance our abilities to resolve conflicts in the most ethically defensible ways.
Kittay and others who have personal stakes in the lives of human non-persons
have succeeded in making more vivid the importance and value of the lives,
experiences, and interests of those living with severe cognitive abilities, and
have reminded us of the importance of epistemic humility. But there is no
reason to extend that humility to all humans then stop at the species border.
Those studying and caring for non-human animals have also enlivened our
understanding of the value of the lives, experiences, and interests of other
animals. Comparing the two is only offensive if one assumes that the lives of
other animals are less valuable or worthy of our attention, and, as I have been
arguing, that assumption is based on an unjustifiable prejudice.
The natural world contains hippopotamuses and crocodiles, dandelions
and dugongs, philosophers and biologists, Sesha and Knuckles. The categories
we now use to distinguish between these various organisms are not some-
thing that we can read off the natural world; we need to make distinctions
and judgments about how to categorize, and then give meaning to those cat-
egories. This is where the normative enters. Whether we tie our normative
evaluations to individual natural properties or relations between organisms
and their environments, or both, those who can make judgments, what I
have been calling persons, have certain ethical and epistemological respon-
sibilities, including justifying the value placed on the various categories as
constructed and, perhaps most importantly, being able to defend that valua-
tion in light of the implication these value commitments have in practice. It
is to the practices that we will now turn.