David Hilbert - 240222 - 141820
David Hilbert - 240222 - 141820
For all his successes, the nature of his proof created more
trouble than Hilbert could have imagined. Although Kronecker
had conceded, Hilbert would later respond to others' similar
criticisms that "many different constructions are subsumed
under one fundamental idea"—in other words (to quote Reid):
"Through a proof of existence, Hilbert had been able to obtain a
construction"; "the proof" (i.e. the symbols on the page) was
"the object".[31] Not all were convinced. While Kronecker would
die soon afterwards, his constructivist philosophy would
continue with the young Brouwer and his developing intuitionist
"school", much to Hilbert's torment in his later years.[32]
Indeed, Hilbert would lose his "gifted pupil" Weyl to intuitionism
—"Hilbert was disturbed by his former student's fascination with
the ideas of Brouwer, which aroused in Hilbert the memory of
Kronecker".[33] Brouwer the intuitionist in particular opposed
the use of the Law of Excluded Middle over infinite sets (as
Hilbert had used it). Hilbert responded:
Axiomatization of geometry
The text Grundlagen der Geometrie (tr.: Foundations of
Geometry) published by Hilbert in 1899 proposes a formal set,
called Hilbert's axioms, substituting for the traditional axioms of
Euclid. They avoid weaknesses identified in those of Euclid,
whose works at the time were still used textbook-fashion. It is
difficult to specify the axioms used by Hilbert without referring
to the publication history of the Grundlagen since Hilbert
changed and modified them several times. The original
monograph was quickly followed by a French translation, in
which Hilbert added V.2, the Completeness Axiom. An English
translation, authorized by Hilbert, was made by E.J. Townsend
and copyrighted in 1902.[35][36] This translation incorporated
the changes made in the French translation and so is
considered to be a translation of the 2nd edition. Hilbert
continued to make changes in the text and several editions
appeared in German. The 7th edition was the last to appear in
Hilbert's lifetime. New editions followed the 7th, but the main
text was essentially not revised.[g]
Hilbert's approach signaled the shift to the modern axiomatic
method. In this, Hilbert was anticipated by Moritz Pasch's work
from 1882. Axioms are not taken as self-evident truths.
Geometry may treat things, about which we have powerful
intuitions, but it is not necessary to assign any explicit meaning
to the undefined concepts. The elements, such as point, line,
plane, and others, could be substituted, as Hilbert is reported to
have said to Schoenflies and Kötter, by tables, chairs, glasses
of beer and other such objects.[37] It is their defined
relationships that are discussed.
The 23 problems
Hilbert put forth a highly influential list consisting of 23 unsolved
problems at the International Congress of Mathematicians in
Paris in 1900. This is generally reckoned as the most
successful and deeply considered compilation of open
problems ever to be produced by an individual mathematician.
[by whom?]
Who among us would not be happy to lift the veil behind which
is hidden the future; to gaze at the coming developments of our
science and at the secrets of its development in the centuries to
come? What will be the ends toward which the spirit of future
generations of mathematicians will tend? What methods, what
new facts will the new century reveal in the vast and rich field of
mathematical
thought?[38]
Hilbert's program
Hilbert's programIn 1920, Hilbert proposed a research project in
metamathematics that became known as Hilbert's program. He
wanted mathematics to be formulated on a solid and complete
logical foundation. He believed that in principle this could be
done by showing that:
Gödel's work
Hilbert and the mathematicians who worked with him in his
enterprise were committed to the project. His attempt to support
axiomatized mathematics with definitive principles, which could
banish theoretical uncertainties, ended in failure.