0% found this document useful (0 votes)
20 views

Logic and Proofs - 3

Math

Uploaded by

ozcan8479
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
20 views

Logic and Proofs - 3

Math

Uploaded by

ozcan8479
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 22

Predicates

and
Quantifiers
SECTION 1.4
Section Summary

 Predicates
 Variables
 Quantifiers
 Universal Quantifier
 Existential Quantifier
 Negating Quantifiers
 De Morgan’s Laws for Quantifiers
 Translating English to Logic
 Logic Programming (optional)
Propositional Logic Not
Enough
 If we have:
“All men are mortal.”
“Socrates is a man.”
 Does it follow that “Socrates is mortal?”
 Can’t be represented in propositional logic.
Need a language that talks about objects, their
properties, and their relations.
 Later we’ll see how to draw inferences.
Introducing Predicate
Logic
 Predicate logic uses the following new features:
 Variables: x, y, z
 Predicates: P(x), M(x)
 Quantifiers (to be covered in a few slides):
 Propositional functions are a generalization of
propositions.
 They contain variables and a predicate, e.g., P(x)
 Variables can be replaced by elements from their
domain.
Propositional Functions
 Propositional functions become propositions (and have
truth values) when their variables are each replaced by a
value from the domain (or bound by a quantifier, as we
will see later).
 The statement P(x) is said to be the value of the
propositional function P at x.
 For example, let P(x) denote “x > 0” and the domain be
the integers. Then:
P(-3) is ?
P(0) is ?
P(3) is ?
 Often the domain is denoted by U. So in this example U is
the integers.
Examples of Propositional
Functions
 Let “x + y = z” be denoted by R(x, y, z) and U (for all three variables) be
the integers. Find these truth values:
R(2,-1,5)
Solution: ?
R(3,4,7)
Solution: ?
R(x, 3, z)
Solution: ?
 Now let “x - y = z” be denoted by Q(x, y, z), with U as the integers. Find
these truth values:
Q(2,-1,3)
Solution: ?
Q(3,4,7)
Solution: ?
Q(x, 3, z)
Solution: ?
Compound Expressions
 Connectives from propositional logic carry over to predicate
logic.
 If P(x) denotes “x > 0,” find these truth values:
P(3) ∨ P(-1) Solution:?
P(3) ∧ P(-1) Solution:?
P(3) → P(-1) Solution:?
P(3) → ¬P(-1) Solution: ?
Expressions with variables are not propositions and therefore do
not have truth values. For example,
P(3) ∧ P(y)
P(x) → P(y)
 When used with quantifiers (to be introduced next), these
expressions (propositional functions) become propositions.
Quantifiers
 We need quantifiers to express the meaning of English
words including all and some:
 “All men are Mortal.”
 “Some cats do not have fur.”
 The two most important quantifiers are:
 Universal Quantifier, “For all,” symbol: 

 Existential Quantifier, “There exists,” symbol: 


 We write as in x P(x) and x P(x).
 x P(x) asserts P(x) is true for every x in the domain.
 x P(x) asserts P(x) is true for some x in the domain.
 The quantifiers are said to bind the variable x in these
expressions.
Universal Quantifier

 x P(x) is read as “For all x, P(x)” or “For every x,


P(x)”
Examples:
1) If P(x) denotes “x > 0” and U is the integers, then x P(x) is
false.
2) If P(x) denotes “x > 0” and U is the positive integers, then
x P(x) is true.
3) If P(x) denotes “x is even” and U is the integers, then  x
P(x) is false.
Existential Quantifier
 x P(x) is read as “For some x, P(x)”, or as “There is
an x such that P(x),” or “For at least one x, P(x).”

Examples:
1. If P(x) denotes “x > 0” and U is the integers, then x P(x)
is true. It is also true if U is the positive integers.
2. If P(x) denotes “x < 0” and U is the positive integers, then
x P(x) is false.
3. If P(x) denotes “x is even” and U is the integers, then x
P(x) is true.
Thinking about Quantifiers
 When the domain of discourse is finite, we can think of
quantification as looping through the elements of the domain.
 To evaluate x P(x) loop through all x in the domain.
 If at every step P(x) is true, then x P(x) is true.
 If at a step P(x) is false, then x P(x) is false and the loop
terminates.
 To evaluate x P(x) loop through all x in the domain.
 If at some step, P(x) is true, then x P(x) is true and the loop
terminates.
 If the loop ends without finding an x for which P(x) is true, then x
P(x) is false.
 Even if the domains are infinite, we can still think of the
quantifiers this fashion, but the loops will not terminate in some
cases.
Properties of Quantifiers
 The truth value of x P(x) and  x P(x) depend on both the
propositional function P(x) and on the domain U.
 Examples:
1. If U is the positive integers and P(x) is the statement
“x < 2”, then x P(x) is true, but  x P(x) is false.
2. If U is the negative integers and P(x) is the statement
“x < 2”, then both x P(x) and  x P(x) are true.
3. If U consists of 3, 4, and 5, and P(x) is the statement
“x > 2”, then both x P(x) and  x P(x) are true. But if P(x) is
the statement “x < 2”, then both x P(x) and x
P(x) are false.
Precedence of Quantifiers

 The quantifiers  and  have higher


precedence than all the logical operators.
 For example, x P(x) ∨ Q(x) means (x P(x))∨
Q(x)
 x (P(x) ∨ Q(x)) means something different.
 Unfortunately, often people write x P(x) ∨ Q(x)
when they mean  x (P(x) ∨ Q(x)).
Translating from English to
Logic
Example 1: Translate the following sentence into
predicate logic: “Every student in this class has
taken a course in Java.”
Solution:
First decide on the domain U.
Solution 1: If U is all students in this class, define a
propositional function J(x) denoting “x has taken a
course in Java” and translate as x J(x).
Solution 2: But if U is all people, also define a
propositional function S(x) denoting “x is a student
in this class” and translate as x (S(x)→ J(x)).
x (S(x) ∧ J(x)) is not correct. What does it mean?
Equivalences in Predicate
Logic
 Statements involving predicates and
quantifiers are logically equivalent if and only if
they have the same truth value
 for every predicate substituted into these statements
and
 for every domain of discourse used for the variables
in the expressions.
 The notation S ≡T indicates that S and T are
logically equivalent.
 Example: x ¬¬S(x) ≡ x S(x)
Thinking about Quantifiers as
Conjunctions and Disjunctions
 If the domain is finite, a universally quantified proposition is
equivalent to a conjunction of propositions without
quantifiers and an existentially quantified proposition is
equivalent to a disjunction of propositions without
quantifiers.
 If U consists of the integers 1,2, and 3:

 Even if the domains are infinite, you can still think of the
quantifiers in this fashion, but the equivalent expressions
without quantifiers will be infinitely long.
Negating Quantified
Expressions
 Consider x J(x)
“Every student in your class has taken a course in
Java.”
Here J(x) is “x has taken a course in Java” and
the domain is students in your class.
 Negating the original statement gives “It is not the
case that every student in your class has taken
Java.” This implies that “There is a student in your
class who has not taken Java.”
Symbolically ¬x J(x) and x ¬J(x) are equivalent
Negating Quantified
Expressions (continued)
 Now Consider  x J(x)
“There is a student in this class who has taken a
course in Java.”
Where J(x) is “x has taken a course in Java.”
 Negating the original statement gives “It
is not the case that there is a student in
this class who has taken Java.” This
implies that “Every student in this class has
not taken Java”
Symbolically ¬ x J(x) and  x ¬J(x) are
equivalent
De Morgan’s Laws for
Quantifiers
 The rules for negating quantifiers are:

 The reasoning in the table shows that:

 These are important. You will use these.


Translation from English to
Logic
Examples:
1. “Some student in this class has visited Mexico.”
Solution: Let M(x) denote “x has visited Mexico” and S(x)
denote “x is a student in this class,” and U be all people.
_____________________

2. “Every student in this class has visited Canada or


Mexico.”
Solution: Add C(x) denoting “x has visited Canada.”
x (S(x)→ (M(x)∨C(x)))
___________________________________
More Predicate Calculus
Definitions (optional)
 The scope of a quantifier is the part of an
assertion in which variables are bound by the
quantifier.
Example: x has wide scope

Example: x has narrow scope


 Kenneth H. Rosen (2012)
Discrete Mathematics and its Applications, 7th ed.

You might also like