John Gage - Color and Meaning - Art, Science, and Symbolism-University of California Press (2000)
John Gage - Color and Meaning - Art, Science, and Symbolism-University of California Press (2000)
— Colour
and Meaning
Art, Science and
Symbolism — a
IN
colour and Meaning
rt, Science and Symbolism
lohn Gage
‘
ilIMM IIi
This book is due for return on or before the last
date shown below.
~ 4 NOY 2006
11 DEC 2006
12 JAN 2007
19 FEB 2997
28 SEP 2007.
Colour and Meaning
Hie oN GeoA GE
Colour
and Meaning
Art, Science and
Symbolism
with 137 illustrations, 37 in colour
AND =
5S INFORMATION Gj
4 SERVICES —2>/
CAERLEON
T&H
——
THAMES AND HUDSON
For Bob Herbert, Thomas Lersch and Georges Roque,
whose writings have so often eased me into colour
Any copy of this book issued by the publisher as a paperback is sold subject to
the condition that it shall not by way of trade or otherwise be lent, resold, hired out
or otherwise circulated without the publisher’s prior consent in any form of
binding or cover other than that in which it is published and without a similar
conditionincluding these words being imposed on a subsequent purchaser.
ISBN 0-§00-23767-0
Introduction 7
Part One
1 The Contexts of Colour 11
The history of art as a unifying subject + Artefacts and attitudes » The harmony ofcolours
The non-standard observer + Colour in context
Part Tivo
4 Colour in History — Relative and Absolute 67
Iconography in the early Middle Ages: brightness versus hue + Colour as symbol
Red and purple in the scale ofcolours +» Medieval blues » The point ofpointillism » The mind
of the mosaicist » Atoms and mixtures + The luminous imperative
13 ‘Two Different Worlds’ - Runge, Goethe and the Sphere of Colour 169
Goethe and Runge + Steffens, Schiffermiiller and the Farben-Kugel
The suppression ofsymbolism
14 Mood Indigo — From the Blue Flower to the Blue Rider 185
The blue flower « Gendering of blue + An anthropology ofcolour + Goethe’s following:
symbol versus substance + Bocklin and Bezold » Experimental psychology: Fechner and Wundt
Kandinsky and blue + Goethe in the twentieth century
Acknowledgments 270
Index 315
Introduction
ce WELCOME WHICH MET my earlier book, Colour and Culture: Practice and
Meaning from Antiquity to Abstraction, has encouraged me to think that my _
curiosity about colour may be shared by a wider public, and that this public could
be further interested in other topics in the history of colour which for one reason
or another could not find a place there.
One controversial area of colour-studies, which has developed substantially since
I wrote that book, has been in philosophy, through which colour became interest-
ing to the philosophical school of deconstruction as it reached beyond literature to
concern itself with the visual arts.’ As it happens Jacques Derrida, who has perhaps
written more than other deconstructionists on visual topics, has admitted that only
words interest him;* and in an essay on the often wordy drawings of Valerio Adami
he has concluded that ‘color has not yet been.named’.3 Adami himself, who is a
painter as well as a draughtsman, argues that ‘color is the instrument for reading
drawing as the voice 1s the instrument for reading writing’.t Colour is thus con-
ceived of as akin to musical timbre, as the ancillary qualifier of design 1n its tradi-
tional role of articulating ideas in a graphic mode like script.
Another deconstructionist, Stephen Melville, has recently posed the philosophi-
cal problem of colour, again without attempting to address it:
color can also seem bottomlessly resistant to nomination, attaching itself
absolutely to its own specificity and the surfaces on which it has or finds its
visibility, even as it also appears subject to endless alteration arising through its
juxtaposition with other colors. Subjective and objective, physically fixed and
culturally constructed, absolutely proper and endlessly displaced, color can
appear as an unthinkable scandal. The story of color and its theory within the
history of art is a history of oscillations between its reduction to charm or
ornament and its valorization as the radical truth of painting. From these oscil-
lations other vibrations are repeatedly set in motion that touch and disturb
matters as purely art-historical as the complex inter-locking borders among
and within the individual arts and as culturally far-reaching as codings of race
and gender and images of activity and passivity.
And Melville continues:
color as they pass from the Renaissance through de Piles and Goethe and
Chevreul, it is in a much harder place when it comes to actually speaking the
work and play of color — not because that work and play are ineffable but
’ is the work ofart and its history.°
because its ‘speakingjust
So, what to do? The chapters that follow attempt to expose and explore the his-
toricity of colour. They deconstruct that immanence, as well as that potential for
organization in colour which has commended it, especially since Locke and Kant,
to philosophical purposes. But if colour, to yield meaning, must be named (and this
is a view which has a good deal to recommend it), the history of thisnaming should
be of absorbing interest to philosophers themselves, who have so far, and for the
most part, been content to accept the assumptions about colour-naming and orga-
nization current until their own times. Thus Kant, who has had such a crucial role
in the shaping of Derrida’s aesthetics, supposed, in the tradition ofAristotle, that
simple colours might be considered beautiful on account of their unmixed purity,
but that they might also be beautiful by virtue oftheir ‘form’ — that is, the ‘regular-
ity’ they derived from their status as vibrations of the ether, a concept he took from
the earlier eighteenth-century German mathematician Leonhard Euler.°® Wittgen-
stein, for his part, assumed that it would be appropriate to work with a six-colour
circle, derived from, say, Goethe or Runge.” Philosophers have not usually been
concerned to question the grounds ofthese assumptions; that is the task ofthe his-
torian of colour.
Any semiotics of colour must be historically contingent, and it is largely the local
historical contingencies which the studies here seek to identify. But an assessment
of historical contingencies must rest on a judgment of the immanent character of
the colour under examination — that is, on a phenomenological approach to colour-
questions, and this is what several recent philosophers of colour, as well as the older
school of Koloritgeschichte have offered (see pp. 36-41).*
This book is, of course, largely a book of words, but it also presents many cases
where words have been felt to be less than adequate to the task of characterizing
colour. If deconstruction sees nothing beyond the ‘text’, colour at least can afford an
instance of where text falls short of any close engagement with phenomena. Which
is why, although colour has offered much to philosophers, philosophy, concerned as
it has traditionally been with discursive thinking, has had little to offer for the
understanding of colour. It is arguable that the reader will find more to stimulate
perceptions of colour in the late painter and film-maker Derek Jarman’s autobio-
graphical rag-bag Chroma (1994) than in, say, Barry Maund’s philosophical treat-
ment in Colours (1995), even though Maund gives an admirable survey of current
thinking on the subject.
My own theoretical position is implicit in the three chapters which together
form Part I of this book. The first, The Contexts of Colour, proposes that an art-
historical approach to colour offers the best opportunity for a unifying vision,
because of the close engagement of practising artists and craftworkers in colour-
perceptions, as well as because many of their works have survived to be analysed by
technical methods which are daily increasing in precision and scope.
INTRODUCTION
The second chapter, Colour and Culture, seeks to illustrate the historical con-
tingency of colour-perceptions, particularly as they are exemplified in colour-
language.
The third, Colour in Art and Its Literature, is intended to lay out various factors
intrinsic to a study of colour in the visual art of the West — from the technological
constraints, to theories accessible to artists and craftworkers, to colour-iconography
and its modern interpretation, to viewing-conditions, and on to the language of
colour-analysis itself. In this sense, it works in the opposite direction to the imma-
nent method of deconstruction, which starts from the ‘text’ immediately present to
the reader. It adopts the view that, although historiography inevitably works back-
wards from the present to the past, history as it is experienced does not. And it is
one of the tasks of the historian to reconstitute the original order of events.
Origins are crucial, since they suggest purposes and functions which are likely to
change over time; and in various studies in this collection I have attempted to go
further into origins, for example, in discussing spectacles (Chapter 5: Colour-words
and Colour-patches) and the triangular prism (Chapter 8: The Fool’s Paradise),
which may at first sight seem to have rather little to do with colour.
Although the idea of ‘clearing the ground’ might be used to characterize the
opening section of the book, all the chapters may be read in a similar light. Since
many of them have their source in occasional papers or catalogue essays they
attempt to look at often familiar art from a new perspective, or to bring newly
recovered texts to bear on old questions. They may thus seem at first to ignore what
have been generally accepted as the central issues in the various periods under dis-
cussion, but this impression will, I hope, prove to be illusory.
If there is a unifying thread running through these chapters, it is that since colour
has a vivid life outside the realm of art, its problems even within that realm cannot
be understood exclusively from within the history and theory of art itself; or rather
that at least in respect of colour, that history and that theory must be seen to be part
of a larger picture. Until the twentieth century, when the formalism that developed
in late nineteenth-century art history began to affect the attitudes of artists and
critics themselves, such a view would have been assumed, rather than thought to be
in need ofdefence.
Perhaps the most important theoretical linking-thread is the consideration that if
art and science have been united in their concern for colour, this unity has not
noticeably involved the subordination of one interest to the other. Historians of
science have long been familiar (in the face of frequent opposition from profes-
sional scientists) with the art of science; historians of art are still perhaps reluctant —
with the frequent support ofartists themselves — to consider the science of art. This
may be because the dominance of literary studies in the recent historiography of art
has tended to limit theory to rhetoric. But if Blake and Matisse are now seen to be
more, and Seurat to be less ‘scientific’ than was once believed, this is surely because
their activities as visual artists engaged them in perceptions which, in their day as in
ours, were scarcely accessible to theory. I hope by looking again at these perceptions
to have restored some fluidity to the notions of ‘science’ and ‘art’ in the visual
sphere.
INTRODUCTION
Another underlying theme is more negative, and it is that, although there must
indeed be a ‘spirit of the times’, which works as mysteriously as the spread of chil-
dren’s games or schoolboy jokes, and directs thoughtful people to common issues of
the day, the history of colour ideas can give little comfort to those who believe in
homogeneous cultures. I have highlighted the contradictions within Meso-Ameri-
can colour-direction systems, for example (Chapter 7: Color Colorado); pointed to
the substantial differences in attitude between Goethe and Runge about the charac-
ter of a coherent colour-theory (Chapter 13:“Two Different Worlds’); and under-
lined the substantial divergencies of view within Neo-Impressionism about the
function of the painted dot (Chapter 16: The Technique of Seurat, and 17: Seurat’s
Silence). The questions addressed in these cases are indeed common to the protago-
nists, and usually specific to their periods; but the differences they represent must
also, I think, make us see the colour ofthe related artefacts in more nuanced ways.
IO
Part One
I - The Contexts of Colour
a
THE CONTEXTS OF COLOUR
on the basis of a severely limited set of stimuli (red, green, blue and dark/ light) just
as colour-vocabularies seem to work with a very limited set of ‘basic’ or ‘primary’
terms. And yet, as I shall show in the following chapters, in practice the idea of
fundamental colours has been far from universal.
Perhaps the most surprising absentee from most general discussions of colour is its
use in the visual arts.’ Two of the most widely used handbooks of recent years deal
extensively with art,’ but appropriately enough, since their authors are closely asso-
ciated with colour-technology, they are more concerned to suggest practical possi-
bilities in colour-usage than to analyse how colour has been (and is) used in artefacts.
In my earlier book Colour and Culture | drew extensively on artefacts for evidence
of attitudes to colour, and in Chapter 3 below I survey a number of other art-
historical studies which have taken up the subject ofcolour in art from varying per-
spectives. So far there has been very little investigation of colour in non-European
artefacts, although, paradoxically, non-European cultures have dominated in the
ethno-linguistic studies of colour-termThus s. the picture at present is essentially
one offragmented interests,'° and research has long been most active in those tech-
nological aspects of the subject which have a direct commercial application.
I2
THE CONTEXTS OF COLOUR
13
THE CONTEXTS OF COLOUR
century Italy devotes a great deal of space to cheap synthetic (‘artificial’) blues,
which were assumed to have similar visual characteristics to these ‘natural’ blues, but
were probably far less stable." Significantly, they have not been identified in the
Italian Renaissance paintings which have survived until our own times.
In the fifteenth century in the Netherlands, where oil painting was first devel-
oped in its modern form, the valuable material lapis lazuli was rather less frequently
used than it was in the South. The new technique of preparation of colours had the
advantage ofcoating each particle in a film ofoil which insulated it against chemi-
cal reaction with other pigments, reducing the risk of changes in their colour.
Extensive mixture was thus a far less chancy business than it had been hitherto, and
a far wider range of pigments could be used than ever before.
Our understanding of the ideas which lay behind the use ofparticular materials
in the North is not helped by the relative lack of contemporary documentation for
most surviving paintings in northern Europe before the sixteenth century, but the
case of one extant work for which the contract is also known, Dieric Bouts’s Altar-
piece of the Last Supper (1464-8) is instructive. Unlike Italian contracts, the contract
here makes no reference at all to the materials to be used, but only to the required
standard of workmanship, and technical analysis of the central panel shows that the
blue used is chiefly azurite with a minimal admixture of lapis lazuli, chiefly in the
sky.'7 It seems that the practice of mixture which the oil medium allowed had led to
a reduction in the status of the materials themselves. The mantle of the Virgin and
16 the blue precious stones represented in the Van Eyck Ghent Altarpiece of some
thirty years earlier, for which no early documentation has come to light, are, on the
other hand, painted in two layers of ultramarine over an azurite base.'* An analysis
of this particular sort of fundamental value attributed to a work of art can only be
made with a clear indentification of the substances employed in the making of it —
an identification which modern methods of conservation have made increasingly
possible; yet the part played by artists’ materials in the conception of the work can
only be assessed on the basis of contemporary written documents.
To the devaluing of intrinsically precious pigments which oil painting brought
with it can be added the identification of asmall set of‘primary’ colours, a set which
became codified, around 1600, as black and white, red, yellow and blue. It was the
oil-painters’ capacity to mix which led to the recognition that only a few colours
were needed to mix many. Although this original set was later joined by other
‘basic’ sets — according to whether the requirement was to mix lights (additive
mixture) or surface-colours (subtractive mixture), or to identify psychologically
‘unmixed’ hues — the notion of reduction itself was to be a very important one,
especially in the study of the mechanisms of colour-vision."®
14
THE CONTEXTS OF COLOUR
Newton's discovery in the 1660s that colours were simply a function of the variable
refrangibility of white light — the red component being subject to the least refrac-
tion and the violet to most when a ray of light is passed through a triangular prism
nAWw
— took the development of the subject away from phenomenology for more than a
century; but it remains the case that his division of the prismatic spectrum into
seven chromatic areas, announced so casually in a letter to the Royal Society of
1675, reflects his interest in the eternally fruitless, eternally stimulating search for
objective principles ofvisual colour-harmony that goes back to Classical Antiquity.
It was the analogy with the seven notes of the musical octave — with its corollary 60
that colour-harmony might be established on the same proportional basis as
musical harmony — that accounts for the remarkable persistence of this error in his
optical writings.”°
Like all colour-researchers in his day Newton was hampered by the lack of stan-
dard colour-nomenclature.*! It is interesting to note that between his letter of 1675
and the Opticks of 1704 he had come to regard indigo, rather than blue, as harmo-
nious with ‘golden’, at the same time as the term for the most refrangible colour in
his spectrum changed from purple to violet. ‘Golden’ itself is an ambiguous term
which was not included in Newton’s analysis of the spectrum: we might well
suppose that it was a yellow, but reference to the 1706 Latin version of Opticks sug-
gests that he used it as a translation of the usual Latin term for orange, aureus. Its
adoption for the remarks on harmony suggest that Newton took the Classical view
that gold had a close affinity with red, and that his beliefin the harmony of gold and
indigo or blue was related, not simply to the musical scale where they form an har-
monic fourth or fifth, but also to the frequency of this combination of colours in
regalia. Since the late Middle Ages the traditional royal purple of Antiquity had
been replaced in robes and heraldry (particularly in France), as well as in the mantle
of the Virgin Mary, by blue. That gold should have had its closest affinity with
orange, rather than with yellow, is remarkable; yellow never seems to have been
regarded as a noble colour in the West until the end of the Middle Ages, and it is
apparently still regarded as one of the least pleasurable of individual hues.”
Despite the casual treatment of both perceptions and language which underlines
the quantitative emphasis of Newton’s work, his circular arrangement of colours in 58
the Opticks (which significantly, in view of his harmonic theory, placed blue oppo-
site orange) formed the starting-point for the investigation of complementarity in
the latter part of the eighteenth century, and thus of the contrast theory of harmony
which was to prevail for most of the nineteenth century, mainly through the influ-
ence of Chevreul (see Chapter 15).*? It would be a mistake to confine Newton’s
influence to his contribution to the quantification of colour in what is now seen as
classical optics.
One of the reasons why scientific students of colour have been reluctant to draw on
the experience of art is that artists are generally considered a small, untypical and
THE CONTEXTS OF COLOUR
16
THE CONTEXTS OF COLOUR
Purpurviolett
N
AD\quody
unsBaqjag
Artists are among the devisers of the numerous scales of colour and value (light and dark) proposed
since the twelfth century. The Bauhaus painter Johannes Itten’s Colour-sphere of 1921, for example,
proposes a grey-scale of seven steps, shown at far left and right. (1)
which is slightly fewer than the number introduced at about the same time by the
German theorist Wilhelm Ostwald and the American Albert Munsell in their
colour-systems. Their colour-atlases and solids, arranging samples of every known
surface-colour in coherent sequences, have offered perhaps the most widely used
standards of colour in the twentieth century.
The first, twelve-step scale had already,
remarkably, been published in the twelfth century, in one of the very earliest
accounts of a tonal scale, this time for red and green, in the technical handbook De
Diversis Artibus by the German monk Theophilus.” Theophilus introduces this scale
in a discussion of painting the rainbow, where a series of nineteen values of red and
green is to be used, and the method is also recommended for the tonal modelling of
round surfaces. It seems unlikely that this extraordinarily nuanced procedure was
17
THE CONTEXTS OF COLOUR
Are artists untypical cases? The greatly reduced palette of Rembrandt’s self-portrait in old age, and even
the large circles in the background, suggest an aspiration towards classical simplicity rather than the
effects of visual impairment associated with ageing. (2)
18
THE CONTEXTS OF COLOUR
French landscape painter Corot, on the other hand, spoke of a series of twenty
values between the lightest and what he called the ‘most vigorous’, which is also the
number presented by the most extensive modern system, the Villalobos Color Atlas
of the 1940s.*7 Scaling has been a major theme in recent research in psycho-physics
and colorimetry, but so far as I know there has been no analysis of these and other
experiments by artists because they have been seen as untypical cases.
Another striking area where it is difficult to relate the general pattern of colour-
experience to the specific work of artists is in the question of the physiology of
colour-vision. Several of the greatest colourists in the history of painting have lived
to a great age, and continued to be productive throughout their latest years. On the
other hand, it is well known that colour-discrimination generally becomes less
acute with age, quite apart from the effect of chronic eye-disorders, like cataract.
This latter defect helps to account, for example, for the strident redness of much of
Monet’ work around the time of the First World War,** and we might expect such
deterioration to be manifest in the work of other ageing artists.
In the case of two painters who worked vigorously until they died at advanced
ages, Titian (?1480/5-1576) and Rembrandt (1606-69), it could well be argued that
the more monochromatic tonality of their latest works, which in Rembrandt’s case
at least is inked to a reduction of the number of pigments used,” derives from the
psycho-physiological effect of ageing. But the question is complicated by the possi-
bility that the style of‘late Titian’, which has been so prized by modern critics, is in
fact ‘unfinished Titian’ — that in works like the Diana and Actaeon in the National
Gallery in London we are dealing with an underpainting, and that the refined and
highly coloured Tribute Money in the same collection is a more authentic example
of the late style.*° It is also very likely that Rembrandt’s restriction of palette at the
end of his life has less a physical than an ideological basis: he was anxious to develop
an economical style of colouring which was then thought to be characteristic of
the great masters of Classical Antiquity, whose works were known only through lit-
erary description.*'
But if the cases of Titian and Rembrandt are more ambiguous than they might
seem at first sight, what of two other aged artists, Turner (1775-1851) and Matisse.
(1869-1954), whose late work shows an increased refinement and subtlety precisely
in the handling of colour? The greatly increased brightness of Turner’s work, both
in oils and watercolours, in the second half of his career and especially during his
late sixties and early seventies, led some contemporaries to suppose that he had
developed a cataract; but this view depended on a very imperfect acquaintance
with the whole range of the painter’s work, where the brighter tonality and the
reduction of more strictly formal elements gave him far greater scope than earlier
for the exploration of infinitely subtle gradations of colour and tone — at its peak in
the great Swiss watercolours of the early and mid-1840s. Similarly, in Matisse’s
cut-paper compositions of the 1940s and 1950s, of which perhaps the best-known
examples are The Snail (1952) and Souvenir d’ Océanie (1952-3) in the Museum of 3
Modern Art in New York, the artist was working more exclusively than ever with
colour, using a wide range of previously painted papers with an unprecedented
freedom, but also with an unprecedented finesse.*
19
THE CONTEXTS OF COLOUR
Clearly both these painters were non-standard observers, and seem to have
escaped the normal ageing processes. Their work is evidence of a constantly self-
refining capacity in visual experience which must surely enter into the larger study
of human responses to colour.
Colour in context
I have introduced here a few examples of the ways in which the experience of
colour in artefacts, especially artefacts from earlier periods, may be enriched by the
collaboration ofscientific analysis, and may in turn contribute to the enrichment of
the understanding of colour-perception in a scientific context. It seems to me that
the aesthetics of colour have developed very little during this century precisely
because they have been too exclusively concerned with laboratory testing, and too
little with colour-preferences as expressed in the practical choices of everyday life.
Similarly, studies of colour-language have been content, on the one hand, with the
vaguest of colour-designations: ‘yellow’ ‘red’, and so on, and on the other, with the
same constricting techniques of assessment through laboratory tests.As an anthro-
pologist put it in a critique of Berlin and Kay’s book: ‘a semiotic theory of color
universals must take for “significance” exactly what colors do mean in human soci-
eties. They do not mean Munsell chips.’
2 - Colour and Culture
inclined to call ‘blue-green’, a colour close to the one which Matthias Griinewald
represented encircling Christ’s red-orange halo in the Resurrection scene in his great
Isenheim Altarpiece of the early sixteenth century, now in the museum at Colmar
in Alsace. Griinewald, who may have been a technologist as well as a painter, had
doubtless experienced this colour, as we all do, as the negative after-image ofafiery
red light.
When in the late eighteenth century the phenomenon of negative after-images
began to be investigated systematically, notably by Charles Darwin’s father, Robert
Waring Darwin, the ‘complement’ to red was also usually described as blue-green,
as it had been about a century earlier in Newton’s experiments with the colours of
61 thin plates (Newton’s Rings’).4 But after 1800 the notion that there are three
‘primary’ colours of light (red, blue and yellow), and that the eye, fatigued by the
strong sensation of one of these colours, ‘demanded’ the product of the remaining
two in order to restore its balance, was allied to an interest in symmetrical, usually
circular colour-systems. It became increasingly common to describe, and even to
represent, the complement of red as simply green, a mixture of equal parts of blue
and yellow.’ Green is still commonly identified as the complement of red, even in
perceptually oriented handbooks of colour such as Josef Albers’s Interaction of Color
(1963);° and this persistent idea suggests a powerful cultural conditioning of the sort
Umberto Eco was concerned to expose.
Charles Hayter’s colour-circle of 1813, however, also introduces us to experi-
ences of colour where culture seems to have worked in precisely the opposite way,
where perceptions appear to take precedence over ideas. Hayter’s polar contrasts,
‘warm’ and ‘cold’, may here be making their first appearance in a colour-system,
although they had been common enough in English painterly discussions for at
least a century.’ But they are contrasts which are still widely endorsed in the charac-
terization of colour. Colours seem ‘warm’ or ‘cool’ only metaphorically, of course,
but the radiation of which they are the visible sympton is radiant energy, and we
have known ever since the introduction of gas heating over a century ago that it
must be interpreted in the opposite sense to this metaphorical usage. The short-
wave, high-frequency energy of the blue-violet end of the spectrum signals the
greatest capacity to heat, and the long-wave, low-frequency red end, the least. Yet
even in the modern world, gas-companies continue to show the warming effect of
red-orange flames where domestic comfort in the living-room is in question, while
they take a much more functional attitude to ovens, which are shown correctly
with the heating flames blue. Laboratory tests in Europe and the United States,
from the 1920s until the present day, have shown that the psychological interpreta-
tion of colour-temperature has been far from unambiguous, but I imagine that
most people will continue to think of yellows, oranges and reds as at the ‘warm’ end
of the spectrum and blues and greens as at the ‘cool’.
In recent years there has been a revival of interest in the idea of a universal or
‘basic’ experience of colour, which is seen to have given rise to those interpreta-
tions that conflict so much with common assumptions. Responses to colour, it is
argued, go back to archetypal human experiences of black night, white bone, red
blood, and so on. Thus A. Wierzbicka proposed in 1990 that:
COLOUR AND CULTURE
cold Colour,
23
COLOUR AND CULTURE
Olympia
Monte
Carlo+
fe
Sar
aR
ioe
BABY
BLUE
Russian
Bl
BRIT-
TANY
ES
ee
a‘
Capri
nl
-
f
Z 7:
I
Saree
AST
eee
SE
PAR
5Udy
CSOT
REE
LL
a
nee
ESIYGRAD
AYRAS
P.AR
BE Cadet Bl
}7
11
©
. st
een
aa
Re
eaaee
TEP
SLMS
FNS
Paras
Eel
eT
ee
A B Cc D E 1S G H I J K 6;
‘Blue’, from Maerz and Paul’s Dictionary of American trade-names. The chart reveals both the arbitrary
nature of colour-naming (note the close proximity of ‘Virgin’ to ‘Pompadour’) and the large areas of
perceptible colour to which no names have been given at all. (5)
(lightness or darkness) in what has turned out to be a far from symmetrical colour-
space.
Probably the most widely recognized of these colour-continuums in the ancient
and modern worlds has been the spectrum light as manifested in the rainbow. It was
the optics of the seventeenth century, notably the work of Sir Isaac Newton, that
made the spectrum into the standard of ‘colour’; and it is striking that in the eigh-
teenth century even a natural philosopher such as the Viennese entomologist Ignaz
24
COLOUR AND CULTURE
A colour-circle of 1771 by Ignaz Schiffermiiller, probably the earliest attempt to arrive at a theory of
harmony by this means. The twelve colours include a ‘fire-red’, but also a ‘fire-blue’ — truer to reality
than the usual warm = red pairing, in that the hottest flame is at the blue end ofthe radiation scale. (6)
25
COLOUR AND CULTURE
torio XXX, 77-8), and illustrated very plausibly in the scene of Noah’s Flood in a
fifteenth-century Norman Book of Hours, now in the Bodleian Library in Oxford,
but Newton repeatedly changed his mind during the course of his career, and
60 opted for the seven-colour version only because he was anxious to sustain an
analogy with the musical octave.
The patriotic English Romantic John Constable, who was famous for his sharp-
ness of observation, seems nevertheless, in his frequent depictions of the rainbow, to
have been content with red, white and blue; and in the modern world of commer-
cial design I have found examples with five, six or seven colours, and a variety of
sequences. It is chiefly the imperceptible transition from one band of colour to the
next which has led to these ambiguities, and it is not surprising that we sometimes
have to resort to mnemonics to remember the order. Constable, a painter who
showed an unusual interest in meteorology, correctly recorded the reversal in the
sequence of colours in the secondary rainbow which is sometimes observed
outside the first, but this phenomenon has not always been respected. One of the
49 most unexpected lapses was in John Everett Millais’s The Blind Girl (1856), where
the Pre-Raphaelite precision of the landscape-setting, painted at Winchelsea in
Sussex, is quite remarkable, but the colours of the secondary bow were not reversed
until the mistake was pointed out by a friend of the painter’s, and corrected — for a
supplementary fee.'° Even in the case of a single bow, the order of colours, running
from red at the top to violet inside the arc, has sometimes escaped the attention of
artists. Some readers may recall the broad upside-down bow in the Pastoral Sym-
phony section of Walt Disney’s Fantasia of 1940.
What the history of the spectrum suggests is that there are real difficulties in per-
ceiving and identifying colours in complex arrays, especially when their edges are
undefined, and that the relative poverty of colour-vocabularies reflects these diffi-
culties, and encourages representations to be far more concerned with ideas about
colours than with colour-perceptions themselves.
The devising of colour-systems, allowing colours to be set out in a logical
sequence which articulates relationships between them, scarcely pre-dates the
seventeenth century, and if the spectrum of white light, especially after Newton
nan(oo) rolled it into a circle in his Opticks of 1704, was embraced as the most coherent of
these systems, it not only remained the conceptual problem to which I have
alluded, but was still impossible to translate into terms ofsurface-colours because of
45 the impurities in the available pigments and dyes. Aristotle had already argued that
the pure colours of the rainbow were impossible to represent in painting, and well
into the nineteenth century, colour-atlases for the use of naturalists might avoid the
spectral colours and base their standards of hue and value on a range of natural
objects. Patrick Syme’s 1821 adaptation ofA. G. Werner's 1774 terminology in the
Nomenclature of Colours, a copy of which accompanied Darwin on the Beagle, is a
prime example of this (as it is also of regional variations in colour-categorization,
even within the scientific community at this date). Werner, a late-eighteenth-century
German mineralogist, had subsumed purple under blue and orange under yellow,
but Syme, a Scottish flower-painter, argued that purple and orange were as entitled
to be considered independent colours as were green and brown (two colours which,
26
COLOUR AND CULTURE
BLUES
Met. tit SS ee ——— SST ieee oa
Vo | Names |Colours | ANIMAL VEGETABLE | MINERAL
26 | Indigo Blue
a Blue | Copper Ore.
is = Lewetts: sea ALS. ple cae aS
pnp ef —— }
ies ’ : yp | Blue Copper
27 China Rlamehites Nitens Back Farts ot | ea
Blue - Gentian I'lower. | fram Chessy.
eee eee Bs eo See
— = eee See aes :
ery alee Breast fTimerald- \ Grape Yyacinth, | Ble
Blue. crested Manatin. Gentian, | Copper Ore. |
Bai a
|
ae rae |
i Clira Upper Side ofthe | | Aeure Stone |
29 | marine Wings or small blive Borrage or Lapis |
Blue. Heath, Buttertly. | Macilt.
pap a oo Sj
erates eee elle = pee ere
Flax- Light Purts of the ; | Bhio
| 30 tlower Margin ef the Wings Max tlover. |p. - Ore
| Blito- at Devils Butter*y . b | Copper Ure
= = anon woabies: 4 — ——|
zal aes
. pty
Wt wag Teathers
ate Hepativa.
: | Bi
uel €
of Jay. PPA aes
iE | i
— | —
es Verditter : Lenticular
32 | Bric Ore.
L T
| | i
2 —————s fE +
“ ,
Blues’. A chart from the | a ne
c : 2 33 Greenish Great Fernel Tiirgiors.
flower-painter Patrick Syme’s Blue Flower. | Hour Spar.
Nomenclature of Colours (1821) I eee ————
which accompanied Darwin | oes Se a gs dies
a opine
on the Beagle voyage. Syme 34 eae ‘
Bach‘ of blueTitmouse Small Fentnel
ee ae: :
| sani Benet
= Le. OWT « ¢
retains colour-names, but Ite ae | yal
adds familiar natural objects
as terms of reference. (7)
27
COLOUR AND CULTURE
rust ochre straw willow fell blue knife blue musk rose
sugar pink alabaster sulphur duck’s egg gh psi ice blue pale lilac
Winifred Nicholson,
Starlight and Lamplight,
1937. The painter is
concerned here with
the character of light
and colour in the natural
world: the strong red
pentagon suggests
artificial light, the soft
bluish circle the light
of the moon. (9)
28
COLOUR AND CULTURE
texture, and especially among Russian artists and critics around the time of the First
World War, texture (faktura) came to be recognized as a specific aesthetic category.
The radically non-representational works painted by Kasimir Malevich under the 7
banner of ‘Suprematism’, for example, depended in their articulation of several
whites partly on very suble textural variation. One of the great masters of texture
appealed to by the Russians was the Monet of the late Rouen Cathedral series, in 83
which an almost relief-like handling of surface-texture was one of the most signifi-
cant of his painterly tools.’* Such a wide-ranging understanding of the phenome-
nology of‘colour’, although it has a substantial history going back to Classical
Antiquity, and has been explored extensively by twentieth-century psychologists
such as David Katz,'® runs counter to the usual modern conception of the phe-
nomenon, which, at least since Newton, has focused almost exclusively on the
characteristic of hue; that is, on spectral location.
The widespread interest aroused, not only among ethnologists and linguists, but
also among semioticians and even physiologists, by Berlin and Kay’s Basic Color
Terms (1969), which argued for the universal recognition of eleven ‘basic’ colour-
categories, whose foci were located by their subjects on a spectrally arranged chart
of Munsell colour-chips, depended very largely on an apparent convergence of
experimental findings between ethnography and physiology, where modern
research has identified a reduced set of colour-receptors in the retina arranged to
process pairs of ‘complementary’ or ‘opponent’ stimuli: red-green, blue-yellow and
light-dark.’® Berlin and Kay identified their eleven ‘basic’ terms in nearly one
hundred widely scattered languages, and even the far larger sample in the World
Color Survey since initiated by them has hardly modified the structure of their
underlying scheme.As the distinguished anthropologist Marshall Sahlins has com-
mented, ‘it is difficult to escape the conclusion that the basic color-categories are
natural categories’.'7 Sahlins was unhappy with this inference, since he supported a |
subtle version of the cultural relativism that Berlin and Kay’s research was proposing
to combat; but he might have escaped from it rather easily had he taken on board
the curious consideration that to the physiologists’ six categories listed above,
even Berlin and Kay’s ‘basic’ set adds five others, including grey, pink and brown.
Their rather arbitrary definition of ‘basic’ has certainly come under fire from T. D.
Crawford, and more comprehensively fromJ.van Brakel and B. Saunders."*
An examination of the history of the notion of ‘basic’ colour-sets — often assimi-
lated to the concept of the four elements, earth, air, fire and water, in Classical 45
Antiquity and the Middle Ages — shows that they shared almost no common feature
other than the desire to reduce the myriad of colour-sensations to a simple and
orderly scheme."? As a leading modern student of the relationship between psy-
chology and aesthetics, Rudolf Arnheim, puts it: ‘neither man nor nature could
afford to use a mechanism that would provide a special kind of receptor or genera-
tor for each color shade’. ‘Basic’ sets of ‘simple’ or ‘primary’ colours are thus a great
COLOUR AND CULTURE
gift to structuralists, but offer little comfort to those of us who are concerned to
interpret the use of colour in concrete situations.
Marshall Sahlins shares with other modern thinkers, notably Ludwig Wittgen-
stein, a belief that the assumptions embodied in ‘ordinary’ colour-language reflect
the logic of modern colour-order systems of the Munsell type, which arrange
colours in a three-dimensional structure, co-ordinating hues in a circle of comple-
mentaries, and relate them to the co-ordinates oflight and dark. Thus he writes:
Blue is always different from yellow, for example: depressed (‘the blues’),
where yellow is gay, loyal (‘true-blue’), where yellow is cowardly, and the like.
Blue has a similar meaning to yellow about once in a blue moon.”
It is true that many Western cultures have taken on board these modern systems
with their emphasis on contrasting hues; but there are instances in the Western
Middle Ages, as well as in several non-Western languages spoken today, where the
same term was used to cover both blue and yellow, including the Old French word
bloi, the ancestor of English ‘blue’. Similarly, the other pair of “opponent hues’ in
modern perceptual theory, red-green, was also covered by a single term in the
Middle Ages: sinople, a red in Old French poetic usage, but green in the specialized
vocabulary of heraldic blazon, which was also French.** Even in our own times,
Wittgenstein’s nonsense-term ‘reddish green’ (Remarks on Colour I, 9-14) has been
perfectly acceptable in some languages (for example one spoken in parts of Japan),
14 and even in Germany in the 1920s in the context of Paul Klee’s design-teaching at
the Bauhaus.*} The anthropologist R. E. MacLaury has recently drawn attention to
instances of non-European languages where white has been assimilated to black; it
is clear that in some cultures which have had a profound effect on Western colour-
ideas, notably ancient Judaism, the semantic polarity of positive and negative which
has usually been regarded as axiomatic for this pair (white=positive; black=negative)
does not apply. An important tradition of Christian mysticism deriving from
Pseudo-Dionysius in the early Middle Ages proposed that darkness was, indeed, the
very seat of God.** These apparent anomalies have been noticed only recently and
need much more investigation; but they suggest that in the case of Western societies
as well as in non-Western ones, colour-usage cannot always be understood in terms
of colour-science.
30
COLOUR AND CULTURE
the precise visual representation of the real world was only the latest phase in the
history of monochrome reproduction which goes back to Classical times. Darwin
himself, who as an undergraduate had frequented the Old Master print collection
of the Fitzwilliam Museum in Cambridge, was content to use black-and-white
engraving even to illustrate his discussions of the highly coloured plumage of exotic
birds, for example in his Descent of Man (1871). At least since the Renaissance,
sculpture in the Western tradition has also been largely uncoloured, partly because
ancient Greek sculpture was thought, quite wrongly, to have cultivated this mono-
chrome convention. Modern studies of colour-vision have tended to reinforce the
fundamental role of the rods in the human retina which process variations in
brightness or value; and it is well known that colour-blindness may pass unnoticed
for many years because it is scarcely a functional disability.
In some European and Oriental cultures, moreover, a disdain for colour has been
seen as a mark of refinement and distinction.*° The taste for black clothing, for
example, was a prerogative of wealth and nobility in the Renaissance, but in suc-
ceeding centuries it spread in Europe to all levels of society, and black still forms
part of our dress-code for some occasions.”” On the other hand, when Vincent van
Gogh made painted versions of some Japanese prints in his collection, and substi-
tuted strident complementaries for the more subtle and reticent colour-harmonies
of his models, it may seem to us to be no more than a case of ignorance and vulgar-
ity. Yet it was one of the important achievements of the experimental psychology
of van Gogh’s time to have shown that a love of strong, saturated ‘primary’ colours
was not the preserve of primitives or of children, but was also common among
educated European adults (see p. 250); and this was a line of research which went
hand-in-hand with the development of a new range of bright synthetic pigments
and dyes. It was these psychological as well as technological developments that lay
behind what has always been recognized as the enormously expanded interest in
highly contrasting hues that marks the visual expression of twentieth-century
Western culture, and which has sometimes been characterized, rather misleadingly,
as the emancipation of colour in the modern world.
31
COLOUR AND CULTURE
closed. This was the sort of research lying behind the development of chromother-
103 apy, a practice which seems to have had its greatest vogue in Europe around the
turn of the century, but which is still in the repertory of alternative medicine. As a
review by the physiologist P. K. Kaiser” indicated, chromotheraphy proved highly
resistant to systematic analysis; but another branch of colour-psychology, which
proposes isolating non-associative scales of colour-preference based on laboratory
testing, has been more widely acceptable, perhaps because it is promoted and used
by powerful marketing organizations for commercial purposes.
The most familiar of these scales is perhaps the test devised in the 1940s by the
Swiss psychologist Max Liischer, which according to his organization is now used
widely in ethnographical research, medical diagnosis and therapy, gerontolgy,
marriage guidance and personnel selection. The Full Test uses seventy-three
colour-patches, but a short and handy version includes only eight samples: dark
blue, blue-green (also called ‘green’), orange-red, bright yellow, violet, brown, black
and grey.The subject is asked to arrange the coloured cards in a descending order of
preference, and an analysis of this order over a number of test-runs allows the psy-
chologist to interpret the subject’s character.This interpretation is predicated on the
meanings attributed to the colours. Thus blue, which Liischer, like most modern
psychologists, has identified as the most widely preferred colour among Europeans,
is held to be concentric, passive, sensitive, perceptive, unifying, and so on, and thus
to express tranquility, tenderness, and ‘love and affection’. Orange-red, however, is
eccentric, active, offensive, aggressive, autonomous and competitive, and hence
expressive of desire, domination and sexuality. The section of the public to which
the Ltischer Test is chiefly directed may be inferred from the interpretation it gives
to an ordering which puts blue at the beginning and red towards the end of the
sequence:
Psychologically, this combination of rejected red and compensatory blue is
often seen in those suffering from the frustrations and anxieties of the business
world and in executives heading for heart disease... Presidents, vice-presidents
and others with this combination need a vacation, a medical check-up and an
opportunity to re-assemble their physical resources.*°
What the English version of the Liischer Short Test, edited by Ian Scott, does not
reveal is that the conceptual framework for these interpretations was found by
Lischer largely in German Romantic theory, in Goethe’s Farbenlehre (Theory of
Colours) of 1810, and in the neo-Romanticism of the early twentieth-century
non-representational painter Wassily Kandinsky, whose treatise On the Spiritual in
Art, published in Germany in 1912 and in England and Russia a few years later,
includes perhaps the most wide-ranging body of colour-ideas for modern artists
(see Chapters 14, 19, 20, 21 below).At one point in the first German edition of his
book, published on the anniversary of Goethe’s birth in 1949, Liischer even intro-
duced the ancient and medieval notion of the correspondence ofthe four humours
and the four elements, with one of the sets of colours attributed to them. Goethe
and his fellow-poet Friedrich Schiller had been working along similar lines at the
close of the eighteenth century.*!
32
COLOUR AND CULTURE
It is no surprise that the Liischer Test has come in for a good deal of criticism
from psychologists for its dogmatic tone, and in particular for its failure to provide a
uniform standard in the colour-samples of its various editions. For the historian of
culture its chief weakness is that it gives no consideration to the crucial question of
whether the psychological response to colours is chiefly to their names, and hence
to a general concept of each of them, rather than to their specific appearance.
Recent work with animals and with infants might suggest the latter,* were it not
that the effects of exposure to colours have hitherto been so limited. But if language
is crucial, the problems inherent in colour-vocabularies outlined above must be
brought into play. Nevertheless the Liischer system certainly rests on what seems to
be a universal urge to attribute affective characters to colours, and it must be taken
at the very least as an important modern manifestation ofthat urge.
T WILL BE CLEAR BY NOW THAT the history of art may well provide the most
|eweee platform for the study of colour - but what methods have art historians so
far brought to this study? Nervousness about methods has increased enormously in
recent years, as a function of the growth ofart history as an academic discipline, but
academics have not always recognized that methods have no autonomous status;
they are tools developed to serve particular ends, and it is these ends, rather than the
methods, that are the primary subject ofdebate. I have argued in Chapter 1 that the
study of colour in art must draw on a wide range of other disciplines;' and these
days interdisciplinarity is a fashionable notion. Yet a glance at the literature of the
humanities as well as of the sciences will show that they have their own purposes
and dynamic, which are not necessarily those of the history of art. Art historians
must use whatever they consider appropriate in the findings of scholars in many
other areas to pursue the aims that only they can identify as their own.’
I have introduced these generalities at the beginning of a review of the literature
of colour in this century, particularly as it relates to art and visual practice (see also
text notes), because colour, in spite of a widespread belief in the universality of
certain colour-ideas, is like all formal characteristics ideologically neutral. It can be
seen to have served a very wide range of aesthetic and symbolic purposes; and the
same colours or combinations of colours can, for example, be shown to have held
quite antithetical connotations in different periods and cultures, and even at the
same time and in the same place.
34
COLOUR IN ART AND ITS LITERATURE
European historians of art there have been occasional and rather half-hearted
attempts, in the tradition of W6lfflinian formalism, to distinguish national charac-
teristics in the colour-usages of painters;” and some more promising work has been
done on the propaganda functions ofthe colours of national flags.*
Within the history of Western painting, the structures of power and influence
may be seen in the economics of picture-making itself, in which raw materials
played a major role. Since Classical times it had been usual for the patron to provide
the most expensive and brightest pigments, such as ultramarine, a practice still fol-
lowed occasionally as late as the eighteenth century.’ This gives us some indication
of a split, particularly developed in the High Renaissance in Italy, between the
aesthetics of patrons and the aesthetics of artists. The lavish use of colour which
Vitruvius and Pliny had condemned on the grounds of wanton extravagance was
now interpreted as a failure to recognize the proper function of painting. This judg-
ment is encapsulated in Vasari’s sixteenth-century story of the fifteenth-century
Florentine painter Cosimo Rosselli, who in seeking to curry favour with his patron,
Pope Sixtus IV, smothered his contribution to a cycle of frescoes in the Sistine
Chapel with the brightest and most expensive colours. The Pope (who according
to Vasari ‘knew little of painting’) awarded Rosselli his prize for the best work in the
series; but to Vasari and to later critics, the Florentine’s extravagance was simply
another example of his lack of invention and disegno.'°
The growing field of patron-
age-studies has usually rested on some perceived community of interest between
commissioner and executant, at least before the nineteenth century: colour is one
area where this was manifestly not always the case. But none of the considerations
mentioned above has so far impinged upon the social history of art.
oh
COLOUR IN ART AND ITS LITERATURE
and real values, on which the warm poles of yellow and orange represented the
‘masculine passion’ and the cool poles of blue and violet the feminine. When this
scheme was taken up about a century later by the neo-Romantic Expressionists in
86 Munich these values were reversed, so that for Franz Marc blue became the mascu-
line principle and yellow the feminine, ‘soft, cheerful, and sensual’.’°
Perhaps the most interesting area for feminists to explore is, indeed, the recurrent
assumption that a feeling for colour is itself peculiarly female province, an assump-
tion touchingly exemplified in the admission by one of the leading mid-twentieth-
century German colour-theorists, Rupprecht Matthii, that he left all judgments of
colour-harmony to his wife.'® Such beliefs, as previously mentioned, may have a
biological as well as a cultural basis, for it is well known that colour-defective vision
is nearly a hundred times more common among white males than among white
females.’ It is also striking that one of the most important areas of colour-study in
the history of art, the study of dress, is — notably through the work of Stella Mary
Newton’s Department ofthe History ofDress at the Courtauld Institute in London
— virtually a female preserve; although the most important large-scale work of
costume history’s ancillary, the cultural history of dyestuffs, has been carried out in
recent years by the chemist Franco Brunello.'* But if the history of costume has
been attacked with great vigour by feminist historians,"? so far the history of colour
has not.
36
COLOUR IN ART AND ITS LITERATURE
Su
COLOUR IN ART AND ITS LITERATURE
But a lengthy book made up of such plums, particularly one for which the pub-
lisher has (justifiably) chosen the austerity ofan unillustrated text, would indeed be
indigestible, and there are fortunately not many set pieces like this. In any event,
Dittmann soon gets into trouble with his principle of personal encounter, because
he has simply not been able to examine in the original all the artefacts he wants to
discuss. His chapter on medieval book illumination — that most inaccessible of art
forms, rarely available for inspection, and usually displayed one opening at a time —
depends entirely on descriptions by Heinz Roosen-Runge: and indeed, Dittmann’s
text in general owes much to quotations from other scholars such as Theodor
Hetzer and Kurt Badt, and most of all, Ernst Strauss, whose unpublished notes as
well as published works (which Dittmann edited) have provided him with a good
deal of material. But the visual analysis of colour can in principle never be at second
hand, for different eyes will, as like as not, see quite different things.**
This type of detailed visual analysis works well enough for gallery paintings such
as Millet’s; far more disturbing than the occasional reliance on informed hearsay
is Dittmann’s almost complete disregard of the context of seeing. The discussions,
for example, of Taddeo Gaddi’s frescoes in the Baroncelli Chapel of S. Croce in
Florence, or Ghirlandaio’s in the choir at Sta Maria Novella,?? do not so much as
mention the stained glass in the windows which gives a pronounced colouristic
atmosphere to the architectural space; and this is the more surprising in that Sch6ne
had devoted a good deal of attention to the problematic effects of environmental
light (Standortslicht), particularly in the context of the modifying effects of stained
glass on the frescoes in the Upper Church of S. Francesco at Assisi.3°
In dealing with the painting of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries,
Dittmann gives less and less space to his own visual analyses and more and more to
the statements of the painters themselves, even to the extent of reprinting Delau-
nay’s short essay on light in both its French original and the German translation by
Paul Klee.A beliefin the primary importance ofartists’ views of their own colour-
practice is also a notable feature of the approaches of Strauss and Badt, whose
studies of Delacroix and van Gogh depend heavily upon those painters’ abundant
writings.*' But we are increasingly aware that painters are not necessarily privileged
spectators of their own works; and when they turn to words they may in fact be
rather less able than other categories of writer to articulate their thoughts about the
notoriously opaque. world of visual sensation. One cannot but be struck, for
example, by the poverty of idea and expression in, say, Mondrian’ writings between
1917 and 1944, or Matisse’s between 1908 and 1947, compared to the richness and
variety of the work to which these writings ostensibly relate. In the case of Matisse
we are dealing with a far more sophisticated thinker than Mondrian, but the simpli-
fications that arise from an essentially propagandistic intent are no less evident.
Artists’ statements are not transparent; they must be unpacked like any others. For
38
COLOUR IN ART AND ITS LITERATURE
example, it would have been helpful to have had Dittmann’s commentary on the
manifest differences of tone and emphasis of Delaunay’s essay La Lumiére, and Klee’s
version of it,in which Delaunay’s loosely structured meditations on the primacy of
sight and the spatial effects oflight — which created what he called ‘rhythmic simul-
taneity’ — were given a far more coherent structure, and a far greater emphasis on
the complementarity of polar energies.
Though my heading above characterized the German school of Koloritgeschichte
rather crudely as ‘formalist’, it is clearly not formalist in any rigorous sense. Since it
grew out of Conrad-Martius’s theory that colour serves to identify the very essence
of being, it could hardly have rested content with the mere analysis of external
characteristics. It is true that one of the few Classical archaeologists to have been
affected by this approach, Elena Walter Karydi, has undertaken the improbable task
of draining the symbolism even from archaic Greek colour.*? But the search for lit-
erary ‘meaning’ in colour has been pursued by followers of this tendency, not only
where we should most expect it (for example in Uwe Max Riith’s dissertation,
Colour in Byzantine Wall-painting of the Late Paleologian Period, 1341-1458),}} but even
in Gisela Hopp’s monograph on Manet - a painter whose style has until very
recently been interpreted as a ‘realist’ ancestor of Impressionism, and hence largely
free of literary or symbolic content. Hopp’s treatment of expressive colour in
Manet is particularly interesting because in her analysis of a number of the major
canvases she makes much of the painter’s use of emerald green, a pigment that in
German has quite deservedly been named ‘poisonous green’ (Giftgriin). In The
Balcony, Hopp saw this green as overwhelming and oppressive,** and in her discus- 20
sion of the late Bar at the Folies-Bergére she was even tempted to identify the charac- IO
teristically bulbous bottle on the bar to the right as holding green absinthe, and, by
contrasting with the ‘heated orange’ next to it, helping to establish a mood of
tension and irritation in the picture. But, as Frangoise Cachin noted in her account
of this painting for the Manet exhibition of 1983, the green bottle contains, not
absinthe, but the far cosier creme de menthe, which is still marketed in this format.» IEA
The créme de menthe sits very well with the equally identifiable bottle of English
beer. Perhaps Hopp’s interpretation of the greens in Manet’s paintings was largely .
conditioned by her use of this particular German term, and thus raises the question,
to which I shall return later in the chapter, of how far symbolic interpretation may
simply verbalize a visual attribute.
Central to the problem of formalism in this style of colour-analysis 1s its relation-
ship to a notion of history. Dittmann’s meticulous and highly selective method
resists historical generalization; and Schéne has stated quite categorically that the
starting point of any investigation must be the impressions made on the modern
investigator him- or herself.*° It is not at all surprising that there is a certain lack of
historical dynamic in this sort of writing. Dittmann, to be sure, makes historical
judgments from time to time, for example that the seventeenth century saw the
fullest development of chiaroscuro,’’ or, less plausibly, that colour in the twentieth
century gained a quite new independence in art. But these judgments are quite
ancillary to the detailed characterization of a selection of ‘key works’. Sometimes
Dittmann is struck by what seems to him to be the earliest significant use of a par-
39
COLOUR IN ART AND ITS LITERATURE
40
COLOUR IN ART AND ITS LITERATURE
Al
COLOUR IN ART AND ITS LITERATURE
materials that have often been part of an ideology or mystique of technique specific
to those periods and to particular places.
There have been a number of recent exhibitions devoted to techniques and
materials,‘ but rather less attention has been given to tools. The pioneering work of
E Schmid and J.W. Lane and K. Steinitz fifty years ago on that most important con-
ceptual as well as practical tool of the artist, the palette, has only recently been
developed.°>
Colour-symbolism itself has sometimes been thought to depend on the qualities
of materials; Michael Baxandall has pointed to the way in which certain Florentine
contracts ofthe fifteenth century prescribed specific qualities of ultramarine for the
most important areas of the picture, such as the Virgin’s robe, because it was the
most costly of all pigments (see pp. 13-14 above); and this is an attitude also found
in seventeenth-century Spain.°° Yet, as both contracts and the technical analysis of
surviving works abundantly show, other blue pigments were used as frequently
in these vital places, and the most important Italian recipe book of the period
described synthetic blues that were claimed to be indistinguishable from the best
ultramarine.‘’? Contracts often specified other particularly expensive pigments, as
well as gold, and the use of these specified colours was prescribed by many Italian
guild regulations:>* rather than demonstrating a ‘materialist’ attitude to colour-sym-
bolism in the spectator, they show a concern for the colour-stability of the product,
which, it was assumed, could only be guaranteed by the use of the ‘best’ materials
(see p. 13 above).*
One of the important conclusions to be drawn from much recent research in
conservation 1s that artists’ practice at all periods was often far more complicated
than the handful of surviving technical texts would suggest; and with the excep-
tion of Roosen-Runge’s study of the Mappae Clavicula and ‘Heraclius’ texts in rela-
tion to English Romanesque manuscript illumination, David Winfield on Byzantine
mural-techniques, and Mansfield Kirby-Talley’s account of the theory and practice
of the eighteenth-century English portrait-painter Thomas Bardwell, there has, it
seems, been little attempt to test the texts against the practice.°' Nor has the corpus
of written texts expanded much in recent years, although there have been impor-
tant new editions of some ofthe standard ones.
A systematic survey of scientific sources, particularly medical literature, would
certainly extend the range of technical sources for the arts:° there is, for example,
some particularly rich material on dyeing and painting — including what appears to
be the earliest textual reference to oil painting — in a recently published treatise on
the elements by the southern-Italian physician Urso ofSalerno, dating from the late
twelfth century.”
The vastly expanding technical literature for artists in the nineteenth century has
still to be surveyed and evaluated, although Anthea Callen has used some of it in her
important study of Impressionist technique.® Virtually no work at all has appeared
so far on the technical interests of twentieth-century painters, although the com-
mercial development of new artists’ materials has been greater in our time than in
any earlier period, and they have as usual formed an important part of the prevailing
aesthetic ideology.”
42
COLOUR IN ART AND ITS LITERATURE
43
COLOUR IN ART AND ITS LITERATURE
Greek examples of painting that are coming increasingly to light. The key text has
always been Pliny’s account (Natural History, XX XV, 50) of the four-colour palette
of Apelles and some of his contemporaries, which has been related to an archaic
Greek doctrine of the ‘basic’ colours of the four elements. While several modern
scholars have continued to use Pliny’s text as a guide to colour-principles in the
fifth and fourth centuries Bc, others have more plausibly placed it, with the related
judgments of Vitruvius and the orator Cicero, in the context of aspecifically Roman
polemic against extravagance in decoration.”
Alberti to Dtirer
44
COLOUR IN ART AND ITS LITERATURE
Only around 1600 did the theory of colour seem to offer something new and excit-
ing to artists, and the widespread movement to integrate the art and the science of
colour, which began essentially at the court of Rudolph II in Prague, was to last for .
nearly two centuries. In the the era of the Kunst- and Wunderkammer, colour and
colours, like painting and engraving, were among the wonders of art to be set
beside the wonders of nature. In Rudolph’s entourage several artists and scholars —
the painter Arcimboldo, the mathematician Kepler, the physicians de Boodt and 45
Scarmiglioni (see Chapter 8) — were interested in colour, and especially in its rela
tionship to music.*” During the seventeenth century many artists became involved
in colour-theory, and many theorists of colour looked to painting for enlighten-
ment. It was the period when Leonardo’s writings were first evaluated and pub-
lished, and when artists in both northern and southern Europe turned their hands
to writing. There are now studies of the theoretical interests of Rubens, Poussin,
and Pietro Testa,** as well as of the minor painter but influential theorist Matteo
Zaccolini.*? In the burgeoning French Academy of the 1660s colour and its rela~_ 57
tionship to design became a standard topic of formal, as well as informal debate,
generating an important and influential literature, especially by Félibién and De
45
COLOUR IN ART AND ITS LITERATURE
Piles.” Paradoxically, since this was also the period that gave the greatest value to
darkness, both in theory and painterly practice,” light and colour found for the first
time a unified theory in the work of Descartes and, especially, Newton, who
showed that colour was indeed illusory, and that light was its only begetter. Yet
artists were at first both willing and able to draw on Newton’ ideas, especially his
conjectures about harmony, and his circular arrangement of colours which eventu-
ally gave them a clue to the nature of‘complementary’ contrast (see p. 142 below).??
Contrasts are, of course, subjective effects, and it was one of the greatest achieve-
ments of Newton to have shown that all colour is intrinsically subjective.
46
COLOUR IN ART AND ITS LITERATURE
47
COLOUR IN ART AND ITS LITERATURE
doxically, as an inferior part of painting; and it was from a pupil of Ingres, Jules-
Claude Ziegler, that he took his colour-diagram and, probably, his first knowledge
of Chevreul.'” Like Ziegler, Blanc moved easily between the fine and the applied
arts — he also wrote a Grammaire des arts décoratifs — and he saw no contradiction in
applying the same colour-theory to both. With far-reaching consequences, he also
praised Oriental cultures, especially the Chinese, as expert in colour and models for
European colour-usage. It was on to an Oriental — albeit a Turk — that Gauguin
foisted his amusing pastiche, the brief essay on colour-harmony that he circulated
among some friends in Paris in 1886.'"
Seurat’s reputation as a theorist has suffered somewhat in recent years, and it is
certainly not easy to understand why he remained so loyal to Chevreul, when the
literature of colour for artists in the 1870s and 1880s had introduced the far more
sophisticated notions of Hermann von Helmholtz (see Chapters 16, 17).''* The
explanation may lie in Seurat’s belief in Blanc’s view of Delacroix as a Chevreulian
painter; for it seems that the colour-circle that Seurat drew on a sheet of sketches
106 for La Parade is a reminiscence of the circle that Delacroix sketched in a notebook
iene) of about 1840, and that had been published by Auguste Laugel in 1869. Laugel’s
commentary is interesting for he introduces the new research of Helmholtz into
the colours of light, with its scheme of complementaries red-blue/green, orange-
cyan, yellow-indigo, yellow/green-violet, but he argues that Delacroix’s ‘crude
diagram’ of Chevreulian complementaries is far more practical for artists. Seurat
clearly agreed.''’ The context of Seurat’s scientism has still be be fully examined,
but it seems likely that in future less emphasis will be placed on the physics of
109-10, 105 Helmholtz and more on the psycho-physics of Charles Henry.''®
4
If Seurat as a colour-theorist has been the victim of revisionism, knowledge of
van Gogh’s approach to colour has remained essentially where Kurt Badt left it in
his 1961 study, which gathered a large number of references to colour from the
painter's extensive correspondence and related them only very loosely to his
work."'” Vincent’s own writing has continued to be the almost exclusive source of
documentation, and although we know a good deal about his reading of the theo-
retical literature of the period, very little has been done to evaluate his use ofit."'®
Nor has the crucial friendship with Gauguin in 1887 and 1888 been looked at
closely from the point of view oftheir rival conceptions of colour. Gauguin’s sym-
pathy withVincent’s notions, shown in the very flatly painted and strongly coloured
Vision after the Sermon in Edinburgh, and in the lesson he gave to Paul Sérusier in
1888, gave way increasingly to dislike for what he considered to be van Gogh’s very
crude colour-aesthetic. Although Gauguin never showed much interest in colour-
theory as such, the colour-system later published by Sérusier, with its emphasis on
warm browns and cool greys and its avoidance of complementarity, may substan-
tially represent Gauguin’s views."!?
Cézanne’s late work is perhaps the highest exemplification of a nineteenth-
century theory of colour-perception as a sequence of naively apprehended flat
patches, made popular in France by the publications of Helmholtz and his follow-
ers. Shiff has drawn attention to this strand of thought,'”° but he has not explored
the consequences ofthese ideas for Cézanne’s style; and the debates continue about
48
COLOUR IN ART AND ITS LITERATURE
whether Cézanne may be considered to have had a ‘theory’, and the relationship of
theory to his painterly practice.'?' Here is one area where formal analysis still has a
major role to play.'”
Tiventieth-century theory
The historiography of colour in the art of the recent past has faced two intractable
problems.The first is that the categories of colour-analysis — the terminology intro-
duced in modern colour-systems, and the concepts of the psycho-physiological
effects of colours — are the very same ones that have been developed over the past
century or so; and they have thus tended to be taken for granted and exempted
from historical analysis. The second problem has been the hermetic character of
modernist criticism, and, together with this hermeticism, the extensive self-analysis
of artists themselves, which this criticism has often seen as sufficient. Criticism, that
is to say advocacy, has naturally taken precedence over the more analytical proce-
dures of history. Thus, although the more or less collected writings of some of the
major movements, such as Russian Constructivism and the Bauhaus, and some of
the major figures, like Matisse and Mondrian, and minor ones, like Marc and van
Doesburg, Hans Hoffmann and Winifred Nicholson, are now readily available,
there has been remarkably little secondary discussion of the colour-ideas of twenti-
eth-century artists.'*3
Several general treatments of individual artists, however, such as Hoelzel, Itten,
Matisse and van Doesburg, and of groups such as the Orphists, Russian Construc-
tivists and De Stijl, have included important considerations of their theoretical
interests in colour.’ There has also been a handful of short essays on Orphism, on
Russian Constructivism, on Marc, Klee, Picasso and Rothko, that have focused on
colour, '?> and a few monographic studies with the same emphasis.'*°
Several exhibitions in recent years have dealt with colour-theory in the twentieth
century, or have given a large place to it in the context of some other concern.‘
What these studies have usually lacked has been some sense of the ways in which
the discussions and usages of artists have related to the more general concerns of
colour-theory in their time. I have made a limited attempt to point to the psycho-
logical context of Kandinsky’s, Delaunay’s and Mondrian’s ideas (see Chapter 20),
and to the debates on the structure of colour-space that form such an important
part of early twentieth-century colour-science (see Chapter 19).'** The wide range
of attitudes toward colour as dynamic and affective that Kandinsky deployed, for 125
example in his On the Spiritual in Art (1911-12), including a colour-system that
owes as much to the late-nineteenth-century Viennese psychologist Ewald Hering
as it does to Goethe, can be paralleled closely in the responses revealed in a long
series of interviews and experiments, chiefly with artists and professional people,
conducted by the psychologist G. J. von Allesch in Germany in the decade before
the First World War.'”? At the Bauhaus in the 1920s Kandinsky was probably the
teacher most inclined to draw, as we know from his lecture notes, on the recent lit-
erature of experimental psychology, notably Neue Psychologische Studien (19266).
49
COLOUR IN ART AND ITS LITERATURE
The Bauhaus represents a particularly rich field of colour-study, where the tradi-
tional concentration on the ideas of the most famous ofthe individual teachers has
civen quite a false impression of what was actually taught about colour there. It
never seems to have been a central issue. Itten is assumed to have taught the Basic
Course (Vorkurs), compulsory for all students, from the outset in April 1919, but the
first prospectus makes no reference to it, and it does not appear in the deliberations
of the Masters’ Meetings until October 1920."°AtWeimar, after Itten’s departure in
1923 colour was taught in the Vorlehre by Kandinsky for a mere hour a week, com-
pared to the eight hours of form-study under Moholy-Nagy plus an hour of the
same with Klee, two hours of drawing with Klee, and two of analytical drawing
with Kandinsky." Klee’s colour-lectures of 1922-3 (excerpted by Spiller in his
edition of the Notebooks and now available in facsimile) must have been given to
more advanced students in only some of the workshops.'** After the move to
Dessau, under Moholy-Nagy and Albers colour appears to have been dropped from
the Vorkurs entirely.'33 Albers, however, came to put colour at the centre of his inter-
ests, and after his move to the United States he taught the colour-course that gave
birth to his great Interaction of Color of 1963. In this beautiful and influential book,
Albers relegated ‘theory’ to the final stages of practice; and it is certainly question-
able how far he had a coherent conception ofcolour-theory at all."
Colour as content
$O
COLOUR IN ART AND ITS LITERATURE
si
COLOUR IN ART AND ITS LITERATURE
green, for example, so often encountered together in the drapery of Trecento paint-
ing, had been since Antiquity regarded as the light or dark species of the same genus
of hue." The pairing of black and blue, mentioned by Cennini in his chapter on
block-printing, and recognizable in many paintings, is subject to the modern eye to
similar confusions. Cennini (ch. LXXVII) assumed that cangianti draperies were
suitable for angels, and this is often, though not exclusively, where they appear in
Italian Trecento and Quattrocento painting. But what was perhaps most important
was that they clearly connoted silk, probably exotic silk, and hence great expense: at
the end of the sixteenth century Lomazzo, who provides the most extensive treat-
ment of cangianti combinations (Tiattato della pittura, II, X) and regards them as
appropriate to nymphs and angels, insists that they are silks, and seeks to restrict the
vast range of colour-possibilities to those giving a convincing rendering of actual
stutis.A8
§2
COLOUR IN ART AND ITS LITERATURE
brilliant perception that imaginary coats of arms might be more revealing of atti-
tudes to symbolism than historical ones; and he has gone on from there to survey
the vast field of medieval secular and ecclesiastical symbolism. Heraldry offers a par-
ticularly fruitful area for the study of colour-language because of the abundance of
more or less datable armorials, from the early thirteenth to the seventeenth century,
many of which are illuminated.The detailed analysis of this language remains to be
done, but it is likely to reveal a gradual shift from object-based terms to more
abstract ones, a shift in line with the greater capacity for conceptualization percep-
tible in other areas of colour-experience in the later Middle Ages. Closely allied to
heraldic attitudes to colour-meaning are those of liturgical usage in the Christian
Church; and the study of liturgical colour, both Catholic and Protestant, has now
received an incomparable boost from the exhaustively documented articles in the
Reallexikon zur deutschen Kunstgeschichte, which, as usual in this encyclopaedia, are
far from confined to German examples.'*°
In the post-medieval period the colour-content of paintings has sometimes been
extended far beyond symbolism and into the often highly complex iconography of
colour. Painters began, from around 1600, to refer in some works directly to the
colour-theories of their day, for example to the new doctrine of primary colours,in
Rubens’s Juno and Argos (1611) or Poussin’s Christ Healing the Blind (1650). Even
more explicitly, Turner took up a contemporary debate about the relationship of
the hues to light and dark in a pair of paintings of 1843: Shade and Darkness, and
Light and Colour (Goethe’s Theory) .'*7 A conspicuous modern instance, characteristi- 76, 77
cally more self-referential than these, is Joseph Albers’s long series Homage to the
Square, beginning in 1950 and continuing until the year of the artist’s death, 1976,
which relates very closely to his experimental work published in 1963 as Interaction
of Color. '**
A good deal ofrecent art-historical writing has been concerned with the reception
ofartefacts, and it would be surprising if colour did not find an appropriate place in
these discussions. Museology has certainly given an impetus to the study of the
visual context, in particular to the history of frames and hanging, and to the hghting
of the gallery environment. Framing is perhaps closest to the interests of the origi-
nating artist, who at least from the mid-nineteenth century often designed his
frames himself: but, like the conservationist, the modern framer is often at a loss
to know what the original character of the artefact was.’ Lighting has naturally
been far more the preserve of curatorial specialists, but even here the experience of
conservators and other optical scientists is emerging from the technical literature
and appearing in more general art-historical publications.'* Framers and lighting-
technologists are usually, I suppose, animated by the same urge to recreate an
‘original’ state of affairs that stimulates conservationists and even art historians:
Wolfgang Schéne once proposed — seemingly without irony — that historians of art
should equip themselves with sets of dark glasses that approximated as closely as
53
COLOUR IN ART AND ITS LITERATURE
possible the original lighting-levels of the artefacts under examination.'®' But the
technician, like the conservationist, has to come to terms with the fact that the
history of the object in question may include the history of its presentation in an
inappropriate frame or environment; and that the response of the public to the
work in these unoriginal circumstances must be seen as no less valid than that of the
originator and his or her circle.
Perhaps the least developed area in the history of colour is indeed the area of
spectator-response, and this is probably because the very impressive advances in the
modern understanding of colour-vision have not been matched by advances in the
theory of colour-perception.As I have suggested in Chapter 1, it may well turn out
to be in this area that the historian of art has most to offer the sciences at large. The
distinction is, of course, that vision is a matter largely of bio-physical mechanisms,
whereas perception depends upon the psychological controls to which this vision is
subjected. The one is relatively easy to examine and test by laboratory methods; the
other is not. This distinction is very graphically illustrated by the fact that the
number of colour-sensations that can be discriminated by the human visual system
is numbered in millions,'® while the number of ‘basic’ terms used to classify these
sensations in most languages is believed to be around a dozen (see pp. 29, 68). The
number of these ‘basic’ terms can be further reduced to three or four ‘primary’
colours, relating to the mechanisms of the eye which translate incident light into
sensations of colour; and the idea of primariness itself has had a particular resonance
in modernist art."
Several researchers into colour-defective vision have turned their attention to
artists: Patrick Trevor-Roper’s major study The World Through Blunted Sight has now
appeared in a revised edition.'*t The effects of congenital or temporary abnormali-
ties, of ageing, and even of drugs'®’ might have been expected to be very marked on
the colour-practice of artists; yet the very tentative results these studies have pro-
duced must remind us that, in its broadest sense, psychology is more important than
physiology for colour-usage, and psychology depends upon a wide range of often
imponderable cultural factors."
The study of the effects of colours on the physiological functions, a branch of
research that was especially active in Europe in the late nineteenth century (and, in
the form of chromotherapy, especially interesting to Kandinsky), has also proved
surprisingly inconclusive, although this therapy is a form of alternative medicine
still practised in several countries." A century of research seems to have shown
136 little more than that, as previously mentioned, exposure to red light increases the
pulse-rate and blue and violet light retards it.
Also heavily implicated in modern practices is the use of colour in psychological
tests, notably in the personality-testing developed in the 1940s by the psychologist
Max Liischer (see pp. 3 1-3 above). In the Liischer Test (in which the subject is asked
to arrange eight coloured cards in descending order ofpreference of hue), the order
which, according to Liischer, gives the ‘surface indications of complete normality’
— dark blue, blue-green, green, orange-red, yellow, violet, grey, brown (‘a darkened
yellow-red’), black — is close, in the broadest terms, to the results of earlier tests with
many thousands of subjects." Liischer’s widely used Test'”? has as we have seen
54
COLOUR IN ART AND ITS LITERATURE
come in for a good deal ofcriticism for its lack of precision and concreteness.'7' But
there has also been some scepticism about the capacity of colours to evoke or
expose states of mind at all'?* — a scepticism that has spread to the very notion of
colour-harmony which was such a sustaining ideal for colour-theorists until well
into this century.
Theories of harmony
Traditional theories of colour-harmony may be grouped roughly into three classes:
those regarding the spectrum of white light as in some sense analogous to the
musical scale, so that it could be treated in a ‘musical’ way (Newtonian); those 60
requiring the presence ofall ‘primary’ colours in any harmonious assortment, often
in a ‘complementary’ arrangement (as in Goethe’s theory); and those regarding the 78
value-content of hues as the primary determinant of their harmonious juxaposi-
tion (as expressed in Ostwald’s colour-solid).'73 More recently, experimental psy- 133
chologists have sought to ground theories of colour-harmony in the empirical
study of responses to single and paired colour-samples by a variety of subjects.'”
This empirical work has done little either to substantiate any of the traditional
systems, or to replace them;'7 and yet it remains that harmony is still a very promi-
nent concept among students of colour, and that behind several of the colour-
systems currently in use among painters and designers as well as art historians, in
Europe and the United States, lies the urge to organize colour in a harmonious
way.'”° Is this another instance of the gap between theory and experience in
modern colour-practice?
One aspect of the doctrines of harmony that has maintained a certain buoyancy
among historians of art is the analogy with musical harmony, whether through that
branch of psychology known as synaesthesia (not necessarily involving musical, 1.e.,
pitched sounds), or through looser associations. The high period of synaesthetic
research was from about 1890 to about 1930, and it made a notable impact on atti-
tudes toward colour among painters during this period, especially in Germany and
Russia (see Chapter 21).'7” In recent years there has been something of a revival of
interest among psychologists in cases of synaethesia;'” but it no longer seems to
play a role in visual aesthetics, as it did at its beginnings in the nineteenth
century.'”The looser affinities between colour and music, on the other hand, con-
tinue to fascinate painters and other students of the harmony of colours. The links
between colour-interests and musical skills in Matisse, Kandinsky and Klee, for 129
example, have always impressed critics; and in the case of Kandinsky we can now
be more certain that his friendship with Arnold Schoenberg helped him to move
away from a traditional striving after colour-harmony. It was, as he wrote in On the
Spiritual in Art (1911-12), no longer in tune with the age:
From what has...been said about the effects of colour, and from the fact that
we live in a time full of questions and premonitions and omens — hence full of
contradictions...we can easily conclude that harmonization on the basis of
55
COLOUR IN ART AND ITS LITERATURE
simple colours is precisely the least suitable for our own time... Clashing dis-
cords, loss of equilibrium, ‘principles’ overthrown, unexpected drumbeats,
great questionings, apparently purposeless strivings, stress and longing (appar-
ently torn apart), chains and fetters broken (which had united many), oppo-
sites and contradictions — this is our harmony.'*°
Representing colour
The central angel and that on the beholder’s right wear full-sleeved robes,
round which cloaks are draped to cover one arm and shoulder. On the central
angel these garments are respectively of rich flat chocolate, tinged with red,
and of a brilliant lapidary blue, a colour so emphatic, yet so reserved, that in all
nature I can think of no analogy for it. The angel on the right wears a robe
whose tint is of this same blue, but whose intensity is less. Across this is draped
a cloak of dry sapless green, colour ofleaves at the end of summer, whose
high-lights are rendered in light grey-green shading off into pure white... All
the faces and hands are nut-brown, modelled only by variations in the tone of
the same colour, and outlined in black. The outspread wings, whose feathers
are denoted by thin gold lines, are a flatter and paler brown, something
between tea and toffee, which strikes a mean plane between the figures and
thetree.
56
G
Minox
DAM
[NESS
F =
Derk
vee Exatse)
SoyS
In the early Middle Ages blue was seen as akin to darkness — it is even associated with the dark
angel of evil in a sixth-century mosaic panel in S. Apollinare Nuovo, Ravenna. Later, blue became the
colour oflight. In the eleventh-century book-cover of Aribert (above) the cross and mandorla are
coloured in two shades ofblue, and in an inscription Christ is characterized as Lux Mundi. (12)
Red and green
Stare for a moment at the red disc (right), and then, with eyes unfocussed, at the white disc (left). Most people will see
an after-image they would call ‘blue-green’. Yet since about 1800 red’s complement has usually been described simply
as ‘green’— partly because in the system of the three primaries red, blue and yellow, the complement of each colour
was deemed to be an equal mixture ofthe other two. The optical evidence is secondary. (13)
In his Bauhaus exercises and watercolours such as Crystal Gradation of 1921 (below), Paul Klee constructed a scale of
colours from red to green, one of whose steps must be the ‘red-green’ which the philosopher Wittgenstein declared to
be a logical impossibility. (14)
58
Unstable hue
a
as
1
! t
Blue and the advent of oils
60
Confronting colour
Millet’s highly nuanced handling of colour in the monumental composition The Gleaners, 1857, gave rise to one ofthe
great set-pieces of German formalist criticism. Lorenz Dittmann observed in 1987 how: “The unusually restrained colours
(which seem to contradict the monumental forms) follow a closely stepped sequence: reddish tones in the central figure,
based round copper-reddish, brownish and bright carmine; delicate nuances of colourful greys in the standing figure to
the right; silvery bright blue-grey, dove-grey, blue and turquoise greys. The colour-thresholds are kept so low that
induction effects are made much easier, which allows the indefinite colour-tones to appear as ‘resonances’ ...’ (18)
The rich, close-toned palette of Andrej Rublev, the greatest master of Russian Renaissance painting, has inspired a vivid
modern ekphrasis by the traveller and art historian Robert Byron. Of the hues of the robes and cloaks in The Trinity he
writes: ‘On the central angel these garments are respectively of rich flat chocolate, tinged with red, and of a brilliant
lapidary blue... The angel on the right wears a robe whose tint is of this same blue, but whose intensity is less. Across this
is draped a cloak of dry sapless green, colour of leaves at the end of summer, whose high-lights are rendered in light grey-
green shading off into pure white... The reddish mauve and the pale slate, the leaf-green lit by grey-green and white, are
seen to compose, on examination of the miracle, all the colours of the pearl spectrum. (19)
Even formalist critics have sometimes been tempted to ascribe literary
meaning to colour. Perhaps because
of the German rendering of emerald green as ‘poisonous green’ (Gifigriin),
the characteristic Parisian green of the
woodwork and rail in Manet’s The Balcony has been identified
bya xerman scholar as heightening the sense of
anxiety conveyed byManet’s
M figures, and establishing a mood of oppression. (20)
COLOUR IN ART AND ITS LITERATURE
65
COLOUR IN ART AND ITS LITERATURE
commercial colour film became generally available.'®* This was not the case in Europe:
Edgar Wind never used them at Oxford in the 1950s,'”? and when I first lectured at
Cambridge a decade later they were the exception rather than the rule. This is not
the place to argue the pros and cons of photographic colour-reproductions, whose
limitations are as well known to technologists as to their clients;*”° it is only neces-
sary to point out that, as Wind recognized, these limitations are themselves part of
the history ofcolour in art.
66
Part Tivo
4 - Colour in History — Relative
and Absolute
67
COLOUR IN HISTORY — RELATIVE AND ABSOLUTE
seventy-eight, Berlin and Kay in 1969 drew up a list of eleven basic colour-categories
which they suppose to have entered these languages in the following order: white
and black, red, green or yellow, blue, brown, purple, pink, orange and grey.’ While
as we have seen their study has been criticized both on account ofits method and
for its handling of detail, it agrees substantially with independent studies of three
obsolete languages of special interest to students of early medieval art: Classical
Greek, Latin and Old English.+
68
COLOUR IN HISTORY — RELATIVE AND ABSOLUTE
it was heir. Classical colour-theory had passed on very little about the nature of
colour that could be regarded as certain. Medieval readers of the then best-known
of the Platonic dialogues, the Timaeus, can hardly have been other than confused:
But in what proportion the colours are blended it were foolish to declare, even
if one knew, seeing that in such matters one could not properly adduce any
necessary ground or probable reason...Should any enquirer make an experi-
mental test of these facts, he would evince his ignorance of the difference
between man’s nature and God’s — how that, whereas God is sufficiently wise
and powerful to blend the many into one, and to dissolve again the one into
many, there exists not now, nor ever will exist hereafter, a child of man suffi-
cient for either ofthese tasks. (67D-68D, trans. Bury)
The more empirical Peripatetic tradition was hardly more reassuring:
We do not see any of the colours pure, as they really are, but all are mixed with
others; or if not mixed with any other colour they are mixed with rays of light
and with shadows, and so they appear different, and not as they are...
(De Coloribus, 793b, trans. Hett’)
In Greek thought the idea of colour (chroma) was itself related on the one hand to
skin (chros), that is, to the surface rather than to the substance, and on the other to
movement and change.'® A sixth-century Christian commentator on Aristotle,
Johannes Philoponus, denied that colour was itself an indication of substance, and
in the twelfth century a south-Italian theorist came to the remarkable conclusion
that even taste was a better guide than colour to the real nature of things."
This theoretical uncertainty was fully supported by the experience of ancient
and medieval technology. The most important colour-technology in the ancient
world was the manufacture of purple dye from the murex, or whelk. The process
involved a photo-chemical development in the dyestuff, which passed through a
sequence of colours from yellow, yellow-green, green, blue-green, blue and red,
to violet. The technical literature, from the Peripatetic De Coloribus of the fourth
century Bc (79sb10, 79745) to the Onomastikon of Julius Pollux, compiled in the
second century AD (I, 49), laid particular emphasis on this colour-change.'* A similar
colour-sequence also characterized another technology which was developed in
Antiquity and much amplified during the Middle Ages, namely alchemy, by virtue
of which base and unstable substances were supposed to be transmuted into the
stable substance, gold, by a process whose stages were marked by the successive
appearance of black, white, yellow and violet, or, later, black, white, perhaps yellow,
and red."3 The identical substance might be characterized by entirely different
colours: in the manufacture of stained glass the same copper oxide was used to
colour white glass red and green, simply by varying the time of heating, and this too
was noticed in the early literature of glassmaking.'t The dominant red-green tonal-
ity of the earliest surviving figurative glass (c.1135), in Augsburg Cathedral, suggests 15
what a very significant process this was. Thus the world of colour in the early
Middle Ages was an essentially unstable one in respect to hue: the only fixed points
are those of light and dark. What are the consequences of this for the history of art?
69
COLOUR IN HISTORY — RELATIVE AND ABSOLUTE
Colour as symbol
The most obvious consequence of this pre-eminence oflight and dark is that we
shall not be able to expect an early medieval colour-symbolism or iconography
based upon hue, and the few serious attempts made by historians of art to establish
such an iconography do not carry much conviction.'’ This is not to say that there
were no instances of the use of hues symbolically during the early Middle Ages;
there is, indeed, an abundance of them, and they are often mutually incompatible: in
a single twelfth-century manuscript of Joachim of Flora’s Liber Figurarum, even the
colour-symbols ofthe Trinity are not constant: Christ appears as blue and the Holy
Spirit as red in one context, but in another, these equivalents are reversed."° As in
the case of the interpretation of colours in primitive societies, their connotations
must be inferred from their cultural or ritual context, rather than the context from
the colours.'” In an area where we might have expected a uniform system of colour-
values to have established itself at an early stage, namely in the Christian liturgy,
we find what the linguistic studies of colour-terminology have already suggested:
although by the early twelfth century, black, white, red, yellow, blue and possibly
green vestments were in use in the Western Church, only black, white and red
had achieved any general acceptance for specific offices. Black, wrote Innocent II
about 1200, is emblematic of penance and mourning, and was thus used for Advent
and Lent, white of innocence and purity, and was used on the feasts of the Virgin,
and red was used for the feasts of both Apostles and Martyrs, since it symbolized
both blood and the Pentecostal fire."*
Yet there are some remarkable constancies in medieval colour-usage. The white
robe of Christ in the Transfiguration — one of the very few colour-traditions
recorded in the Byzantine Painter’s Manual of Dionysius of Fourna'? — seems to pre-
dominate in the painted iconography from the sixth century onwards (Sinai, apse
mosaic in the Monastery ofStCatherine), although there are examples of the use of
gold (e.g. Chios, Nea Moni), and an interesting variant appears in the eleventh-
century mosaics of Daphni, in the twelfth-century wall-paintings at Nerezi in
Macedonia and in a thirteenth-century iconostasis beam at Sinai, where His robes
are pale red and green. This pair was important in a tradition of rendering the
rainbow in medieval art and thought: in a literary convention which goes back at
least to Gregory the Great (Homiliae in Hiezechihelem Prophetam, VII), and a visual
one which is seen as early as the miniature of the Flood in the Vienna Genesis, this
type of bow presents the colours of fire and water, and it was glossed as a symbol of
the destruction of mankind by water at the Deluge and by fire at the Last Judg-
ment.*° The combination of colours was also used in the rainbow mandorla and
throne of the Maiestas Domini type, in the West as early as the Carolingian period,
and it is surely from this connotation ofChrist as God and Judge that it passed into
renderings of the Transfiguration, where He appeared, according to the Gospel
accounts, as an aweful manifestation of light.*" I shall discuss other readings of the
same episode later in this study.
There is, too, a surprising uniformity in the rendering ofthe robes ofSt Peter in
both the Eastern and Western Churches over a period of many centuries. His usual
7O
COLOUR IN HISTORY — RELATIVE AND ABSOLUTE
dress was a blue tunic and a yellow cloak, or pallium, although in the fourteenth and
fifteenth centuries in the West this cloak was increasingly coloured vermilion or (in
the north) pale greenish-blue.” But the blue and the yellow were clearly considered
less as simple hues than as families of related hues. The blue might be a positive blue
(Chios, Nea Moni), or a pale green (eleventh-century mosaics at Hosios Loukas).
The yellow might be a clear yellow ochre (fourteenth-century wall-paintings at
Sopocani in Serbia), a pale chocolate-brown (Sinai apse) or a pale pink (thirteenth-
century Psalter, Bologna, Biblioteca Universitaria, Cod. 346) — hence perhaps the
later transition to vermilion. There are discrepancies of hue even within the same
building: in the mosaics ofS.Marco in Venice Peter’s cloak varies from brownish-
grey to pale green and yellow ochre, and his tunic from blue to purple; at Hosios
Loukas, in the scene of Doubting Thomas among the wall-paintings of the crypt,
he wears a pale green cloak over a blue tunic, but in the contemporary mosaic
of the same subject upstairs, he is in a dull-brown cloak over pale green. In the
Nea Moni on Chios he has a deep blue tunic and a greyish cloak in the scene of
the Raising of Lazarus, but as he cuts off the High Priest’s servant’s ear he wears
greenish-yellow over deep purple. The medieval spectator would clearly have been
able to recognize Peter more readily by his physiognomy, which had been estab-
lished as that of ‘an old man with hair and beard cut short’ by the end of the fourth
century,* than by the colour ofhis robes: in the scene of Foot-washing in the Nea
Moni three other Apostles wear exactly the same combination of colours as he.
Yet it was none the less clearly felt appropriate that he should be clothed in robes of
the same general family of hues.
7a
COLOUR IN HISTORY — RELATIVE AND ABSOLUTE
scenes of the Crucifixion at Hosios Loukas: in the mosaic of the church the haloes
are gold; in the Deposition mural in the crypt they are red.
What may seem even more surprising to the modern observer is the Antique and
medieval location of purple at the light end of the colour-scale. According to his
commentator Theophrastus, Democritus referred to a purple (porphurios) which
was a mixture of white, black and red: red constituted the largest proportion, black
the smallest and white the intermediate. “That black and red are present is patent to
the eye; its brilliance [phaneron] and lustre [lampron] testify to the presence of white,
for white produces such effects.*” The beauty ofthis colour as a dye was also attrib-
uted to its surface lustre by Pliny and by Philostratus, who in his Imagines (I, 28)
noted, ‘though it seems to be dark, it gains a peculiar beauty from the sun and is
infused with the brilliancy of the sun’s warmth’. Pliny’s account in the Natural
History is the fullest and the most interesting: of the Tyrian purple manufactured
from murex he wrote, ‘it brightens [illuminat| every garment’ (IX, xxxvi, 127); and
although he claimed that a frankly red colour was inferior to one tinged with black
(Rubens color nigrante deterior: (X, xxxviii, 134), he later explained precisely how this
blackness was achieved. Distinguishing between two types of shellfish yielding
dyestuff, the small buccinum (2purpura haemastroma) and the purpura (?murex bran-
daris), he explained, ‘the buccine dye is considered unsuitable for use by itself, for it
does not give a fast colour, but it is perfectly fixed by the pelagian [purpura] and it
lends to the black hue of the latter that severity [austeritatem] and crimson-like
sheen which is in fashion’ (nitoremque qui quaeritur cocci: ibid.).“The Tyrian colour is
obtained by first steeping the wool in a raw and unheated vat of pelagian extract
and then transferring it to one of buccine. It is most appreciated when it is the
colour of clotted blood, dark by reflected, and brilliant by transmitted light’ (colore
sanguinis concreti, nigricans adspectu, idemque suspectu refulgens: LX, xxxvili, 135). In a
later passage (IX, xxxix, 138), Pliny noted that a paler shade of purple was fashion-
able in his own time (laudatus ille pallor).
Pliny’s account was well known in the Middle Ages. Descriptions of the
amethyst — whose colour Pliny had cited to characterize the best purple (IX,
XXXvill, 135) — by Isidore of Seville, Bede and Marbod of Rennes related it, as he had
done, to the colour of a rose.** Pliny’s formula, ‘that precious colour which gleams
with the hue ofa dark rose’ (nigrantis rosae colore sublucens: 1X, xxxvi, 126) may derive
from a Greek source, for a version of it appears in Greek in some eighth- or ninth-
century technical treatises, the Lucca MS and the Mappae Clavicula.*? The stress on
lustre which is such a feature of his account also emerges from some late Antique
Greek technical literature, and from that of the medieval West. The Stockholm
Papyrus of the late third or early fourth century Ap has three recipes for dyeing
with other purple dyestuffs which refer to lustre; one of them has the prefatory
remark, ‘keep this a secret matter, because the purple has an extremely beautiful
lustre’.*° And the craftsman known as the Anonymus Bernensis, who discussed egg
tempera in the late eleventh century, claimed that his preparations would give a
shine to red, that is ‘almost the effect of the most prized purple’.3' Rabanus Maurus,
in his ninth-century encyclopaedia De Universo (XXI, xxi, Patrologia Latina, CXI,
col. 579), derived the very word purpura in Latin usage from puritate lucis. Thus the
72
COLOUR IN HISTORY — RELATIVE AND ABSOLUTE
linking of purple with red, and hence with light, is rooted in the early medieval
conception of this colour; and it may be sensed in the sumptuous ‘purple’ codices of
the Carolingian period (for example the Centula Gospels at Abbeville and the
Coronation Gospels in Vienna), which interpret the hue in a remarkable range of
fiery reds and pinks.
Medieval blues
The question of the enormous prestige of purple in Antiquity is too large a one to
be entered into here; but it is worth noting that Bede characterizes the purple
amethyst as emblematic of Heaven, and in this he is following Classical prece-
dents.*° This heavenly connotation of purple passed during the Middle Ages
increasingly to blue (quite apart from the more purely naturalistic identification of
blue with Heaven in the mosaics of Ravenna and Rome), especially in its precious
form of lapis lazuli, although the purple cast of this latter was prized as late as the
fourteenth century.*? In one of the very rare attempts to trace the history of a
_ colour, Kurt Badt has pointed to the double nature ofblue as a hue related both to
light and to dark.*#The later medieval appraisal of blue, which may well be linked to
the development of stained glass, tended to move the colour from the dark to the
light end of the colour-scale, for there can be no doubt that, for the early Middle
Ages, blue was seen as essentially akin to darkness. An essay on the red and blue
angels in a mosaic panel in S. Apollinare Nuovo in Ravenna has shown brilliantly
that the red figure, who is on the side of the sheep, represents the fiery nature of the
good angels, and the blue, on the side of the goats, the dark angel of evil, whose
element is the air.** The concern to associate the ‘primary’ colours and the four
elements is one which goes back to the earliest period of Greek colour-theory, but
these early systems do not include blue, and air is designated red and fire yellow,
for example, in the scheme of the second-century AD astrologer Antiochus of
Athens.*° But in a study with the playful title, “What color is Divine Light?’, Patrik
Reutersward discovered that this light could be both red and blue.*”7 The examples _
of blue light he adduced are all late; an earlier one is on the eleventh-century
Crucifixion book-cover of Aribert in the Cathedral Treasury at Milan, where the 12
cross (and Christ’s mandorla above) is in two shades of blue, and Christ himself
is characterized in an inscription as Lux Mundi.**
One of Reuterswird’s examples, the Transfiguration in a fourteenth-century
manuscript of John Cantacuzenos in Paris, is of a type which goes back to the sixth-
century apse mosaic of St Catherine’s on Mount Sinai. The treatment of Christ's
mandorla in this mosaic, and in many subsequent versions of the theme such as
those at Daphni, is an unusual one, for it is dark at the centre and becomes progres- 21
sively lighter towards the edges: precisely the reverse of what we expect from a
source of light, whose effect grows weaker the farther it extends. Where the rays
emitted from this mandorla touch the cloaks of Saints Peter and James, they turn
the pale chocolate-brown and purple of the material to a pale blue. This inconsis-
tency might not itself be a very significant one; other scenes in the mosaics of St
v3
COLOUR IN HISTORY — RELATIVE AND ABSOLUTE
The dark blues of the mandorla surrounding the transfigured Christ suggest the “dark cloud of
unknowing’ which had been given great prominence in the theological writings of the Pseudo-
Dionysius. The Transfiguration, c. 1100, church of Daphni. (21)
Catherine’s themselves show the more expected sequence, from light in the centre
to dark at the edges;#° but if we look at a twelfth-century Byzantine commentary
on this iconographical type of the Transfiguration, we see that it may well illustrate
a rather precise doctrinal idea. Of the (lost) version of the subject in the Church of
the Holy Apostles in Constantinople, Nikolaos Mesarites wrote:
The space in the air supports a cloud of light and in the midst of this bears
Jesus, made more brilliant than the sun, as though generated like another light
from his Father's light, which, as though with a cloud, is joined to the nature of
man. For a cloud, it is written, and darkness were about Him (Psalm 96-7: 2)
and the light produces this [cloud] through the transformation of the higher
nature to the lower, because of this union which surpasses all understanding,
and is ofan unspeakable nature... *!
There are elements in the Gospel accounts of the Transfiguration which support
Mesarites’s view that the union of God and man in the transfigured Christ was
productive of darkness, and that it was a phenomenon beyond understanding.
Matthew (17:5,6) records the bright cloud that overshadowed the Apostles after the
appearance of Christ, and from it God’s voice proclaiming His Son:‘And when the
disciples heard it they fell on their face and were sore afraid.’ The frightened, falling
74
COLOUR IN HISTORY — RELATIVE AND ABSOLUTE
postures of the three Apostles in this type of the scene suggests that this was indeed
the moment represented, and that the dark mandorla is a solution to the problem of
representing the obscured Christ without in fact obscuring Him from the specta-
tor. Mark (9:7) and Luke (9:34) emphasize the darkness of the cloud which over-
came the disciples, and Mesarites himself refers in this passage to the Old Testament
tradition ofthe ineffable darkness surrounding God.* It was a tradition particularly
associated with Mount Sinai, for it was there that Moses ‘went into that darkness
where God was’, to receive the Tablets of the Law (Exodus 20:21), an episode repre-
sented on the triumphal arch at St Catherine’s, where, however, the cloud from
which God’s hand emerges takes a more rational course, from light to dark. The
tradition had been revived in the fourth century by Gregory of Nyssa, but it was
especially developed at the end of the fifth in the body of writings attributed to
Dionysius the Areopagite.* The Dionysian ‘negative theology’ gave particular
prominence to the concept of God as darkness: ‘Intangible and invisible darkness’,
wrote the Pseudo-Dionysius in his treatise On the Divine Names (VI, 2),"we attribute
to that Light which is unapproachable because it so far exceeds the visible light’;
and in his fifth Epistle:‘the Divine Darkness is the inaccessible light in which God is
said to dwell’ (10738 f). In his gloss on the four horses of the Apocalypse (Revela-
tions 6:2ff), he attributed the blue (kuanos) of the dark horses to the ‘hidden depths
75
COLOUR IN HISTORY — RELATIVE AND ABSOLUTE
[chruphion| of their nature’.*t The link with Sinai is an interesting one, for the
mystical role of Moses on the mountain is underlined in the Dionysian Mystical
Theology (I, 3), and the author also cites the episode of the Burning Bush (Celestial
Hierarchy, 1, ) — which was located in the Monastery of St Catherine itself, and is
the subject of another mosaic scene on the triumphal arch — as a further symbol of
the nature of God, for fire ‘burns with utter brilliance and yet remains secret, for in
itself it remains unknown outside the matter which reveals its proper operation’
(Celestial Hierarchy, XV, 2).
The identity of Pseudo-Dionysius is still mysterious: the first references to him
appear in Syria (Antioch) about 520; his writings were defended as Apostolic by
John of Skythopolis about a decade later.** None of the seven manuscripts from the
Corpus in the library of St Catherine’s is earlier than the eleventh century,*° but
there may be good reason to associate the apparently novel programme of the apse
mosaics, which date from after 548, with his views.
Because ofhis ostensible Apostolic connection, as the philosopher converted by
Paul in Athens (he also claimed to have been present at the death of the Virgin, and
is sometimes included in this scene, for example in the Martorana at Palermo),
Pseudo-Dionysius was perhaps the most discussed theologian of the Middle Ages,
especially in the West, where the Corpus was translated several times before the
twelfth century. Later commentators, however, tended to stress the exoteric rather
than the esoteric aspects of his doctrine, and in this sense they interpret the Nature
of God increasingly simply in terms of light.‘? Similarly, some twelfth-century
accounts of the Transfiguration no longer allude to the element of darkness,** and
in the representations of this subject in the Life of Christ window at Chartres (c.
1150) and in some late Byzantine versions (e.g. ceiling painting in the Church of
the Hodgetria at Mistra of the fourteenth century, and Asinou, Cyprus, Panagia
Phorbiotissa of the fifteenth century), Christ’s mandorla is red. In the twelfth-
century mosaics at Monreale, and on a possibly contemporary iconostasis beam in
St Catherine’s on Sinai, there is no mandorla at all: the rays emanating from Christ
are simply rays of golden light. And blue itself, as I have suggested, came increasingly
to be seen as emblematic of Heavenly light.
I have tried to show in the first part of this chapter that our understanding of
colour in remote historical periods, and of the symbolic language that has been
attracted to colour, must be an historical and a relativistic understanding. What I
propose to do in the second part is precisely the opposite: to suggest that there may
indeed be colour-preoccupations in painting which remain constant over a period
of many centuries.
76
COLOUR IN HISTORY — RELATIVE AND ABSOLUTE
Crucifixion scene, c. 1180, church of Daphni. The ‘staggering’ ofthe dark cubes defining the Virgin’s
chin (left) creates a soft and shimmering flesh-tone. (23, 24)
of the shadow along her upper jawline was due to an attempt by the setter 23
to mix optically the tones which he could not make from a rather restricted range
of individually coloured cubes.*? In a slightly later study he expanded the analogy
by referring to the way in which fifth-century setters (e.g. at S.Vitale in Ravenna)
used several small cubes for each detail to be represented, ‘very much in the way of
nineteenth-century pointillism. Like illusionistic painting in general, this technique
of mosaic was meant for the distant view. Looked at from a distance, the colour-
dots appear as modelled forms...’. “The evolution from the fourth to the eighth
century’, he concluded, ‘may be likened to the stylistic developments of modern
French painting from Monet to Seurat.*° The analogy, as Demus’s own examples
suggest, is not perhaps a very helpful one for the understanding of the develop-
ment of early mosaic style: an ‘Impressionist’ and a more regular, disciplined ‘Neo-
Impressionist’ method of setting seem to have co-existed ever since Antiquity, and
to be characteristic of places rather than of times; but it is an analogy which deserves
examination from the point of view of the rationale of the technical device it so
sensitively describes.
The paintings which were nicknamed ‘Neo-Impressionist’ at the last Impres- 104
sionist exhibition of 1886 have a very good claim to being the first modern pic-
tures, in that they show an unprecedented unity of method and style: in them oil
paint, which had been developed as a supremely flexible medium for representing
appearances, was wilfully deprived of this capacity, and used to make layers of dots
TV
COLOUR IN HISTORY — RELATIVE AND ABSOLUTE
and short strokes related, in size, shape and even colour, far more to each other than
to the subject-matter of the painting, which was for the most part left to the specta-
tor to reconstitute for himself. Georges Seurat, the leader of the group who pro-
duced these works, claimed that his paintings were simply a matter of method,”
which he preferred to call Chromo-Luminarism, or ‘optical painting’, and the origins
of this method have been hotly debated. The sketching-techniques of Delacroix
and ofSeurat’s master, Henri Lehmann, the more regular and divided brushwork of
late Impressionism, the teaching of Charles Blanc and Thomas Couture and the
colour-theories of M.-E. Chevreul and Ogden Rood, early colour-photography,
Japanese prints, and a method of colour-printing developed during the 1880s
have all been advanced to account for the astonishing procedure which made its
27-8, 104 appearance in Seurat’s Grande Jatte of 1884-6.* Although critics of later Neo-
Impressionism, where the paint is applied in far larger and more homogeneous
colour-patches, occasionally related it to mosaic,*' and although the discussion of
mosaic methods in France during Seurat’s lifetime — an interest much stimulated by
Garnier’s use of the medium at the Paris Opéra — sometimes interpreted it in optical
terms,** I do not propose to burden these richly suggestive sources still further by
proposing medieval mosaic as yet another precursor of Neo-Impressionist dotting.
I have not discovered that Seurat was aware of it, and the chief propagandist of
the movement, Paul Signac, seems to have been surprisingly uninterested in the
medium when he visited Venice and Constantinople in the early years of this
century.°> To the earliest practitioners and supporters of Neo-Impressionism, there
was no doubt that the essential rationale of the method was to be found in the
science ofoptics: a friendly and well-informed critic wrote in 1886 of their ‘intran-
sigent application of scientific colouring’;*° and Camille Pissarro, a convert from
the older Impressionist movement of the 1870s, referred to Seurat in the same year
as the first painter to have the good sense to apply to painting the discoveries of
Chevreul.*’We must leave aside here the question of how far these claims to being
scientific were justified (see Chapter 16),°* and return to the mosaicists ofthe early
Middle Ages to ask whether, and in what sense, they may have shared the Neo-
Impressionist preoccupation with optical phenomena.
The crucial justification of the Neo-Impressionist dot was the phenomenon of
optical mixture: the light reflected from contiguous patches of two or more colours
will mix on the retina to form a third colour, more luminous, it was claimed, than if
it had been mixed beforehand on the palette.°° It was a phenomenon known to
Antiquity, and it had been treated in some detail by Ptolemy in the Optics, written,
probably in Alexandria, in the third quarter of the second century ap. Ptolemy
discussed two causes of optical fusion, the confusion of images caused by distance,
and that caused by motion:
Now we see... how, because of distance or the speed of movement, the sight
in each ofthese [cases] is not strong enough to perceive and interpret the parts
individually. For if the distance of the objects to be perceived should be such
that, even though the angle [of vision] which includes the whole be of the
appropriate size, the individual angles which include the various colours
78
COLOUR IN HISTORY — RELATIVE AND ABSOLUTE
would none the less be imperceptible; and it would appear, by the grouping
together [comprehensione] of parts which cannot be distinguished individually,
that the perception of each of them is gathered into one perception |omnium
sensibilitas congregabitur],
forthe colour of the whole object will be unified, and
different from [that of] the individual parts.
Something similar occurs through movement at high speed, as in the case of
a [spinning] disc [painted] with several colours, since a single visual ray cannot
fix [for long] on one and the same colour, as the colour flies [recedit] from it on
account of the speed of turning. And so the single visual ray, falling on all the
colours [in succession], cannot distinguish between the original one and the
most recent one, nor between those which are in different places. For all
the colours, spread over the whole disc, seem to be one colour at one and the
same time, and what is in fact made up of a mixture of colours, one uniform
colour. ..if lines are drawn across the axis of the disc, when it is in motion the
whole surface will appear to have a single uniform colour...
79
COLOUR IN HISTORY — RELATIVE AND ABSOLUTE
80
COLOUR IN HISTORY — RELATIVE AND ABSOLUTE
touches in flesh, a procedure not unknown in Antiquity, but which became such
a striking characteristic of Italian mosaic, from the Chapel of S. Aquilino in S.
Lorenzo at Milan and the nave mosaics of Sta Maria Maggiore in Rome to the
ninth-century Roman mosaics of Sta Prassede.”!
8I
COLOUR IN HISTORY — RELATIVE AND ABSOLUTE
Ses
oeop aeee
stitches used to firm t GcuP)
328
)
ovo o
OS,
aoaf
foal
Rls:
G
ob
Nees
bs
(5)&n=Ome
vy
ges Ese
grass. (27, 28)
lag)
COLOUR IN HISTORY — RELATIVE AND ABSOLUTE
figure-mosaics of Haghios Georgios at Salonika are some of the most refined pro-
ductions of Greek craftsmanship, yet they are placed some sixty feet (c. twenty
metres) above the spectator’s head, and their workmanship cannot be appreciated
by the unaided eye, whereas the astonishing broadly handled ninth-century mosaics
in the Chapel ofS.Zeno in Sta Prassede in Rome are only a few metres above eye-
level. The fine ‘chequerboard’ shadow on the neck of the Virgin in the Deesis panel
at the Church of Christ in Chora (Kariye Djami) in Istanbul can never be made to
fuse into a tone in the rather cramped narthex where it is seen. Totally different
setting-styles and textures are to be found in the same work, from the second-
century BC pavement in the House of the Masks on Delos, where the minutely
detailed inset panel of Dionysus is flanked by coarsely executed centaurs, to the
sixth-century triumphal arch in S. Lorenzo fuori le Mura in Rome, where the heads
of Sts Pelagius and Lawrence are in a broad ‘local’ style while St Paul is clearly by a
craftsman trained in the more refined, linear manner of Byzantium.”
And yet, this anomaly is itself very close to Neo-Impressionist practice. Although
the critic Fénéon once claimed that the dots could be fused by retiring “deux pas’,**
it is clear to the viewer that they do no such thing, and that the Neo-Impressionists
are direct heirs to that tradition of painterly painting, whose aesthetic enjoyment
derives from an interplay between the forms represented in the subject and those
which are entirely in the medium of representation, and which invite a continual
advance and retreat on the part of the spectator. It is a tradition whose earliest for-
mulation is perhaps in Vasari’s account of late Titian, and whose locus classicus is
Reynolds’s somewhat grudging admiration of Gainsborough’s last, broad style, but
which in France had been ushered in above all by the arrival of Constable’s Hay
Wain at the Salon of 1824."
The attitude is, at least in germ, one which goes back to Antiquity, to Horace’s ut
pictura poesis: some poems, like some paintings, are best studied at a distance, others
examined closely; and there are hints of precisely this ‘painterly’ attitude to mosaic
in Byzantium itself. Several writers of the ninth century play on the dual identity of
mosaic, as material and as representation: a biographer of the Emperor Basil I
described what appears to be a bedroom in his palace in these terms:
In the very centre of its pavement by means of the stone-cutter’s art is repre-
sented the Persian bird |i.e. the peacock] all of gleaming tesserae, enclosed in
an even circle of Carian stone, from which spokes of the same stone radiate
towards a bigger circle. Outside the latter there extend into the four corners of
the building streams, as it were, or rivers of Thessalian stone (which is green by
nature) encompassing within their banks four eagles made of fine, variegated
tesserae, so accurately delineated that they seem to be alive and anxious to fly.*®
There is good reason for thinking that the early medieval spectator was impressed,
not simply by precious materials, but also by the craftsman’s power to transform them
into images, and he often repeated Ovid's tag to this effect: materiam superabat opus.’?
84
COLOUR IN HISTORY — RELATIVE AND ABSOLUTE
A clue to some of the larger assumptions that lie behind the early mosaicists’ use of
the techniques of optical mixing may be found ina deceptively casual conceit pre-
sented by the Patriarch Photius in a sermon on the Church of the Virgin of the
Pharos in Constantinople:
The pavement, which has been fashioned into the forms of animals and other
shapes by means of variegated tesserae, exhibits the marvellous skill of the
craftsman, so that the famous Pheidias and Parrhasius and Praxiteles and Zeuxis
are proved in truth to have been mere children in their art and makers of fig-
ments. Democritus would have said,I think, on seeing the minute work of the
pavement and taking it as a piece of evidence, that his atoms were close to
being discovered here actually impinging on the sight.**
Although no mosaic pavements of the ninth century have come to light in Con-
stantinople, we know from those in the Imperial Palace, which date perhaps from
two centuries earlier, that the Imperial court (and the Virgin of the Pharos was a
Palatine Chapel) commanded at a very late date mosaic craftsmanship of a finesse
unmatched elsewhere. But the real interest of Photius’s remark lies in its reference
to Democritus and his atomic theory, for this theory was intimately bound up with
the idea of the mixture of elements, with the theory of colours, and in a tradition
which goes back at least to Empedocles, with the analogy between the organization
of nature and the processes of the painter.*? Democritus himself wrote treatises on
colour and on painting, although neither of them has survived.” The clearest state-
ment of the relationship of the atomic structure of matter to optical mixture 1s in an
account written in the third century AD by Alexander of Aphrodisias:
Democritus, therefore, considering that [chemical] ‘mixture’, so called, occurs
by the juxtaposition of bodies, which are divided into minute particles and
produce the mixture by the positions of the particles alongside of each other,
asserts that in truth things are not mixed even in the beginning, but the appar-
ent mixture is a juxtaposition of bodies in minute particles, preserving the
proper nature of each, which they had before the mixing. They seem to be
mixed because, on account of the smallness of the juxtaposed particles, our
senses cannot perceive any one ofthem by itself."
85
COLOUR IN HISTORY — RELATIVE AND ABSOLUTE
Empedocles, he reduced the number of simple (/apla) colours to four: white, black,
red and yellow (or green), which were themselves simply the function of particular
arrangements of atoms:
Such are the figures which the simple colours possess; and each of these
colours is the purer the less the admixture ofother figures. The other colours
are derived from these by mixture.”
This emphasis on the primary and on purity in colour is an interesting one, and is
clearly also related to Neo-Impressionist practice. In 1885 Seurat seems to have been
working with a palette of three primary colours (colorations), red, yellow and blue,
plus white; later, in order to avoid palette-mixtures with anything but white and so
retain the greatest purity, he used eleven colours, including a violet, two greens and
two oranges, arranged on his palette in prismatic order, next to a row ofthese same
colours mixed with white, and then a row of pure white.**
More important, Democritus’s emphasis may be related to a preoccupation with
unmixed purity of hue which seems to characterize the early medieval approach to
painting. Mixture in general had been stigmatized as violent and morally reprehen-
sible by Plutarch, who referred to the workshop-term ‘deflowering’ (phthoras) which
was still in use in the Middle Ages;% for the craftsman himself it seems rather to
have been a matter of chemistry, but the effect on practice was essentially the same.
When the compiler of the most complete (probably late twelfth-century) manu-
script of the Mappae Clavicula prefaced the treatise with a jingle claiming that the
first stage of the artis pictorum was to know how to make colours, and the second to
know how to mix them, he did not understand by mixtione the blending of pig-
ments on the palette, but the laying of one colour over another, when the first was
dry, in order to model drapery.°® Medieval painting-instructions of this sort invari-
ably specify a pigment rather than an abstract ‘colour’; and with the exception ofa
green made from orpiment and black, which appears in the Mappae Clavicula and a
number of later manuscripts, and one or two instances in Theophilus (who, perhaps
because he was not himself a painter, seems to have had a more relaxed attitude to
mixture), I have come across no colours mixed by the artist in this context. Mix-
tures are, however, occasionally described as a process of glazing one transparent or
semi-transparent colour over another, which is, again, a form of optical mixture.%”
In two cases where the physical composition of samples of medieval fresco has been
analysed — some thirteenth- and fourteenth-century examples in Trebizond and
Istanbul — it has been discovered that the pigments used had been mixed only with
black and white (the most ‘primary’ colours), never among themselves, and this
agrees precisely with the treatises on method.°*
Thus the early medieval painter had little or no recourse to the palette for the
immediate preparation of mixtures, and this tool seems to have made its appearance
only about 1300 (see the following chapter), by which time a great relaxation of the
early inhibitions about physical mixture had made itself felt in the technical litera-
ture, and, most importantly, in the methods of painting themselves.’? Curiously
enough, it was in flesh-painting that physical mixtures seem to have been most
commonly used, in those greenish shadows whose blending is described by
86
COLOUR IN HISTORY — RELATIVE AND ABSOLUTE
Theophilus and several later writers. This flesh-green was taken over by mosaicists
from the painters — a particularly strident example is in the thirteenth-century
mosaics at Arta'°° — and used, of course, in just those places where optical mixture
was also most cultivated. For mosaicists as for the Neo-Impressionists, optical
mixture was an aid to purity; for both, it was close to the elemental operations of
nature (Signac quoted Ruskin to precisely this effect),'°! and the mosaicists chose to
use it chiefly in areas where purity and luminosity were the most important aims.
87
COLOUR IN HISTORY — RELATIVE AND ABSOLUTE
Seurat’s Les Poseuses (1886-7), showing the artist’s cramped studio-space, with La Grande Jatte viewed
obliquely in the corner behind the models. (29)
generally receive now: the even glare of modern Italian floodlighting is especially
inappropriate to them. The Early Christian and Byzantine sources insist on a prolif-
eration of lamps and candles, and it seems a good deal of emphasis was placed on
nocturnal offices. But the technique implied, too, that the spectator was not static;
he was constantly moving his eyes about over the mosaic surface, which is, indeed
the only way a surface part-matt and part-highly reflective can properly be seen.
Movement is a feature of both Byzantine and Western Ekphrases. In the sermon by
Photius from which I have already quoted, there is a remarkably vivid account of
the spectator’s reaction on entering his church:
It is as if one had entered heaven itself with no one barring the way from any
side, and was illuminated by the beauty in all forms shining all around like so
many stars, so is one utterly amazed. henceforth, it seems that everything is in
88
COLOUR IN HISTORY — RELATIVE AND ABSOLUTE
ecstatic motion, and the church itself is circling round. For the spectator,
through his whirling about in all directions and being constantly astir, which
he is forced to experience by the variegated spectacle on all sides, imagines
that his personal condition is transferred to the object.”
The arrangement of small narrative scenes, where they exist in mosaic (as for
example along the naves of Sta Maria Maggiore in Rome and S. Apollinare Nuovo
in Ravenna), also require a good deal of movement on the part of the spectator.
Nothing could be further from the viewing-conditions of Neo-Impressionist
pictures, where the spectator moved at right-angles to their surface. In Seurat’s
Poseuses, set in the painter’s own studio, where we see the picture of La Grande Jatte 29
in the left background, the heavy white frame is pressed into the corner of the
room, and the large canvas will rarely have been seen at an angle (as it is in the
Poseuses itself) .'°* The Neo-Impressionists cultivated a uniformly smooth surface so
that there should be no shadows cast from ridges of paint, and their practice of
putting their paintings under glass, rather than varnishing them, had the effect (at
least with their customarily small works) of anchoring the spectator to a single
-viewpoint.'® It is worth noting that the Classical ideal of an impeccably even
mosaic-surface of tightly-packed tesserae, even for walls and vaults, re-emerged in
fifteenth-century Venice, where the mosaicists of the Mascoli Chapel in S. Marco
were using a single-point perspective system with a narrow angle of vision, quite
unlike the more casual perspective arrangeinents of the early Middle Ages.''® The
codifier of this novel perspective scheme was Leon Battista Alberti, who also
attacked the use of real gold in panel-painting on the grounds that it had a variable
value, a phenomenon due, of course, to its high reflectivity and the varying angles
from which it was seen in different parts of the panel by the static spectator.'!
Alberti and the artists of the Mascoli Chapel mark the beginning of an attitude
towards looking at pictures to which the Neo-Impressionists were heir; cabinet-
pictures are, after all, not architectural mosaics, and their conventions cannot be
entirely interchangeable. The cultural and ritual context is decisive. Which is
perhaps to say no more than that, however enticing the idea of the universal pattern
of optical responses in the history of art, we must be historical relativists in the end.
89
5 - Colour-words
and Colour-patches
go
COLOUR-WORDS AND COLOUR-PATCHES
Tomaso da Modena’s portraits of the cardinals Hugh de St Cher and Nicholas de Fréauville, showing
the one (left) wearing spectacles, leaving both hands free for writing, and the other (right) reading with
a magnifying glass. These images of around 1352 are the earliest known depictions ofthe use oflenses.
(30, 31)
QI
COLOUR-WORDS AND COLOUR-PATCHES
Willem Key’s painting of an unknown Flemish illuminator of the sixteenth century. Wearing spectacles
such as those the artist is holding (left) had become a common practice among painters. (32, 33)
eS)bv painter Willem Key, dated 1565, now in the National Museum of Fine Arts at Val-
letta in Malta.
Whether or not the introduction of spectacles is closely related to the produc-
tion of manuscripts, their diffusion in the fifteenth century — when the convex
lenses for the myopic were supplemented by the concave lenses for the long-
sighted — does seem to be associated with the development of the printed book, and
consequent spread of reading and small print.'®
Nequam’s colour-terms
minium (red oxide of lead), which is used here to make mbeus or ‘Phoenician’
(puniceus or feniceus) letters. Puniceus is described in the early fifteenth century by
the French student of colour, Jehan Le Begue, as a reddish yellow, but he lists feniceus
separately as a rose-red.'* Minium is glossed in Nequam as vermiloun, and puniceus as
vermeilles or ruge; and vermilion was, of course, derived from natural cinnabar or
made artificially by processing mercury and sulphur.? We need not worry too
much here about the chemistry of these pigments, even though Nequam was
something of a natural philosopher,'*
but we should note that he and his glossators
were happy to qualify ‘red’ with a number of different terms. It may, however, be
significant that in the early French treatise on making paints by Peter of St Omer it
is advised that, in order to give the illuminator’s red some body, minium should be
mixed with vermilion, ut pulchriores sint (so that they may be more beautiful by
being less pale).'5
Nequam’s blues are similarly imprecise. His fuscum pulverum may conceivably,
from the phrasing of the passage, be the same as the azuram a Salamone repertam, that
is, lapis lazuli from King Solomon’s mines, a formulation which is remarkably early
for the reference to its origins in the Levant (Badakshan). The Norman glosses
translate it as asure. Peter of St Omer says that azurium or lazurium is also called perse,
and this may also offer a hint of a Levantine origin, although perse is still one of
the most contested colour-terms of the Middle Ages, and like fuscus (bloye) may
sometimes mean little more than ‘dark’ (see p. 68 above).'° In a list of equipment
for the scriptorium in a manuscript in Cambridge (Gonville and Caius MS 38s),
also attributed to Nequam, venetus is added to the blues, and green to the colours
required for painting capital letters.'7
Nequam’s colour-list, short as it is, thus introduces us to ambiguities both in the
Latin originals and in the Norman-French translations.We might have expected
that such ambiguities would have been an obstacle to communication in the scrip-
torium, especially since manuscript scholars are increasingly finding that instruc-
tions to illuminators were often in verbal form, and not simply dependent on visual
models.
Marginal notes
One of the most expansive areas of recent codicological studies is in the interpreta-
tion of marginal notes to scribes or illuminators, and many of those so far discov-
ered refer, either in Latin or in the various vernaculars, to the colours which were to
be used in decoration. Sometimes, as in a loose late-fourteenth-century leafin the
Bibliothéque St Genevieve in Paris (MS 1624), whole words were used, even the
enigmatic French term ‘fausse rose’;"* but far more commonly they are simply ini-
tials, or the first two or three letters of the words. They can tell us something about
the working language, or languages, of a particular scriptorium; they can show that
in a few cases illuminators -were either unable or unwilling to follow instructions
and, most important in the present context, they can tell us something about the
precision of colour-terminology in common use in the High Middle Ages.
93
COLOUR-WORDS AND COLOUR-PATCHES
One unusual example is the use of a cross to signify red in a late twelfth-century
Psalter in London (British Library Harley MS 2895).'° This is surely a cross rather
than an ‘X’, and it probably refers to Christ, whose frequent depiction in red robes
was due to the traditional associations of red with light and royalty; and perhaps, in
the painterly context, to the process of manufacturing vermilion from sulphur and
mercury — well described by Peter of St Omer — which was regarded as re-creating
all metals, including the most precious, gold.*? So the meaning of colours was not
confined to their optical properties, but may be a function of their ‘chemistry’ or
composition; and it is also remarkable how often red was designated merely by ‘v’
(vermiculum, vermeille), even though this might be easily misinterpreted as green
(viridis, vert).
But it has also been pointed out that most colour-terms in the Romanesque MSS
which have been surveyed so far are not pigment-terms, but general colour-words:
minium and vermiculum are exceptions to this rule;*' The letter “p’ for pourpre or pur-
pureus may be an example of this; but this initial has been found set against grey
paint in the Bible of Manerius in the Bibliotheque St Geneviéve, where ‘AV’ and
‘N’ are also used, as well as ‘p’ for violet.” ‘N’ has been interpreted as ‘nubilus’ (cloudy),
and ‘AV’ as a mixture of azurium and vermiculum.* But although Le Begue described
violetus quite properly as a mixture of rubeo et perso, seu azurio, his rubeo is a vegetable
lake, and a mixture of vermilion and lapis lazuli is chemically very risky as well as
costly, so that ‘AV’ probably refers to the appearance of the colour, not its chemistry.
Purpureus need not refer to the hue we call ‘purple’, but ‘p’ might equally denote
perse or persus, that tricky obsolete term which was used to characterize dark greys
and violets as well as blues. The use of ‘w’ (waeden = woad) for purple-blue has been
noted in an Oxford MS (Bodleian MS 156);*4 and in some mid-thirteenth-century
English dyeing regulations woad (wayda) is reported as producing perse cloth.*
Here the English term for a known dyestuff gave the illuminator some guarantee
that a particular hue was in question. These ambiguities present problems to the
modern reader, but did they also present problems to the illuminators themselves?
How did artists in the scriptorium organize their colours? Did they organize them
at all?
94
COLOUR-WORDS AND COLOUR-PATCHES
} OS “oe
DP. wera) shen QP’
James Le Palmer’s letter C (for Color) from the fourteenth- The late twelfth-century German illuminator Brother
century encyclopaedia Omne Bonum. The collection of nine Rufillus painting from a shell. Each colour is mixed
colours shown tallies loosely with the ten of the text. (35) individually with the medium. (36)
COLOUR-WORDS AND COLOUR-PATCHES
96
COLOUR-WORDS AND COLOUR-PATCHES
And therefore deep rede toschedeth [separates] the sight, as bright light doth,
and gadereth nouyt the sight, as blak doth. Therefore draperes that selleth
clothe hongeth rede clothe tofore the light, for rednesse scholde toschede the
spirit of sight, and men that seeth othre clothes of other colour schulde knowe
the worse the verrey colours.’
This was precisely the opposite effect to that of green.
Thus both Nequam and Bartholomeus showed an acute awareness of the fallibil-
ity of colour-judgment, which is amply reflected in the great variety of terms in use
in the scriptoria of the twelfth and thirteenth centuries. It would be thoroughly
consistent with this awareness of human frailty that spectacles should have made
their first appearance in the context of manuscript production. Only perhaps the
personal, ‘hands-on’ experience of the workshop and its tools and materials could
bring order to this chaos — if indeed that was ever seriously required.
97
6 - Ghiberti and Light
98
GHIBERTI AND LIGHT
Pittura, which had probably appeared in Italian in 1435 and in Latin a year later.
Ghiberti’s text is generally dated to the late 1440s, but it probably reflects his
reading over many years — he was certainly working on the First Commentary as
early as 1430.
Some of these examples of light and translucent bodies come directly from Ghiberti’s
practice as a jeweler, the craft he had recorded enthusiastically in the Second Com-
mentary, where he recalled, for example, that
Pope Eugene [IV] came to live in the city of Florence; he had me make a mitre
of gold which weighed fifteen pounds, the gold alone; the stones weighed
five-and-a-half pounds. They were valued by local jewellers at 38,000 florins:
oo
GHIBERTI AND LIGHT
they were rubies, sapphires, emeralds and pearls...it was a magnificent piece
of work.?
Before the later Renaissance practice of facetting stones was widely developed they
were usually cut en cabochon: round or oblong with a smooth and rounded surface.
When they were treated in this way the coloured light did not seem to be received
and refracted in flashes, but to glow softly, as if generated from within, as Ghiberti
suggested in his example of light-giving bodies.
Most of the first part of his Third Commentary is devoted to an account, taken
from Alhazen, of the effects of the persistence of vision, of the after-images pro-
duced within the eye by strong light-stimuli, and of the varying appearance of
objects seen under different conditions of lighting. Here there are again indications
that Ghiberti was not merely copying what he had read, but had repeated some of
Alhazen’s experiments himself,'® and again he was ready to elaborate on his source
by reference to familiar examples. Discussing the dazzling effects of lustre, which
hinder the perception of form in delicate carvings, Ghiberti adapted his source so as
to modify its sense completely."!
Alhazen had been concerned with the problem of perceiving forms where there
was no contrast of colour, Ghiberti with the added complication of parti-coloured
gemstones, such as a chalcedony engraved with the Rape of the Palladium of which
he later gave a celebrated description:
among the [most] remarkable things I ever saw is a wonderfully engraved
chalcedony which was in the collection of one ofour citizens, by the name of
Niccolo Niccoli, a very energetic researcher and investigator of many and
excellent antiquities in our time, and into books of Greek and Latin writings.
And among his other antiques he had this chalcedony which was more perfect
than anything I had ever seen. It was oval in shape, and on it was the figure ofa
youth holding a knife. He was almost kneeling with one foot upon an altar, the
right leg resting on the altar with its foot on the ground, and foreshortened so
cunningly and with such skill it was marvellous to see. In his left hand he held
a small idol in a napkin; it seemed he was threatening it with his knife. This
carving was said by every expert in sculpture and painting, without exception,
to be a marvellous thing, and with all the measurements and proportions that
any statue or sculpture should have: it was praised to the skies by all the intel-
lectuals. You could not see it well in a strong light, because when fine and pol-
ished stones are deeply cut [essendo in cavo], the strong light and reflections
obscure the understanding of the form.This carving could be seen best when
the deeply-cut part was held against the strong light, when it could be seen
perfectly.”
This example, as well as the immediately preceding descriptions of the Antique
sculptures Ghiberti had seen in Rome, Padua and Siena, grew out of Alhazen’s
discussion of the need to view fine and delicate carving in a moderate light, a pre-
occupation which may well be understood as close to the heart of asculptor who
was concerned above all with chasing and gilding bronze, and whose supreme qual-
ities as a goldsmith were, according to Benvenuto Cellini — himselfofcourse a fine
100
GHIBERTI AND LIGHT
The admired chalcedony carved with the Rape of the Palladium has not survived, but another version
of the same subject, a cornelian formerly in the collection of Lorenzo de’ Medici, demonstrates the
problem discussed by Ghiberti, of reading gemstone carvings by (right) reflected and (left) transmitted
light. (38, 39)
IOI
GHIBERTI AND LIGHT
Antonio da Pisa’s workshop has been seen as very active in Florence during the
last quarter of the fourteenth century,'” and, although too little is known of its
personnel to determine whether the executants of Ghiberti’s designs came from
it, a number of the features in the windows designed by him are recommended
by Antonio — for example the ubiquitous blue grounds and the yellow capitals
and white or flesh-pink columns seen in the St Barnabas window of 1441 in the
Chapel of Sts Barnabas and Victor in the south tribuna of Sta Maria del Fiore."*
Between 1404 and 1443 Ghiberti submitted some thirty window-designs for the
Cathedral, not all of which were accepted or executed. Modern scholarship is
divided as to the extent ofhis freedom of operation in these designs and the degree
of his participation on their execution, and the documentary evidence is certainly
full of ambiguities.
The only specific reference to the nature of Ghiberti’s contribution speaks of
some designs of 1438 as being on paper (in charte di banbagia ),'? which may or may
not imply indications of colour. Antonio da Pisa had recommended the glass-
painter to study frescoes in order to work out his colour-schemes, which suggests
that the cartoons supplied to these painters were usually uncoloured; and Cennini
implied that it was rare for the non-specialist painter to work on the glass himself,
although he gave instructions how to do so.*° On the other hand, we know that
coloured cartoons were used in Florence, for in 1395 Agnolo Gaddi was paid by the
Cathedral pro pingendo designum dicte fenestre:*' and the first glass-painter to execute
a design by Ghiberti, Niccolé di Piero, who made the magnificent Assumption
for the oculus in the Cathedral facade in 1405, was soon to execute windows in
Orsanmichele after coloured cartoons by Lorenzo Monaco.” Paolo Uccello, who
had trained in Ghiberti’s workshop, was paid in January 1444 ‘pro suo labore in pin-
gendo unum oculum factum per dictum Bernardum |di Francesco|’: the Ascension for the
drum of the Cathedral, the design for which had prevailed over Ghiberti’s own in a
competition the previous summer.”
But whether or not Ghiberti chose his own colour-scheme, and painted on the
glass from his designs, the long series of commissions for the Cathedral windows
will surely have brought him into close contact with the glass-painters’ milieu,
where it is likely that he will have discussed technical and even aesthetic problems
common to the jeweler and glass-painter. And in the Third Commentary, quoting
from Roger Bacon (Opus Maius,V, 1, dist. vi, ch. iv) on the substantial and sensible
nature of images (species), Ghiberti included the observation that, ‘when the sun’s
ray passes through a glass [window] or through a strongly coloured [oiled] cloth, the
image of the colour appears upon the dark body |opposite]’.*4
102
GHIBERTI AND LIGHT
I first looked at the superb cathedral with its silver altar, from which rise five
silver columns, and with its silver baldaquin. As if this were not enough, there
are also marble capitals jutting from the altar, for the decoration of the church,
and which in ancient times were clad in silver, most of which has survived.
I must admit that I have not seen more beautiful holy edifices even in Rome.
There are rows of huge marble columns, and the interior of the building is
clad almost entirely with sheets of variegated marble and porphyry. I have
scarcely seen more beautiful mosaics anywhere. I inspected the highly deco-
rated Baptistry next to this large church, and then went to look at the most
astonishing and magnificent church of St Vitale the Martyr, which is actually
circular, and is decorated with every superior and excellent kind of mosaic.
There are columns around the circumference of the Sanctuary, and various
marble incrustations cover the inner walls. It has a raised platform [peripatum]|
from which the columns spring, and an altar of such shining [lucidam] alabaster
that it reflects images like mirrors...
In the monastery of Sta Maria in Porta Traversari found ‘a beautiful twisted por-
phyry urn’ which the simpliciores fratres held to be one of those used by Christ at Cana
of Galilee when changing the water into wine.’? His response to Ravenna may be
seen on the one hand as the revival of a peculiarly Early Christian and Byzantine
aesthetic;3' but it was also a response in sympathy with the Neo-Platonism of the
Niccoli circle, which Traversari was himself very active in promoting. For in the
103
GHIBERTI AND LIGHT
early 1430s Traversari was engaged upon a new Latin translation of the fifth- or
sixth-century Greek works of the Pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite, a translation
which he carried out in consultation with Niccoli, and which gained the warm
recognition of both his friend and other humanist scholars for its clarity and its
improvements on the ninth-century versions of Hilduin and Johannes Scotus
Eriugena.*? Pseudo-Dionysius’s writing was essentially theological, but his treatise
On the Divine Names included a chapter, ‘On the Good and the Beautiful’, which
became one of the most important texts in medieval aesthetics, and was extensively
glossed by, for example, Albertus Magnus and Aquinas.*} In this account, the quali-
ties of beauty (itself identified with good) are recognized as harmony (consonantia)
and luminosity (claritas), which are said to extend over the created world ‘in the
likeness oflight’3+Light thus becomes the chief manifestation of beauty, and clarity
and lucidity become the highest qualities in a work ofart.
The connection ofsuch an aesthetic outlook with the work of the glass-painter
and jeweler is inescapable: it has been long recognized in the patronage and propa-
ganda of Abbot Suger at Saint-Denis in the twelfth century.** But it was also an
attitude of some importance to Ghiberti, who had been in touch with the latest
translator of the Pseudo-Dionysius at least since 1430, when through him he had
sought to borrow another Greek manuscript for use in the First Commentary.*°
Ghiberti’s thoroughly eclectic discussion of optics in no way constitutes a mani-
festo of Neo-Platonism, although Plato is mentioned from time to time among his
authorities; but in proposing to give a scientific basis to the study and use of light in
the arts of sculpture and painting, and especially in the arts of gem-cutting and
glass-painting, he was adding substance to the aesthetic of light which was so alive
in the Niccoli circle; and in so doing, he contributed to that strand of artistic theory
which passed, not through Alberti, but through Marsilio Ficino (who re-translated
the Pseudo-Dionysius) to the synthesis of Leonardo da Vinci.
104
7° Color Colorado —
Cross-cultural Studies in the
Ancient Americas
105
COLOR COLORADO
that it must be psychologically salient (that is, in common use among all users ofa
language); that its application must not be confined to a narrow class of objects; that
it should not also be the name of a coloured object; and that it should not be a
recent loan-word.} In the absence of any agreement about what constitutes ‘recent’,
according to these criteria at least five of the eleven ‘basic terms’ in Spanish are prob-
lematic, since all of them derive from concrete objects and are borrowings from
other languages. Azul and anaranjado derive from the Arabic for a blue stone and
probably a fruit; café, gris and rosa derive from the French.*
Berlin and Kay’s method for establishing the corpus ofbasic colour-terms in the
various languages is similarly suspect.They first elicited a list of colour-terms from
each informant — sometimes only one informant for each language — and as most
of their informants were living in the San Francisco Bay area of California, the
question of the influence of bilingualism should have been addressed at every stage
of their enquiry.’ Berlin and Kay did indeed address it in the context of their most
important procedure, which was to ask each informant to plot both the focus
and the perimeters of each colour-category on a chart made up of Munsell chips
arranged in a broadly spectral order, but also showing light and dark values of each
hue. They argued that English usage could hardly influence the identification of
foci in a range of twenty genetically diverse languages; and in the case of Tzeltal,
where a group of forty informants was tested in their own region of southern
Mexico, no appreciable difference was found between the responses of monolin-
gual informants and those bilingual in Tzeltal and Spanish.°
Tzeltal, as a Stage IV language, has a single term, yas, covering green and blue,
although most of Berlin’s informants interpreted it as having its focus in the green
area; and all the twenty-six Mayan languages included in Berlin and Kay’s survey
also show this Stage IV characteristic of a common term for green and blue. It is worth
noting that a very prominent type of indigenous Mexican artistic practice is the
43 incrustation of objects with a mosaic of turquoise and jadeite, or the decoration of
earthenware with a turquoise glaze, probably in imitation of these precious materi-
als.’? The earthenware glaze might well be described by most English-speakers as
‘blue-green’, or, indeed, ‘turquoise’, and the coloured stones incorporate a range of
blue-green and green tones in the same object (and are of course made of the same
materials), so that a single term would certainly be appropriate to describe them. In
his wonderfully comprehensive Nahuatl encyclopaedia oflife in Mexico after the
Spanish Conquest, Fray Bernardino de Sahagun describes the dealer in turquoise,
green jade and blue obsidian under the heading of ‘green-stone-seller’ (chalchiuhna-
mac). Thus sixteenth-century Nahua usage comes close to modern Tzeltal usage,
even though it was perfectly possible in classical Nahuatl to find more than one
term even for ‘blue’.* According to the late sixteenth-century dictionary of Fray
Alfonso de Molina, which was consulted by Sahagun, classical Nahuatl had a
colour-vocabulary ofat least eleven terms, and would thus have been, like modern
Spanish, one of Berlin and Kay’s Stage VII languages.°
Berlin and Kay’s scheme of evolution depends upon the location of foci for
each basic colour-term; they found that the perimeters of colour-categories, where
they shaded into the areas of other colours, were far more fluid, and that even the
106
COLOR COLORADO
same informant might draw these perimeters in different places on different occa-
sions. They were thus unable to use category-boundaries or total ‘colour’ area as
indicative ofthe identification of‘basic’ colours.'° But in excluding these peripheral
judgments they were surely disallowing what is precisely our normal experience of
colour-usage. Disputes about colour hinge, more often than not, on the identifica-
tion of these liminal areas as belonging to one colour-category or another. We still
have many difficulties in assigning particular nuances to one or other category, and
attempt to resolve them by discussion.
In everyday life we are, I suggest, far more concerned with nuances than with the
saturated ‘primary’ colours whose identification has been relatively recent, and
whose importance has largely been confined to the specialized contexts of the
painters workshop and the physical or psychological laboratory.'' The search for
the ‘primaries’ or ‘basics’ of colour, whose linguistic dimension is encapsulated in
Berlin and Kay’s enterprise, has proved to be remarkably inconsequential, and it has
been freighted with a heavy burden of ideology which seems far from the concerns
of the ordinary user of colour-language. Richness and variety are far more charac-
teristic of colour-vocabularies than restriction, and in Meso-America and South
America this richness is amply embodied in the artefacts, especially the feather-
work,"* textiles and painting which are so characteristic of the periods before the
Spanish Conquest.
107
COLOR COLORADO
108
COLOR COLORADO
109
COLOR COLORADO
i ie)
COLOR COLORADO
American weaving, Bernabé Cobo dwelt on the fine and multicoloured cloths he
found there, woven ofyarns dyed
yellow, black and many other colours, and above all crimson or grana, which
makes them famous throughout many parts of the world, and their dyes can
compete with the best to be found...3!
Cobo is echoing Sahagin who, at least for the benefit of his Spanish readers,
included an enthusiastic endorsement of the international fame of this Mexican dye:
This grana is well-known inside and outside this country, and it is big business.
It has been exported as far away as China and Turkey, and it is prized and
respected throughout almost the whole world.The grana which is already refined
and made into cakes is called strong [recia] or fine grana.They sell it in the market-
place in cake-form, and in this form it is purchased by painters and dyers...3
So valuable were these coloured grains, the dried bodies of the female insect Dacty-
lopius coccus cacti, that they were used as tribute money by the Aztecs: we have
records of such tribute to Moctezuma from the cities of Oaxaca and Cuyalapa
(?Coyolapan).*3
The use of the Spanish term grana for cochineal arose from a confusion with the
very similar European and African insect, coccus illicus, which also yielded the most
important red dye of the Middle Ages and the Renaissance, kermes (Arabic: qirmiz),
not least in Spain, where it had long been harvested in Andalusia. Grana was simply
the Italian word for the grain-like bodies of the insects processed to make the dye.
Kermes was the colorant often used to dye the expensive woollen cloth known in
England as ‘scarlet’; and by the later Middle Ages, again notably in Spain, escarlata
had come to signify the red colour itself.34 Scarlet was enormously prestigious: the
thirteenth-century sumptuary laws of the kingdom of Castile and Leon restricted
its use to the king.* It was the natural successor to the Roman Imperial purple, and
had, indeed, by the end of the fifteenth century in Spain acquired the same
meaning as purpura.*° F
This prestige and these royal associations also characterized puca.When Francisco
Pizarro met the Inca Atahualpa at his residence near Cajamarca the Inca’s headdress
included his specifically royal tassel, ‘de lana muy fina de grana’.*” The second Inca
language, Aymara, had a particular phrase for ‘parading about the town dressed in
red’ (pucaq thaaratha), using in this instance the Quechua term puca for the dyed
cloth. Since it is a Spanish report of Pizarro’s audience with Atahualpa, and since all
our records of these linguistic usages are by Spanish-speaking lexicographers, it
may be that we are simply witnessing the attitudes of the Spanish conquerors,
whose colour-language was absorbed in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries
into indigenous usage.** But there is at least a hint that the traffic in ideas was not all
one way, in the case of the developing meaning of the Spanish term colorado.
Colorado, from the Classical Latin coloratus, had been used in medieval and
Renaissance Spanish sometimes to mean simply ‘well-coloured’, but usually in con-
nection with the pink colour of flesh (as in the English ‘to colour’, meaning ‘to
blush’).3° But during the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, especially in Spanish
Ill
COLOR COLORADO
America, the term came to replace bermejo as a general term for ‘red’. Molina’s
Nahuatl dictionary records the phrase chichiltic tlapalli (chilli-red dye) for color
bermejo 0 colorado, but also shows that tlapalli was used alone to refer to grana; and
gives the term flapalteoxiutli for the ruby, which Sahagun, in his chapter on precious
stones, explained as made up of ftlapalli (red) and teoxiutl (fine turquoise), since the
stone was simply a chilli-red turquoise.*? Sahagiin also glossed flapalli as ‘good’,
‘fine’, ‘precious’ and ‘wonderful’, so that it was, like colorado, a general term for
colour which had come to mean specifically ‘red’, and red of the finest and most
precious kind.‘ Although this usage was in line with far earlier developments in
Europe (cf. scarlet) there is no reason to assume that it originated there, since the
technology that lay behind it had long existed in Central and South America; and
the spread of the new connotations of colorado in this region suggests that the
Spanish was itself inflected by indigenous ideas.
Critics of Berlin and Kay’s treatment of colour-vocabularies have remarked that
their experimental methods overlooked the practical contexts in which these
vocabularies developed. An historically oriented study of colour-language can help
to establish the ways in which particular terms come to be used, and how usages
change. The Munsell colour-charts which Berlin and Kay employed in their
research present a highly specialized view of colour-relationships, hence the diffi-
culties many informants had in knowing how to use them. Their spectral sequence
has become generally familiar only relatively recently, and the apparently ‘natural’
49 spectrum of the rainbow has always presented problems to perception.*
I have suggested in this study that the notion of ‘basic’ colours has been far from
common among the Central and South American cultures, which have made an
exceptional use of a variety of colours in their artefacts, and have developed an
extensive vocabulary to describe this use. Most of the historical examples of colour-
usage available to us are inevitably from the highest strata of these traditional soci-
eties; extensive access to bright colour was the prerogative of the wealthy and the
well-born, and it was usually only in the context of public ceremonial that colour
impinged upon the population at large. Hence the hierarchy of colour as a system
of values, with red at the top. There could scarcely be a greater contrast with Berlin
and Kay’s informants in and around San Francisco, for whom the spectacle of the
polychrome consumer society has become one of the more commonplace, if more
attractive aspects of modern life.
Modern ethno-linguistics, with its emphasis on ‘basic’ colours, has tended to
look for, and to find, its allies in physiological optics and experimental psychology,
where the method of procedure has normally involved a small number of subjects
and a straightforward notion of stimulus and response. We have learned a good deal
from this direction about the mechanisms of colour-perception; but we have
learned far less about the preferences and interests which shape the uses of colour in
human societies. Students of the development of colour-language cannot afford to
ignore the artefacts which usually offer the most vivid evidence of a concern for
colour-discrimination; and among the Aztecs and the Inca who had been the
subject of this study, the highly developad capacity to discriminate was clearly
intrinsic to the formal inventiveness of their art.
a — se ee o
4 “int aa “i ii
Pg ee, ae ry
.
re
alt
7X
ae
ee ks
* le
i xe
ae CAS Na
Th YY an ay
}Ge .
= Aes =< BSS
; wh Wey sf aX sid hs
<a
hd a hud may Wy
i we
re:
NY A 6! 4 :
mK I, f Le "be
j mt “tne x
I
A ddoesta
dea" e ae
Tat
“i) a
wile ei
, = ~~ et
Pia Ne ZN.
| oot oe e r io 2) hod [DRG
4 my e iy és
; 3
pa ar a Ybor:
ff ei
7
:
Florence Cathedral (right). rs
: .
-~ is
Some of da Pisa’s . i: A aa
recommendations for
colour-composition (such e: fon
9
We }
as yellow capitals and pink
ih d
columns) appear to have aes
i ¥,) %.-
ene tp @ # Bi :
7
; > 2 Das a9mm peed| gre
men creeon"5 eae PaO? Star
*eaper
© vamea
Colour-terms and colour-products
The incrusted turquoise and jadeite of this Pre-Columbian Mixtec mask (left) will most likely be described as
‘blue-green’ by English-speakers, but in the various Pre-Columbian languages it could only have been ‘green’, for
green and blue were not discriminated. In Basic Color Terms Berlin and Kay categorize as at Stage IV of development
such languages in which green and blue are denoted by a single term. (43)
The figured textiles of Pre-Columbian America reveal colour-designing at its most complex and sophisticated. Woven
designs such as this tapestry Inca tunic (above), rhythmical with irregularly repeating motifs, offer the most compelling
evidence of colour-discrimination at a given period in a particular culture. (44)
Colour as substance, colour as light
Earth (c. 1570) by Giuseppe Arcimboldo (left) is less playful than it seems. The ancient doctrine ofthe four elements
comprising substance, earth, air, fire and water — and the colour proper to each — were subjects much debated in the
scientific circles of Rudolph II’s Prague, to which the artist belonged. (45)
Artists were fascinated by Newton’s clear demonstration that light was the only begetter of colour, and his division
of the spectrum into seven. Claude Boutet’s painter’s circle of 1708 (above) was probably the first to be based on
Newton’s (58). But unable to match spectral red with pigment, Boutet substitutes two reds — fire-red
and crimson - omitting one of Newton’s two blues. To compound confusion, the colourist has evidently misread
two ofthe labels, ‘oranger and ‘violet’. (46)
Nor owns itfelf a Cheat, tlhItexpires «
“Ts little Joys go out by- One,’ and-One ;sid fai 1
And leave poor Man, at length, in perfe& Night; —
Night darker, than. what, ew, involves the Pole.
In his poignant study of visual deprivation, The Blind Girl of 1856, Millais’s
exact rendering of
the landscape-setting did not extend to the secondary rainbow, where he
failed to notice the reversal
of the spectral colours until the mistake was pointed out to him by a friend.
Imperceptible transitions
of hue make the bow a particularly subjective scale of colour. (49)
8 - The Fool’s Paradise
...that Triangular Glass call’d the fool’s Paradise, though fit for the wits of
wiser men, which representeth so lively Red, Blew and Green, that no colours
can compare with them...
(Christopher Merrett, 1662!)
if AN ESSAY OF 1983 THE DOYEN OF modern students of medieval and Renaissance
optics, David Lindberg, argued that ‘there was much in sixteenth-century optics
that was new, but nothing that was revolutionary’.* This was not a surprising
conclusion given that Lindberg dealt with only two sixteenth-century writers,
Francesco Maurolico and Giovanni Battista della Porta, and that his understanding
of the history of optics was essentially confined to its geometrical branch, which
traces a line from Euclid, through Robert Grosseteste and Theodoric of Freiberg to
Descartes and Newton in the seventeenth century. But there are of course several
histories of optics: one of them involves the medieval and Renaissance metaphysics
of light,’ and another, which I shall call ‘perceptualist’, runs from Aristotle through
Alhazen and Witelo to Leonardo da Vinci and on to Chevreul in the nineteenth
century (Chapter 15) and takes in Newton on the way. It is this ‘perceptualist’
history which is the subject of the present chapter.
These histories are not, of course, mutually exclusive; it is rather a question of
emphasis; but I think it has been generally understood that the geometrical optics
of the seventeenth century presented a quite new evaluation of the relationship of
light to colour: where for Aristotle light was the activator of colour, and where for
most medieval thinkers it was the vehicle of colour, for many scholars in the seven-
teenth century, notably Descartes and Newton, it came to be identified with colour
itself. Colour was inherent in light, and light was the efficient cause of colour in all
its manifestations, for colour was the inevitable consequence of the variable refrac-
tion of light. And so, by and large, it has remained. The ‘perceptualist’ account, on
the other hand, is concerned, not with the causes of colour, but with its effects, with
the way in which a radiant stimulation of the human visual system becomes identi-
fied as colour at all. In this account, which developed essentially within a tradition
of medical research, the experimentation of the sixteenth century had indeed a
major role to play.
The history of the rainbow, characterized in the classic study by Carl Boyer as
‘from myth to mathematics’, shows how a phenomenon which was traditionally
seen as an exemplar of the nature and meaning of colour, became from the seven-
teenth century a demonstration of the nature of light, to which the perceptual
characteristics of colour were largely irrelevant.t Seeing the rainbow continued 49
[21
THE FOOL’S PARADISE
to be a thoroughly uncertain business, since the number and order of the colours
was far from easy to ascertain, and this was true not only of the celestial bow, but
also of the terrestrial spectrum, created in the laboratory precisely for the purposes
of study.
i)
THE FOOL’S PARADISE
less dense to a denser medium shortens the distance travelled, and thus compensates
for its slower velocity in that denser medium)."°
Given that Grosseteste had proposed that sight and colour offered a paradigm of
the corporeal and incorporeal elements in the Holy Trinity, and that his follower
Bacon had urged the important theological significance of numerology, and had
indeed argued that the equilateral triangle gave insights into the nature of the
Trinity itself,"° we might well have expected that Witelo’s emphasis on the three
active faces of his crystal would have led, by the power of symbolizing as well as by
the principle of simplicity, to the development of the modern triangular prism.
Certainly, in the fourteenth century the notion of the three colours of the Trinity
was articulated very forcefully in a popular French devotional poem, Guillaume de
Digulleville’s Pilgrimage of the Soul (c.1355).But so far from appealing to the rainbow,
with all its traditional connotations of the Covenant between God and man, the
bridge between Heaven and Earth, Digulleville exemplified his triad of colours in
the unity of a single phenomenon, colour-change: the unchanging gold of the
Father, the scarlet (vermeil) blood of the Son and the comforting green of the Holy
Spirit, in the colours of the peacock and the shot-silk cloth which was also com-
monly associated with the colours of the peacock’s feathers.'7
Bacon, in his lengthy discussion of the crucial usefulness of physics and mathe-
matics in the Opus Maius, had adduced the equilateral triangle as a perfect image of
the Trinity precisely because it was a figure which could be found nowhere else in
nature. And of course, unlike the lense, whose early development was based on an
analogy with the crystalline lense of the eye, the triangular prism is in no way a
natural shape.'* Perhaps in the thirteenth century the association of the Trinity
with the triangle, a Manichean notion which had been roundly condemned by
St Augustine, was still too theologically suspect; it only became less so in the early
Renaissance, when the triangle appeared increasingly as the form of the halo of
God.This suspicion was in spite of the growing popularity in the later Middle Ages
ofthe triangular devotional image ofthe Trinity known as the Scutum Fidei (Shield
of Faith), which seems to have been devised by Grosseteste himself."
The triangular prism was thus an astonishing development: a purpose-built tool
for which there were no precedents either in nature or in the Ancient world. The
philosophical and theological contexts would have led us to expect its appearance
no later than the fourteenth century, but there seems to be no evidence for it before
the middle ofthe sixteenth.
cultivated in Renaissance Italy, where his works were studied and published at
Bologna in the 1490s.** Theodoric of Freiberg’s work was less known, although it
was summarized by Jodocus Trutfetter in his Philosophie Naturalis Summa, printed
at Erfurt in 1517. Trutfetter’s version is especially interesting, not least because it
gives some precocious attention to the shifting Latin vocabulary of the rainbow-
colours; and it also offers perhaps the earliest published analysis of the use of tonal
contrast by painters in order to create the effect of space.** But in the present
context what is most striking is Trutfetter’s description of the optical experiments
he conducted, using a darkened room with a single hole in the shutter to allow the
sun’s rays (radii solares) to enter and create colours by the interposition of various
optical devices. Trutfetter mentions a mirror, a cristallo longa ac angulosa, and also
the glass rod cited by Seneca in the first century AD (Natural Questions, I, vi, 7). He
also lists the hexagonal stone called iris.** But he does not refer to the triangular
prism; nor is it mentioned in the very popular sixteenth-century encylopaedia, the
Margarita Philosophica of the German Carthusian monk Gregor Reisch, which was
published in a dozen editions, including Italian translations, between 1503 and
1600, although Reisch, too, mentions the hexagonal stone.”5
It does not seem to be before the middle of the sixteenth century, and in Italy,
that triangular prisms came to be part of the equipment of optical experiment.
The Milanese physician and philosopher Gerolamo Cardano seems to be the first
to mention the ‘triangular crystal, or prism’ in his scientific encyclopaedia De
125
THE FOOL’S PARADISE
Subtilitate, first published in 1550; and by the time of Giovanni Battista della Porta’s
wn
De Refractione of 1593, which may be the first text to illustrate this triangular form,
it seems to have become the standard shape.”°
The triangular prism was, however, not yet a shape widely known and used in
optical experiments. Perhaps the most substantial sixteenth-century discussion of
the prism and its uses occurs in the fourth book of Opticae Libri Quattuor, the
product of a collaboration between the French philosopher Pierre de la Ramée,
who had a strong interest in empiricism, and his German pupil Friedrich Reisner
(Risner) during the 1560s, although their work was not published until 1606.*’ Ina
chapter on the elemental structure of the rainbow Ramée and Reisner reviewed the
instruments used in creating artificial spectra, including the natural hexagonal
crystal which, according to Pliny, could not be matched by art. Sometimes its shape
was that of a truncated pyramid, sometimes that of aprism with six lateral faces and
two bases. Witelo’s prism, they argued, should be understood as a hexahedral paral-
lelepiped; and they made the especially striking observation that the pentahedral
prism (i.e. the new triangular form, with three sides and two bases) was the wonder
of France and Italy (quaquam et prisma pentaedrum tota Italia Galliaque his etiam mirac-
ulis celebratur).
Yet they were only concerned to examine the various properties of
the traditional hexagonal prism ofcrystal or glass.
Ramée and Reisner, following Witelo, argued that the rainbow-colours, which
they had already accepted as the Aristotelian puniceus, viridis and purpureus, were
three because the incident light underwent a triple refraction from the three upper
surfaces to the three lower. They described the effect of masking off first one, then
two faces of the prism, adducing Witelo’s experiment where two sides were covered
with wax and sunlight was admitted into a darkened room through a small hole.
The spectrum cast in this case was large (maxima) and very beautiful, with especially
bright colours as a result of concentrating all the refractions into one. They also
described the colour-generating properties of clear gemstones and Seneca’s glass
wands; but they gave no discussion at all to the characteristics of the new triangular
prism.**
THE FOOL’S PARADISE
Scarmiglioni on colour
Around 1600 the triangular prism was being used in experiments by the English
mathematician Thomas Harriot and by an Italian physician working in Vienna,
S4
Guido Antonio Scarmiglioni, whose book, De Coloribus, published at Marburg in
1601, offers a very useful benchmark for the perceptual approach to colour at the
end ofthe sixteenth century — not because it is particularly original, but because it
presents a remarkably comprehensive overview of colour-problems in optics, in
psychology, in language and in art. Scarmiglioni was well read in ancient, medieval
and modern authors on colour, and he also seems to have conducted some experi-
ments himself. Of his life we know nothing but what he tells us in his short book,
which is apparently his only published work. But as a synthesizer, he is worth giving
more attention than history has accorded him so far.
Scarmiglioni was born at Foligno in Umbria and educated there, possibly at the
still-mysterious Accademia Medica, set up around the middle of the sixteenth
century and with some claim to being the first scientific academy.”? Scarmiglioni
related how the Archbishop of Naples, Prince Annibale di Capua, whom he served
as personal physician, sent him on a ‘serious mission’ to the Emperor Rudolph II.
While he was in Vienna he was invited by the Chancellor of the Archigymnasium
in Prague, Melchior Khlesl, who was Chancellor of the Jesuit College, the Clementi-
num, after 1579, to move to Prague to teach and practise medicine, which, as
Scarmiglioni writes in 1601, he had done ever since. By that time he was also
Professor of Theoretical Medicine in Prague and Vienna.*° The American National
Union Catalog tells us that he died in 1620. Otherwise he seems to be almost
entirely unknown to history.*!
It was the Prague lectures that Scarmiglion1’s pupils persuaded him to publish in
1601, and they are a very remarkable document. His wide reading 1s freely acknowl-
edged, but he was very conscious of his own originality, and many of his chapters,
after reviewing the opinions of others, advance his own contributions to the debate.
In some cases these contributions appear to be based on Scarmiglion1’s visual expe-
rience, for example of the mixing-practices of painters and dyers, of the spectrum
cast on the floor by light passing through the edge of a window-pane, or of the
colour of German beer.?? In this he was perhaps most clearly in the tradition of
Leonardo, but, unlike Leonardo, he was never really concerned with the problems
of geometrical optics, and although he was familiar with a number of scholastic
writers, including Albertus Magnus, he never cited the medieval perspectivists
who were.
One area in which Scarmiglioni went beyond the medieval optical tradition
was in his treatment of ‘real’ and ‘apparent’ colours.The rainbow had been for the
Middle Ages and the Renaissance a prime example of ‘apparent’ colours: those
colours whose existence was dependent on the position of the spectator viewing
them, and opposed to the ‘real’ colours inherent in objects themselves. These ‘real’
colours subsisted in matter by virtue of its being a mixture of the four elements,
earth, air, fire and water, and the four related temperaments, hot and cold, wet
and dry. This Aristotelian doctrine of the temperaments was still very active in
127
THE FOOL’S PARADISE
were between the ‘light’ (Jucidi) colours, as in the spectrum, and the ‘obscure’, as in
matter.** All this looks remarkably familiar from a seventeenth-century point of
view, but Scarmiglioni had reached his conclusions, not by the mechanical inter-
pretation of refraction, but largely, as he said, through quotidiana experientia, everyday
experience.
Scarmiglioni was, nevertheless, far from indifferent to the problems of colour and
refraction. We saw his reference to the ‘triangular crystal’ in the passage on apparent
colours quoted above, and there are other chapters in his book where he dealt with
the creation ofspectral colours, for example the weak spectrum cast by the edge of
the window-pane, and that produced by the triangular prism itself. Like so many
of his contemporaries, Scarmiglioni seems to have used the prism as a lense to
examine the prismatic fringes between the light and dark areas of surfaces. He was
clearly impressed by the bright cyan blue at the junction of light and dark, which he
called hyacinthinus, and by the appearance of red next to the dark, as light was
replaced by dark, so that, like his immediate source, Filippo Mocenigo, who was
also an experimenter with the triangular prism, he took the unconventional view
that, in a tonal scale of hues, red is closer to black than is blue.*°
Like Mocenigo too, Scarmiglioni thought that the appearance of colours
depended on the thickness of the prism; and Mocenigo speaks of reversing the
instrument, so that the red and the blue change places, while green remains con-
stant between them.*’ This was an interpretation close to that of Albertus Magnus,
and depended on the still very active notion that colours were the product of
obscuring or modifying light, in this case, by the glass of the prism. The manipula-
tion of the triangular instrument became a key procedure in seventeenth-century
optics, notably in Descartes, Boyle and Newton, whose observations, oncourse, $3
were far more precise and whose conclusions far more radical than any in the
sixteenth century.
129
THE FOOL’S PARADISE
Giovanni Battista della Porta, like Scarmiglioni, referred both to glass and crystal
triangular prisms, although Cardano at the middle of the century had only men-
tioned crystal. It might well have been thought that the rapidly developing Italian
glass-industry of the Renaissance supplied one of the necessary conditions for the
development of the prism as an optical instrument. But crystal prisms, cut from
the larger hexagonal stones, seem to have been in use at least until the end of
the sixteenth century: the English mathematician Thomas Harriot, who did very
significant but unpublished work on refraction, mentions a badly-ground crystal
prism lent by an acquaintance in a note of around 1610.** Perhaps the problems of
the precision-cutting, grinding and polishing of crystal were too great, although
ever since the late thirteenth century Venetian rock-crystal workers had been
making spectacle lenses, which their guild allowed glassmakers to produce from
1301.*? Venetian crystal-glass was internatjonally famous for its purity and trans-
parency by the early sixteenth century, and it is perhaps no coincidence that it is in
an account of using the prism by the Venetian Mocenigo, Archbishop of Nicosia,
published in 1581 and one of Scarmiglioni’s major sources, that, so far as I have been
able to discover, the term ‘vitrum triangulare’ first occurs.*°
As Albertus Magnus andJodocus Trutfetter had noticed, glass rods had been used
by the Romans to generate rainbow-colours, and the sixteenth-century Sienese
technologist Vannoccio Biringuccio already marvelled at the glass of Murano as,
‘most clear and transparent like the proper natural crystal...so that it seems to me
that all other metals must yield to it in beauty’.*' That Scarmiglioni refers to glass
prisms may also reflect the great development of Bohemuan glass in his day under
the specific sponsorship of Rudolph II, so that it too reached new levels ofpurity.°?
However, no glass of this period was of optical quality in the modern sense, and as
late as the end of the following century Newton and his contemporaries were
complaining that the available prisms were optically very imperfect.°} Nevertheless,
the use of glass in the long run solved the problem of size and expense, and made
these triangular glass prisms a very common commodity in the seventeenth and
eighteenth centuries.
130
THE FOOL’S PARADISE
oO
S pene bot fe
B
t+ 1 ife: fe . Wee
Thomas Harriot’s prism-diagram of around 1610. His note that ‘Mr Cope’s Cristall’ was concave underlines
the difficulty of cutting and grinding large quartz prisms at the time. Harriot may have a claim to being the
first scientist to measure the width of the spectral colour-bands. (54)
O31
THE FOOL’S PARADISE
of this sort are those made and publicized by Goethe about 1790, observations
which led him to refute Newton’s theory that colours are a function ofthe variable
refrangibility of rays of light.** But just as these indoor experiments prevailed, in
Goethe’s case, over his observation of the rainbow outdoors, so experiments with
the prism before Newton brought little clarity to the question of the number and
nature of the spectral colours.
The thirteenth-century German encyclopaedist Arnoldus Saxo identified four
colours, rubeo, flava, viridi ac citrino, in the spectrum projected by the iris;°° Albertus
Magnus, although he was familiar with Arnoldus’s work, opted for the Aristotelian
triad of red, green, and that confusing colour caeruleus, which sometimes meant blue
and sometimes yellow, although here it clearly means the latter.*7 Theodoric argued
for four colours in the rainbow and the hexagonal prism, specifically including the
yellow which Aristotle had regarded as a mixture of red and green, but which
Theodoric and della Porta after him insisted was a principal colour. Yet in his pris-
matic experiments he mentions only red and blue.** Cardano in the sixteenth
century saw four or five colours; Mocenigo identified three, although he also
admitted that there might be others in between; and Scarmiglioni himself also
seems to have been reluctant to identify the precise character and number of the
colours, although he claimed that they were plain enough to see.*? Harriot calcu-
lated the angles of refraction of five colours,” but della Porta’s prismatic experi-
ments revealed only three colours to him: red, yellow and blue (rubeus, flavus,
caeruleus /halurgus).°' Even Newton was to divide his visible spectrum into as many
as eleven colours and as few as five, before finally settling on the seven, which, as we
shall see in the next chapter, he was to adopt for the largely metaphorical reason
60 that he was pursuing the analogy with the notes of the diatonic scale.” It is difficult
49 to resist the conclusion that, as in the case of the rainbow at large, the perception of
the prismatic spectrum was very much in the shadow ofpreconceptions.
Whatever the perceptual difficulties in identifying the colours in a prismatic
spectrum, the origins of the triangular prism would still be of compelling interest
even if it had been no more than the toy (the popular creator of the multicoloured
‘fool’s Paradise’) which provided Descartes and Newton with their proofs of the
quantitative nature of colour. The elegant simplicity of their arguments was made
possible partly by the elegance ofthis simplest of tools.At some time during the two
centuries between Theodoric of Freiberg and Gerolamo Cardano, some perspec-
tivist must have decided to reduce the hexagon ofthe quartz crystal to a triangular
form. It may well have been that a large hexagonal crystal was first sawn in half and
polished; but this would still leave a good way to go before the adoption of the
equilateral triangle which we see in the sixteenth- and early seventeenth-century
illustrations.”
The balance of evidence suggests that this reduction took place during the
early sixteenth century; but it is unlikely to have been achieved by Cardano him-
self, since, although he was proud of a number of his efforts to provide simpler
explanations of the structures of nature, he included no allusions to optics in his
autobiography, De Vita Propria Liber, where he listed his various and notable
achievements.”
THE FOOL’S PARADISE
gernanaanenteamtiaingece's
peener
Nore
The diagram ofSir IsaacNewton’s crucial experiment, 1666-72. A ray oflight is divided into its
constituent colours by the first prism, and the resulting bundle of coloured rays is reconstituted into
white light by a second. (55)
Newton's experimentum crucis, developed between 1666 and 1672, in which two
prisms were arranged so that the colours of the spectrum formed by the first were $5
shown to be unmodified by the second, and were thus each the product ofa single
refraction,® depended upon the complete symmetry and reversibility of the trian-
gular prism, noticed but not interpreted by Mocenigo about 1580. Seldom can so
simple a device have been so freighted with important consequences, but seldom,
too, can it have developed so slowly as did the prism, from its theoretical grounding
in the thirteenth century to its practical realization in the fifteenth and sixteenth
centuries, and its effective use in the seventeenth.
133
9 - Newton and Painting
134
NEWTON AND PAINTING
figure]: whereas colouring has yet hardly any well-known rules, and since the
studies made have differed according to the different subjects they treated, no
very precise body ofrules has yet been established.°
A French didactic print of 1677/83, after a design by the influential Roman teacher 56
Carlo Maratta, sums up this situation: students busy themselves with the study of
drawing, perspective, anatomy, and above all, ancient sculpture, while a palette and
brushes stand idly by.’ Since the French Academy was the mother of all the many
art academies founded during the eighteenth century, and the large body of theo-
retical writing it engendered was the model for most subsequent theory, these
colouristic concerns carry a good deal of weight.
Doctrines of mixture
It may at first sight seem surprising that Newton’s theory had any part to play in
these developments, for it was chiefly concerned with the causes of colours, and
only marginally with those subjective effects which were the central concern of
painters. This is especially so in the case of the notion of primary colours, which
135
NEWTON AND PAINTING
had been clarified over the previous half-century or so through the experience of
mixing paints. Robert Boyle, in a treatise of 1664 which stimulated Newton to
make some ofhis earliest colour-experiments, claimed that
much of the Mechanical use of Colours among Painters and Dyers, doth
depend upon the Knowledge of what Colours may be produc’d by the Mixtures
of Pigments so and so Colour’d. And.. .’tis of advantage to the contemplative
Naturalist, to know how many and which Colours are Primitive. ..and Simple,
because it both eases his labour by confining his most solicitous Enquiry to a
small Number of Colours upon which the rest depend, and assists him to
judge ofthe nature of particular compounded Colours, by showing him from
the Mixture what more Simple ones, and of what Proportions of them to one
another, the particular Colour to be consider’d does result.®
Boyle had already stated that these few ‘primitive’ or ‘simple’ colours ofthe painter
were black, white, red, yellow and blue.
But Newton had thrown this neat symmetrical scheme of simple colours into
confusion in his first paper of 1672 by showing that there were as many ‘simple’ (or
‘primary’, ‘primitive’ ,“‘uncompounded ’,‘original’, or ‘homogeneal’) colours as there
were refrangible rays of light,’ and that these same colours (for example green, and
even yellow) might occur in both a simple and a compounded form. Newton's
leading opponent on this occasion, Robert Hooke, who had himself developed a
radically reductive theory of only two primary colours, understandably sought to
apply Ockham’s Razor;'° and during the eighteenth century Newton’s number of
primaries (which was generally and erroneously thought to be seven) continued to
present something of an obstacle to students with painterly connections. And yet
the circular diagram of colour-mixtures which Newton introduced in the Opticks
of 1704 gave promise that a white might indeed be compounded from two or three
of the colours lying opposite each other, which could thus be regarded as primary
by themselves.'' Newton claimed in the text to this figure that he was never able to
mix more than a ‘faint anonymous Colour’ by means of the proportions indicated;
but in his experiments with the mixture of coloured powders (I, ii, prop. v, theor. iv,
exper.15), he had succeeded in making a‘mouse-colour’ (his surrogate for white in
SS =
caesar COTTA ~
a
————S
——=——
—<——<——
Mi
He
.
fi ‘
kHi
‘i\\ \\Y
\\S
Cc
Colour-circle from Moses Harris, The Natural System of Colours, c. 1776. Harris’s is probably the first
completely symmetrical circle of primary and secondary colours, and it also suggests the progressive
darkening of each hue to black at the centre. (59)
pigment-mixtures) with only two: one part red lead and five parts copper-green,
which he concluded, to save his theory, must themselves be compounds of other
colours.
This circular diagram became the model for many colour-systems in the eigh-
teenth and nineteenth century, from the supplement to the Tiaité de la Peinture en
Mignature, attributed to Claude Boutet, in The Hague edition of 1708, where the
seven-colour division (with two reds) seems clearly to reflect the Newtonian
arrangement of four years earlier, to the first completely symmetrical and comple-
mentary colour-system of Moses Harris, The Natural System of Colours, published
about 1776. Newton’s scheme provided, too, the starting-point for the first attempt
to apply the Newtonian system to the practical problems of colour-mixture, pub-
lished by the Cambridge mathematician Brook Taylor in the second edition of
se
NEWTON AND PAINTING
his treatise New Principles of Linear Perspective in 1719. Taylor amplified Newton's
conception of mixture to emphasize the co-ordinate functions of hue, value and
saturation in each colour; and he observed that white ‘breaks’ (1.e. desaturates)
colours far more than black, hence the prime importance of the lightest pigments,
for ‘it is easier to make clean dark tints with light Colours and Black, than to make
the bright light ones with dark Colours and White’. Taylor also noted that because of
the impure nature of pigments, mixtures could not always be accurately predicted:
and although he seems to have been an amateur painter himself, he concluded,
‘these Properties ofparticular Materials I leave to be consider’d by the Practitioners
in this Art’.'*
138
NEWTON AND PAINTING
this expedient in order to make the process faster, and hence cheaper.
The question
of three or four plates became a matter of controversy after his death in 1741,
when a former pupil, Jacques Gautier d’Agoty, was anxious to protect his own
patent for this four-colour process, and disputed the claims of Le Blon’s workshop
that the master had ever used more than three. The debate was long and tedious, but
It is of some interest to us because Gautier d’Agoty sought to bolster his method
with a vigorously argued anti-Newtonian theory of colour, which was essentially a
revival of the traditional Aristotelian view that all hues are generated by the interac-
tion of black and white, or light and darkness.'8
The apologists for Le Blon in this exchange argued that their master never spoke
of his fourth plate precisely because he used it in spite of himself, and felt that it
would dishonour the system.'? If we cannot establish the formative effect of theory
on the practice of these print-makers, it was certainly in the forefront of their public
relations. Le Blon’s appeal to Newton was not itself essential to his three-colour
system, for that system had already been proposed by Boutet in his treatise of 1708,
where Le Blon, as a miniature-painter himself, may well have found it. Perhaps
what had really attracted him to Newton’s theory of colours was the promise it pre-
-sented of a quantifiable theory of colour-harmony. The Venetian writer Antonio
Conti, to whom we owe the first record of Le Blon’s ideas, reported that he was
indeed preoccupied with harnionic proportions:
...the Newtonian theory of colours has given many [painters] the opportu-
nity of determining their compositions by the mechanical rule of the centres
of gravity [a concept deriving from Newton’s circular mixture-diagram].That 58
German painter who prints pictures [Le Blon] derived his secret from this
source...I met [him] at The Hague, and he assured me that following Newton’s
principles of the immutability and unequal refrangibility and reflexibility of
the rays of light, he had established the degrees of strength and weakness
which colours required to be harmonized...*°
039
NEWTON AND PAINTING
...as the harmony and discord of sounds proceeded from the proportions of
the aereal vibrations, so may the harmony of some colours, as of golden and
blue, and the discord of others, as of red and blue, proceed from the propor-
tions of the aethereal. And possibly colour may be distinguished into its
principal degrees, red, orange, yellow, green, blue, indigo and deep violet, on
the same ground that sound within an eighth is graduated into tones.
For,some years past, the prismatic colours being in a well darkened room cast
perpendicularly upon a paper two and twenty foot distant from the prism, I
desired a friend to draw with a pencil lines across the image, or pillar ofcolours,
where every one of the seven aforenamed colours was most full and brisk, and
also where he judged the truest confines of them to be, whilst I held the paper
so, that the said image might fall within a certain compass marked on it. And
this I did, partly because my own eyes are not very critical in distinguishing
colours, partly because another, to whom I had not communicated my thoughts
about this matter, could have nothing but his eyes to determine his fancy in
making those marks. This observation we repeated divers times, both in the
same and divers ways, to see how the marks on several papers would agree; and
comparing the observations, though the just confines of the colours are hard to
be assigned, because they pass into one another by insensible gradation; yet the
differences of the observations were but little, especially towards the red end..."
It seems clear that, in spite of Newton’s efforts to make the experiment ‘objective’,
the isolation of seven prismatic colours was itself the result of the musical analogy, in
which he had been interested for some years.** The conception of the especially
harmonious character of acombination of gold and blue which (shifted to indigo
in the Opticks, as purple was renamed violet), and the discord of red and blue, have
no justification other than their relative places in Newton’s scale.
140
NEWTON AND PAINTING
I41
NEWTON AND PAINTING
A rather more durable theory of the harmony of colours, current among painters,
was based on the idea of complementary colours, and this too derives from
Newton. In his experiments on the colours ofthin plates Newton had long recog-
nized that certain colours were ‘opposite’ or ‘contrary’,** and the diagram in his
61 classic exposition of what came to be known as ‘Newton’s Rings’ in the Opticks
became the starting-point for the study of complementarity in the latter half of the
century.”? The experiment with the mixing of red and green powders (pp. 136-7)
could also be interpreted in terms of the complementarity of these colours. By
about 1800, both scientists and painters?° had come to believe that the simplest form
of colour-harmony was in the juxtaposition of complementaries. This view
became canonized for the nineteenth century in Chevreul’s On the Law of Simulta-
neous Contrast of Colours (1839),and through him, became a decisive stimulus to the
developing painterly methods of Seurat, for whom, too, harmony was implicit in
contrast (see Chapter 16).3' It is appropriate that what is perhaps the only series of
paintings to be based directly on Newtonian ideas about colour, Frantisek Kupka’s
47 Discs ofNewton of 1912, should look back to these influential experiments.**
I have tried to show that during the late seventeenth and eighteenth centuries
the scientific and painterly students of colour, under the dominant influence of
Newton, shared several common interests, and were each prepared to draw on the
experience of the other. These interests were not yet considered to be antithetical,
Sir Isaac Newton, Colours of Thin Plates (Newton’s Rings), from the Opticks, 1704. “Newton’s Rings’ are
the concentric circles of colour spreading out from the point of maximum pressure when two thin
transparent plates (or here, a convex lense and a plane glass surface) are pressed together. They gave
the first clear demonstration of complementarity in colours — although this was not something that
interested Newton himself. Black appears at the centre by reflected light, white by transmitted light,
red opposite blue or green, violet opposite yellow, and so on. (61)
142
NEWTON AND PAINTING
although by the middle of the eighteenth century some writers, like Castel, and
Gautier d’Agoty who owed a good deal to him, sought to drive a wedge between
the quantitative study ofthe colours of light and the qualitative study of colorants.
Both controversialists were much used by Goethe.*? It was not until the close of the
century that Wiinsch in Germany and Young in England began to bring clarity to
the notions of additive and subtractive mixtures, and not for another half-century
again that these ideas became widely accepted.As late as Mondrian in the 1920s the
whole universe of colour could be symbolized in terms ofthe subtractive primaries,
red, yellow and blue.
The fascinating question of the harmony ofcolours also led Newton to propose
some far-reaching, but ultimately unsuccessful hypotheses about the relationship of
colours to musical sounds; but it was a notion of complementarity, latent 1f undeve-
loped in his work, that came to have the greatest resonance in the history of painting.
Bale
RedMole
card ILYH
Jaj0V4
fu
143
10 - Blake’s Newton
Adapting Michelangelo
MONG THE EARLIEST DOCUMENTS OF William Blake’s activity as a graphic artist
is a series of copies in pen and wash from Adamo Ghisi’s engravings after
Michelangelo, now in the British Museum.' These copies already show a character-
istic freedom in handling their source: just as the engraving Joseph of Aramathea
(1773) was adapted by Blake from the Centurion in Michelangelo’s Crucifixion of
St Peter in the Cappella Paolina, so Blake’s group of Matthan from the Sistine
lunettes (LB6r) transposes the titular great-grandfather of Jesus into a young
mother, and Aminadab (LB7v ) has become, in a pencil caption possibly contempo-
rary with the copy, The Reposing Tiaveller.* But twenty years later Blake seems to have
become far more concerned with Michelangelo’s own iconography of the Sistine
63 ceiling, and in adapting the figure of Abias (LB6v), long recognized as the prototype
64 for the posture of Newton in the colour-print of 1795,' he extended visually the
connotations of this symbol of oppressive rationalism by his borrowing.
Blake had been in touch with the painter Henry Fuseli since the late 1780s, and it
was from Fuseli that he may have understood the programme of Michelangelo’s
great cycle.“The subject’, as Fuseli put it in a later lecture,‘is theocracy, or the empire
of religion...the progress, and the final dispensation of Providence...the relation
of the race to its Founder.* From Fuseli, too, Blake may have learned the role of
Abias (= Abijah) in the genealogy of Christ, a role of absolute submission to the
Divine Authority. In Il Chronicles 13 Abias upholds Judaic orthodoxy against the
rebellion of Jeroboam, which he put down with great slaughter.» He would thus
serve in Blake’s eyes as a fitting model for Newton, who was also associated in his
imagination with the tyrannical figure of the Ancient ofDays.
Fuseli was certainly familiar with the details of the Sistine lunettes in the
66 sixteenth-century engravings of Giorgio Ghisi, which had served as models for his
65 Shakespearean fantasies;° and Ghisi’s arrangement may also have affected Blake, for
it brought the Ancestors into direct visual relationship with the Prophets and Sibyls
between them. Abias appears here as one of the supporters of the Persian Sibyl,
whose shadowed and obviously short-sighted features are buried in a book.? The
mystical darkness she engenders has cast both her flanking Ancestors into postures
of sleep, one of which postures Blake has adapted to his Newton, who sits similarly
shrouded in darkness. While it seems improbable that he is seated on the sea-
bed (i.e. beneath the waters of materialism) as has been suggested,’ the encircling
darkness may be related to the gloomy bottom of the Cave of the Neo-Platonic
144
BLAKE’S NEWTON
Henry Fuseli, Twelfth Night, 1777, a design for a proposed Giorgio Ghisi, The Persian Sibyl, after Michelangelo.
chapel to Shakespeare based on Michelangelo’s Sistine Ghisi’s illustration-format separated the left and right
Chapel lunettes, known to Fuseli via Giorgio Ghisi’s figures of each lunette, so allowing Blake to associate the
engravings (66). It was probably Fuseli who instructed sleeping Abias-figure, left, with the defective vision of
Blake on Michelangelo’s programme. (65) the Sibyl, centre. (66)
material world, which had recently been expounded by the leading English Platonist
of the period, Thomas Taylor, in his translation of The Hymns of Orpheus;? and perhaps
Blake, in his conception of Newton’s lichen-covered seat, was thinking, too, of the
‘oozy rock, inwrapped with the weeds of death’, which in his own prophetic book
Vala (1795-1804) supported the Eternal Man, who ‘sleeps in the earth’."°
Newton in Blake’s print is wide-eyed and active, but his posture and his setting
are, on our showing, those of somnolence: he seems the visual embodiment of
Blake’s prayer in the verse-letter to his patron Thomas Butts of 1802 (p.826):
... May God us keep
From Single vision & Newton’ sleep.
146
BLAKE S NEWTON
dp Lug 2.
Cc
147
BLAKE S NEWTON
In his 1802 letter to Butts (p.860) Blake had already referred to the spiritual idea
of double vision:
Here the idea is that the perception of the material world must be complemented
by the visionary’s perception ofa second world. On a purely material level, Priestley
was also occupied by the contrast between single and binocular vision, which a
number of eighteenth-century ophthamologists had brought on to the optical
agenda. He quoted the Cambridge philosopher Robert Smith’s view that “Objects
seen with both eyes appear more vivid, and stronger, than they do to a single eye’;
and he gave an anatomical explanation of why this should be so which showed that
Newton’s account ofthe matter had now been superseded:
It was the opinion of Sir Isaac Newton and others, that objects appear single
because the two optic nerves unite before they reach the brain. But Dr
[William] Porterfield shows, from the observations of several anatomists, that
the optic nerves do not mix, or confound their substance, being only united
by a close cohesion; and objects have appeared single where the optic nerves
were found to be disjoined... Originally, every object making two pictures,
one in each eye, is imagined to be double; but by degrees, we find that when
two corresponding parts of the retina are impressed, the object is but one; but
if those corresponding parts be changed, by the distortion of one of the eyes,
the object must again appear double as at the first... '7
The implication of the priority of double vision over single would have appealed
especially to Blake; and in a later account of the experiments of Dr Smith, Priestley
64 showed that, as in the case of Blake’s Newton, it was with the aid ofa pair of com-
passes that the transition from double to single vision might be demonstrated."
Priestley’s History and Present State offered Blake, in its account of‘fallacies in
vision’, many testimonies to the imperfection of the corporeal eye which he did
not hesitate to adopt. A draft for The Everlasting Gospel, a poem which linked
Priestley and Newton as doubters and experimenters, concluded with a passage
closely related to part ofPriestley’s explanation ofthe apparent size of the horizon-
tal moon:
This Life’s dim windows of the soul
Distorts the Heavens from Pole to Pole
And leads you to believe a Lie
When you see with, not thro’ the E ye
That was born in a night to perish in a night,
When the Soul slept in the beams of Light."
The well-known passage at the close of the Vision of the Last Judgement:‘ “What”,
it will be Questioned, “When the Sun rises, do you not see a round disc of fire
somewhat like a Guinea’ relates to the use of a wafer to simulate the moon in
an experiment in the same chapter of Priestley.*° It was not simply the spiritual
148
BLAKE'S NEWTON
Newton and the Prism, an engraving after George Romney. Newton is shown demonstrating the
formation ofthe spectrum to his daughters, with blue and violet at the top of the column and the long-
wave-length red at the bottom. From 1803-4, when he will have seen the original painting, Blake
tended to show the spectral colours in this order even in the rainbow, where they are reversed. (68)
149
BLAKE'S NEWTON
than six? or, why not double that number, or even more, if all the intermedi-
aries are attended to? It may be worth remarking that Milton has,in a few words,
described this appearance with a much more accurate and happy propriety:
and in a cloud, a bow
Conspicuous, with three listed colours gay
and in another place:
His triple-coloured bow, whereon to look ...
But lest any one should think that our poet had from defect of sight over-
looked the four other colours, we may quote the testimony ofAristotle, who
has with his usual accuracy fallen upon the same tri-partite division.”
Certainly Dante may have presented Blake with the idea of a seven-colour bow,
but Dante specified neither the colours nor their order, which in Blake’s usage are
always Newtonian.** One curious circumstance, indeed, reinforces the impression
that in the construction of his rainbows, Blake was making a specifically and self-
consciously Newtonian reference. In the known coloured bows before 1804 the
order of the colours runs, from top to bottom, as in a perfect natural bow: red,
orange, yellow, green, blue [indigo], violet.** Rainbows painted after 1804, on the
other hand, show this order of colours in reverse, and run, top to bottom, from
violet to red.*° The crucial moment seems to be the winter of 1803-4, a time when
Blake was helping William Hayley collect material for his Life of Romney. Hayley’s
68 Life published an aquatint after Romney’s Newton and the Prism, a painting which
remained in the painter’s studio with his posthumous collection until 1807.7” Blake
saw this collection in October 1803, and remarked on a companion-picture to the
Newton there, Milton and his Daughters, in a letter to Hayley (p. 878).We may assume
that he also saw the Newton on this occasion, and in it, owing to the relative posi-
tions of the light-source and the prism (which seems to be held as in Opticks, I, ii,
prop. viii, prob. iii; fig. 12), the projected spectrum runs, from top to bottom,
through violet to red. Romney has even added a band of indigo below the red,
which seems to correspond to a thin band ofviolet in Blake’s Noah.
150
BLAKE'S NEWTON
element of water; and in Vala (p. 256) he presented Enion (earth) and her spectre in
these terms:
Thus they contended all the day among the Caves ofTharmas,
Tivisting in fearful forms & howling, howling, harsh shrieking,
Howling, harsh shrieking: mingling, their bodies in burning anguish.
Mingling his brightness with her tender limbs, then
Above the ocean; a bright wonder, Nature,
HalfWoman & half Spectre; all his lovely changing colours mix
With her fair crystal clearness. . .
Bryant had indeed suggested that the Egyptian Thamus signified the wonder; and
in his final vignette to A New System (vol. iii), which may have been engraved by
Blake, the Genesis story has been compressed to show the Rainbow of the Covenant 69
rising directly out of the Flood. Similarly, in a monochrome wash-drawing in the
Abbot Hall Art Gallery, Kendal (Butlin no. 690), variously entitled The Rainbow over
the Flood and God moving on the Face of the Waters, but which might perhaps more
appropriately be called Thaumas and Iris, Blake has shown again this close relation-
ship of bow and sea.
Both in illustrating other poets’ verses and in illuminating his own, Blake used
the rainbow as an emblem of materialism. In a watercolour for Night Eight of
Edward Young’s Night Thoughts, the image precisely interpreted a passage (II, 138- 48
42) on the transience of the sublunary world:
What is this sublunary world?A vapour;
A vapour all it holds; itselfavapour;
From the damp bed of chaos, by Thy beam
Exhaled, ordain’d to swim its destined hour
In ambient air, then melt, and disappear.
In Jerusalem (ii, 48, p. 493) Blake described the creation of a bow by the emanation
of the Friends of Albion:
With awful hands she took
A Moment of Time, drawing it out with many tears and afflictions
And many sorrows, oblique across the Atlantic Vale,
Which is the Vale ofRephaim dreadful from East to West
Where the Human Harvest waves abundant in the beams of Eden.
Into a Rainbow ofJewels and gold, a mild Reflection from
Albion’s dread Tomb...
The rainbow is a reflection of death, too, in the watercolours of Mary and Joseph on
Vala, or Nature,’Mother of
their biers. Blake saw Mary, like Beatrice, as a daughter of
the Body ofDeath’ (p. 152), and Joseph, as her spouse, clearly belongs to the same
cycle of generation. It is he who, in a drawing in Walsall Museum and Art Gallery,
appears to have given the young Christ a pair of compasses in the carpenter's shop.”
It is, indeed, the compasses — which Blake may well have thought of as dividers —
that Christ holds in common with the Newton of Blake’s print; and the man Jesus
ISI
BLAKE SNEWTON
Vignette of The End of the Deluge, 1774, probably a design by Blake for Bryant. The Rainbow of the
Covenant is shown rising directly out of the waters. (69)
152
It - Magilphs and Mysteries
...such people as ours who are floating about after Magilphs and mysteries
and are very little likely to satisfy themselves with that saying of Annibal’,
‘Buon disegno e colorito di fango [good drawing and muddy colouring].
(James Barry RA, 1769')
AN (ie WILLIAM SANDBY PUBLISHED the first history of the Royal Academy
in 1862 he made a special plea for instruction in the chemistry of colours,
citing the physical decay of many pictures by Reynolds, Turner and Etty, and the late
works of Wilkie.* The professorship of Chemistry at the Academy was not estab-
lished until 1871, but already, by mid-century, the work of testing-bodies such as the
Society ofArts, and of individual colourmen like George Field, had made available
to artists proven methods and materials which have lasted extremely well, as for
instance in the paintings of the Pre-Raphaelites.'
Earlier students and academicians were not so fortunate. None of the later
eighteenth-century academies seems to have concerned itself with the teaching of
technique, which was left to private masters,* and in England these masters were
often unable or unwilling to provide instruction.’ The technical manuals com-
plained of secretiveness,° and recipes were spread by rumour and hint, rather than
by any systematic teaching.” This atmosphere of uncertainty and speculation was
naturally fertile in quack formulae, the grossest of which, the ‘Venetian Secret’
which was brought to general notice at the Royal Academy Exhibition of 1797,
retained its echo of derision well into the following century.
about Miss Provis'' except that she was a miniaturist who had been at some time in
the care ofthe alienist and patron Dr Thomas Monro."*
Her secret, of which the diarist Farington’s copy is preserved in the library ofthe
Royal Academy, was by no means exclusively Venetian. It offered, indeed, a ‘System
of Painting according to the Several Great Italian Schools’, and among the recipes
for painting draperies is a ‘Raphael Green’, mixed from indigo, yellow ochre and
orpiment, with powdered glass as a dryer."’ Farington’s Diary also tells us that Miss
Provis was prepared to teach Roman practice,"* and the manuscript even has some
notes on the procedures of the Dutch painters Ruisdael and Wynants.'* Her advice
on method was also generously vague:
Be particular to remember that all the before-mentioned Carnations may
either be finished at one painting so as to deceive the eye as if they were
Glazed, or heightened lastly by various Glazings of Transparent Carnations,
Shades &c. mixed only in Linseed Oil very sparingly."®
Nearly half, however, of the Academy manuscript is in Farington’s hand, which
suggests that much was communicated by word of mouth, and there may have been
more detail which has not survived. Stephen Rigaud, who records in a memoir the
copy sold by Miss Provis to his father, the Royal Academician John Francis Rigaud,
recalled that she
committed very little of [the secret] to writing, but explained it principally by
exhibiting [to a Royal Academy committee] several little pictures painted in
that manner, from the first sketch to the finished work; as also by herself paint-
ing in their presence some specimens of the different processes through which
the picture had to pass in order to its completion, according to the Venetian system.
This sounds remarkably like the then-current method of teaching watercolour
painting to amateurs in a series of graded lessons.'7
The three key elements of the Secret seem to have been the use of pure linseed
oil, dark absorbent grounds,"* and the “Titian Shade’, made up of equal quantities of
lake, indigo, and Hungarian (Prussian) or Antwerp blue, plus rather more ivory
black. This was the universal shadow-colour for flesh, drapery and clouds,'® and it
has been pointed out that the blues in this recipe were first developed in the eigh-
teenth, not the sixteenth century.’°
Examples of Miss Provis’s paintings according to this system had been known
7O for some years, and she had apparently worked on West’s Venus Comforting Cupid
(Cupid stung by a Bee).*' But it was not until January 1797, when it seemed that the
President might buy the monopoly of the secret, that interest began to spread
widely in the Academy.** West asserted that ‘A new Epocha in the Art... would be
formed by the discovery’; and Alderman Boydell had already dismissed a number of
painters from his Shakespeare Gallery project, and refused to engage others until
sp the process had been tested more fully.” In Gillray’s satire Titianus Redivivus Boydell
is seen slinking off with West and clutching a volume of Shakespeare, with the com-
plaint that the Secret might spawn ‘another Gallery’. Even before they had been
convinced of the improvement in the President's ‘Venetian’ pictures, Farington and
154
MAGILPHS AND MYSTERIES
This typically
‘Venetian’ mytho-
logical scene, Venus
Comforting Cupid,
c. 1796-1802, was
apparently started by
Benjamin West, the
President of the
Royal Academy, in
collaboration with
the miniature-painter
Ann Jemima Provis,
the chief author of
the “Venetian Secret’.
(70)
Robert Smirke and half-a-dozen other Academicians suggested that the Provises
should be offered an annuity; but West proposed private subscriptions and the
establishment of Ann’s father, Thomas, as an artists’ colourman.** According to
Farington (25 January) Thomas Provis would have been satisfied originally with
fifty guineas for the process, but when the copyright agreement was drawn up
with Farington’s help,*> six hundred guineas was the sum which the two partners
were to be allowed to collect, before subscribers were free to divulge the Secret, for
which they had paid ten guineas apiece. Until then, it was reported, the fine for a
breach ofsecrecy would be £2,000, and the buyers undertook never to divulge it to
any foreigner, ‘thereby to preserve the advantage to their own country’.”® J. F
Rigaud proposed that Academy students competing for medals should not use the
Secret, as this would discriminate against the poorest.*”
Almost as soon as rumours of the Secret reached the outside world they met
with ridicule as well as with rivalry and support. By March 1797 the watercolourist
Paul Sandby RA had composed what he later described as a‘doodle-do song’ on the
affair; and he declared that he and the portraitist Sir William Beechey had quickly
discovered the process for themselves ‘without subscribing a shilling’.**
Reynolds’s former colourman, Sebastian Grandi, later described by Field as ‘a
most ignorant Italian quack in Colours’, was found successfully passing off a picture
155
MAGILPHS AND MYSTERIES
painted by Henry Tresham RA to the Provis formula as a product of his own ‘Venet-
ian’ system.” At the Society of Arts, another and more modest ‘Venetian’ expert,
Timothy Sheldrake, gave a tentative recognition to the Provis method, which he
imagined was similar to his own.’°
Edmond Malone, in the first edition of his Works of Sir Joshua Reynolds (1797),
welcomed the advantages of the Secret, which his subject had unhappily not lived
to see; and, although he alluded to the Ireland Shakespeare forgeries of afew years
earlier, he declared confidently that the authenticity of the process could easily be
established by experiment.’' Malone predicted with some confidence the appear-
ance of several ‘Venetian’ pictures at the coming Royal Academy Exhibition; but
those that were exhibited — by West, Tresham, Smirke, Thomas Stothard and
MAGILPHS AND MYSTERIES
Richard Westall — generally met with a poor reception. The Tive Briton approved of
Westall’s Infant Bacchus (a thoroughly ‘Venetian’ subject), but other critics found
that the effect of the ‘Titian Shade’ varied from a ‘dark and purpurine hue’ to ‘the
chalky and cold tints of fresco and that gaudy glare and flimsy nothingness of fan
painting’.*’ Even West was becoming increasingly dissatisfied with the process, and
complained to Provis of his lack of success.**
Vie
rythe
illatnis
t
TS
MAGILPHS AND MYSTERIES
Sa
Miss Provis demonstrating her technique ofportraiture on a dark ground. The ass Pegasus’s wings
display the names of the newspapers who supported the Secret. (73)
himself, John Opie, Stothard, John Hoppner, Smirke, Rigaud and Westall, each
neatly characterized on their canvases or in their speech-bubbles by some telling
weakness, such as Farington’s ‘Filchings from Wilson’, Opie’s thick impasto and
Stothard’s obsession with white grounds. Among the swarm of increasingly ape-
like painters clamouring for the Secret are James Northcote, Tresham, Thomas
Lawrence and Ozias Humphry, most of whom are well known for their technical
74 curiosity. Two of the pufti of puffing patronage above the artists represent Sir George
Beaumont, one of the first amateur painters to buy the Secret,3° and Edmond
Malone; and the painters whose work is suffering defilement to the left include
Sandby and Beechey, whose scepticism about the Secret we have seen, Gillray’s
friend and collaborator Phillip Jacques de Loutherbourg, one of the soundest
technicians of the period, Henry Fuseli who was a lifelong opponent of the Venet-
ian School, and the rising Academy star Turner, who was to be praised in a review
MAGILPHS AND MYSTERIES
a)
MAGILPHS AND MYSTERIES
of the Exhibition of 1798 for keeping aloof from ‘these ridiculous superficial
expedients’. *7
The effect of Gillray’s satire, or the disillusionment of which it was a symptom,
was soon clear. Malone’s second edition of Reynolds’s Works (1798) carried an
embarrassed recantation of his earlier enthusiasm, which concluded that, ‘however
ancient...these documents may be, they hitherto appear to be of little value’.*
The editor himself was attacked, and Reynolds defended as a naturally ‘Venetian’
colourist, in the bitterest criticism to arise from the affair, James Barry’s Letter to the
Dilettanti Society, which included the splenetic protest that
such a concurrence of ridiculous circumstances, ofsomany, such gross absur-
dities, and such busy industrious folly, in contriving for the publicity, and
exposure of aquacking disgraceful imposture is, I believe, unparalleled in the
history ofthe art.
As the epigraph to this chapter shows, Barry had long been an opponent oftechni-
cal nostrums, but the tone of his vituperation on this occasion may well have
contributed a good deal to his expulsion from the Academy in the following year.
A critic noted that there were no ‘Venetian’ pictures to be seen at the Exhibition
of 1798.39
The aftermath
But the matter was not entirely closed: critics of the Academy continued to use it as
ammunition, and the acute anxieties about technique, together with a belief in the
essentially painterly qualities of British painting, did not go away. In 1802 John
Singleton Copley claimed to have found the ‘vehicle’ which was the key to the
Secret, and, about the same time, the new exhibiting society, The British School,
which introduced George Field into the world of art, showed ‘a specimen of the
Venetian process of Painting’ by the Irish artist Solomon Williams, who was touting
his own ‘Venetian’ vehicle among the Royal Academicians, including, notably,
Farington.*° In 1806 it is curious to see the duped of 1797 — Farington, West, Opie
— joining with the sceptical — Loutherbourg, Richard Cosway, Beechey — in endors-
ing Sebastian Grandi’s absorbent grounds, ‘in the old Venetian stile’, before the
Society of Arts, which awarded him a silver medal and a bounty of twenty pounds.*!
Miss Provis was lost to view, together with her process; but the continued attrac-
tion ofVenetian secrets for lady amateurs is shown by the Account of aNew Process
in Painting by means of Glazed Crayons; with Remarks on its General Correspondence
with the Peculiarities of the Venetian School, which was published anonymously at
Brighton in 1815. The author was the daughter of William Cleaver, Bishop of
Bangor and later of St Asaph, and she claimed to have discovered her process by
accident in 1807.** The quality of this strange pamphlet on ‘dry colouring’ may
perhaps be judged from its assertion that ‘oil colour is...incompatible with the
essential characteristics of flesh, suppleness and transparency...’,? and from the
introduction of only a single Venetian painting (Bassano) among the twelve visual
160
MAGILPHS AND MYSTERIES
examples to which the pamphlet was to serve as text. The specimen thought to be
closest to Venetian effects was after an etching by the Bolognese painter Guercino.4
Miss Cleaver’s work, which was re-issued in an expanded London edition in
1821, would hardly merit attention in this context had she not made repeated
applications for support to the British Institution, and been taken up by Sir George
Beaumont, who approached Constable to make trials of her process in 1824.
Constable’s deep sympathy for Titian, and probably his closeness to George Field,
which developed at this time, inclined him to be suspicious of all formulae; and
although he heard that Miss Cleaver ‘had been boring at [it] these twenty years’,
he concluded that he did not much like it. Cleaver hoped the Institution would
send several artists to test her process at her home in Brighton ‘and offer very
high premiums for their success’, but it is not known whether anything further
was done.*
Miss Cleaver claimed that she had never had the opportunity of consulting orig-
inal Venetian manuals;*° but soon, with the publication of the historical researches
into technique by Charles Lock Eastlake and Mary Merrifield, there could be very
little possibility of further impostures of the “Venetian Secret’ type. Both historians
and chemists were making artists and their public more aware of the limitations and
legitimate uses of materials; possibly they were also changing an attitude of mind
which looked for art in easy recipes. ‘Itwill soon be discovered, wrote a critic of the
eighteenth-century Venetian scandal, ‘that the colour-shops of ancient as well as of
modern times have not dealt in the ingredients of genius.’*”
161
12 - Turner as a Colourist
4 S FOR TURNER, AT FIRST HE STUNS YOu. You find yourself facing a confusion of
WANS a and burnt siena, of blue and white, rubbed on with a rag, sometimes
round and round, sometimes in lines, or in zig-zags in several directions. You might
say that it was done with a rubber-stamp brushed over with breadcrumbs, or with
a pile of soft paints diluted with water and spread on to a sheet of paper, which is
folded and then scraped violently with a stiff brush. This gives rise to an astonishing
play of mixtures, especially if you scatter a few flecks of white gouache on it before
folding the paper.
‘That is what you see from close to, and from a distance...everything balances
itself out. Before your incredulous eyes a marvellous landscape rises, a fairy place, a
radiant river flowing beneath a sun’s prismatic rays. A pale sky vanished into the
distance, engulfed in a horizon of mother-of-pearl, reflecting and moving 1n water
that is iridescent like a film of soap, and the spectrum of soap-bubbles. What land,
what Eldorado, what Eden flames with this wild brilliance, these floods of light
refracted by milky clouds, flecked with fiery red and slashed with violet, like the
precious depths of opal? And yet these are real places; they are autumn landscapes
with russet trees, running water, forests shedding their foliage; but they are also
landscapes that have been vapourized, where dawn fills the whole sky; they are
jubilant skies and rivers of a nature sublimated, husked, and rendered completely
fluid by a great poet’ (J. K. Huysmans, “Turner et Goya’, Certains, 1889").
Huysmans’ vivid characterization of Turner as a colourist places the painter
firmly in the Elysium of Symbolist heroes; and it is no surprise that Gustave
Moreau and Edmond de Goncourt found him to be something of a ‘jeweler’ when
they went to look at his work in the Groult collection in 1891, and may have seen
80 there the Landscape with a River and a Bay in the Distance — possibly also the work,
exhibited at the quai Malaquais, which had aroused such an enthusiastic response in
Huysmans. Goncourt wrote of one TurnerVenetian scene there — alas, likely to have
been a fake — that it was ‘liquid gold, and within it an infusion ofpurple. ..it has the
air of a painting done by a Rembrandt born in India’.
But for the Impressionists in these years it was a very different story. In a conver-
sation with the dealer René Gimpel in 1918, Claude Monet explained that ‘Dans le
temps j’ai beaucoup aimé Tirner, aujourd’huijel’aime beaucoup moins.— Pourquoi? — Il n’a
pas assez dessine la couleur et il en a trop mis [Over the years I have liked Turner a great
deal, but now I like him far less. He has given too little attention to the arrangement
of colour, and he has used too much of it].””
162
TURNER AS A COLOURIST
Local colour
Of course Monet was right. If we place one of his Rouen Cathedral paintings beside 83
Turner’s small gouache of the same subject,} or one of his or Renoir’s Venetian 82
subjects beside one of Turner’s, we see that even the late Impressionist approach to
colour is very different from that of the late Turner. In Monet and Renoir colour is
a function of the light which floods into the picture, animating the complex sur-
faces of objects, but also bringing them into unison by the homogeneity which it
confers on the whole. However strange or ‘recherché’, the colours in Impressionist
paintings are always echoed in every part of the canvas; like the unified brushstroke,
light and colour weld the surface into a unity. Turner handled his colour in quite a
different way. Just as his brushstroke varies from object to object and from area to
area on canvas or paper, now broad and fluid, now crisp and impastoed, now swift
and calligraphic, so Turner’s colour is used, for the most part, to discriminate
between objects, not to unify them. The strong red and green costumes of the
figures in the foreground of his Rouen Cathedral —a colour-combination so charac-
teristic of his work in the early 1830s —are used as maximal contrasts of local colour,
ot, as they might be in Monet, as complementary colours of light: they give us
neither the appearance nor the conception offigures in full sunlight.
During the second half of his career Turner was always searching for ways of
introducing local colour into the various areas of his works. A Venetian subject,
painted for the sculptor Sir Francis Chantrey, was the subject of a conversation at
some reception, where a discussion ensued among a number of spectators about the
identity of a large orange object floating in the water, which some considered
might be a gorgeous turban. Then Turner came up, and ‘after two or three twitches
of his lips, and as many little half h-ms, he replied, ““Orange-orange.”
Turner's liking for fruit and vegetables in his pictures, which Ruskin attributed to
tastes developed during his boyhood near Covent Garden market, served in the
event a much more purely formal purpose. They were the landscape-painter’s sur-
rogates for the coloured draperies of the history-painter or the bric-a-brac of the
still-life artist, to be manipulated at will, according to the exigencies of a pictorial
idea. But they must not be wholly arbitrary: Turner’s resistance to abstraction is
nowhere more evident than in his urge to give these patches of brilliant local
colour a recognizable — and more or less reasonable — physical form. The need for
reason is emphasized in a story circulating in the 1850s at Petworth House in
Sussex, the home of Turner’s most important later patron, Lord Egremont, about
Brighton from the Sea, one of the painter’s florid footnotes to the family portraits by
Van Dyck. As one visitor wrote: [Turner] introduced in the foreground of it a
broken basket with some floating turnips, carrots, etc., and, as the old butler told
me..., was savage when, at Lord Egremont’s suggestion as to their specific gravity,
he asked for a tub of water and some of the identical vegetables, and found the latter
all sank. They were evidently too useful in his picture to be removed.’
They were indeed extremely useful, and as late as 1847, when Turner had taken
to repainting some of his early canvases, he introduced into Tapping the Furnace (a
work originally produced nearly half a century earlier) a strikingly characteristic
163
TURNER AS A COLOURIST
device to accentuate the flames of the furnace. “Turner, not satisfied with the daz-
zling effect obtained by surrounding the blazing fire with broad masses of shadow
on the walls and roof of the foundry? recalled a contemporary, ‘had determined
to make the glow and glare still more effective by opposition of colour. He could
conceive of nothing that would naturally be seen in the place to answer the desired
purpose; and so he introduced, in the immediate front of his picture, stretching
from side to side, a row ofcut cabbages ofthe greenest possible hue. These cabbages
were a great puzzle to many visitors to the exhibition.®
The public certainly saw the work primarily as a matter of colour: as the critic of
the Atheneum put it, it was ‘full of fine passages of chromatic arrangement; it has so
little foundation in fact that the sense is merely bewildered at the unsparing hand
with which the painter has spread forth the glories of his palette’. Turner's inten-
tions were essentially colouristic, but he was not prepared to allow colour to stand
by itself. By an irony of history, the cabbages in Tapping the Furnace are still some-
thing of apuzzle, and their presence has barely been noticed by modern commen-
tators on the picture, for the hasty methods used by Turner to improvise his
repainting in time for the Exhibition have meant that they have now darkened and
cracked to the point of being virtually invisible.
Thus, ifTurner’s later treatment of colour was not abstract, seen from the point of
view of ‘realism’ or ‘naturalism’ it could none the less be thoroughly wilful, and
Monet’s strictures in 1918 are entirely in order. Yet it had not always been so, and if
Monet saw Turner’s early work, like the Cilgerran Castle (Leicester) which passed
through the Paris saleroom in 1874, at a time when the English painter was still
something of a hero to the Impressionists, he will surely have recognized a kindred
spirit.? For between about 1800 and 1812 Turner’ art saw a naturalistic phase which
is precisely parallel to the ‘high’ period of Impressionism in the 1870s. He developed
an interest in more informal pastoral subjects, and he took to the practice of working
directly from nature in the open air, both on small oil-sketches and on the earlier
stages of canvases destined for the Exhibition. This was the time when he believed,
as he told a travelling-companion in 1813, that ‘we can paint only what we see’.*
164
TURNER AS A COLOURIST
colours which came to be chosen were for the most part the three subtractive
primary colours, yellow, red and blue, which Turner felt were an epitome of the
whole of visible creation.Ashe wrote in a lecture of 1818, yellow represented the
medium (i.e. light), red the material objects, and blue, distance (1.e. air) in landscape,
and in terms of natural time, morning, evening, and dawn."° In common with many
artists of his generation Turner was fascinated by the idea of discovering an irre-
ducible number of elements in nature and art: his interest in primary colours is
matched by a belief in the underlying geometrical simplicity of forms.
165
TURNER AS A COLOURIST
J. M. W. Turner, Shade and Darkness: the Evening ofthe Deluge (above), and Light and Colour (Goethe’s
Theory): the Morning after the Deluge — Moses writing the Book of Genesis (right), both of 1843. Turner
contrasts the dark prelude to the biblical Deluge and its brilliant aftermath, when the sun brought
prismatic bubbles to the surface of the Flood. The Goethe reference is probably to the poet’s table of
polarities — blue and yellow, dark and light, and so on —in The Theory of Colours, of which Turner
annotated his own copy at this time. But Turner felt that even Goethe had not sufficiently stressed the
constructive role of darkness in the generation of colour. (76, 77)
166
TURNER AS A COLOURIST
blue, was also of course derived from the painterly experience of mixing material
pigments, rather than from an analysis of the prismatic spectrum, and all these
notions allowed Turner to resist the conclusion that colour, even as it is perceived, is
simply a function ofthe action oflight on surfaces.
and the notion that contrasts and juxtapositions may work miracles with percep-
tion. ‘Stay there’, Turner is reputed to have muttered to a patch of yellow pigment
on his canvas, ‘until I make you white.’'® And he was prepared to turn the accidents
of perception into a painterly method during those “Varnishing Days’ at the Royal
Academy and British Institution exhibitions. A younger contemporary recalled
how, when Turner arrived to hang his work at the Royal Academy exhibition in
1846,‘some ofhis work was, as usual, only rubbed in, and it was common practice of
his, when he saw how his pictures were placed, to paint first a little on one, then on
another, and so on till all were finished to his satisfaction’.'”
This procedure was very much a method ofself-defence, as the critic of L’Artiste
had noted, with pardonable exaggeration, as early as 1836:
There is no doubt that the chief reason for the great change which has crept
into his style derives from the rivalries occasioned by the annual exhibition of
paintings at Somerset House, where the paintings are so crowded together,
that the artist most ambitious for reputation tries to attract attention by the use
of bright colour and the most dazzling effects of light. When a man of genius
like Turner makes this effort, the result is overwhelming for artists with less
imagination."*
And not for these nameless artists of lesser imagination alone, for in 1832 John
Constable himself was to find the red robes of the dignitaries in his picture of the
Opening of Waterloo Bridge (London, National Gallery) cast into obscurity by the
wafer of red sealing-wax which Turner applied to the water of his cool green sea-
piece next to it, Helvoetsluys, and later painted into the form ofa buoy.‘He has been
here’, said Constable when he saw it, ‘and fired a gun.”
As he grew older, Turner paid more and more attention to these subjective effects
of colour;in 1845 a group ofvisitors to the private gallery he had designed and built
to provide the best lighting and coloured background for his paintings was told to
wait for some time in a totally darkened anteroom before they were allowed to see
the pictures themselves, since ‘the bright light outside would have spoilt their eyes
for properly appreciating the pictures, and that to see them to advantage an interval
of darkness was necessary’ .*°
We return here to where we started, to the world of late Monet, for it was
Monet who proclaimed, just before he died, that he would have liked to have been
born blind and to have had his sight suddenly restored, so that he could see the
world afresh as nothing but an arrangement of coloured patches, without reference
to any knowledge of objects. It is fitting that Monet should here have been
echoing a notion he had found in that most admired of Ruskin’s works in late
nineteenth-century France, The Elements of Drawing, translated as it was by the
Neo-Impressionists Henri-Edmond Cross and Paul Signac,?' and that Ruskin
himself should have come to recognize these principles of colour-relativity above
all from his experience oflate Turner.
168
13 - °Iwo Different Worlds’ —
Runge, Goethe and the Sphere
of Colour
However disparate these two contemporary treatises may seem, they have usually
been considered together because Goethe and Runge were, in fact, closely involved
169
TWO DIFFERENT WORLDS
J. W. von Goethe, frontispiece to Die Farbenlehre (Theory of Colours), 1810. Nos 3 and 7 show the
basic colours of light (or flame) as yellow and blue, while circles 1 and 2 have at the top Goethe’s
most important colour: Purpur (red), produced by the ‘augmentation’ of polar yellow (light) and blue
(darkness). The landscape below contains no blue — a precocious investigation of colour-blindness. (78)
in each other’s developing interest in colour over a period of nearly ten years; and
theirs is an exceptionally well-documented relationship which promises many
insights into the interaction of practice and theory in the visual arts. And yet the
completeness and intelligibility of this record is more apparent than real,and I hope
in this chapter to suggest that we are still faced with as many questions as answers,
to point out what these questions are, and to go some way towards answering some
of them.
170
TWO DIFFERENT WORLDS
BP SRN Z = Aft fe
Sartentugel,
“ Sovsioll? MOS BOI ENE Distes fa KY é jp
Eisen haan Sele.
To the central, ‘Didactic Part’ of his Farbenlehre Goethe appended a letter which
he had received from Runge in 1806:a letter, as the poet wrote in a prefatory note,
which showed ‘that artists have already opened up the path which we see as the
correct one...’,so that:
without being informed of my efforts, through his own inclinations, his own
practice and his own thought, [Runge] has found himself on the same path.
I7I
TWO DIFFERENT WORLDS
A careful comparison of this letter and my sketch will reveal that in several
places they agree precisely, and that others may be interpreted and illuminated
by my work, so that the writer has anticipated me in several points by his lively
conviction and true feeling.’
A ‘careful comparison’ of the two texts will, however, show us that there are
remarkably few points of comparability between them: Runge, for example, is not
at all concerned with the origin ofcolours in the interplay oflight and dark, which
is the keystone of Goethe’s theory; and Goethe, for his part, shows no special inter-
est in the distinction between transparent and opaque colours, which is Runge’s
chief preoccupation in this letter. But by the time the Farbenlehre appeared in print
Goethe had received a further sample of Runge’s colour-ideas in the form of the
Farben-Kugel, which the poet read in manuscript during 1809 and in its printed
version early the following year. This text he also welcomed as being close to his
own views,* although again, with the exception of the appendix on harmony
(which recommended complementary contrasts), it had little to do with the
leading arguments in Goethe’s book, and was indeed even further in general terms
from Goethe’s approach and tone than the 1806 letter had been. In particular,
Runge had now abandoned that arrangement of the colour-circle with red at the
top, which had a crucial significance for Goethe, but none for Runge, who tried
many orientations quite indifferently during the preparation of his treatise.
Goethe’s concept of Steigerung (augmentation) by means of the semi-opaque
medium, by which the two basic colours, yellow representing light and blue repre-
senting darkness, are acted upon to produce the highest, noblest colour, red
78 (Purpur), was the driving force behind the poet’s attack on the Newtonian doctrine
that all colours inhere in white light alone, without the intervention of darkness.
But Runge came late to Newton — as late as September 1806 he was asking Goethe
where he could find a good account of Newton’s theory® — and opposition to
Newton was never a central issue with him, since he avoided any engagement with
the crucial matter of the origin of colours (Farben-Kugel, §4). The Farben-Kugel
was at once recognized as in no way an anti-Newtonian treatise,” and Runge, like
Blake, continued, for example, to use the Newtonian seven-colour schema of the
rainbow-colours.*
When in the summer of 1810, and shortly before his death, Runge came to read
Goethe's Farbenlehre itself, he found
that there is much that I have not understood or see differently, and since
several errors have slipped into [my] book, [Goethe] will have something to
forgive: my goal is really a different one...°
And the only recorded note which the painter made in the course ofhis reading of
the poet’s text was to counter one of Goethe’s arguments about subjective, physio-
logical colour-phenomena by an appeal to the effects of objective transparency. '°
At no stage in the interchanges between Goethe and Runge between 1806 and
1810 do we have a sense of the unity of minds.
Why then did Goethe claim so vigorously that there was a close similarity between
172
TWO DIFFERENT WORLDS
his and Runge’s views on colour? Certainly we know from their correspondence
that he was aware of a far greater range of Runge’s thoughts and experiments than
was ever published in either of their books; but that is hardly the point, and there
was, in any case, little in these further thoughts and experiments which came close
to Goethe’s central concerns. Some indication of what was in Goethe’s mind
emerges from a letter to the composer and musical-theorist Zelter in August 1806,
and from a remark made both to Runge and to Steffens in 1809:
It would be very congenial to me if, on the completion of my work, I can
appeal to sympathisers among my contemporaries, since so far I have been
able to find support only among the dead."
Goethe was above all anxious to find support among the living, for he had already
enrolled the dead in the ‘Historical Part’ of the Farbenlehre, and if there was nothing
in Runge’s work that was specifically anti- Newtonian, nor was there anything there
which clashed directly with his own views.
173
TWO DIFFERENT WORLDS
174
TWO DIFFERENT WORLDS
Is not the dawn to be seen as the red side of the great colour-structure [|
Farben-
bild] which is every day in motion, which projects itself into the brightness of
day? And noon as the dominant yellow, and evening the violet, which loses
itself in the darkness of night?3"
These equivalents, which seem to be related to Steffens’s unusual idea that red and
blue are the most basic primaries,” do not agree with Runge’s earliest (1802) for-
mulation of the relationships between colours and the Christian Trinity and three
times of day where, in a thoroughly idiosyncratic way, blue was held to characterize
the Father (morning), red the Son (noon) and yellow the Holy Ghost (night).33 But
morning, for example, soon became red in Runge’s system, and in the 1808 Small 84
Morning the central focus in the frame is on the red lily, Amaryllis formosissima,
which thus comes to embody the dawn or Morgenroth, and, together with the aban-
donment of the name of God, Jaweh, which appeared in earlier versions of this
frame, to throw the emphasis of the Morning entirely on to red. It is clear, too, from
the way in which the Times of Day series developed, that Runge was increasingly
anxious to move away from more conventional Christian or Classical imagery and
towards something more ‘abstract’; in describing a preparatory study for the Small
Morning in April 1808 he avoided any specific mythological reference to the figures:
they are simply general embodiments of the forces of nature.™*
And yet Runge was still uncertain of the precise relationship of theory to prac-
tice. Writing to his brother Gustav in November 1808 he characterized the Farben-
Kugel as:
that it is necessary for me, when I am working as an artist, not to know any-
thing about it, since these are two different worlds which intersect in me...*
175
TWO DIFFERENT WORLDS
176
S.
Oe pis ane es
177
Colour in Turner and in Impressionism
Turner’s small gouache of Rouen Cathedral, c. 1832, uses colour chiefly to discriminate between objects,
not to unify them (above), whereas in Monet’s painting of the same subject in 1892-4 (right), colour is
a function of the light which floods into the picture, animating complex surfaces, but also bringing
them into homogeneity. Turner’s handling of the bustling street-scene shows a far greater
preoccupation with local colour. (82, 83)
178
Red and the feminine
A systematic conception of colour, as espoused by Goethe in the Theory of Colours (78), and colour as ‘the ultimate art’ — were
represented respectively in the Hamburg painter Philipp Otto Runge’s Colour-Sphere (79) and his paintings of the three Times
ofDay. Morning was seen as red in Runge’s system (left: The Small ‘Morning’, 1808). In the gendering of colour, red is here
linked to the female figure of Aurora, flanked by the red lilies in the frame. (84)
In anthropological vein, the German Romantic painter Franz Pforr believed colour to be expressive of character (above). His
Sulamith and Maria of 1811 clothes the allegorical figure of the South, brown-haired Sulamith, in white, red and green, and
the blonde northerner Maria in a bright-red dress and white apron. (85)
German Modernism and Goethe’s theory
Both Franz Marc (above: Blue Horse I, 1911) and Kandinsky were persuaded of the masculine
spirituality of blue — the Romantic colour par excellence. “We both loved blue,’ Kandinsky
mentioned a propos the name of the almanac Der Blaue Reiter — ‘Marc horses: I riders’. (86)
Perhaps under the stimulus of Goethe in 1910-11 Mare painted his dog Russi as seen through a
prism, recording the coloured fringes at the junction of light and dark (above right), and also, as
he explained, to study the contrasts between yellow, white and blue. (87)
In Yellow-Red-Blue of 1925 (right), Wassily Kandinsky, then a teacher at the Bauhaus, exemplifies
a further aspect of Goethe’s theory — the creation of red from the ‘augmentation’ (Steigerung) of
yellow (light) and blue (dark) as described in Goethe’s 7 heory of Colours. (88)
The polar interaction of light and darkness made v ble — the most striking instance of the
application of Goethe’s the ry of colour to painting. The German artist Arthur Segal’s Fisherman’s
House on Sylt I (1926) po ys the spectral edges engendered at the meeting of light and dark.
In this same series of paintings the a ist hoped to find a way of reconciling the equal demat
of colour and form. (89)
14 - Mood Indigo — From the Blue
Flower to the Blue Rider
Price question:
1. Anna Blossom has wheels.
2. Anna Blossom is red.
3. what colour are the wheels?
Blue is the colour of thy yellow hair.
Red is the whirl of thy green wheels.
Thou simple maiden in everyday-dress,
Thou dear green animal,
I love Thine! -
(Kurt Schwitters, Anna Blossom has Wheels,1942"')
185
MOOD INDIGO
a scientific background, and in this chapter I want to look at the way in which some
of his Expressionist contemporaries took up and revalued the approaches to colour
first articulated so vividly in German Romanticism.To do so I shall focus on that
supremely Romantic colour, blue.
186
MOOD INDIGO
Gendering of blue
Novalis was probably introduced to colour-systems by his teacher and friend the
geologist A. G. Werner, who like many natural scientists in the eighteenth century
had introduced colour into his own taxonomical scheme (see p. 26 above).? Novalis
was probably also familiar with the early theory of Goethe, whom he had met in
1798.A note on coloured shadows in blue and yellow’ seems to point to the older
poet,"’ and it is likely to have been important for the scheme of polarities, blue-
yellow and red-green, which interested Novalis as it interested so many exponents
of Naturphilosophie in his day.'"? The polarity of colour was one ofits characteristics
which, as we shall see, continued to fascinate German artists and theorists well into
the twentieth century, for it could readily be understood in terms of either a physi-
ological or a psychic dynamism.
The contrasting dynamics of blue and yellow seem hardly to have concerned
Novalis, but in a dream-sequence in a novel by his contemporary Jean-Paul
Richter, which may well have given some stimulus to the introduction of the
central motif in Heinrich von Ofterdingen, the hero 1s sucked like a dewdrop into a
blue flower and lifted up into a lofty room within reach of the mysterious sister of
his own genius-figure. As in Novalis’s novel, the blue and the feminine share an
active power of attraction.’ Goethe was soon to write in his Farbenlehre (“Didactic
Part’, §781):‘As we readily follow an agreeable object that flies from us, so we love
to contemplate blue, not because it advances to us, but because it draws us after it.’
This gendering ofblue was also felt by Runge, who in a diagram of about 1809 90
conceived of the warm, yellow-orange side of the colour-circle as male, and the
cool, blue-violet side as female. Runge may have been responding to the chemical
ideas of Steffens, who in his essay of 1810 argued for red as a sign of the contractive,
oxygenizing effect in metals, and blue of the more expansive effect of hydrogen on
them.'’ Goethe, in a similar vein, included the affinity with acid and affinity with
alkalis among the characteristics of his polar blue and yellow.'® But in a much earlier
statement about the natural meaning of the primary colours, which may be linked
to the first versions of the Times of Day, Runge had characterized blue as emblem-
atic of God the Father and red of God the Son; we saw that in the painted Morning
(small version of 1808), red is clearly linked to the female figure of Aurora as well as 84
to the small baby beneath her. Here Runge may have taken his cue from J. G.
Herder’s aesthetic treatise Kalligone, in which that precocious anthropologist
187
MOOD INDIGO
IDEALES
Liebe
argued, unfortunately without giving details, that because of the colours’ supreme
beauty (after white), ‘several nations’ called blue and red the ‘beautiful colours’,
attributing them to man and woman: ‘firm blue to the man, soft red to the
woman’.'? Although this common belief in the polar structure of colour-space was
to be characteristic of German thought throughout our period, here as usual there
was no consensus about the meaning ofspecific colours.
An anthropology of colour
Herder’s appeal to popular ‘national’ usage proved very congenial to German artists
in the Romantic period, and especially to painters of the figure. The two young
painters Friedrich Overbeck and Franz Pforr, who moved from Vienna to Rome in
1810 to found the Lukasbund, had already shared a belief that the colours of dress
were, and should be, represented in pictures as expressive of character. These notions
would be most appropriate for depicting women, since men’s clothing, they
thought, was largely determined by profession; and yet there was a remarkable uni-
formity in female dress. Black hair, said Pforr, went best with combinations of black
and violet, black and blue, or white and violet; brown hair with green and violet,
white and blue, yellow-green and violet, and so on; blonde hair suited quiet
colours, such as blue and grey, grey and crimson, reddish-brown with a crimson
cast, violet-grey and black. Black hair, he thought, was expressive of a proud and
cool personality or, on the other hand, of cheerfulness and happiness; brown hair of
happiness and good temper, innocent roguishness, naiveté and cheerfulness; blonde
of solitariness, modesty, good-heartedness and calm, more passive than active. Pforr
added that he did not need to spell out the meaning of red hair, ‘with an appropriate
face’, probably an allusion to the legendary red hair of Judas and the Jews."* Yet in
85 Pforr’s Sulamith and Maria of 1811, the allegorical figure of the South, the brown-
haired Sulamith, wears white, green and red, and the blonde northerner Maria
wears a bright red dress with a white apron.'? Overbeck, who dressed his later Italia
91 and Germania (1828) respectively in red, dark blue and white for the dark-haired
Italia, and salmon pink, green, pale blue and yellow (a touch in a lining) for the
188
MOOD INDIGO
Friedrich Overbeck’s Italia and Germania, 1828, an allegory ofthe friendship of southern and northern
Europe in which contrasts of hair-colour match contrasts of dress. (91)
blonde Germania, had argued to his father in 1808 precisely that blonde hair with
grey and crimson was expressive of ‘feminine gentleness and amiability, or rather,
true femininity’.*° The move to Rome may well have worked a powerful change in
the Nazarene’s colour-perceptions. As that veteran grand tourist Goethe wrote in
these years, when he was in touch with if not entirely sympathetically disposed
towards their art: ‘the inhabitants of the south of Europe make use of very brilliant
colours for their dresses. The circumstances oftheir procuring silk stuffs at a cheap
rate is favourable to this propensity. The women, especially, with their bright-
coloured bodices and ribbons, are always in harmony with the scenery, since they
cannot possibly surpass the splendour ofthe sky and landscape.’*!
Perhaps, too, for Pforr and Overbeck this iconography of colour had to yield in
practice to more private aesthetic considerations: Pforr’s detailed account of his
Sulamith and Maria mentioned Maria’s red dress, ‘just as we have so often spoken
about it’, and even then not all his details of the colouring were followed exactly in
the painting.»
189
MOOD INDIGO
190
MOOD INDIGO
IQI
MOOD INDIGO
Munch exhibition in Berlin in 1906, the politician and critic Friedrich Naumann
could appeal quite naturally to the psychologist Wundt for an explanation of the
Norwegian painter’s divided touch.** It was in Wundt’s laboratory that the most
sustained experimentation on the non-associative effects of colour was carried out
in the twenty years up to the First World War. In a study of fourteen young,
professional and mainly German subjects in the early 1890s, Jonas Cohn found a
surprising love of contrasts of highly saturated colours, and he concluded that there
was a common, basic, sensual instinct for strong colour which was only later modi-
fied by culture.*° A later researcher in the same laboratory, F Stefanescu-Goanga,
reinforced Cohn’s conclusions, emphasizing ‘the individual consciousness and
above all individual experience’.*’
Stefanescu-Goanga found that blue was experienced as calming, depressing,
peaceful, quiet and serious, nostalgic (sehnsuchtig), melancholy, cool and calm, or
dreamy. Several of his subjects followed Goethe in feeling that this colour drew
them after it, and others described it as a ‘mysterious’ colour.** All this seemed to
reinforce the attitudes of recent researchers into synaesthesia and chromotherapy,
that colour was primarily a question of immediate feeling rather than of intellectual
judgment, and it was thus of the greatest importance to artists engaged in develop-
ing a non-representational art. As the critic Karl Scheffler wrote in an article which
may have introduced Kandinsky to both synaesthesia and chromotherapy (see
Chapter 21),‘never before was the sense of colour such a matter of nerves’.*”
192
MOOD INDIGO
What links the Blue Rider group most clearly to the Romantic tradition of colour-
theory is the belief in polarity, in contrast, which informs all their thinking, and
which often seems to be related specifically to Goethe. Kandinsky’s table of polarity 92
between blue and yellow is perhaps the most succinct illustration of this, but
Macke, too, in response to a questionnaire from the art magazine Kunst und Kunstler tot
in 1914, also argued that the supremely modern means of pictorial organization was
the strong overall effect created by individual areas of contrast in the painting; and
he cited especially the work of Robert Delaunay.*° In the early years of the century
Goethe’s Farbenlehre underwent a wide-ranging revaluation among German artists,
from the apparently academic circle around the scientist Arnold Brass in Munich to
the Expressionist E. L. Kirchner in Dresden, who was anxious to move on from
Neo-Impressionism.*7
193
MOOD INDIGO
TABLE I.
Warm Cold
I = I contrast
Yellow Blue
2 movements:
1. horizontal
Light Dark
0 = [| contrast
White Black
2 movements:
1. The movement of resistance
Eternal resistance complete lack of
and yet possibili- White Black resistance and no
ty (birth) possibility {death}
Wassily Kandinsky’s table of polarities from On the Spiritual in Art, 1911-12.This table was probably
developed from Goethe’s polarities of yellow and blue in the Theory of Colours, but Kandinsky gives the
opposites a particularly dynamic twist. (92)
It was probably under the stimulus of Goethe that Marc in the winter of 1910-11
87 began to look through a prism at the snowy landscape and his dog Russi, and to
attempt to match on the canvas the brilliance of the coloured fringes he saw at the
junctions oflight and dark. Goethe had described his own experience of brilliant
and delicate-coloured shadows on the snow during a journey in the Harz moun-
tains, although on that occasion he had not used a prism.** Marc told Macke ofthe
‘amazing coloured fringes’ he saw around his dog, a Siberian Shepherd, and of how
he completed the painting as a study of the contrasts between yellow, white and
blue.*?
This fascination with the prism, and enthusiasm for the powerful effects of colour-
contrast it revealed, was shared by a number ofartists and critics close to Herwarth
Walden’s Sturm Gallery in Berlin during and after the war. In 1916 S. Friedlander
(later Friedlander-Mynona) published in the gallery’s journal Der Sturm an article
in which he argued that colour-polarity was Goethe’s distinctive discovery, and in
the following year he amplified this view in a discussion of Goethe’s prismatic
194
MOOD INDIGO
experiments (p. 132 above).°° Arthur Segal, a painter who had exhibited with Der 89
Sturm during the war, began to experiment with Goethe’s prismatic fringes in
paintings of the early 1920s in order to find a way of reconciling the equal demands
of colour and form: ‘The polar interaction of light and darkness’, he wrote, ‘is
manifested in the optical effect ofthings, thus in forms and colours_s!
Goethe's theory was an abiding presence among German modernist painters;
Kandinsky began to engage with it in a more thoroughgoing way as a teacher at the
Bauhaus in the 1920s, and in- Yellow-Red-Blue of 1925 he developed an unusually 88
sophisticated visualization of the creation of red from the augmentation (Steigerung)
of yellow and blue, as described in Goethe’s Farbenlehre.s? Extracts from a later
section of the book which also treats of this process appear among the lecture-notes
for Kandinsky’s Bauhaus courses, but he amplifies them with his own myth of the
sun (yellow) and the moon (blue), which link on the edges of night and day as red
sunrise or sunset.*’ It was perhaps in the context of this new agenda that Kandinsky
reversed the Theosophical and Blue Rider concept of the masculine spirituality of
blue, and suggested again that blue represented the feminine, for in many cultures
the moon was conceived of as female — although not, of course in Germany (der
Mond), so that Kandinsky was drawn to its Latin and feminine title,‘Luna’.*+ At the
Dessau Bauhaus, with its decisively modern and technological orientation, he was
now taking a more detached view of ‘the Theosophists’, and made much more
Wilhelm Ostwald (pp. 257-8), the best-known of German
reference to the ideas of
scientific colour-theorists, to Wundt and to the recent German school of Gestalt
psychology. But in an institution where the systems of Runge and Ostwald were
given equal attention, Kandinsky was also investing the abstract categories of
German Romantic colour with a new vitality.*
195
15 - Chevreul between Classicism
and Romanticism
IVE YEARS BEFORE the death of the French chemist Michel-Eugéne Chevreul
le. the age of one hundred and three, the up-coming Neo-Impressionist Paul
Signac visited him in the company of another painter, Charles Angrand, with the
intention of discussing some problems about the division of light. When he heard
that they were concerned with painting, Chevreul advised them to call on his col-
league at the Institut, Monsieur Ingres, who would be able to tell them all they
needed to know.' This advice has puzzled historians of art, who, following the hints
of the critic Charles Blanc, have generally believed that Chevreul’s influential ideas
on colour were transmitted to French artists in the nineteenth century through the
agency of Ingres’s great rival, Delacroix.This is a view which has something to rec-
ommend it, but I want in this chapter to suggest that the great chemist’s suggestion
was perfectly correct — apart from the fact that Ingres had been dead for eighteen
years — and that it was among painters of a classicizing tendency, such as Ingres, that
we may find the most immediate heirs of Chevreul’s principles.We may well recall,
as Meyer Schapiro noted many years ago, that Chevreul had been appointed to the
Gobelins tapestry works in the 1820s, not simply to regulate the dyes, but also to
banish unforeseen and unwanted colour from the woollen threads and produce
pure blacks by the removal of the subjective effects of simultaneous contrast.* If
Romanticism meant colour, then the mere removal of it could align Chevreul
immediately with the rival school ofthe classicists.
In 1828 Chevreul published his first discussion of colour:‘Memoir on the influ-
ence that two colours may have on each other when they are seen simultaneously’3
in which he announced the laws ofsimultaneous and successive contrast; but it was
largely through the biennial courses of public lectures that he gave at the Gobelins
from this date until the 1850s that his ideas passed into the orbit of painters, who
began to take notice of these ‘laws’ in the 1830s, and to heighten their contrasts by
juxtaposing complementary colours.* A decade later, when Chevreul’s monumen-
tal study, On the Law of Simultaneous Contrast of Colours, was finally published, not
only were his principles taken up in a number of professional journals, such as
L’Artiste, but his lectures were also advertised at the Paris ai exhibition as ‘a
course which all artists may follow with profit’.
Chevreul was increasingly consulted by painters. One was Louis Hersent, a pupil
of the Neo-Classical painter Regnault and a long-time professor at the Ecole des
196
CHEVREUL BETWEEN ROMANTICISM AND CLASSICISM
Beaux-Arts; another was Louis Daguerre, who before turning to photography was
the best-known painter of that popular spectacle, the Diorama, both in France and
in England. Chevreul had been able to show Daguerre how the effects of successive
contrast would enable him to rest his eyes during prolonged work on the large-
scale Diorama, if he turned to look at sheets of paper painted with colours comple-
mentary to those on his canvas.°
Chevreul’s most important contact among painters, however, was certainly Horace
Vernet, who soon became a friend.’ As a specialist in battle-painting,Vernet shared 93
with the chemist a particular interest in military uniforms; Chevreul argued that 94
strong combinations of colours would allow simultaneous contrast to counteract
the effects of fading and wear, and thus prove to be more economical than more
closely-related tones.* But, of course, the development of more effective artillery
and rifles meant that the tradition of hand-to-hand fighting was increasingly irrele-
vant, and camouflage became more important than impressive display. As Chevreul
himself recognized:
If uniforms which present contrasts of colour are advantageous in an econom-
ical point of view, if uniforms of light colours are advantageous when we wish
to impress an enemy by the number of combatants opposed to him, there are
cases where, far from deploying battalions and squadrons, with the intention
197
CHEVREUL BETWEEN ROMANTICISM AND CLASSICISM
In spite ofhis links with the French Romantic school in his youth, Vernet became
an establishment figure, member of the Institut, professor at the Ecole and the
predecessor ofIngres as director of the French Academy in Rome (1829- 34), loaded
with honours both in France and abroad, and perhaps the French painter best
known to the general public of his day. But did Vernet learn something about
colour from the theorist? Not perhaps very much.
Chevreul’s ‘laws’ were promoted largely as a key to colour-harmony ~ the first
English translation of his book was entitled The Principles of Harmony and Contrast of
Colours (1854); and in a subsequent revision Chevreul had hoped to include a
section specifically on aesthetics.’ But Vernet had the reputation of being a poor
harmonizer; as one of his bitterest critics, Théophile Silvestre, put it in 1856:
He lacks character in his drawing and at the same time unity in his composi-
tion, magic in his chiaroscuro, concentration of effect, and harmony of colour.
Particularly in recent years his work has displayed a harsh crudity, and I believe
it was according to the formula of some [paint] merchant from Saint-Germain
that he sang his last clashing scale:
The shrill harmonies of these words will perhaps give you some idea of the
arrangement ofhis hues.'°
for in every instance where painting is an accessory and not a principal feature,
painting in flat tints is in every respect preferable to the other.
(Law, $302)
198
CHEVREUL BETWEEN ROMANTICISM AND CLASSICISM
And he instanced the remote distance of represented objects which would make
the finish of ‘an elaborate picture’ disappear, so that the economy of means of
decorative painting would make it far clearer. Simultaneous contrast was to play a
major role in this style of painting, and in the harmony of contrast, as opposed to
the harmony of close tones, the complementaries provided the best combination of
colours (§237).
Chevreul’s reference to Oriental painting was very much in tune with the inter-
ests of both classicists and Romantics in France from the 1820s onwards;Vernet for
example had a room at the Villa Medici, the seat of the French Academy in Rome,
decorated for himself in the Turkish style while he was director there. Delacroix’s
Algerian Women in their Apartment of 1834, a painting used by the mid-century critic 95
Charles Blanc to illustrate Chevreul’s principles of contrast in its handling of tex-
tiles,"' was matched by Ingres’s Odalisque of 1814 (Louvre) and his Odalisque with a
Slave of 1839-40, and Delacroix remarked to George Sand particularly about the 96
‘flat’ decorative emphasis in Ingres’s painting, complaining:
he puts a bit of red on a cloak, some lilac on a cushion, some green here, some
blue there, a vivid red, a spring green, a sky-blue. He has a taste for dress and a
knowledge of costume. He has interspersed in his coiffures, in his fabrics, in his
ribbons, a lilac of exquisite freshness, coloured borders and the attractiveness
of a thousand pretty ornaments, but they do nothing at all to create colour.”
But for Ingres himself this was a matter of principle; as he wrote:
the essential qualities of colour are...in the brightness and individuality of the
colours of objects. For example, put a beautiful and brilliant white drapery
against an olive-dark body, and above all distinguish a pale blonde colour from a
cold colour, and a transient colour from the colours of figures in their local
tints. This observation was provoked by the chance sight of a brilliant and
beautiful white drapery against the thigh of my Oedipus reflected in a mirror
beside the warm and glowing colour of the flesh."
It is thus no surprise that one of the earliest discussions of Chevreul’s ideas in the
context ofart was that of the decorative painter Clerget, in the Bulletin de l’Ami des
Arts in 1844; nor that it was a pupil of Ingres also concerned with applied art, Jules-
Claude Ziegler, who six years later published the first extended, if not entirely
favourable account of Chevreul’s principles in Etudes Céramiques, perhaps the earli-
est treatment in a French book."
There is a certain irony in Charles Blanc’s determination to treat Delacroix’s
Algerian Women as if it were based on complementary contrasts, since there are very
few Chevreulian complementaries in this painting, and the painter’s theoretical
interests at this time seem to have been informed rather by a colleague, the painter
When Blanc met Delacroix, perhaps for
and colour-technologistJ. F L. Mérimée.'’
the first time, round 1850, the painter was certainly very interested in Chevreul’s
ideas and hoped to visit the chemist, but was prevented from doing so by a throat
infection. It was about this time that Delacroix must have acquired a notebook
summarizing a course of lectures given by Chevreul during the winter of 1847-8
199
CHEVREUL BETWEEN ROMANTICISM AND CLASSICISM
Shades ofgrey
Thus artists learned much from Chevreul during his own lifetime; but it seems to
have been largely for the purposes ofstructuring their paintings, rather than for the
creation of colour-harmonies, or to understand more clearly the manifestations of
colour in nature. French painters looked to Chevreul for essentially formalist reasons,
and formalism was already a major concern of academic art. It will be recalled that
at the beginning of his work on colour, Chevreul had been concerned to remove all
unforeseen colours from the Gobelins tapestries and, like a true classicist, he loved
greys, especially in female dress.'* For, as he had established in his On the Law of
Simultaneous Contrast of Colours, it was contrasts ofvalue, not ofhue, that offered the
most powerful effects of simultaneous contrast (§339). Both the brilliant lithogra-
pher Delacroix and the grisaille-painter Ingres would probably have agreed with
him on this; and among artists of the next generation, the etcher and former pupil
of Ingres, Felix Bracquemond, an associate of the Impressionists as well as an orien-
talizing designer, made a similar point in his Du Dessin et de la Couleur of 188s,
where he argued that even Chevreul had been rather casual about establishing a
comprehensive grey-scale.'? In the notes which Georges Seurat made from
Chevreul’s treatise it is clear that he was also much impressed by the idea of the
dominant role of black and white; and all Seurat’s major compositions until 1890
are based on an underlying tonal structure (see the following chapter). The notori-
ous greying, the suppression of colour, for which so many artists and critics attacked
Seurat’s paintings, may well turn out to be the most sincere of the tributes paid by
nineteenth-century painters to the work of Chevreul.?°
The bright military uniforms ofthe French battle-painter Horace Vernet (1824). Vernet’s
who
colourful painting links his interests to those of his friend, the chemist Michel-Eugéne Chevreul,
reason that
advocated the use of strong complementary colours for military wear for the very practical
they would offset the effects of fading. (94)
Chevreul and contrast
iS) oO we)
Indefinable colour
With fluid, shimmering, subtly dissolving areas of pinks, blues, greens and oranges, Georges Seurat’s
Evening, Honfleur of 1886 gives a particularly vivid sense of the shifting colours of nature — indefinable,
and hence resistant to analysis. (97)
Black is offered as a subject in this canvas (right) more radically than in any other work by Matisse.
French Window — Collioure (1914) relates closely to Manet’s The Balcony (20). The window, opening
not out on to a landscape, but in to a dark room, presents a quality of luminous blackness as the
main theme of the painting. It was first exhibited in 1966, in the United States. (98)
04
The theoretically oriented artist Louis Hayet devised ten different colour-circles incorporating
the newest conceptions of complementarity, such as Helmholtz’s pair of yellow and blue that
mix to white.One (above) he sent to Pissarro, another to the younger painter Seurat, whom he
met in 1885. The circles’ very fine divisions made them frustratingly impractical for artists.(99)
The rainbow-like gradations of M.-E. Chevreul’s 1864 colour-circle (below) suggest how hard
it was for Hayet to define the edges of his many segments in colour-space. (100)
Shaping colour
Stimulated by Delaunay’s Wind vs (p. 255-6), in 1912 August Macke adopted a similar technique
for Large, Bright Shop Window. Transpare ncy is rendered with facetted planes of colour, lustre with
dots of the complementaries. (I0T)
Gavlemens of the I ‘ant a’gon fo ask you to give even a moments consideration
to the evidence _— before you If ‘aint worth shucks, It dont count , and even if it did , it dont proveas my
client werent there. No gentlemen , You can't convict even a white man on such evidence much lessa mgger.
A rare vizualization ofthe colours of spoken words: ‘Lawyer Spoke Stith’s address to the jury’, 1900, from The Music of
Color and the Number Seven by the American architect and designer E. J. Lind. (102)
Ree STUDIES of Seurat have usually focused on his subject matter, but there
can be little doubt that the painter himself nailed his flag firmly to the mast of
technical innovatio n. as he wrote to his friend, the critic Félix Fénéon,
‘Téchnique’,
was ‘the soul and the body of the art’;' and he complained that it was a mistake to
see poetry in his work, which was simply a matter of method.’ Seurat’s working
methods have been treated in some detail, and the full-length monograph by W. I.
Homer, Seurat and the Science of Painting, which has been reprinted several times
since it was first published in 1964, has seemed to most commentators to be exhaus-
tive,’ which is one reason, perhaps, why the subject now attracts relatively little
attention. In his book Homer wrote of La Grande Jatte, the key painting in the 104
development of Neo-Impressionism:
First, [Seurat] discovered and applied physical laws governing the behaviour of
light and color in nature, rather than merely relying on his sensations; by doing
so, he was literally able to make his picture duplicate nature’s mode of opera-
tion, thus obtaining a degree of luminosity far greater than that achieved by the
Impressionists. Second, Seurat successfully integrated a carefully thought-out,
wide-range value-scheme with a color system that could accurately represent
nature’s hues and values. In other words, he united the traditional elements of
chiaroscuro, both in modeling and pictorial planning, with colors that, like
those of the Impressionists, were extremely accurate in representing the actual
hues present in the subject — local colors, the tone of the illuminating light, and
diverse reflections. Third, he harmonized the colors of La Grande Jatte accord-
ing to the principles of contrast and analogy drawn largely from the writings
of Chevreul and Rood, rather than relying on instinct or rule of thumb.+
This thesis, which is essentially the theme of Homer’s book as a whole, rests on a
number of misunderstandings of Seurat’s ideas and practice; and these have tended
to suggest that the painter’s approach to ‘scientific’ theory was unproblematic. Even
Meyer Schapiro, whose healthy scepticism about the scientific credentials of Neo-
Impressionism has been too little heeded by later commentators, was content to
argue that they simply do not matter for the aesthetic understanding of Seurat’s art:
‘Too much has been written, and often incorrectly, about the scientific nature of
the dots. The question whether they make a picture more or less luminous hardly
matters. A painting can be luminous and artistically dull, or low-keyed in color
and radiant to the mind’ Indeed it can; but if Seurat, who identified himself as
an ‘impressioniste-luministe’,° adopted the dotted technique in the expectation of
209
THE TECHNIQUE OF SEURAT — A REAPPRAISAL
Seurat’s reading
It is not at all surprising that Homer should have developed the thesis implicit in
the statement quoted above, for it derives essentially from the criticism of Fénéon,
which, in its turn, had received the sanction of Seurat himself.” Fénéon’s first and
most substantial analysis of the painter’s work appeared in La Vogue for June 1886:
If you consider a few square inches of uniform tone in Monsieur Seurat’s Grande
Jatte, you will find on each inch ofits surface, in a whirling host oftiny spots, all
the elements which make up the tone.Take this grass plot in the shadow: most
of the strokes render the local value of the grass; others, orange-tinted and
thinly scattered, express the scarcely felt action of the sun; bits of purple intro-
duce the complement to green; a cyanic blue, provoked by the proximity of a
plot of grass in the sunlight, accumulates its siftings towards the line of demar-
cation, and beyond that point progressively rarifies them. Only two elements
come together to produce the grass in the sun; green and orange-tinted light,
any interaction being impossible under the furious beating of the sun’s rays... *
This formulation was very similar to Seurat’s own summary characterization of his
technique in a letter to the journalist Maurice Beaubourg of 28 August 1890:
The means of expression is the optical mixture of tonal values and colors
(both local color and the color ofthe light source, be it sun, oil lamps, gas, etc.),
that is to say, the optical mixture of lights and their reactions (shadows) in
accordance with the laws ofcontrast, gradation, and irradiation.®
Yet there are several anomalies in these accounts. One is the notion of‘local’ colour
(i.e., the colour conceived as a constant attribute ofthe object) in a context so evi-
dently flooded with ‘the furious beating of the sun’s rays’, for there is, strictly speak-
ing, no colour except that inherent in the rays of light reflected back into the eyes of
the spectator. Fénéon’s remarks have been appropriately traced back to a passage in
the American physicist Ogden Rood’s Modern Chromatics, a work he cites in his
review of 1886, and which Seurat implies he had himself seen as early as 1881, the
year of the French translation.'° Rood, however, was considering a laboratory situa-
tion in which surfaces are lit simultaneously by white and coloured light; he was
210
THE TECHNIQUE OF SEURAT — A REAPPRAISAL
Georges Seurat, Sunday Afternoon on the Island of La Grande Jatte, 1884-6. The pointillist technique is
here applied to a major subject for the first time, although not introduced until the later stages of the
execution, in 1886. (104)
careful to explain that the ‘natural’ colour of surfaces, which, he says, artists call ‘local
colour’, is their colour in white light, and he allows his objects no inherent colour,
irrespective of their lighting.”
Seurat’s endorsement of the conventional notion of local colour is the more
surprising in that, in his letter of 1890 to Fénéon, he also listed in his early reading
Charles Blanc’s essay on Delacroix of 1864.'* Blanc had begun his account by recall-
ing a conversation among Delacroix, the painter Chenavard and himself, in the
course of which the aged master had asserted that the great colourists had always
perceived the essential relativity of colour: they had never sought to establish ‘le ton
local’, but had always worked through the manipulation of optical contrasts. It was
this very passage in Blanc which, also in the early 1880s, had especially intrigued
and puzzled van Gogh, and had led him at Neunen specifically to reject the idea of
‘local colour’ with which he had been brought up." Not so Seurat, and his practical
exemplification of the idea is well illustrated in La Grande Jatte, where, as Fénéon 104
observed, the more transient effects of light are scattered over much more broadly
and solidly established areas of ‘local’ tone and hue. But this was a procedure that he
progressively eliminated in favour of a more uniform overall structure of dots,
expressive entirely of the action of light.
THE TECHNIQUE OF SEURAT — A REAPPRAISAL
212
THE TECHNIQUE OF SEURAT — A REAPPRAISAL
213
THE TECHNIQUE OF SEURAT — A REAPPRAISAL
difficulty fitting his own sexpartite Chevreulian scheme (also discussed by Henry in
this book) into this format, hence the indecision about the position of yellow.”
Robert Herbert has pointed out to me the co-existence of Chevreul’s and
Helmholtz’ pairs in the painted complementary frame of the small ensemble study
of Les Poseuses in the Berggruen Collection;** but the Chevreulian set was what
Seurat recalled in his unpublished letter to Beaubourg (cited p. 210 above), as well as
in his published statement to Jules Christophe, as late as 1890.*°
I have suggested that one ofthe great virtues of Rood’s handbook was its practi-
cality: it discussed colour-effects not simply in terms of abstract hues, but also in
terms of pigments available to artists. Homer’s important article on a (late?) palette
in the Nachlass does not go into details about the pigments on it,*° but although
Seurat’s arrangement of hues does not seem to be quite that recalled by Signac for
his own practice after 1883, it is reasonable to assume that their pigments were very
similar, and that Seurat’s were arranged, from the thumbhole, in this order:
cadmium yellow, orange(?), orange(?), vermilion, cobalt violet, artificial ultrama-
rine, cerulean or cobalt blue, viridian (emerald) green, chrome green.*’ This palette
was described by Fénéon as organized along prismatic lines, but it is not strictly the
case, and the arrangement can be contrasted with the truly spectral palette pub-
lished in these years by the teacher of technique at the Ecole des Beaux-Arts, the
genre-painter J.-G.Vibert, in his Science of Painting.** What seems chiefly to concern
Seurat is to reconcile as far as possible the traditional, tonally arranged academic
palette, running from white to black through yellow, red, and blue, with the order of
hues in the solar spectrum; and this is of some importance for the assessment of the
role of tonal values in Seurat’s painting.
Rood, whose experiments with disc-mixtures were conducted in watercolours,
listed a palette of gamboge, Indian yellow, chrome yellow, vermilion, red lead,
carmine, Hoffmann’s violet, cobalt blue, cyan blue, Prussian blue, and emerald
green, many of which had to be mixed on the palette to achieve the appropriate
effect on the discs.’ It is a palette similar in character to the one reconstructed for
Seurat above, and although it is more traditional than that of the French painter, it
also excludes earth-colours.
That Seurat continued to use earths at least until 188 4°
suggests either that he had not read (or had not understood) Rood by that date, or
that he was not yet interested in the method of optical mixing for which Rood’s
suggestions about pigments would have been especially helpful. The emergence of
a regularly dotted technique only in the later stages of painting La Grande Jatte
suggests that the latter hypothesis is the case.
Painterly experiment
Seurat styled his new method of working ‘peinture optique’>' It was based on a
specific philosophy of perception; and it might well be that the painter’s evident
disregard of current theory had no damaging consequences for his work, which
could have started with a few simple notions, for example of optical mixture, and
then developed under the independent momentum of his practice. He did, after all,
214
THE TECHNIQUE OF SEURAT — A REAPPRAISAL
claim that he had ‘discovered scientifically the law of pictorial colour... with the
experience of art’.**It is one of the strengths of Homer’s study that he shows how
Seurat’s technical strategies were modified with each of the major compositions of
the 1880s as a result of a continuous programme of experimentation. Here I shall
look at three aspects of the method that might be expected to depend essentially on
this programme: viewing distance, the relationship of contrasts to mixtures in the
structure of the surface, and the relationship of hues to values.
Homer, following Fénéon, has opted for a relatively fixed viewing distance, at the
point where the eye has difficulty in resolving the discrete marks into a single tone,
and in the effort to do so continually changes its focus, producing that rich shim-
mering effect which Rood characterized as ‘lustre’.33Homer cites Pissarro’s dictum,
that a picture should be seen at a distance ‘which allows its colors to blend’, which
that painter thought was usually three times the diagonal of the canvas.* Signac,
too, seems to have felt that the colours should fuse, and sought to devise a technique
of blending the brushstrokes where this did not happen at the appropriate dis-
tance.** But what is very striking in La Grande Jatte and Les Poseuses, as well as in 104, 29
several late works like La Poudreuse in London, is the great variety in size and shape
of Seurat’s brushstrokes; and we know from Signac that at least the two earlier
pictures were painted in a studio too confined to allow the artist to stand back very
far, with the result that he found the dots too small for the large size of the canvas.3°
Seurat must clearly have had his reasons for the variety in his touch, and in some
cases they are very obvious: sometimes, for example, he wanted to firm up the
contours of his shapes by making the dots along them much smaller than average,
and hence fusible by the spectator closer to the surface of the picture.*” But this
cannot be the only reason.
In his classic study of the technique of Impressionism,J. Carson Webster showed
that optical mixtures in La Grande Jatte seem in some cases to offer no advantages
over ordinary palette-mixtures;** and this can be demonstrated even more effec-
tively in the case of the recently cleaned Bathers at Asniéres,a pre-Divisionist work of 107
1883-4 that received a few local revisions in the later technique in 1887. The
retouchings in bright blue and orange on the back of the central bather fuse at a
distance to a warm bluish-pink, which is very close to the original palette-mixed
shadows under his arm. It seems clear that Seurat was not so much interested in the
optically-mixed tone as in the lively texture created by the separated dots them-
selves. In the area around the hat on the grass in this picture, the darkened yellow
revisions — due, according to Signac, to inferior paints and already apparent very
soon after Seurat’s death*? — can still be seen clearly at the far end of the gallery, long
after the other retouchings have disappeared.
Seurat must have realized after only a few experiments with optical mixture that
there is, indeed, no constant viewing-distance for fusing the various separate colours.
In particular, he must have noticed that contrasting values resist fusion far longer
than even complementary hues,*° and this is surely of the greatest consequence
to our understanding of his use of values in the structure of his major paintings.
Yet there is no indication in Seurat’s work that he sought to vary the size of dot for
specific hues, to achieve fusion at a constant distance, and it is difficult to resist the
215
THE TECHNIQUE OF SEURAT —A REAPPRAISAL
Georges Seurat, Bathers at Asniéres, 1883-4. That Seurat repainted only parts of his Bathers in a dotted
technique in 1887 suggests that even at this late date he did not insist upon a unified surface nor a fixed
viewing distance. (107)
conclusion that, as Meyer Schapiro noticed long ago, the dotting has itself an impor-
tant aesthetic, and even a political resonance, in that it draws attention to its own
mode of operation, and makes itself accessible to every spectator.*'
Seurat’s major compositions, up to Le Cirque of 1890, rest on a magnificent series
108, II] of charcoal and conté drawings, and it was the secure knowledge of tonal structure
that these studies provided that made the painter feel free to ignore some of the
more problematic aspects of the theory of colour. In an article on Signac, Fénéon
noted that contrasts of value ‘regulate’ contrasts of hue;** and Seurat himself copied
from Chevreul a passage that includes substantially the same point:‘To put a dark
colour near a different but lighter colour is to heighten the tone ofthe first and to
lower that of the second, independently of the modification resulting from the
mixture of the complementaries.’’ As Seurat told his fellow Neo-Impressionist H.
E. Cross, the ‘ensemble’ first presented itselfto his imagination ‘by the masses, and
by the interplay of values’;** and Signac told Daniel Catton Rich that even during
the course of working on the final canvas of La Grande Jatte the painter would fix
the large conté studies of figures against the appropriate part of the picture to assess
the effect.*5
216
THE TECHNIQUE OF SEURAT — A REAPPRAISAL
It was probably this tonal anchor that allowed Seurat to overcome the contradic-
tions inherent in a method that sought to combine optical mixture which creates
soft contours with complementary contrast which requires hard ones.
As Signac wrote in his attack on mindless ‘pointillism’ in his pamphlet From
Delacroix to Neo-Impressionism:
The role of dotting [Pointillage] is more humble: it simply makes the surface of
the paintings more lively, but it does not guarantee luminosity, intensity of colour,
or harmony. For the complementary colours, which are allies and enhance
each other when juxtaposed, are enemies and destroy each other if mixed, even
optically.A red and a green surface, ifjuxtaposed, enliven each other, but red dots
mingled with green dots make an aggregation which is grey and colourless.*°
It was probably for this reason, too, that Seurat, finding that his optical mixtures
would not provide surfaces so intensely coloured that they could, when juxtaposed,
create of their own accord the contrast effects described by Chevreul, painted these
effects into his pictures, darkening edges where they met the light, and lightening 27-8
them where they met the dark, as well as tingeing the coloured boundaries with
their complementaries.*’ His ‘optical painting’, deprived of the powers of nature
itself, could be truly optical only in one dimension.
Georges Seurat, The Nurse, 1884. The large number of conté crayon drawings prepared for each of
Seurat’s major compositions — here for La Grande Jatte — show how firmly the paintings were based on
a tonal rather than chromatic structure. (108)
iy
THE TECHNIQUE OF SEURAT — A REAPPRAISAL
Seurat emerges as a painter who, unlike some ofthe critics of Impressionism such as
Duranty and Huysmans, was not really abreast of the colour-science of his period,
even though it had been specifically popularized for the use of artists.‘* But his
painterly sensitivity and technical ingenuity nevertheless enabled him to extract
from the theoretical literature a number of simple concepts and put them to work
in the formation ofa new style, avoiding many of the pitfalls that situations of such
enormous complexity were bound to present. What is most surprising is that
Fénéon’s ill-informed resumé of some of the principles he found in Rood’s text-
book should for so long have passed muster, not simply with painters like Signac or
Pissarro, to whom, when Seurat himself was not forthcoming, he turned for the
checking ofhis texts,” but also with a polymath trained in the natural sciences like
Charles Henry.*° Perhaps the separation ofthe spheres ofart and science at this time
was rather more complete than we have been led to expect.
What, then, was Seurat after in his theoretical reading, and in particular, why did
he remain attached to the superannuated Chevreul in the face of the more recent
work of Helmholtz, which was readily available to him in Rood and in many other
French sources? It was I think chiefly because ofhis overriding preoccupation with
harmony:‘Art is Harmony, as he put it at the head ofhis statement in the 1890 letter
to Beaubourg; and Chevreul had far more, and far simpler things to say about
harmony than any of his successors. Most important, Chevreul had equated the
maximal contrast of the complementaries with maximum harmony.*' Rood, in the
chapter of his treatise on “Combinations of colors in pairs and triads’, in which he
chiefly discussed harmony, was content essentially to follow Chevreul; but it is clear
that his own preferences as a painter and a theorist were rather for ‘the small inter-
val’ (that is, juxtapositions of colours close to each other on the circle) than for
maximal contrasts.** Seurat’s aesthetic credo of 1890, although it begins by stating
that harmony is the analogy of similar elements as well as of opposites, gives no
further attention to the former; and it has frequently been observed that his style of
Neo-Impressionism differs from that of, say, Signac or Pissarro precisely in a liking
for sharp contrasts, especially in the period 1886-7.
Can Seurat’s technique, therefore, be understood as ‘scientific’, and if so, in what
sense? I think it can, and most of all in its experimentalism, which provided an
unusually precise focus for the assessment of visual effects, and allowed Seurat, as
well as his many successors in the years up to the First World War, to test the effec-
tiveness of their methods, and, of course, ultimately to reject them. Seurat’s pro-
gramme of experimentation is also seen in a negative light in his obsessive concern
with the chronology of his researches, and in his wish, expressed in his letter to
Fénéon ofJune 1890, to set the record of his own priority straight.53 The idea of
painting as a progressive series ofvisual discoveries is, of course, as old as art histori-
ography itself, but with Seurat it took on a particular urgency, and has become part
of the mythology ofspecifically modernist art.
218
17 - Seurat’s Silence
Helmholtzian chromatics
The key theorist of the period was the German physicist and physiologist Hermann
yon Helmholtz, who in the 1850s and 1860s had effectively displaced the French
chemist Chevreul as the leading scientific interpreter of colour for painters. Although
the distinction between additive light- and subtractive pigment-mixture had been
explored by a number of scientists earlier in the century, it was Helmholtz who
made it widely known. His fundamental article on colour-mixing had been pub-
lished in Germany in 1852, and was almost immediately translated into French.’
In it, Helmholtz showed that the mixture of lights yielded only two complemen-
tary colours (i.e. colours mixing to white), spectral yellow and indigo, which in
219
SEURATS SILENCE
Rouge. Pourpre. |Rose foncé. Rose Blanc. Jaune Jaune d’or. Orangé.
blanchatre blanchatre.
Bleu Bleuindigo
cyanigue.
Hermann von Helmholtz’s table of colour-mixtures, based on experiments with spinning discs — the
first sign that painters’ traditional assumptions about the mechanics of mixture were no longer valid.
Colours are given along the top and left, their product at the intersection. The table was reproduced
in a number of French artists’ handbooks of the 1860s and 1870s. (109)
220
SEURAT’S SILENCE
BLEU D’|OUTREMER
Helmholtz’s complementaries in August Laugel’s colour-circle, from L’Optique et les Arts, 1869.
Laugel’s was perhaps the first attempt, in a painters’ handbook, to incorporate the Helmholtzian
complementaries in a traditional format. But he warned that artists might find them too nuanced
to remember. (110)
it is difficult for the artist to be taught the theoretical science he needs, and
even more difficult for him to learn it. Leonardo da Vinci was thoroughly
familiar with all the knowledge of his day; he knew geometry, mechanics,
physics, physiology, anatomy, all that was known of them in his time. That is
impossible now because of the developments which all the sciences have
undergone.*
One of the phenomena which Helmholtz cited in this instance was irradiation, by
the action of which the colour ofa bright object spread to the surrounding space in
the visual field; and this was taken up in a series of articles on The Phenomena of
Vision (1880) by the Swiss aesthetician David Sutter, which Seurat certainly read."°
It is particularly in the cunningly managed contrasts of Seurat’s conté crayon draw- ITI
ings that we sense a familiarity with these scientific arguments.
SEURAT’S SILENCE
Georges Seurat, Seated Nude Boy, 1883, a conté crayon study for Bathers (107), illustrating Helmholtz’s
dictum that ‘the impression which objects give’ must be rendered by ‘the contrasts they produce’. (111)
Whether or not Seurat knew much of Briicke’s and Helmholtz’s ideas, he cer-
tainly knew Helmholtz’s name,"' and could have read about some of his optical
experiments in Théorie Scientifique des Couleurs of 1881 (the French version of
Modern Chromatics by Ogden Rood of Columbia College, New York), which we
i) i)
SEURATS SILENCE
know the painter consulted."? But a rather sceptical attitude to the applicability
of the most up-to-date theory might well have been fostered in Seurat by his
contact with the two most theoretically oriented of the Neo-Impressionists, Albert
Dubois-Pillet and Louis Hayet.
Louis Hayet, Banks of the Oise, 1888. Hayet, the most theoretically oriented of the Neo-Impressionists,
used soft optical mixtures and attacked Seurat for his crude contrasts. (112)
pure scarlet, it is sort of brick-red or a muted scarlet? Seurat represents that sort
of colour by scarlet desaturated with the help of its complementary. In the
pluralist mode, on the other hand, it could be obtained by the optical mixture of
various oranges, of various carmines, of various violets; there are nuances which
have still to be precisely established. It is easy to understand that the pluralist
mode will give more flexible and harmonious hues because it offers a larger
choice of forms of expression. It is immediately apparent that we need a colour-
99 circle to attain this; and it was that which, later on,I set out to construct."
Hayet also claimed to have discussed these ideas with Seurat and Pissarro in 1887;
and he went so far as to propose that the Neo-Impressionists should set up what
he called ‘an Institute for experimental research into the laws of optics as they relate
to painting’, a proposal remarkably close to one mooted forty years later by the
Russian Suprematist Malevich, and again with pointillism in mind.'? Hayet com-
plained that on this occasion he had met with a rebuff, since the group thought that
their theories stood in no need of improvement.
Whatever credence we may give to Hayet’s recollections, written down a quarter
of a century after the event, it seems clear that he was an obsessive who was likely
iS)
SEURAT S SILENCE
sooner or later to become a bore. Even Camille Pissarro, the least contentious ofall
the members of the Neo-Impressionist group, when Hayet criticized the work of
his son, Lucien, could not refrain from complaining about Hayet’s scathing attitude
to the world, and also about his superficiality: ‘in spite of all his grand airs, Hayet
only understands the surface of things’.*°
It is also clear that Seurat, for his part, was a highly experimental artist who mod-
ified his methods from picture to picture. But it is one thing to experiment and
quite another to be able to give a coherent account of the underlying principles of
this experimentation. Seurat’s silence reminds us of Pissarro’s reaction to the critic
Fénéon’s constant requests for more technical information. In a letter of February
1889 in response to the critic’s queries about his own conception ofpassage, or tonal
liaison, Pissarro wrote:
gas
SEURATS SILENCE
Indefinable colour
97 In a letter to Signac from Honfleur in June 1886 Seurat spoke of the sea as of ‘an
almost indefinable grey’.*° We too would, I think, be hard put to find colour-terms
for the subtly dissolving areas of pinks, blues, greens and oranges which are, miracu-
lously, common to Seurat’s marines and his figure-subjects at this time. Here surely
is a democracy ofstyle. But in Seurat’s day the language of colour was no less con-
tentious an issue than its physics. Synthetic dyes and their marketing had led to a
plethora of fashionable terms which could only confuse.Vibert had his Chevreul in
The Science of Painting tell the young artist that his numbered colour-system had
enabled him to replace uncertain and ephemeral terms such as ‘dove-grey’, ‘dead
226
SEURAT’S SILENCE
227
18 - Matisse’s Black Light
N THE THIRTEENTH number of the arts review Verve (1045), Which its editor, Matisse’s
friend Tériade, devoted to the painter's recent work under the title De la Couleur,
the elderly artist gave a new twist to his life-long preoccupation with art as process
by setting beside each of the sixteen colour-reproductions a diagram of the precise
palette he had used for the painting, even to the extent of giving, in some cases, the
name of the colour-supplier, Lefranc.' These ‘palettes’ were surely made to satisfy
a public curiosity, rather than as an aide-memoire for the artist himself and one of
the colours listed on them most intriguingly is ‘black’. Thus the door of La Porte
Noire of 1942 was painted with ‘pure Prussian blue’ (blew de prusse pur), but the
darkest blues in Le Tabac Royal of 1943 were made with ‘pure black on blue’ (noir pur
sur bleu). The background darks of La Robe Jaune et la Robe Ecossaise (Les Deux Amies)
I14 of 1941 were ‘black on red’; and the black of Danseuse, fond noir fauteille rocaille of
1942 was specified as ‘ivory black’ (noir d'ivoire). Other blacks in the series were
simply described as noir, but in a striking paradox, the grey dress in L’Idole of 1942 is
characterized as ‘black white’ (blanc noir), An even greater paradox, perhaps, is the
original stencilled print of 1943 which served as the title-page to the album, where,
above the title De la Couleur initialled by Matisse, and above two landscape-like
strips ofyellow and brown, rises a multi-rayed sun which is entirely black.
On Colour included a short untitled essay by Matisse on the relationships of
modern painters to tradition, which barely mentions colour, It has been suggested
T400-— 57. 8
that, as Matisse wrote to Tériade in 1944, he was too exhausted to write on a subject
which ‘disgusted’ him. But a year after the Verve article, Matisse wrote in another
review a short note on black as a colour in its own right in which he appealed to the
example ofJapanese prints, of Manet, and of a painting of his own, The Moroccans, 1 ef
painted more than thirty years earlier.‘
A remark in a treatise on colour by the nineteenth-century Japanese draughts-
man, painter and printmaker Hokusai — which could well have been familiar to
Matisse, since it had been published in a French translation in an 1895 article on
Hokusai’s technical treatises — also listed a whole range ofblacks:
There is a black which is old and a black which is fresh. Lustrous [brillant] black
and matt black, black in sunlight and black in shadow. For the old black one
must use an admixture of blue, for the matt black an admixture of white; for
the lustrous black gum [colle] must be added. Black in sunlight must have grey
reflections.>
i)
MATISSE’S BLACK LIGHT
Edouard Manet, Portrait of Zacharie Astruc, 1866. Matisse particularly admired this painting for its
‘luminous black’. (116)
Here, with the addition ofa highly reflective medium, black may have lustre or bril-
lance; but it was in modern French painting that Matisse detected that even matt
black, as in his black sun in Verve, was not simply used as a colour, but specifically as
a colour oflight.
Matisse’s Manet
In his note on black as a colour, Matisse mentioned two Manets, Breakfast in the
Studio of 1868, in which the velvet jacket of the young boy in the centre (Leon
Leenhoft) was of a ‘frank and luminous black’ (un noir franc et lumineux), and the
116 Portrait of Zacharie Astruc of 1866, where the black-velvet suit worn by Astruc had
the same luminous quality. The portrait was perhaps the more significant picture for
Matisse, not simply because Manet showed Astruc as a connoisseur of the Japanese
prints to which Matisse referred later in his note, and which appear as an album on
MATISSE’S BLACK LIGHT
the writer's table, but also because Manet had divided his composition boldly into
two tonal areas, light on the left, dark on the right, and furnished the right-hand
portion with a whole gamut ofblacks. The black-haired Astruc in his black suit and
black silk cravat is set against a flat black ground. It was relatively simple to argue for
the luminosity of a lustrous material such as velvet, especially when it clothed a
three-dimensional form, but to set black against black required extraordinary per-
ceptual virtuosity, especially in the handling of auniform background which, from
the 1910s, became a special area of experiment for Matisse, and conspicuously in
the great Moroccans of 1915-16. II7
Matisse may have been able to examine both the Portrait ofAstruc and Breakfast in
the Studio in the gallery of the Impressionist dealer Durand-Ruel in the late 1890s,
before they were sold on;° he was himself introduced to Durand-Ruel about this
time by his friend Simon Bussy.? But in an interview with André Marchand in
1947, Matisse stated that it had been the veteran Impressionist Camille Pissarro who
had observed to him one day that Manet ‘made light with black’.* Matisse had also
been introduced to Pissarro by Bussy in the spring of 1897, and he went with the
old painter to see the newly displayed Caillebotte Bequest of Impressionist works at
the Luxembourg Museum soon after the exhibition opened that year. It is tempting
to think that the remark about Manet’s black was made on that occasion, and that it
Henri Matisse’s The Moroccans, 1915-16, where the praying figures are set against a flat black
background. (117)
MATISSE’S BLACK LIGHT
was linked to Pissarro’s observation on Matisse’s major painting of that same year,
The Dinner Table, that ‘it is impossible to create light with white’.? For the more
important of the two Manets in the Bequest was The Balcony (1868-9), which sets
the landscape-painter Antoine Guillemet, in a black coat, against the deep luminous
darkness of aroom in Manet’s studio on the rue Guyot in Paris, in which can just be
discerned the figure of the youth, Leon Leenhoff, who also posed for the Breakfast.'°
The austere, symmetrical format of a dark space between shutters recalls one of
Matisse’s first paintings in the period when he first became so pre-occupied with
98 black: the large French Window — Collioure (1914), in which it is still just possible to
detect a balcony grille and the shapes of landscape or figure, which were then
blacked-out in such an unrelenting way.'! When this painting was exhibited for the
first time, in the United States in 1966, that modern American master of black,Ad
Reinhardt, identified it as one of the most significant European paintings of 1914."*
In its original form the French Window had reversed Manet’s viewpoint to present,
albeit in an unprecedentedly reduced format, the motif which had occupied
Matisse for a number ofyears, that of awindow opening on to landscape or sea. In
reverting to Manet’s own subject of an opening into a dark room, Matisse seems to
be presenting a quality of luminous blackness as the main subject of the painting. I
say ‘seems’, because the lack of a signature and date has already suggested that
Matisse regarded the work as unfinished; but in a number of signed and dated
paintings of the following years, such as The Moroccans, black fulfills no less signifi-
cant a role, and there is good reason to believe that in them Matisse saw himself as
striking out in an important new and experimental direction.
Half a scientist
When in the 1940s Matisse reconstructed the outline of his ‘black’ period during
the First World War, he dated his discovery of black light, not from the French
Window of 1914, and still less from the highly original series of black-ground
monotypes which he began in the winter of that year,"? but rather from a smaller
118 painting of a year or so later, the Gourds, of which Matisse claimed, in an answer to a
questionnaire sent to him by Alfred Barr in 1945:‘in this work I began to use pure
black as a colour oflight and not as a colour of darkness’.'t Gourds were also the
subject of ablack-ground monotype in 1916, but there the white-line image was
presented three-dimensionally in a sharply receding space. In the painting all the
objects are seen flattened against a two-dimensional ground which is bisected
emphatically into areas of black and grey-blue.
In a letter of late 1914 Matisse had told his close friend the painter Charles
Camoin how he had borrowed from Félix Fénéon, now of the Bernheim-Jeune
Gallery, two small Seurat panels, one of them highly coloured, which set him
thinking about Seurat’s composition in relation to that of Delacroix’s mural of
Jacob Wrestling with the Angel in the church of Saint-Sulpice in Paris. The Delacroix
was rather cobbled-together, whereas Seurat had organized his material ‘more
scientifically’,
MATISSE’S BLACK LIGHT
In Gourds of 1915-16 Matisse lays out his objects like a set ofscientific specimens, flat against a black
and grey-blue ground. It was in this work, he wrote, that he ‘began to use pure black as a colour of
light and not as a colour of darkness’. (118)
offering our eyes objects constructed by scientific means, rather than with the
images [signes] which arise from feeling. This lends his works a positive quality,
a rather inert stability arising from his composition, which is not the result ofa
mental act [une creation d’esprit], but of a juxtaposition ofobjects."
This sounds remarkably like the method of Gourds, of which Matisse also said to
Barr in 1945 that it was ‘a composition of objects which do not touch — but which
all the same participate in the same intimite’.
But Fénéon also owned a number of strikingly flat and sparsely constructed
black conté crayon drawings by Seurat, including The Balcony (1883-4), The Gateway 119
(1882-4), and probably The Nurse (1884), whose radically stylized back seems to be 108
behind both the right-hand figure in The Moroccans and the third of the series of 117
Backs sculpted by Matisse in 1916."°
33
MATISSE S$ BLACK LIGHT
Modern commentators have also pointed to the black ground of Picasso’s 1915
Harlequin, also in the Museum of Modern Art in New York, a painting which
Matisse noted in a letter to Derain early the following year, but without alluding to
the colour.'’ All these could plausibly have offered very striking visual stimuli to the
118 painter; but what made Matisse respond in Gourds to the idea of black as light in
such a dramatic way?
The concept of black as a colour (not simply as a darkener) had been much
debated in painterly circles since the Renaissance, and had been more or less gener-
ally accepted by the close of the nineteenth century.'* Among Matisse’s contempo-
raries, a painter well-read in theory, such as Malevich, might even interpret the
Fraunhofer absorption lines (lines at certain wavelengths where radiation — light —
is absorbed by elements in the atmosphere) as evidence that there was black (as well
as white, the sum ofall the colours oflight) in the spectrum itself.'? But the notion
of black as a light is so novel, so paradoxical and so radical, that it invites a more
thorough circumstantial examination. A recent perceptualist analysis links the
development of the idea to Matisse’s move from a well-lit to a dark studio in the
autumn of 1913, and appeals to the laws of simultaneous and value contrast which
make the lights look lighter as they abut on the areas of dark.’ Such effects were
234
MATISSE’S BLACK LIGHT
indeed abundantly present in Seurat’s drawings, although, because he did not use
absolutely flat, dense tones, he was obliged to represent, and not simply to create
them. Certainly Matisse recalled that ‘blacks and their contrasts’ first came to be
exploited in The Moroccans; and in addition, a prolonged inspection of Matisse’s 117
sizeable paintings will induce a strong, luminous after-image of the blacks. But
quite apart from the question of whether Matisse’s work, with its complex rhyth-
mic surfaces, invited this sort of inspection, there was another approach to black
which seems to have been crucial to this period of experimentation, and that was
the idea of black light as a physical phenomenon, which was then a fashionable
topic in French science.
In his 1914 letter to Camoin, Matisse followed his mention of Seurat with the
confession that:
I am a romantic, but with a good half of the scientist, the rationalist, in me,
which makes for a struggle from which I emerge sometimes triumphant, but
breathless.”
Already in his 1908 Notes of a Painter, where he had expressed dissatisfaction with
the limitations of Neo-Impressionist technique, Matisse had looked forward to
defining ‘certain laws of colour’ by studying the colour-handling of many intuitive
artists:*> an aspiration which was very far from being purely intuitive itself. Matisse’s
interest in Bergson’s philosophy of duration has long been appreciated;** but his
knowledge of contemporary scientific ideas has been less examined. In the letter to
Derain early in 1916, Matisse drew that painter’s attention to some ‘dizzying’
hypotheses he had found in the book Science and Hypothesis (1902) by the distin-
guished mathematician Henri Poincaré, and said that he had been particularly
impressed by the notion that:
Movement exists only by means of the destruction and reconstruction of
matter.*
Poincaré’s account in this book of one of the leading tendencies of modern physics
also sounds remarkably like Matisse’s characterization, in his response’to Barr, of the
intimité of objects in Gourds: 118
new relations are continually being discovered between objects which seemed
destined to remain for ever unconnected; scattered facts cease to be strangers
to each other and tend to be marshalled into an imposing synthesis. The march
of science is towards unity and simplicity.”°
His book had been commissioned by the editor ofthe series Bibliotheque de Philoso-
phie Scientifique, Gustave Le Bon, who was also much concerned with the instability
of matter, and who quoted Poincaré enthusiastically in his own L’Evolution des
Forces of 1907. And it was Le Bon who, from 1896, began to develop the theory of
Black Light.”
The 1890s was a decade in which interest in all forms of radiation, which had
begun to occupy scientists since the Romantic period, took on a more precisely
phenomenological form. It was the period of the discovery of X-rays by Rontgen,
235
MATISSE’S BLACK LIGHT
and of radium and uranium by Marie and Pierre Curie, who, with Henri Bequerel,
won the Nobel Prize for their work on radioactivity in 1903. Le Bon, who had
made his reputation earlier in the century with a study of the psychology of crowds,
gave a candid account in one of his most popular books of how he came to publi-
cize his own work on radiation:
The appearance in 1896 of the work of Réntgen on the X-rays determined
me to publish immediately, in order to settle the order of dates, a note on some
particular radiations capable of passing through bodies...1 called them by the
name of Black Light by reason of their sometimes acting like light while
remaining invisible.**
The rays in question were radioactive particles such as cathode rays (later removed
by Le Bon from the category of Black Light), the long-wavelength radiations in the
infra-red of the spectrum and beyond, and radiation due to invisible phosphores-
cences. Although the term Black Light was not generally accepted, Le Bon’s work
was widely regarded by 1900 as having demonstrated that invisible radiation was a
universal property of matter: the physiologist Albert Dastre of the Sorbonne told
readers of the non-specialist Revue des Deux Mondes in 1901:
Not a sunbeam falls on a metallic surface, not an electric spark flashes, not a
discharge takes place, not a single body becomes incandescent, without the
appearance of a pure or transformed cathode ray.To Gustave Le Bon must be
ascribed the merit of having perceived from the first the great generality of
this phenomenon. Even though he had used the erroneous term of lumiére
noire, he has none the less grasped the universality and the principal features of
this product. He has above all set the phenomenon in its proper place by trans-
ferring it from the physicist’s cabinet to the great laboratory of nature.”
The fundamental premise of Le Bon’s theory was the recognition that in the con-
tinuous spectrum of radiation the visible spectrum, that is, visible light, formed less
than a tenth of the whole. Thus ‘the invisible region of the spectrum constitutes...
the most important portion ofthe light. It is only the sensitiveness of the human eye
which creates the division between the visible and invisible parts ofthe spectrum.’3°
It might be that there were animals able to see into those parts of the spectrum
invisible to the human eye, but it was certainly the case that Black Light could be
registered on photographic plates. Le Bon published a number of experiments
using statuettes to demonstrate that photographs could be made in total darkness by
Black Light, which, since it had the same properties of rectilinear propagation and
refraction as visible light, produced perfectly sharp images. In one experiment, a
replica of the Venus de Milo was coated with photo-sensitive sulphide of calcium
and exposed to light for three or four days until it had become ‘entirely dark’ by
. 4y 3h 2h iH
Gustave Le Bon, The ‘black spectrum’, 1908, from L’Evolution des Forces, showing how little of the
spectrum of radiation is composed of visible light. (120)
236
MATISSE’S BLACK LIGHT
Gustave Le Bon’s ‘black light’ experiment with Venus de Milo statuettes. Coated with photo-sensitive
sulphide of calcium and exposed to light until they blackened, they were then photographed in
darkness by the ‘invisible rays emitted by them eighteen months after having been struck by light’
(as the original caption has it). The black patches are uncoated areas. (121)
the observer sees, at the end of one or two minutes, the statue light up and
come forth from the darkness. The experiment is a very curious one, and has
always vividly impressed the spectator. It is, in fact, very strange to see the dark
iw) bo“NI
MATISSE’S BLACK LIGHT
238
MATISSE’S BLACK LIGHT
radiations of the lamp, added to the dark radiations of the sulphide, produce
visible light. It is almost the converse of the celebrated interference experl-
ments of Fresnel, in which light added to light produced darkness. In my
experiment, it is darkness added to darkness which gives birth to light.”
Le Bon might almost be describing the coming into light of the variegated silver
Jug in Matisse’s Gourds — the highest contrast with the black in the picture—andthe 118
mysteriously flat grey gourd, which speaks across the composition to the grey of the
casserole and the blue-grey of the lighter ground itself. Certainly the slanting edge
of the black suggests that these objects are caught in a shaft of Black Light.
Dark light
Le Bon’s experiments were published in a popular book: his L’Evolution des Forces
sold twenty-six thousand copies and was in print until at least 1917; and his concept
of universal radiation remained interesting, at least to newspaper journalists, for
many years. It has been suggested that Matisse read an article published in L’Intran-
sigéant in 1913 which claimed that the rays emanating from human bodies, as well as
from plants and minerals, could be photographed, and that this reading relates to the
extraordinary Portrait of Mile Yvonne Landsberg (1914), on which, after many sittings 12 1S)
and repaintings, Matisse finally scratched arching lines of force around the young
body.*3 Emanations have rarely been so graphic; but in the present context what is
perhaps even more striking is that here, as in Matisse’s portrait of his wife painted
the previous year, the large eyes, those windows of the soul, have been completely
blacked out.
So far as I know, the name of Gustave Le Bon appears nowhere in Matisse’s writ-
ings, but there is at least one slight indication that he might have looked at the long
Black Light section in L’Evolution des Forces. Another experiment published there 123
illustrated an apparatus designed by the scientist to demonstrate the transparency of
Matisse’s design for a black chasuble, 1950-2, inscribed with the Provencal word esperlugat, meaning
‘to open the eyes’. (124)
opaque bodies to invisible light. It consisted ofan ebonite plate to which metal stars
had been glued, placed beneath a photographic plate of which the upper half had
been exposed to candlelight. When exposed to full sunlight and developed, the
lower half of the plate was black, while the upper half showed the image ofthe half-
stars. Their metal had protected the plate from infra-red rays passing through the
bo
ebonite. The resulting image is strikingly close to Matisse’s design for the title-page
wn of Verve in 1945, and would have been even more so in the negative, where, as Le
Bon points out in his caption, the half-star shape rising above the ‘horizon’ would
have been black.
In spite of the great interest shown in his work in the 1890s, especially in France,
and in spite of the popularity of his later books, Le Bon’s reputation as a physicist
scarcely survived the turn of the century. It was argued that his essentially qualita-
tive experimental procedures were faulty, and — in England — that his results had for
the most part been anticipated at Cambridge.** Black Light was not a concept
which had any lasting impact on the study of radiation. Matisse’s ‘black light’, on the
other hand, propelled partly by the inner turmoil brought about by illness and war,
had a long life ahead of it. The ‘black’ paintings of 1914-16 were joined by a cluster
of predominantly black subjects around 1940;%* and at the close of Matisse’s life, by
cut-paper designs such as The Sorrows ofthe King (1952) and the series of maquettes
for black chasubles for the Chapel of the Rosary at Vence (1950-2), most of which
are now in the Matisse Museum at Nice.’° One of these, bearing the inscription
esperlucat,a Provengal word meaning ‘to open the eyes’ or ‘to perceive’, may serve as
a summary ofthe painter's fifty-year meditation on ‘black light’. What proved to be
contingent and provisional in science has revealed itselfasenduring in art.
Nv 40
I9 - Colour as Language in
Early Abstract Painting
241
COLOUR AS LANGUAGE IN EARLY ABSTRACT PAINTING
242
COLOUR AS LANGUAGE IN EARLY ABSTRACT PAINTING
Kandinsky’s pairs of opposites, from On the Spiritual in Art, 1911-12. His scheme is close to the
Viennese psychologist Ewald Hering’s ‘opponent colours’, although his orange-violet opposition and
his characterization of black and white as ‘death’ and ‘birth’ are both unusual. (125)
243
COLOUR AS LANGUAGE IN EARLY ABSTRACT PAINTING
to reduce. But there is one factor which I think has an important bearing on the
role ofcolour as system in early abstract painting.AsHarris had already shown, the
painter's application of the principles of contrast, as presented in his Natural System
of Colours (c. 1776), was made very difficult by his inability to find colorants which
would exactly match ideal colours. The developing paint-industry of the nine-
teenth century addressed this problem: the Englishman George Field, for example,
who was both a theorist and a manufacturer, was careful to specify the pigments he
used in his diagrams; and by the 1880s the influential circle of contrasts published by
Ogden Rood was able to give precise pigment-equivalents for complementaries,
and Seurat was able to set his palette with a series of paints approximating to the
colours ofthe solar spectrum, at least in hue."
This increasing range of colorants was of great importance in the practical appli-
cation oftheory, and in particular for theories ofthe affects of colours on spectators,
who could now be presented with standard, measured hues, so that dependence on
language, and hence on associations, could be reduced to a minimum. Not that
technology had yet succeeded in providing a categorically ‘pure’ primary colour:
it is no surprise that early abstraction, especially in Russia and Germany, sought
to exert its influence on paint-manufacture, or that the most influential colour-
theorist of these years, the chemist Wilhelm Ostwald, was in the 1920s and 1930s an
important consultant to the paint-industries of several countries. The Hungarian
painter Vilmos Huszar, who introduced Ostwald’s system into the Dutch De Styl
group in 1917, noted once again that the aspiration for ‘pure’ colours was still frus-
trated by imperfect materials.'* Of this group Mondrian, who perhaps more than
any of its other artists had the capacity to produce work of great formal and
colouristic sensitivity, continued to be vexed by the problem of finding a perfect
red, and his reds even more than his other ‘primary’ colours continued to be struc-
turally complex well into the 1920s.'’ Mondrian, too, was an admirer of Ostwald’s
principles (see the following chapter), and as late as 1920 he was still using the
fourth ‘primary’ colour, green, which Ostwald had adopted from Hering, as were
Huszar, and the founding father of the De Stijl group, Theo van Doesburg.'4
ipEmains
ped17 ae
The Last Futurist Exhibition, 0.10, Petrograd, 1915. Malevich has placed his Black Square (on a white
ground) in the traditional position of the most important icon in the Russian house — in the ‘red’ corner
of the room, so making this corner of the exhibition-space symbolically black, white and red. (126)
245
COLOUR AS LANGUAGE IN EARLY ABSTRACT PAINTING
set had an especially prominent place in Russia in the first school of geometric
126 abstraction, the Suprematism of Malevich. In an essay of 1920 Malevich divided his
movement into three phases, according to the proportion of black, red and white
squares introduced into its pictures. Black represented a worldly view of economy,
red revolution, and white pure action; and of these, white and black were more
important than red, and white the culmination of all.** Although Malevich paid a
rather ambivalent tribute to colour-science, considering black and white ‘to be
deduced from the colour spectra’,*? and although the command of many nuances
127. of white which informs his great series of‘white on white’ paintings may have been
stimulated by the revival of interest in early Russian icons, with their creams and
off-whites which often served as a surrogate for gold,** there can be little doubt that
the place of white in the Suprematist colour-system was essentially associative and
literary. Malevich’s best-known statement,
246
COLOUR AS LANGUAGE IN EARLY ABSTRACT PAINTING
the blue of the sky has been defeated by the suprematist system, has been
broken through, and entered white, as the true, real conception of infinity, and
thus liberated from the colour background of the sky... Sail forth! The white,
free chasm, infinity, is before us...?5
A language of colour
Malevich was also a friend of the poet and theorist Velimir Khlebnikov and of the
linguistic scholar Roman Jakobson, through whom the work of the burgeoning
Moscow Linguistic Circle on basic phonetics must have become very familiar to
him. Khlebnikov had indeed collaborated with Malevich in 1913 on the opera
Victory over the Sun,in which one aria was composed entirely of vowels and another
entirely of consonants; and the painter’s austere geometric designs for the sets and
costumes of this production have rightly been seen as embodying the seeds of the
Suprematism which emerged two years later.” Both Khlebnikov and Jakobson
were interested in that aspect of synaesthesia known as audition colorée, in which
spoken sounds, particularly vowel-sounds, were involuntarily associated with
colours ;and Jakobson indeed seems to be one ofthe very few students oflanguages
to have maintained an interest in the phenomenon (see Chapter 21). The sound-
colour association is probably best known from one of the earliest recorded exam-
ples, Rimbaud’s Sonnet des Voyelles (p. 263 below), but by the time ofthe First World
War it had become a major preoccupation of experimental psychologists. In 1890
the Congrés Internationale de Psychologie Physiologique set up a committee to
investigate the phenomenon, and this was productive of a spate of publications, but
even before that, audition colorée had been investigated on a statistical basis in the
influential aesthetic publications of G.T. Fechner.**
Jakobson, who had become friendly with Malevich by 1916, may have already
begun to relate infant preferences for black, white and red to the early development
of speech-sounds, in which ‘a’ (which was often associated with red in these psy-
chological experiments) provided the basic phonetic contrast to ‘w’, which accord-
ing to several authorities was associated with black.* In a manifesto of 1919,
Khlebnikov appealed to the painters of the world to help in the establishment of a
universal language, for
the task of the colour-painter is to give geometrical signs to the basic units of
understanding...It would be possible to have recourse to colour and express
M with dark blue,W with green, B with red, E with grey, L with white...*°
Painterly and linguistic research in Russia was thus directed to the identification
and expression of fundamentals, and this area of enquiry became part of the cur-
riculum of the Soviet State Art Schools in the 1920s, a period which saw perhaps
the last major flowering of interest in audition colorée until very recent times.
COLOUR AS LANGUAGE IN EARLY ABSTRACT PAINTING
The painter and teacher K. V. Matiushin’s vast array of colour-charts, Moscow, 1924, suggesting the
laboratory rather than the studio. (128)
Kandinsky, who had been engaged on drawing up some of the teaching pro-
grammes there immediately after the Revolution, took with him an interest in this
sort of research when he returned to Germany and the Bauhaus later in the
decade." In Russia, indeed, where Ostwald’s colour-theories were widely adopted,
it was the psychological laboratories of late nineteenth-century Germany which
i) CO provided the models for the art institutions of the Revolutionary and immediately
post-Revolutionary periods.
We are now,I think, in a better position to interpret an extravagant remark by the
Suprematist Ivan Klyun, who in a manifesto of 1919, summarized the theme ofthe
present chapter in claiming:
our colour-compositions are subject only to the laws of colour and not to the
laws of nature.*3
Early abstract artists were thus presented with a number of well-articulated colour-
systems which allowed them to consider colour as in the nature ofa language. But it
is not surprising that their use of this language should have depended upon princi-
ples of salience and symbolism, rather than on notions of mere perceptibility. Nor is
it altogether surprising — although it may be a matter of regret — that this language
of colour, which seemed around 1900 to offer the prospect of universality, should
have turned out to be so thoroughly hermetic.
20 - A Psychological Background for
Early Modern Colour
6 ee. TODAY HAVE A REMARKABLE relationship with colour. Our time, which
depends on the past more than any other for its forms, has produced a kind of
painting in which colour is independent. Thus
’ claimed the critic Karl Scheffler in
an essay, Notizen tiber die Farbe’, in the journal Dekorative Kunst in 1901. Scheffler’s
view of the centrality of colour in modern painting was reinforced by many critics
and artists in France and Germany before the First World War, and if colour came to
play a leading role in early abstraction, this was not so much because it had lost its
traditional mystery, but rather that this mystery had been deepened and ramified by
developments in colour-study during the second half of the nineteenth century, to
the point where it could become a central preoccupation of painters seeking new
means of expression.
The aims of abstraction were spiritual, but to realize those aims, painters were
ready and able to use the very substantial body of colour-theory which had been
published by 1900.The classic studies of Goethe (1810) and M.-E. Chevreul (1839)
had established the study of colour firmly on a subjective basis, and the developing
science of experimental psychology, and later of phenomenology, gave a good deal
of attention to the perception of colour. Experimental psychologists frequently
drew on their experience of painting: several, like David Katz, were themselves
painters, and others, like Miiller-Freienfels, were also historians of art. Their tastes
were usually conservative, but this was not always so.
In 1913 a painter from the Cleveland School of Art and a physiologist from the
Western Reserve Medical School published a study which examined, not simply
the physiological basis of Neo-Impressionism, but also the reaction against Neo- »
Impressionism in the work of the Fauves, who had found, like many other artists
around 1906, that the pointillist technique produced a decidedly achromatic, greyed
effect, and who sought to base a new colouristic style on the contrast oflarge areas
of flat tint.’ Matisse’s thoroughly phenomenological ‘Notes of a Painter’, in which
he described his painting procedure as starting from the immediate, naive sensation
of a colour-patch set down on the canvas, was published in the same year, 1908, as
E. Utitz’s Principles of the Aesthetic Theory of Colours (Grundztige der aesthetischen Far-
benlehre), which claimed that the painter ‘does not take his habitual colours [i.e. the
colours expected in objects, and hence perceived in them] to his subject, but gives
himself up naively to the immediate impression’. This view was quoted approvingly
by David Katz in an early classic of phenomenology, The Modes of Appearance of
Colours and their Conditioning by Individual Experience (Die Erscheinungsweise der
Farben und Ihre Beeinflussung durch die Individuelle Erfahrung,1911).The interests and
249
A PSYCHOLOGICAL BACKGROUND FOR EARLY MODERN COLOUR
even the methods adopted by painters and psychologists were very much in tune.
A series of studies carried out in the Leipzig psychological laboratory of Wilhelm
Wundt in the 1890s and early years of this century was directed towards establishing
colour-aesthetics on an empirical basis by means of controlled experiments with
many subjects. In an early study of 1894, Jonas Cohn had already discovered that
most of his subjects (who were all educated men) preferred combinations ofhighly
saturated colours, and particularly saturated complementaries, and he noted that
this preference had hitherto been regarded as peculiar to primitives and the uncul-
tivated. In a series of experiments of 1910-11, F Stefanescu-Goanga came to the
conclusion that the feelings produced in his subjects by colours were the direct
effect of sensory perception, rather than the result ofassociations, which were sec-
ondary phenomena.” This work tended towards the view that colour-sensations
themselves could be free of associative elements — could be more abstract.
It is not at all certain how far these studies were accessible to painters in the way
in which the earlier, simpler and more comprehensive manuals of Goethe,
Chevreul and Ogden Rood had been; but what is clear is that, in the early develop-
ment of abstraction, painters interested in colour were experimenting in very much
the same way as the psychologists; that they used analogous experimental proce-
dures, and sometimes came to very similar conclusions. Painting had been estab-
lished as an experimental activity in the 1880s by Seurat: after the death of Cézanne
in 1906 it became more insistently so; and if we examine painterly practice and
theory in the years around 1912 with a view to discovering its preoccupations and
motivating forces, we may go far towards reconstructing the processes of trial and
error which more than ever shaped the non-representational painting of that time.
250
A PSYCHOLOGICAL BACKGROUND FOR EARLY MODERN COLOUR
suggest a far earlier interest than that. One of his preoccupations at this time was
the establishment of a ‘grammar’ of painting on a level with what he saw as the
‘srammar’ of music: again and again he quoted a remark of Goethe’s, that painting
needed a thorough-bass — the eighteenth-century method of establishing a base-
line in a score which predetermined the subsequent elaboration of the other parts —
and this is a quotation not without its irony in the context of 1912, since at this time
Kandinsky’s friend and collaborator Arnold Schoenberg was asserting that the
method was entirely outmoded (Theory ofHarmony, 1911).
Kandinsky had been concerned with the theory of colour at least since 1903,
the year of the German translation of Signac’s manifesto From Delacroix to Neo-
Impressionism, and it is very likely that he had already read Scheffler’s article of 1901
on colour, cited above, for he referred to it in On the Spiritual in Art, where the
treatment of mental disturbances by chromotherapy was one of the subjects under
251
A PSYCHOLOGICAL BACKGROUND FOR EARLY MODERN COLOUR
discussion. Some aspects of the dynamic of colour which Kandinsky made the basis
of his colour-system have rightly been traced to a pamphlet on chromotherapy by
A. Osborne Eaves, Die Kriifte der Farben (The Powers of Colours) of 1906, where red
and blue were characterized as the most contrasting and the most therapeutically
effective colours, and where Kandinsky made his characteristic diagrams of expan-
sion and contraction in the margin of his own copy. But Kandinsky’s system was
based upon the primary polarity of yellow and blue which goes back ultimately to
Goethe’s table of plus and minus, active and passive colour-sensations (Theory of
Colours, § 696), albeit much amplified by Wundt in his Principles of Physiological
Psychology (1874, sth edn 1902) into what he called the ‘unique contrast of feeling
[Stimmung] in colour’: the lively yellow and the calm blue. Wundt had described a
two-fold movement from yellow to blue — an unstable, labile progression through
red, and a stable, balanced, restful progression through green — which colour,
according to Kandinsky, also represented ‘the passive principle’.
In his discussion of synaesthesia (the simultaneous response of two or more
senses to a single stimulus) Wundt introduced some musical-chromatic examples
which are close to Kandinsky’s: their scarlet trumpet was a very traditional equiva-
lent which goes back to the eighteenth century, but the light blue of the flute is a
more recently experienced correspondence, noted in the psychological literature
of the late nineteenth century. And like Wundt’s pupil Stefanescu-Goanga, Kandin-
sky felt that ‘the theory of association is no longer satisfactory in the psychological
sphere. Generally speaking, colour directly influences the soul’
But the detailed correspondences between the ideas of Kandinsky and those of
Wundt and his school are only occasional, and rather unimportant: what is more
interesting is the painter’s method of proceeding in his enquiry, whose conclusions
were, as he said, the result of ‘empirical feeling’ ‘not based on any exact science’, but
which could be substantiated by ‘proceeding experimentally in having colours act
upon us’. Kandinsky, who had been trained in law and ethnology before he turned
to painting, was no stranger to the experimental method. It was not until after the
publication of On the Spiritual in Art early in 1912, under the influence of the Amer-
ican printer Edward Harms, that he subjected Goethe’s Theory to experimental
testing with the prism, hoping in vain to substantiate Steiner’s Theosophical inter-
pretation of that work: but that he should have felt such experimentation to be
appropriate at all is witness to a remarkably positivist element in his mind.
After the war Kandinsky introduced the study of the medical and physiological,
as well as the occult aspects of colour into his proposals for the curriculum of the
Moscow Institute of Art Culture; and three years later, at the Bauhaus, he dropped
the occult, and added psychology, stressing that all these studies should be carried
out by means of exact measurements and experiments. His most notorious excur-
sion was the test with a thousand postcards sent out to a sample of the Weimar com-
munity, asking that the three ‘primary’ colours, red, yellow and blue, should be
allotted to the three ‘primary’ shapes, the triangle, circle and square. The question-
naire produced an ‘overwhelming majority’ in favour ofthe yellow triangle, the red
square, and the blue circle. But like its results, the psychological presuppositions of
this survey had already been suggested in Kandinsky’s On the Spiritual in Artin 1912,
252
A PSYCHOLOGICAL BACKGROUND FOR EARLY MODERN COLOUR
where he proposed that ‘sharp colours have a stronger sound in sharp forms (e.g.
yellow in a triangle). The effect of deeper colours is emphasized by rounded forms
(e.g. blue in a circle), Introspection needed only the authority ofa statistical survey
to become the compelling basis of a universal pictorial language.
Kandinsky’s interest in a universal language of colour is nowhere more apparent
than in the almanac of the Munich Blue Rider group (p. 193 above). His stage-piece
The Yellow Sound, published there, is one of the earliest manifestations of synaesthe-
sia as an aesthetic principle. But more important, the almanac brought together for
the first time high art and popular art, the art of children and amateurs, art from
Africa, Asia, Polynesia and the Americas. The group’s leading enthusiast for non-
European art was August Macke, who wrote for it an essay on masks. But Macke 101, 130
also found himself increasingly unhappy with the introspective emphasis of
Kandinsky, and looked for a more objective handling of colour.This he found in the
work of the French painter Robert Delaunay, whose Paris studio he visited in 1912.
253
A PSYCHOLOGICAL BACKGROUND FOR EARLY MODERN COLOUR
The poet Blaise Cendrars, writing in Aujourd’hui in 1931 (138f), is describing here
the Paris circle ofartists which included Robert Delaunay, whom he had met at the
end of 1912. Delaunay was still working on a series of paintings of Windows which
he had begun a year earlier, but probably in 1913 he began painting the Sun and
Moon series which was to mark an entirely new direction in his work, and was
effectively to form its basis until his death in 1941.The painter and his critics have
seen the work ofthis period as the first non-representational art in France, and it is
worth examining the painting ofthis seminal year 1912 in the light of the theory of
art that Delaunay began to elaborate at the same time, for the comparison will show
how close he was also to developing an experimental method.
Delaunay called this style of painting Simultané, taking up the term applied by
Chevreul to a particular kind of colour-contrast which he had made the focus of
his 1839 treatise, On the Law of Simultaneous Contrast ofColours, declaring that,
in the case where the eye sees at the same time two contiguous colours, they
will appear as dissimilar as possible, both in their optical composition and in
the height oftheir tone. (§16)
Delaunay may have studied Chevreul as early as 1906, when his painting and that of
131 his friend Jean Metzinger passed through a Neo-Impressionist phase. The large,
square brushstrokes which characterize the work of this period were a reaction
against the greying effect of Seurat’s smaller dots, and, in Delaunay’s Landscape with
Disc of 1906/7 (Paris, Musée d’Art Moderne), were also used as an expressive means:
the vibration created by the refusal of the large colour-patches to mix optically has
a direct relation to the dynamic subject of the painting, the sun. This picture also
makes some play with complementary after-images (red-green), but there is no
reason to suppose that it represents any sustained study of Chevreul.
When, probably early in 1912, Delaunay wrote to Kandinsky outlining his
theories, he had shifted to a rather different approach, claiming:
254
A PSYCHOLOGICAL BACKGROUND FOR EARLY MODERN COLOUR
Jean Metzinger like Delaunay turned the pointillist ‘dot’ into a mosaic of close-packed ‘cubes’. This
more abstract method, as he explained in 1907, was not intended for ‘the objective rendering oflight’,
but to capture ‘iridescences and certain aspects of colour still foreign to painting’. The handling of the
sun of Landscape (Coucher de Soleil) of 1906/7 is close to Delaunay’s in Landscape with Disc. (131)
255
A PSYCHOLOGICAL BACKGROUND FOR EARLY MODERN COLOUR
If the coloured lines or dots are quite distant from the eye, the mixture is of
course perfect...but before this distance is reached there is a stage in which
the colours are blended, though somewhat imperfectly so that the surface
seems to flicker or glimmer — an effect that no doubt arises from a faint per-
ception from time to time of its constituents. This communicates a soft and
peculiar brilliancy to the surface, and gives it a certain appearance of trans-
parency: we seem to see into it and below it.
And Rood continues:
That summer Delaunay was staying outside Paris, and according to his wife Sonia
he was much occupied with the clouds and the heavenly bodies by day and night:
the material of his new repertory of Disc subjects in 1913(for example Sun, Moon,
Simultané I:see Colour and Culture, pl. 208).’ The use of the term simultaneity suggests
a renewed interest in Chevreul, and by August 1912 Delaunay was no longer speak-
ing in terms of depth: he was now focusing solely on the complementary contrast
of colours as pictorial means. Of Seurat he wrote:
His creation remains the contrast ofcomplementary colours (optical mixture by means
of dots... since it is nothing but a technique, does not have the same importance
as contrast. THE MEANS OF CONSTRUCTION FOR PURE EXPRESSION).
The aspect of Chevreul’s work which now absorbed Delaunay was painting in flat
tints, whose characteristics, according to Chevreul, ‘necessarily consist in the per-
256
A PSYCHOLOGICAL BACKGROUND FOR EARLY MODERN COLOUR
fection of the outlines and colours. These outlines contribute to render the impres-
sion of colours stronger and more agreeable...’ (§303). For Chevreul in 1839 such
painting had only a decorative, accessory function, but the Delaunays did not feel
the distinction, and Sonia had recently been experimenting with flat colours in
appliqué textiles and in bookbindings decorated with collage.° This new experi-
ence culminated in Robert’s Disc of 1914, an experiment designed to test the
psycho-physiological effects of certain colour-combinations, and painted in bands
of flat colour with hard contours.As Delaunay wrote to Mlle de Bonin, the near-
complementaries of blue and red at the centre of the circle produced a slow-
moving contrast, and the dissonances towards the edges moved rather faster.’
The summer sky gave Delaunay the experience necessary to create a number of
pictures of 1912-13: the Circular Forms, with references to sun and moon, several of
which, like the Sun No. 1, are painted in largely flat tints, and have very pronounced
and regular contours. It was perhaps this picture to which Delaunay referred in a
letter of 2 June 1913 to August Macke:
My last picture is the ‘Sun’: it shines more and more strongly the more I work
on it:it is from this movement that from now on all my new Synchromies will
be born. The ‘Windows’ saw the opening of them.
The place of Delaunay’s Disc of 1914 in his experimental approach to painting
cannot be overestimated. The Circular Forms, like Kupka’s Discs of Newton of 1912, 47
are still subject-pictures, and it is arguable that Delaunay, unlike his German admuir-
ers Klee and Marc, had no conception of anon-objective art before the First World
War: but the Disc and its antecedents show clearly that Delaunay conceived of the
role of the painter in relation to his expressive means as akin to the role of the
experimental psychologist.
The chemist Wilhelm Ostwald’s colour-circle of 1916, giving an unusually prominent place to green. (132)
258
A PSYCHOLOGICAL BACKGROUND FOR EARLY MODERN COLOUR
In the Composition with Grey, Red, Yellow and Blue of 1920 the De Stijl artist Piet Mondrian uses the red
that he regarded as an ‘outward’ colour together with the more ‘inward’ blue and yellow — but
combined with greys, to which he gives the unusual role of ‘primary non-colours’ — suggesting the
continuing influence of Ostwald, for whom grey was the chief controller of harmony. (133)
founded in 1917 by Theo van Doesburg, Piet Mondrian, Bart van der Leck and
Vilmos Huszar, who published an article on Ostwald’s system in the first volume of
the group’s magazine.* Huszar stressed that Ostwald, who as a chemist had given
particular attention to the properties of available pigments, was far more useful to
artists than earlier theorists, and that his system was the first to be based on geome-
try, a feature which would especially appeal to the De Stijl group members who
were establishing a geometrical aesthetic. He was, however, quick to warn of the
subjectivity of colour-sensations, and to insist that Ostwald’s circle of hues had no
compelling aesthetic validity — and it is true that Ostwald’s four primaries had
a limited interest for the group apart from Mondrian and van Doesburg, who con-
tinued to make use of green.’ Far more important to De Stijl was the concept of
iS)
A PSYCHOLOGICAL BACKGROUND FOR EARLY MODERN COLOUR
harmonizing colours by balancing their white and black content: and the first
painter to show a close interest in this aspect of Ostwald’s ideas was Mondrian.
Mondrian had been painting in a brilliant, Fauve-like palette since about 1908,
and about the same time a brief involvement with Neo-Impressionism had led him
to formulate a simple doctrine of pure colours laid side by side ‘in a pointillist or
diffuse manner’. But the impact of Cubism from 1911 to 1912 directed his attention
away from questions of colour, and it is only in the 1914 sketchbook that we find
hints that he had come across Kandinsky’s On the Spiritual in Art, and had been
pondering the complementary relationship of red and green as female and male,
external and internal colours.'? Mondrian’s characterization of red and green as
respectively external and internal might simply refer to their role in the modelling
of flesh, but the context suggests that they were far more than this, and, although
they are not Kandinsky’s values for these colours (p. 242), they are very close to those
of the Theosophists, to whom Mondrian had been attached since 1909. In Besant
and Leadbeater’s Thought-Forms (1901) red, Mondrian’s female, material colour, is
characteristic of pride, avarice, anger and sensuality, and green, his male, spiritual
value, of sympathy and adaptability.'' By 1917, perhaps following the lead of Huszar,"*
Mondrian had adopted a basic palette of white, black and grey, plus three primaries,
red, yellow and blue. He still regarded red as essentially an ‘outward’ colour, and,
following Goethe, Kandinsky and the Dutch Theosophist H. Schoenmaekers, he
claimed that yellow and blue were more ‘inward’, but that, for the moment, the
three primaries together could not be dispensed with in painting."
Mondrian’ earlier interest in green as a male and internal colour may have been
reinforced about 1920 by his knowledge of Ostwald’s emphasis on unnatural greens,
for in a number of Neo-Plastic paintings of that year he experimented with a dis-
tinctly greenish yellow or yellow green. Yet, unlike van Doesburg or Vantongerloo
among De Stijl artists, he never used green as a fourth Ostwaldian primary.'* On the
other hand, he was certainly very much affected by Ostwald’s views on grey.
In a footnote to an article dealing with colour in the journal De Stijl, Mondrian
wrote that black and white might be mixed with yellow, red and blue and yet these
would still remain primary colours.'’ In his painting of the period he used planes
of very desaturated primaries which may be clearly related to Ostwald’s view
that colour-harmony was to be achieved chiefly by regulating value. The earliest
composition to make use of this principle seems to be Composition — 1916 in the
Guggenheim Museum in New York, but the idea was explored far more systemati-
cally in 1917 and 1918, for example in Composition with Colour-Planes No. 3, Compo-
133 sition: Colour-Planes with Grey Contours and Composition with Grey, Red, Yellow and
Blue of 1920; and well into the 1920s Mondrian was mixing a good deal ofgrey into
his primary colours.'®
During that decade he moved away from this interest in desaturation and in
grey, but the colouristic element in his Neo-Plasticism, his first thoroughly non-
representational style, during and immediately after the war, had been given a
powerful impetus by Ostwald’s promise that it was possible to quantify the psycho-
logical response to colour, and thus to make it into a mathematical study.
260
21 - Making Sense of Colour — The
Synaesthetic Dimension
increased to 40,000, although only 10,752 (!) were classified. Like Forbes, Galton
hoped to acquire a set of standard cubes to be supplied to art schools by the South
Kensington Museum, but the Vatican asked too high a price.’
The Vatican practice of numbering nuances of hue has been adopted by most
modern colour-systems, although the range of nuances has been substantially
reduced: the American Munsell system, which is very generally used as a standard
for surface colours, comprises somewhat over fifteen hundred plastic chips. And
although a modern dictionary of European colour-names lists about five thousand,
many of these are short-lived fashion names, and only around a dozen are in
common use.‘ There is thus a marked discrepancy between the large number —
some psychologists say millions — of perceivable colours and the handful of names
we use to identify them. Language labels only those few segments of the continu-
ous colour-space which are important to us, and thus the study of colour as we
understand it becomes very much the study of colour-language.
This radical imbalance between sensation and language means that the experi-
ence of colour will be very largely associational. Colour has always lent itself very
readily to association and symbolizing, whether on the general level of identifying
the sensuous, unstable, indeterminate characteristics of colour as such with the
female, as opposed to the determinate, stable, male element of line or form;> or
grouping individual colours into categories such as ‘warm’ and ‘cool’;® or character-
izing colours as, for example, ‘cheerful’ or ‘sad’.? But the course of the nineteenth-
century developments in the physiology of the nervous system, in experimental
aesthetics, as well as in the understanding ofpainting as less and less related to direct
representation, increased the tendency to detach colour-expression from associa-
tion, and to see colour as evoking immediate physical and mental responses.
262
MAKING SENSE OF COLOUR
which must remain untranslated, because it was the sounds and not the visible
letters that were generally thought to evoke the synaesthetic effect. Although the
poet soon disclaimed any involuntariness for the colour-vowel correspondences in
his poem, which he had invented, he said, specifically to open it up to all the senses
(and it does indeed introduce analogies of touch and smell as well as of colour), the
work was very quickly adopted by the scientists.’ But it was almost certainly
Rimbaud’s poetic reputation and the growing Symbolist movement which made
the phenomenon of particular interest to artists and writers. As the’distinguished
French psychologist Alfred Binet wrote in 1892, audition colorée had become a vogue
in science, literature, poetry, and the theatre:
While medical doctors have preferred to see in audition colorée nothing but a
disturbance in sensory perception, literary people believe that they have found
in it a new form ofart.’®
Perhaps one of the very few visualizations of coloured words from this period 1s by
the American architect and designer E. J. Lind, who put together his ideas on this 102
subject in the 1880s, although he traces them back to 1850 when he was a student at
the School of Design in Somerset House in London. There, one or other of the
then very common analogies between music and colour may have been on the
agenda:"° two of the extensive treatments of colour, those by George Field and 134
David Hay, recommended in the 1853 Manual of Colour by the Art Superintendent
of the School of Design from 1852, Richard Redgrave, included highly specific
263
MAKING SENSE OF COLOUR
AEIOU
MODERN DIATONIC.
red. blue.green,
yellowpurplebown,
Golden.silver. ick
While voletor
Left: George Field’s “Colours and Sounds’ from
Chromatics, 1845, one of many diagrams ofthe
Romantic period to link the scale of colour and
the diatonic musical scale. (134)
*AUVILUAT,
Genus Spissum.
treatments of the analogy with music. Field’s Chromatography (1835) argued that the
painter should follow the musician in matters of harmony, identifying blue specifi-
cally with C; and Hay’s Laws of Harmonious Colouring (4th ed., 1838) include a scale
linking music and colour in the most direct way.'7
4 But Lind’s interest in the colour of words probably developed out of the growing
literature of the 1880s, and perhaps from the discussion in Francis Galton’s important
"35 book, Inquiries into Human Faculty and its Development, which was first published in
1883 and included a diagram of a coloured alphabet. Galton discussed colour-hearing
in the context of many varieties of visionary experience and colour-association,
and he summarized its characteristics as follows:
the vowel sounds chiefly evoke [colour-associations] ...the seers are invariably
most minute in their description of the precise tint and hue of the colour.
They are never satisfied, for instance, with saying ‘blue’, but will take a great
264
MAKING SENSE OF COLOUR
deal of trouble to express or to match the particular blue they mean...no two
people agree, or hardly ever do so, as to the colour they associate with the same
sound.
Lastly, and perhaps most importantly, Galton found that the tendency to colour-
hearing was hereditary.'’ Thus his emphasis was both on the involuntary character
and on the extraordinary concreteness of the phenomenon.
Interest in the variable effects of different coloured lights on plants, animals and
human beings had been growing throughout the nineteenth century,” and had 136
attracted the attention of, for instance, Galton’s cousin, Charles Darwin. As Binet
suggested in 1892, these early experiments in synaesthesia were posited on the
belief in some anomaly in the nervous system which might be understood and
treated in purely physiological terms. About the time of the First World War a good
deal of work was being done to give a specifically therapeutic function to the deco-
ration of hospital wards, although in Britain at least, the medical establishment 103
265
MAKING SENSE OF COLOUR
remained sceptical, and this scepticism has accounted, perhaps, for the very limited
modern research into the physiological effects of exposure to colours.”
Most recent work on colour-word synaesthesia has been conducted by neurolo-
gists, who are largely concerned to understand the mechanisms of transference from
one mode ofbrain activity to another, and they have emphasized the absolute nor-
mality of the experience.”
During the high period of colour-hearing, however, this faculty was seen as a
symptom of abnormality, of heightened sensibility, and the belief that colour could
exert an immediate, non-associative effect on the human organism became crucial
to avant-garde artists such as Kandinsky who were concerned to develop a non-
representational art in the early years of this century.
In his 1912 book, On the Spiritual in Art, Kandinsky concluded a review of some
of these synaesthetic experiments with the thought that their effects
would seem to be a sort of echo or resonance, as in the case of musical instru-
ments, which without themselves being touched, vibrate in sympathy with
another instrument being played. Such highly sensitive people are like good,
much played violins, which vibrate in all their parts and fibres at every touch
of the bow.”
Here Kandinsky, who as we have seen was not only a string-player but also seems to
have possessed a synaesthetic gift himself, was writing in a remarkably positivist vein;
but we must remember that neither in his writings nor in his paintings of these years
did he abandon associations. Nor did he engage with the specific topic of colour-
vowel synaesthesia until he was teaching at the Bauhaus in the 1920s, and possibly
then only as a result of his teaching experiences in Moscow just after the war.”°
266
MAKING SENSE OF COLOUR
So, although a recently reported case study of nine female students has found a
very high degree of consistency in the attribution of white to O, white or pale grey
to I and yellow or light brown to U,*° and a remarkable study carried out half a
century ago by the structural linguist Roman Jakobson found that in several cases,
Czech, German, Serbian and Russian speakers found E was always either yellow or
bright green,*' regularities have in fact been very hard to identify; and it has come
to be argued in some quarters that the discrepancies may be reconciled by assuming
that the synaesthetic process lies in a pre-perceptual stage of neural activity.” But
if, at the level of perception, synaesthetic correspondences are no more universal
than the symbolic attributes of colour have proved to be, this must have serious
267
MAKING SENSE OF COLOUR
268
Acknowledgments
Notes to the Text
Select Bibliography
List of Illustrations
Index
Acknowledgments
Many of the chapters have their origin in articles and conference 1983,Common Denominators in Art and Science; Chapter 10 appeared
papers written and published over the last thirty years, while others in 1971 in the Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes, XXXI;
are previously unpublished or are written specifically for this book. Chapter 11 is an expanded version of a study in Apollo, LXXX,
Chapter 1 stems from an article of 1984 in Interdisciplinary Science 1964; 12 appeared in the exhibition catalogue Turner en France, Panis,
Reviews, IX; Chapter 2 from part of the 1993 Darwin Lecture Series 1981, Centre Cultural du Marais.
on Colour at Cambridge University, first published in T. Lamb and Chapter 13 is a revised version of a paper presented at the sympo-
J. Bourriau (eds) 1995, Colour: Art and Science. Chapter 3 is a revised sium Runge Fragen und Antworten arranged by the Hamburg Kun-
version of ‘Colour in Western Art: An Issue?’ Art Bulletin, LX XI, sthalle in 1977, and published with the other papers in 1979 under
1990. the editorship of Hanna Hohl; Chapter 14 appeared in the catalogue
Chapter 4 arose from a research seminar at the University of East of the exhibition
The Romantic Spirit in German Art, 1790-1990, Edin-
Anglia and lectures given in 1977 at the University of East Anglia, burgh, London, Munich, 1994-5. Chapter 15 is an expanded version
the Colour Group Symposium, and in 1978 at the Centre for Byzan- of a paper given at the Journée Chevreul arranged by the Musée
tine Studies at the University of Birmingham. It was published in National d’Histoire Naturelle in Paris in 1989, published in French
1978 in Art History, 1. My colleagues at the University of East Anglia in F. Viénot and G. Roque (eds), Michel-Eugene Chevreul: un Savant,
gave generous leave of absence to pursue these enquiries, and I am Des Couleurs!, 1997. Chapter 16 was first published in 1987 in Art
particularly indebted for help and advice to David Chadd, Robin Bulletin, LXTX and is reprinted here with revisions to the notes. I am
Cormack, Richard Gordon, Paul Hetherington, John Mitchell and especially grateful to Bob Herbert for having read my original type-
Paolo Vivante. Chapter 5 is an expanded version of apaper given in script and making several suggestions about the argument. Chapter
1995 at a Manuscript Workshop: Colour and Pigments in Manuscript 17 is an expansion ofa paper given in 1991 at the Seurat Symposium
Illumination, arranged by the Parker Library at Corpus Christi College, at the Metropolitan Museum ofArt in New York. I am particularly
Cambridge. Another version was published in 1998 in Leids Kun- grateful to Bob Herbert for inviting me to contribute. Chapter 18 is
sthistorisch Jaarboek X1. Chapter 6, on the background to Ghiberti’s written specifically for the present book
Third Commentary, was first published in 1972 in Apollo, XCV. I am Chapter 19 is a revised version of paper given at the 1985 Royal
grateful for the generous advice of the late Andrew Martindale Institute of Philosophy conference at Bristol, published in A. Harri-
during its preparation. son (ed.), Philosophy and the Visual Arts: Seeing and Abstracting, 1987.
Chapter 7 is a modified version of a paper given in 1994 at the Chapter 20 originated as an essay first published in M. Compton (ed.),
conference El Color en el Arte Mexicano arranged by the Universidad Towards a New Art: Essays on the Background to Abstract Art, 1910-20,
Nacional Autonoma de Mexico, published in a Spanish version Tate Gallery 1980. Chapter 21 was first presented in 1994 as a paper
with the other papers. I am particularly grateful to Georges Roque at the conference Son et Lumiére held at Sussex University. I am
for giving me the occasion to investigate the subject of this paper, indebted to Nigel Llewellyn for inviting me to contribute.
and to Daniéle Dehouve for her advice on Nahuatl colour-terms. For permission to reproduce material am indebted to the editors
Chapter 8 derives from a paper on “Rainbow and Prism’ given in of Art Bulletin; Apollo; Interdisciplinary Science Reviews; Art History; the
Edinburgh in 1994 at the Interalia Conference Visions of Light, and Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes; the former Centre Cul-
another, “The De Coloribus of V. Scarmilionius’, presented to the turel du Marais, the University Presses of Cambridge and Aberdeen,
1995 Symposium ofthe Leonardo da Vinci Society and the Society to Prestel Verlag, D. Riedel Publishing Company and the Tate
for Renaissance Studies: Art and Science in the Italian Renaissance: Gallery.
Light. I am grateful to Richard Bright and Martin Kemp for their My great indebtedness to individuals is expressed above and in
invitations to contribute to these events. Chapter 9 originates in a the Notes to the Text below, but my greatest thanks go, as always,
paper given in at a conference arranged by the School of Epistemics to my family for their patience and support.
at Edinburgh University in 1981, first published in M. Pollock (ed.) cS.
270
Notes to the Text
271
NOTES TO THE TEXT
22 Burnham, Haines and Bartleson (op. cit. n. 1 above) 209-10. considerations concerning the effects of ‘warm’ and ‘cool’ colors on
energy conservation’, ibid. 23, 949-54. : ;
23 G. Bierson, ‘Why did Newton see indigo in the spectrum?’,
American Journal ofPhysics, 40, $20 (1972). . 9 A. Wierzbicka 1990, “The meaning of color terms: semantics,
cultures and cognition’, Cognitive Linguistics, I, 99-150. See also the
24 E. Fletcher (ed.) 1901, Conversations ofJames Northcote with James
more cautious remarks in H. B. Nicholson, ‘Polychrome on Aztec
Ward, 217-18. Cf. J. Burnet 1822, Practical Hints on Composition in
sculpture’ in E. H. Boone (ed.) 1986, Painted Architecture and Poly-
Painting, 23. Purkinje’s observations were stimulated by Goethe s
Theory of Colours, espec. §s4, and first publ. in J. E. Purkinje, chrome Monumental Sculpture in Mesoamerica, 147: ‘Certain associa-
tions seem reasonably obvious and ‘natural’, such as black with night
Beobachtungen und Versuche zur Physiologie der Sinne II, 1825 (Opera
Omnia, vol. 1, 1918), 118f. and darkness and the sub-terrestrial realm, blue with the diurnal
celestial sphere and aquatic phenomena, green with vegetation and
25 J. Gage, ‘Colour at the Bauhaus’, AA Files, 1, $1 (1982), 1993,
259-63.
preciousness in general, red with sacrificial blood, and red and
26 Theophilus, On Divers Arts, trans. J. G. Hawthorne and C.)S. yellow in combination with fire and solar heat. However, more
Smith, 2nd ed. 1979, 24f. subtle and complex connotations were probably also involved...’.
27 Corot raconté par lui-méme, 1946, 83; for the Villalobos system see 10 J. G. Millais 1899, Life and Letters ofSirJ. E. Millais, 1, 240 and the
Burnham, Haines and Bartleson (op. cit. n. 1 above) 172. letter from ‘Chromos’ to Millais, publ. by P. Fagot, “Témoignages
28 Burnham, Haines and Bartleson (op. cit.) 91-2. synoptiques de William Blake et d’Emmanuel Swedenborge sur
29 See the technical notes in Rembrandt in the Mauritshuis, 1978. l’arc-en-ciel’ in P. Junod and M. Pastereau (eds) 1994, La couleur:
30 C. Hope 1980, Titian, 161-3. regards croisés sur la couleur, 93. Millais was, however, still having
31 Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, 168. trouble with the order of the rainbow colours in what seems to be a
32 R. Liebreich, ‘Turner and Mulready — On the effect of certain later picture: see J. Larmor (ed.) 1907, Memoir and Scientific Corre-
faults of vision on painting’, Notices of the Proceedings of the Royal spondence of the late Sir George Gabriel Stokes, Bt., 1, 20 (I owe this
Institution, VI, 450-63 (1872). The argument was countered by W. reference to Joanie Kennedy). On the perception and representa-
M. Williams 1872, Nature, 500, and especially in an anonymous tion of the rainbow, Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, ch. 6.
review of Liebreich, ‘Painters and the Accidents of Sight’ in The 11 P. Syme, Werner's Nomenclature of Colours adapted to Zoology,
British and Foreign Medico-Chirurgical Review, 50, Oct. 1872, 284-306. Botany, Chemistry, Mineralogy, Anatomy and the Arts, 2nd ed. 1821, 11.
Cf. P. D. Trevor-Roper, The World Through Blunted Sight, 2nd ed. For Darwin’s use of Syme/Werner in 1832 and 1833, F. Burkhardt
1988, 2-3. See also below, ch. 3. and S. Smith (eds) 1985, The Correspondence of Charles Darwin, I, 280,
33 J. Cowart,J.D. Flam, D. Fourcade andJ.H. Neff 1977, Henri 353.
Matisse: Paper Cut-Outs, 28-30. British Journal of Aesthetics, XVUI, 12 For Darwin’s few marginal notes in his copy of Syme, M. A. Di
1978; G. W. Granger, ‘Colour Harmony in Science and Art’, Colour Gregorio 1990, Charles Darwin's Marginalia, 1, col. 797. Some 1,868
73 (cit. n.8 above) 502-5. colour-notes on the feathers of Polypection Napoleonis use very
34 M. Sahlins, ‘Colours and Cultures’, Semiotica (1976), 16, 12. general terms and include a correction from ‘ashy brown’ to “black-
ish’ (Cambridge University Library, Darwin Papers 84.2, ff63-4).
13 W. Dacre (Nicholson), ‘Liberation of Colour’ (1944) in W.
2 Colour and Culture Nicholson 1987, Unknown Colour: Paintings, Letters, Writings, 125.
14 For faktura, Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, 225.
1 J. M. Oxbury, S. M. Oxbury, N. K. Humphrey 1969, “Varieties 15 D. Katz 1935, The World of Colour (repr. 1970).
of colour anomia’, Brain 92, 847-60; A. Damasio, ‘Disorders of 16 See H. P. Barlow andJ.D. Mollon (eds) 1982, The Senses, 112-13.
complex visual processing: Agnosiasis, Achromatopsis, Balint’s 17 M. Sahlins 1976, “Colors and Cultures’, Semiotica, 16, 8.
syndrome and related difficulties of orientation and construction’ in 18 T. D. Crawford 1982, ‘Defining “Basic color terms”, Anthropo-
M.-N. Mesulam (ed.) 1985, Principles of Behavioural Neurology, logical Linguistics 24, 338-43; B. Saunders 1995, ‘Disinterring Basic
259-88. See also M. H. Bornstein 1985, ‘On the development of Color Terms: a study in the mystique of cognitivism’, History of the
color naming in children: data and theory’, Brain and Language, 26, Human Sciences 8, 19-38.
85-6. 19 Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, espec. 32-3.
2 U. Eco, ‘How culture conditions the colors we see’ in M. Blonsky 20 R. Arnheim, Art and Visual Perception: a Psychology ofthe Creative
(ed.) 1985, On Signs, 157-75. Eye, 2nd ed. 1974, 340.
3 M. Kemp, The Science ofArt, 2nd ed. 1991, Part III. 21 Sahlins 1976, 16. L. Wittgenstein 1978, Remarks on Colour, speaks
4 R. W. Darwin 1786, ‘On the ocular spectra oflight and colours’, casually ofthe colour circle (III, 80) and the ‘colour-octagon’ (III, 197).
Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, LXXVI, ii, espec. 328. 22 For sinople and bloi, Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, 81-2, 90.
5 See G. Roque 1994, “Les couleurs complémentaires: un nouveau 23 Wittgenstein (op cit. n.21 above) I, 9-14. For Japan, N. B.
paradigme’, Revue d'Histoire des Sciences, XLVII, 405-33, espec. 414, MeNeill 1972, ‘Colour and Colour Terminology’, Journal ofLinguis-
423. This is the fullest historical study of complementary colours, tics, VIII, 21; for Slav terms covering yellow and blue, G. Herne
but for Newton see above, 142-3. 1954, Die slavischen Farbenbenannungen (Publications de l'Institut
6 J. Albers, Interaction of Color (1963), rev. ed. 1971, VIII, 22: “green Slave d’Upsal, 9) 73. P. Klee, Beitriige zur bildnerische Formlehre, ed.
or blue-green’. ‘This green is the complementary color of red or J. Glaesemer 1974, facs. 159. C. L. Hardin has pointed to some labo-
red-orange.’ ratory experiments which suggest that subjects may read a surface as
7 C. Hayter 1813, An Introduction to Perspective adapted to the capacities simultaneously red and green all over (Color for Philosophers, 2nd edn.
of youth..., pl. XIV, fig. 4. The earliest record I have found of a 1988, 124f).
perceptual classification of colours as ‘warm’ or ‘cool’ is in Johannes 24 R.E. MacLaury et al. 1992, ‘From brightness to hue: an explana-
Hiibner’s Curieuses Natur-Kunst-Berg-Gewerck und Handlungs-Lexicon, tory model of color-category evolution’, Current Anthropology 33,
Leipzig 1727, col. 1019: ‘dasz die maler die blauen farben Kalte farben 137-86. For Judaism and Pseudo-Dionysius, Gage 1993, Colour and
nennen, engl. cold, die gelben warme’ (cited in Grimm, Deutsches Culture, 60, 71.
Wéerterbuch, sv. kalt, col. 80). Earlier notions of colour-temperature
25 WR. Kuschel and T. Monberg 1974, ‘““We don’t talk much about
had depended on the doctrine of the mixture of the four tempera- colour here”: a study of colour semantics on Bellona Island’, Man 9,
ments, e.g. B. Telesius, Liber de Coloribus in Bernardini Telesii Vari de
213-42; for a further critique of the social attitudes implicit in
Naturalibus, Venice 1590, where white was the warmest colour,
colour-tests in anthropology, Saunders (op. cit. n. 18) 35 n. 17.
8 See the cautious scepticism ofP.O, Fanger, N. O. Breum, E. Jerking 26 T. Izutsu, “The elimination of colour in Far Eastern art and phi-
1977, ‘Can color and noise influence man’s thermal comfort?’ losophy’ in S. Haule (ed.) 1977, Color Symbolism: Six Excerpts from
Ergonomics 20, 11-18; T.C. Greene, P. A. Bell 1980, ‘Additional the Eranos Yearbook 1972, 167-95. ;
a2
NOTES TO THE TEXT
27 J. Harvey 1995, Men in Black. frangaise?, Art de France, 11, 23-42. Souriau’s answer was yes: it is red,
28 C. Feéré 1887, Sensation et Mouvement, 41-6. white, and blue.
29 P. K. Kaiser 1984, ‘Physiological response to color: a critical
8 S.R. Weitman 1973, ‘National Flags: A Sociological Overview’,
review’, Color Research and Application 9, 29-36.
Semiotica, VII, 328-67. See also H. Fischer 1963, ‘Rot and Weiss als
30 I. Scott (ed. and trans.) 1971, The Liischer Colour Test, 68; cf. H. Fahnenfarben’, Antaios, [V, 136ff; L. Schmidt, ‘Rot und Blau. Zur
Eysenck 1941, ‘A critical and experimental study of colour prefer- Symbolik eines Farbenpaares’ in ibid. 168ff; and R. Girardet 1984,
ences’, American Journal ofPsychology 54, 386. ‘Les Trois Couleurs, ni blanc ni rouge’ in P. Nova (ed.), Les Lieuo de
31 M. Liischer, Psychologie der Farben, Basel, n.d. (1949), 32-3 for meéemoire, 1, La République, 5 ff.
Goethe and Kandinsky, 59 for the four humours. For Goethe and 9 For the ancient practice, see Vitruvius, Ten Books on Architecture,
Schiller, Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, 204. VII, 7-8; and Pliny, Natural History, XXXV, 30. For an instance in
32 For a review of the extensive literature on children, Bornstein 15th-century Siena, see G. Milanesi, Documenti per la storia dell’arte
(op. cit. n. 1 above) 72-93; for animals, A. Portmann, ‘Colour sense senese, 1854, II, 307, no. 215; and for another in Baroque Rome, see
and the meaning of colour from a biologist’s point of view’ in D. Mahon 1947, Studies in Seicento Art and Theory, 92. For 18th-
Haule, ed. (op. cit. n.26 above) 977, 1-22. century Spain see Z. Veliz 1986, Artists and Techniques in Golden Age
33 MacLaury, op. cit. n.24 above. Spain, 154.
34 N. A. Stekler and W. E. Cooper 1980, ‘Sex differences in color to G. Vasari, Le vite..., ed. G. Milanesi, 1878-81, II, 187-9. For a
naming of unisex apparel’, Anthropological Linguistics 22, 373-81; Baroque retelling of the story that stressed the Pope’s ‘eye’ over his
J. D. Mollon, ‘Colour vision and colour blindness’ in Barlow and ‘reason’, see G. D. Ottonelli and P. Berrettini, Tyattato della pittura e
Mollon (op. cit. n. 16 above) 187-9; Bornstein, op. cit. n. 1 above; scultura; Uso et abuso loro (Florence, 1652), ed. V. Casale 1973, 58f.
J. Mollon, ‘Seeing colour’ in T. Lamb andJ. Bourriau 1995, Colour: 11 Bernal (op. cit. n. 5above) 343.
Art and Science, espec. 139-40. 12 C. A. du Fresnoy (1667), The Art ofPainting, trans. W. Mason in
The Literary Works of Sir Joshua Reynolds, ed. H. W. Beechey 1852,
II, 274; see also E. Cropper 1984, The Ideal of Painting: Pietro Testa’s
3 Colour in Art and its Literature Diisseldorf Notebook, 252.
13).@? Blane 1867, Grammaire des arts du dessin, 22.
I See below p. 67. 14 H. Matisse, Ecrits et propos sur l'art, ed. D. Fourcade 1972, 201.
2 See particularly the remarks by J. Shearman on the distinction 15 P.O. Runge (1840), Hinterlassene Schriften, repr. 1965, I, 164; Marc
between historiography and science in ‘The Historian.and the to August Macke, 12 Dec. 1910 in W. Macke, ed. 1964, August
Conservator’, J. Shearman and M. B. Hall (eds) 1990, The Princeton Macke — Franz Marc Briefwechsel, 28.
Raphael Symposium. Science in the Service ofArt History, 7-8. 16 R. Matthai 1928, ‘Experimentelle Studien tiber die Attribute der
3 W. Menzel 1842, ‘Die Mythen des Regenhogens’ in Mythologische Farbe’, Zeitschrift
fiirSinnesphysiologie, LIX, 354; see also A. Lichtwark
Forschungen und Sammlungen, Stuttgart and Tiibingen, 241. (1891), Die Erziehung des Farbsinnes, 3rd ed. 1905, 5, 23.
4 For example, G. Dumeézil 1946, ‘““Tripertia” fonctionnels chez 17 H. B. Barlow andJ.D. Mollon (eds) 1982, The Senses, 187. Pos-
divers peuples indo-européens’, Revue d’histoire des religions, CKXXI, sibly the only scholar to contest these figures is G. S. Wasserman
54ff. For a critique, see C. Renfrew 1987, Archaelogy and Language: 1978, Color Vision: An Historical Introduction, 6of€.
The Puzzle of Indo-European Origins, 25 ff. 18 One of the few studies of costume to address itself specifically
5 See particularly M. Bernal 1987, Black Athena: The Afro-Asian Roots to historians of art is by a pupil of Newton: E. Birbari 1975, Dress
of Classical Civilization, I, 240ff. Bernal documents the long-standing in Italian Painting 1460-1500. F. Brunello’s most important study is
European doubts about whether the ancient Egyptians were black L’Arte della tintura nella storia dell’ umanita, 1968 (also publ. in English,
or light-skinned. The transmission of the negative connotations of Vicenza 1968).
black Egyptians to the Christian tradition of the Devil has been 19 A. Hollander 1978, Seeing through Clothes; and R. Parker 1984,
studied by P. du Bourguet 1972, ‘La Couleur noire de la peau du The Subversive Stitch: Embroidery and the Making of Femininity.
démon dans l’iconographie chrétienne: A-t’elle une origine précise?’, 20 G. Berkeley (1709), An Essay towards a New Theory of Vision,
Actas del VIII Congreso Internacional de Arquelogia Cristiana (1969), XLII, Cll, CLVI, CLVII; J. W. von Goethe (1810), Theory of
Citta del Vaticano and Barcelona, 271-2. For Iconoclasts as blacks in Colours, trans. C. L. Eastlake (London, 1840), repr. 1970, Xxxviii-
Byzantium, see R. Cormack 1985, Writing in Gold: Byzantine Society xxxix. For the Sceptics, seeJ.Annas andJ.Barnes 1985, The Modes
and Its Icons, 136f. White and racialism has now been studied by of Scepticism, espec. 38-9; andJ.Locke, An Essay on Human Under-
Richard Dyer 1997, White. For another racially-linked colour preju- standing, 4th ed. 1700, II, xxii, vv. 2, 8, 10-11. See also M. Baxandall
dice, see R. Mellinkoff 1983, ‘Judas’ Red Hair and the Jews’, Journal 1985, Patterns of Intention: On the Historical Explanation of Pictures,
ofJewish Art, LX, 31-46; and M. Pastoureau (1989), ‘Rouge, jaune et 76-80.
gaucher: Notes sur l’iconographie médiévale de Judas’ in Couleurs, 21 J. D. Mollon 1989, ““Tho’ she kneeled in that place where they
images, symboles, n.d., 69-83. erew...”. The Uses and Origins of Primate Colour Vision’, Journal
6 Victor Turner’s classic study, ‘Colour Classifications in Ndembu of Experimental Biology, CXLVI, 21-38. See also the discussion of
Ritual: A Problem in Primitive Classification’ (1966) in The Forest of infants’ observation of contour, as opposed to colour at the centre
Symbols: Aspects ofNdembu Ritual, 2nd ed. 1970, sof, should now be of forms, in M. H. Bornstein 1975, ‘Qualities of Colour Vision in
supplemented by R. Willis, ‘Do the Fipa have a word for it?’ in D. Infancy’, Journal ofExperimental Child Psychology, XIX, 415-16.
Parkin (ed.) 1985, The Anthropology of Evil, espec. 217ff. For a rather 22 See, for example, G. Mancini 1956, Considerazioni sulla pittura,
slight modification of the traditionally negative interpretation of ed. A. Marucchi, I, 162; Domenichino to Angeloni (1632) in Mahon
‘black’ among Afro-Americans, seeJ.E. Williams 1964, ‘Connota- (op. cit. n.9 above) 120; and G. P. Bellori (1732), Vita di Carlo
tions of Color Names among Negroes and Caucasians’, Perceptual Maratti in Le Vite...,ed. E. Borea 1976, 632. A critique ofthe later
and Motor Skills, XVUI, 729; andJ. E. Williams, R. D. Tucker, F. development of this view has been offered by L. Venturi 1933, “Sul
Dunham 1971, ‘Changes in the Connotations of Color Names ‘colore’ nella storia della critica’, L’Arte, [V, 228-33 (repr. in Saggi
among Negroes and Caucasians, 1963-1969’, Journal of Personality di critica, 1956, 159-69).
and Social Psychology, XIX, 228. 23 Fora brief survey of this tradition, see E. Strauss, “Zur Entwick-
7 A. L. Plehn 1911, Farbensymmetrie und Farbenwechsel. Prinzipien lung der Koloritforschung’ in Strauss, Koloritgeschichtliche Untersuchun-
der deutschen und italienischen Farbenverteilung (Studien zur deutschen gen zur Maleri seit Giotto und andere Studien, 2nd ed., ed. L. Dittmann
Kunstgeschichte, CXLII); E. von den Berken 1930, ‘Forschungen 1983, 331-41.
iiber die Geschichte der Farbe in der Malerei’, Forschungen und
24 L. Dittmann (1959), ‘Bemerkungen zur Farbenlehre von Hedwig
1962, “Y-a-t-il une palette Conrad-Martius’, Hefte des Kunsthistorischen Seminars der Universitat
Fortschritte, V1, 262-3; and E. Souriau
273
NOTES TO THE TEXT
Miinchen, v, 1963, 22ff. Conrad-Martius’s most important text in sive but very well-documented discussion by R. Verbraeken 1979,
Clair Obscur— histoire d’un mot. ;
this regard is H. Conrad Martius 1929, ‘Farben: Ein Kapitel aus der
38 Dittmann (op. cit. n. 26 above) 346; cf. also Strauss (op. cit. n. 23
Realontologie’, Festschrift Edmund Husserl, 339-70. For an_excep-
tionally vital and far from formalist analysis in the spirit of Conrad- above) 12.
1961, ‘Zur Kunst Cézannes’ in M. 39 J. Westphal, Colour: A Philosophical Introduction, 2nd ed. 1991, ch. 3.
Martius, see L. Dittmann
Westphal is mistaken in thinking that pigment-mixtures of yellow
Gosebruch (ed.), Festschrift Kurt Badt, 190-212.
and black yield brown (44, n. 7); the product here is green (F.
25, W. Schone (1954), Uber das Licht in der Malerei, sth ed. 1979. For
Kiesow 1930, ‘Uber die Entstehung der Braunempfindung’, Neue
an English summary, see A. Neumayer’s review in Art Bulletin,
Psychologische Studien, V1, 121ff); and idem 1982, ‘Brown’, Inquiry,
XXXVII, 1955, 301ff. Some extracts appear in English in W. Sypher
xxv, 1982, espec. 420. In note 32 here Westphal suggests circum-
(ed.) 1963, Art History: An Anthology of Modern Criticism, 132-52. See
also the only English published study to draw on Sch6ne’s approach:
stances in which brown might be seen to be a spectral colour. See
P. Hills 1987, The Light of Early Italian Painting. Among the several also K. Fuld,J.S. Werner, B. R. Wooten 1983, “The possible ele-
mental nature of brown’, Vision Research, 23, 631-7; P. C. Quinn,
studies of light in European culture are V. Nieto Alcaide 1978, La
Luz, Simbolo y sistema visual (El espacio y la luz en el arte gotico y del J. L. Rosano, B. R. Wooten 1988, ‘Evidence that brown 1s not an
renacimiento); C. R. Dodwell 1982, Anglo-Saxon Art: A New Perspective; elemental color’, Perception and Psychophysics, 43, 156-64.
D. Bremer 1974, ‘Licht als universales Darstellungsmedium’, Archiv 40 C. J. Bartleson 1976, ‘Brown’, Color Research and Application, 1,
fiir Begriffsgeschichte, XVII, 185-206 (with extensive bibliography); 188; M. Sahlins, ‘Colors and Cultures’ in J. L. Dolgin, D. S. Kem-
K. Hedwig 1977, ‘Forschungstibersicht: Arbeiten zur scholastischen nitzer, D. M. Schneider, eds 1977, Symbolic Anthropology: A Reader in
Lichtspekulation. Allegorie-Metaphysik-Optik’, Philosophisches Jahrbuch, the Study of Symbols and Meanings, 170.
LXXXIV, 102-26; idem 1979, ‘Neuere Arbeiten zur mittelalter- 41 Bartleson (op. cit. n. 40 above); B. Harrison 1973, Form and
fiirhrift
lichen Lichttheorie’, Zeitsc philosophische Forschung, XXXII, Content, 108-11.
602-15; Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, ch. 4. 42 Verbraeken (op. cit. n. 37 above) 59, 102; A. M. Kristol 1978,
26 Dittmann 1987, Farbgestaltung und Farbtheorie in der abendlandischen Color: Les Langues romanes devant le phénomene de la couleur, 103, 323,
Malerei, XI, n. 1. The reference is to M. Rzepinska, Historia Koloru w n. 41; K. Borinski 1918, ‘Braun als Trauerfarbe’, Sitzungsberichte der
dziejach malarstwa europejskiego, 3rd ed. 1989. Since I am not familiar bayerischen Akad. der Wissenschaften: Philosophische-Philologische Klasse,
with Polish I have relied for my assessment of Dittmann’s remark on Abhandl. x, 1-18; idem, ‘Nochmals die Farbe Braun’ in ibid. (1918),
I. M. Neugebauer 1979, ‘Die Farbe in der Kunst, Bemerkungen zu 1920, Abhandl. 1, 3-20.
einem Buch von Maria Rzepinska’, Zeitschrift
fiirAsthetik und allge- 43 Conrad-Martius (op. ‘cit. n. 24 above) 365, para. 283; Schone
meine Kunstwissenschaft, XXIV, espec. 228, and B. Zelinsky 1986, (op. cit. n. 25 above) 229-30; E. Heimendahl 1961, Licht und Farbe:
‘Maria Rzepifska tiber die Farbe’ in ibid., XXXI, espec. 182. Useful Ordnung und Funktion der Farbwelt, espec. 69; E. Strauss 1969, ‘Zur
discussions of Rzepinska’s book have appeared in English in Polish Wesensbestimmung der Bildfarbe’ (op.cit. n. 23 above), 18.
Perspectives, X11, 1970, 91-2 (by J. Przybos), and the Journal ofAes- 44 Dittmann (op. cit. n. 26 above) 70.
thetics and Art Criticism, XXXII, 1973, 555-6 (by M. Rieser). 45 H. Soehner 1955, ‘Velazquez und Italien’, Zeitschrift_fiir Kunst-
27 Dittmann (op. cit.) 290. geschichte, xviii, 22-7; K. H. Spinner 1971, ‘Helldunkel und Zeitlichkeit.
28 A good example is the contradictory characterizations of the Caravaggio, Ribera, Zurbaran, Georges de la Tour, Rembrandt’ in
colour of Delacroix’s Liberty Leading the People (Louvre) by Lee ibid., xxxiv, 174. See also Dittmann (op. cit. n. 26 above) 231.
Johnson 1963, who notices a return to the early palette of Géricault 46 Veliz (op. cit. n. 9 above) 3, 109, 154. For Spain as an important
(L. Johnson, Delacroix, p. 38), and Jutta Held 1964, who saw in source for red earths (‘Spanish brown’) in the 17th century, see
Delacroix’s “complementaries’ a contrast to Géricault’s emphasis on R. D. Harley, Artists’ Pigments, c. 1600-1835: A Study in English Docu-
chiaroscuro (Farbe und Licht in Goyas Malerei, 152-3). mentary Sources, 2nd ed. 1982, 120.
29 Dittmann (op. cit) 39-40, 68-9. 47 See H. Jantzen’s remarks on Hetzer’s neglect of such considera-
30 Schone (op. cit. n.25 above) 32-6, 256-65. For the marked effect tions in his review of Tizian: Geschichte seiner Farbe in Deutsche
of the glass on the mural of the Baroncelli Chapel, see Hills (op. cit. Literaturzeiting, XLII, 1937. Cf. also Strauss (op. cit. n. 23 above) 9-
n.25 above) 83. 19. Sch6ne (op. cit. n. 25 above) was certainly less happy about the
31 Strauss (op. cit. n. 23), 340f. Cf. also his essay, ‘Zur Frage des problems he faced: see e.g. his remarks on Romanesque wall-
Helldunkels bei Delacroix’ in ibid., 135-51; K. Badt 1965, Eugéne painting, p. 31; and Dittmann (op. cit. n. 26 above, 47) expressed
Delacroix: Werke und Ideale, 46-74; and idem, Die Farbenlehre Van reservations about the condition of Masaccio’s frescoes in the
Goghs, 2nd ed. 1981. See also W. Hess, Das Problem der Farbe in den Brancacci Chapel in Florence, but not, for example, about Titian’s
Selbstzeugnissen der Maler von Cézanne bis Mondrian, 2nd ed. 1981. Bacchus and Ariadne in London (p. 174) or Seurat’s Grande Jatte in
32 H. Walter-Karydi 1986, ‘Principien der archaischen Farbenge- Chicago (pp. 307-8). From time to time Dittmann cites the work of
bung’, Studien zur klassischen Archiiologie. Festschrift Friedrich Hiller, the conservator Hubert von Sonnenburg in his notes, but none of
ed. K. Braun and A. Furtwingler, espec. 31. See also idem, ‘Ernst his work appears in the text.
Strauss’ Koloritforschuhng und die Antike’ in Munich, Galerie 48 See e.g. Capolavori e restauri, Florence, Palazzo Vecchio, 1986-7;
Arnoldi-Livie, Ernst Strauss zum 80. Geburtstag 30 Juni 1981, n.d. A Venezia restaurata 1966-1986, Milan, 1986; The Hamilton Kerr Institute:
rather loose but well-documented overview of ancient symbolism The First Ten Years, Cambridge, Fitzwilliam Museum, 1988; Art in
has now been given by L. Luzzato and R. Pompas 1988, Il significato the Making: Rembrandt, London, National Gallery, 1988-9, and
dei colori nelle civilta antiche. Impressionism, London, National Gallery, 1990-1.
33 U.M. Riith 1977, Die Farbegebung in der byzantinischen Wand- 49 Among them are the National Gallery of Art, Washington, DC,
malerei der spat-paleologischen Epoche (1346-1453), diss., Bonn, 644, Report and Studies in the History of Art (1967- ); National Gallery,
757, 801f and passim. London, Technical Bulletin (1977- ); Gli Uffizi: Studi e ricerche (1984- );
34 G. Hopp 1968, Edouard Manet: Farbe und Bildgestalt, 54. Hopp OPD Restauro: Quaderni dell’opificio delle pietre dure e laboratorio di
notes (p.100) that this green has not been noticed by later commen- restauro di Firenze (1986- ) and Science et technologie de la conservation et
tators, but more recently, Frangoise Cachin, in the catalogue of de la restauration des oeuvres d'art et du patrimoine (1988- ). See also the
the Manet exhibition in New York and Paris of 1983, talks of its article by J. Plesters, “Scienza e Restauro”: Recent Italian Publica-
‘violence’ (Paris, Grand Palais, Manet 1832-1883, 1983, 306-7). tions on Conservation’, Burlington Magazine, CXXIX, 1987, 172-7.
igs (op. cit. n. 34 above) 8sff; Cachin (op. cit. n. 34 above) 50 E.g. J. Bruyn ef al., Corpus of Rembrandt Paintings, 1, 1625-31,
475. 1982;J.O. Hand and M. Wolff, National Gallery of Art, Washington:
36 Sch6ne (op. cit. n. 25 above) 5. Early Netherlandish Painting, 1986; H. W. van Os et al..,The Early
37 Dittmann (op. cit. n. 26 above) 195; he draws here on the obses- Venetian Paintings in Holland, 1978.
274
NOTES TO THE TEXT
275
NOTES TO THE TEXT
Century Portuguese Work on Manuscript Illumination’, Ambix, groping towards a modern conception of three-dimensional colour-
XXVI, 97ff. E. Vandamme has published a 16th-century MS recipe space. C. Parkhurst, ‘Leon Battista Alberti’s Place in the History
of Color Theories’ in M. B. Hall, ed. 1987, Color and technique in
book from the Netherlands, together with a useful bibliography of
“Een 16e -eeuws zuidnederlands Renaissance Painting, Italy and the North, 161-204, presents some
contemporary printed sources:
valuable new material on Alberti’s Antique sources, but also
receptenboek’, Jaarboek van het Koninklijk Museum voor Schone Kunsten
includes a quite unrealistic account of his medieval background.
Antwerpen, 1974, 101-37; M. Sanz has published an anonymous mid-
M. Barasch 1978, Light and Color in the Italian Renaissance Theory of
17th-century Spanish painter's manual, now translated into English
Art, 27-31, confuses the relationship of the Latin and Italian versions
by Veliz (op. cit. n. 9 above) 107-27; and E. A. de Klerk a treatise
ofAlberti’s text on white, black, and the hues. Certainly in the Latin
by Cornelis Pieterz. Biens, published in Amsterdam in 1639, but
version Alberti shows himself anxious to distance himself from
now known only in a single copy: ‘De Teecken-Const, een 17de
eeuws Nederlands Traktaatje’, Oud Holland, XCVI, 1982, 16ff (with
‘the philosophers’ and to speak ‘as a painter’, which suggests that
English summary). he anticipated the objections of a learned audience. On the two
64 Urso von Salerno, De Commixtionibus elementorum libellus, ed. versions, see also N. Maraschio 1972, ‘Aspetti del bilingualismo
A. Stiirner, 1976, 111-16. There is also a reference to painting in the albertiano nel ‘De Pictura’, Rinascimento, 2nd ser., XII, 183-228,
De coloribus by a follower of Urso (ed. L. Thorndike, ‘Medieval Texts espec. 208-14 on colour-terms. See also L. Gérard-Merchaut 1991,
on Colors’, Ambix, VU, 1959, 7). For the earliest extant oil painting ‘Les indications chromatiques dans le De Pictura et le Della Pittura
on panel, from late 13th-century Scandinavia, see C. Périer-D’leteren d’Alberti’, Histoire de l’Art, XI, 23-36.
1985, Colyn de Coter et la technique picturale des peintres flamands du XV" 72 Alberti, De Pictura, 1, 10, I, 47, and for the contemporary discus-
siecle, 14; and for early oil painting on walls, to which Urso seems to sions of Sendivogius at Cracow and Hamerlin in Vienna, G. Rosin-
refer, see H. Travers Newton 1983, ‘Leonardo de Vinci as a Mural ska 1986, ‘Fifteenth Century Optics between Medieval and Modern
Painter: Some Observations on His Materials and Working Methods’, Science’, Studia Copernicana, XXIV, 127, 152ff (Polish with English
Arte lombarda, LX VI, 72. summary). See also J. S. Ackerman 1980, ‘On Early Renaissance
65 A. Callen 1982, Techniques ofthe Impressionists, espec. 18-27. This Color Theory and Practice’, Studies in Italian Art and Architecture,
study draws on the far richer documentation ofCallen’s 1980 disser- Fifteenth through Eighteenth Centuries (Memoirs of the American Academy
tation, ‘Artists Materials and Techniques in Nineteenth-Century in Rome, XXXV), 3.
France’, PhD diss., London. 73 De Pictura, Il, 48; cf. S. Pezzella (op. cit. n. 62 above). Both Albert
66 A notable exception is D. Cranmer. ‘Painting Materials and Tech- and Antonio da Pisa describe the way that the interposition of white
niques of Mark Rothko: Consequences of an Unorthodox Approach’ makes the other colours ‘joyful’, and Alberti uses the same idea
in Mark Rothko 1903-1970, London, Tate Gallery, 1983, 189-97. when he recommends colours for dress in I libri della famiglia (Opere
67 The post-Antique history of colour as it relates to theories of volgari, ed. C. Grayson 1960, I, 202).
perception has now been well covered in two studies in English: 74 The best edition is K. Bergdolt 1988, Der Dritte Kommentar
D. C. Lindberg 1976, Theories of Vision from Alkindi to Kepler; and Lorenzo Ghibertis: Natunvissenschaften und Medezin in der Kunsttheorie
N. Pastore 1971, Selective History of Theories of Visual Perception, der Friihrenaissance. Ghiberti’s sources have been listed most acces-
1650-1950. A still-useful general history of colour-theories is K. T. sibly by G. ten Doesschate 1932, “Over de Bronnen van de 3de
A. Halbertsma 1949, A History of the Theory of Colour, although its Commentaar van Lorenzo Ghiberti’, Tijdschrfit voor Geschiednis,
early chapters are based almost entirely on material gathered by 432-7. Also G. F. Vescovini 1965, ‘Contributo per la storia della
Goethe: J. W. von Goethe, Zur Farbenlehre: Historischer Teil, in fortuna di Alhazen in Italia: Il volgarizzamento del MS Vaticano
Goethe, Die Schriften zur Naturwissenschaft, ed. R. Matthaei, W. Troll, 4595 ed il ‘Commento Terzo’ del Ghiberti’, Rinascimento, 2nd
K. L. Wolf, Weimar, I, no.6, 1957 (text); II, no. 6, 1959 (Ergdnzun- ser., V, 18-41.
gen und Erldaurungen). 75 C. Maltese, ‘Il colore per Leonardo dalla pittura alla scienza’ in
68 Recent studies of Theophilus have stressed the intellectual P. Rossi and E. Bellone, eds 1981, Leonardo e l'eta della ragione, 171-
background of his writing: W. Hanke 1962, Kunst und Geist: Das 84; idem, ‘Leonardo e la teoria dei colori’, Rémisches Jahrbuch fiir
philosophischen Gedankengut der Schrift, ‘De Diversis Artibus’ des Kunstgeschichte, xx, 1983, 211-19.
Preisters und Monachus Theophilus; L. White, Jr 1964, ‘Theophilus 76 M. Kemp 1990, The Science ofArt, 268f.
Redivivus’, Technology and Culture, v, 226f& J. van Engen 1980, 77 Maltese, ‘Leonardo e la teoria...’ (cit. n. 75 above) 218;J.Gantner
‘Theophilus Presbyter and Rupert of Deutz: The Manual Arts and 1969, ‘Colour in the Work of Leonardo’, Palette, XXXII, 8-26.
Benedictine Theology in the Early Twelfth Century’, Viator, XI, 78 M. Barasch 1978, Light and Color in the Italian Renaissance Theory
1 soft. of Art, 64f; J. Gavel 1979, Colour: A Study of Its Position in the Art
69 V.J. Bruno 1977, Form and Color in Greek Painting, esp. 53ff. J.J. Theory of the Quattro- and Cinquecento, 111f;J.Bell 1993, ‘Aristotle as
Pollitt has criticized the version of the four-colour story given by a source for Leonardo’s theory of colour perspective after 1500’,
Cicero, and regarded as plausible by Bruno (J. J. Pollitt 1974, The Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes, LVI, 100-18. A useful
Ancient View ofGreek Art, 111). See also Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, collection of Leonardo’s notes on colour is in M. Kemp and M.
ch. 2. The fullest discussion of the context of Pliny’s and Cicero’s Walker, eds 1988, Leonardo on Painting. An Anthology of Writings by
account is H. Jiicker 1950, Vom Verhéiltnis der Romer zur bildenden Leonardo daVinci with a Selection of Documents Relating to His Career as
Kunst der Griechen, espec. 140-57. an Artist, Pt IL.
70 D. R. Edward Wright 1984, ‘Alberti’s De Pictura’, Journal of the 79 Barasch, 53f M. Kemp 1981, Leonardo daVinci;: The Marvellous
Warburg and Courtauld Institutes, XLVI, 52-71. Alberti’s Italian and Works of Nature and Man, 97; and idem, 267f.
Latin texts have now been brought together by C. Grayson, ed. 80 Verbraeken (op. cit. n. 37 above) o1ff; G. F. Folena 1951,
1973, Alberti, Opere Volgari, 111, although Grayson has not accepted ‘Chiaroscuro Leonardesco’, Lingua nostra, XII, 56-62; Z. Z. Filipezak
the convincing arguments of Simonelli for placing the Italian 1977, ‘New Light on Mona Lisa: Leonardo’s Optical Knowledge
before the Latin version (M. P. Simonelli 1972, ‘On Alberti’s Trea- and His Choice of Lighting’, Art Bulletin, LIX, 518-22. C. J. Farago
tises and Their Chronological Relationship’, Yearbook of Italian 1991, ‘Leonardo’s color and chiaroscuro reconsidered: the visual
Studies, 1971, 75-102). force ofpainted images’, Art Bulletin, LXXIII, 63-88.
71 S. Y. Edgerton 1969, ‘Alberti’s Colour Theory: A Mediaeval 81 J. Shearman, 1962, ‘Leonardo’s Colour and Chiaroscuro’,
Bottle without Renaissance Wine’, Journal of the Warburg and Cour- ZeitschriftfiirKunstgeschichte, XXV, 30.
tauld Institutes, XXXII, 112ff. C. Maltese 1976, ‘Colore, luce e 82 J. Meder, Die Handzeichnung, 2nd ed. 1923, 116,136.
movimento nello spazio Albertiano’, Commentari, XXVIL, 238-46, 83 T. Brachert 1970, ‘A Distinctive Aspect of the Painting Tech-
has contested Edgerton’s view of Alberti’s traditionalism, but has nique of the Ginevra de’Benci and of Leonardo’s Early Works’ in
replaced it with an equally implausible notion that Alberti was Washington, DC, National Gallery of Art, Report and Studies in the
276
NOTES TO THE TEXT
History ofArt 1969, 84ff idem 1974, ‘Radiographische Untersuchungen 96 For the earlier literature, see F. Amrine, ‘Goethe and the Sci-
am Verkiindigungsbild von Monte Oliveto’, Maltechnik/Restauro, ences: An Annotated Bibliography, VII, Color Theory and Optics’
LXXX, 180; and idem 1977, ‘Die beiden Felsgrottenmadonnen von in F, Amrine, F. J. Zucker and H. Wheeler 1987, Goethe and the
Leonardo da Vinci’ in ibid., LXX XIII, 11. Sciences: A Reappraisal (Boston Studies in the Philosophy ofScience,
84 Dittmann (op. cit. n. 26 above) r19; cf. W.J. Hofmann 1971, XCVII), 419-23; S. M. Gruner 1974, ‘Goethe’s Criticisms of Newton’s
Uber Diirers Farbe. Opticks’, Physis, XVI, 66-82; N. B. Ribe 1985, ‘Goethe’s Critique of
85 B. Saran 1972, ‘Der Technologe und Farbchemiker “Matthias Newton: A Reconsideration’, Studies in the History and Philosophy of
Griinewald’”’, Maltechnik, IV, 228ff. Science, XVI, 315-35; F. Burwick 1986, The Damnation of Newton:
86 Apart from the works by Barasch and Gavel (op. cit. n. 78 Goethe's Color Theory and Romantic Perception (chap. II ofthis study is
above), the chief studies have been J. A. Thornton 1979, ‘Renais- the best English account of Goethe’s theory and its reception); G.
sance Color Theory and Some Paintings by Veronese’, PhD diss., Bohme, ‘Is Goethe’s Theory of Color Science?’ in F. Amrine et al.,
University of Pittsburgh; idem, ‘Paolo Veronese and the choice of Goethe and the Sciences... ,147-73; H. O. Proskauer 1986, The Redis-
colors for a painting’ in M. Gemin (ed.) 1990, Nuovi Studi su Paolo covery of Color: Goethe versus Newton Today (a trans. of Zum Studium
Veronese, 149-65; P. Rubin 1991, ‘The art of colour in Florentine von Goethes Farbenlehre, 1951); D. L. Sepper, ‘Goethe against Newton:
painting ofthe early sixteenth century: Rosso Fiorentino and Jacopo Towards Saving the Phenomenon’, in Amrine ef al., 175-93; idem,
Pontormo’, Art History, XTV, 175-91; M. Hall 1992, Color and Meaning: Goethe contra Newton. Polemics and the Project
for a New Science of Color,
Practice and Theory in Renaissance Painting; C. Wagner 1996, Farbe und 1988 (the most useful history of Goethe’s researches for readers
Matapher: Die Entstehung einer neuzeitlichen Bildmetaphorik in der without German); and M. J. Duck 1988, ‘Newton and Goethe
vorromischen Malerei Raphaels. L. K. Caron 1985, ‘Choices Concern- on Colour: Physical and Physiological Considerations’, Annals of
ing Modes of Modeling during the High Renaissance and After’, Science, XLV, 507-19.
fiirKunstgeschichte, XLVUI, 476-89; idem 1988, ‘The Use
‘Zeitchrift 97 D. Gray 1952, Goethe the Alchemist; and B. J. T. Dobbs 1975, The
of Color by Rosso Fiorentino’, Sixteenth-Century Journal, XIX, 355- Foundations of Newton’s Alchemy. See now the remarks of A. E.
78. | have tried to detach Giorgione and Titian from colour-theory Shapiro 1993, Fits, Passions and Paroxysms: Physics, Method and Chem-
in Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, 34, but see D. Gioseffi 1979, istry and Newton’s Theories of Coloured Bodies and Fits of Easy Reflection,
‘“Giorgione e la pittura tonale’ in Giorgione: Atti del Convegno Inter- 74-6, 1160n.
nazionale di Studio per il 50 Centenario della Nascita 1978, 95, for an 98 See, however, the over-pessimistic discussion by M. K. Tor-
attempt to link Giorgione’s practice with the ‘four-colour theorem’ bruegge 1974, “Goethe’s Theory of Color and Practicing Artists’,
of mathematics. Germanic Review, XLIX, 189-99. Torbruegge finds little evidence of
87 For Arcimboldo, see T. D. Kaufmann 1989, The School ofPrague. Goethe’s effect on artists in any period, although his impact on the
Painting at the Court of Rudolph I; for Kepler, Opera Omnia, ed. C. early 20th century, on the avant-garde, and on other artists is well
Frisch 1858, I, 200; and for de Boodt, C. Parkhurst 1971, ‘A Color documented: A. Brass 1906, Untersuchungen tiber das Licht und die
Theory from Prague: Anselm de Boodt’, Allen Memorial Art Museum Farben, I, Teil. Brass was close to an unspecified group of artists in
Bulletin, XXUX, 3-10. Scarmilionius’s De Coloribus was published at Munich (M. Richter, Das Schrifttum tiber Goethes Farbenlehre, 1938,
Marburg in 1601. For the general cultural milieu of Prague, see R. J. no. 41). For the revival of interest in Goethe’s work in Kandinsky
W. Evans 1973, RudolfIIand His World; and Essen, Villa Hiigel, and and Mondrian, see below pp.195, 252, 260. The use of Goethe’s
Vienna, Kunsthistorisches Museum, Prag um 1600: Kunst und Kultur Theory by E. L. Kirchner and the Dutch painter Jan Wiegers was the
am Hofe Rudolphs I, 1988. subject of the exhibition, Goethe, Kirchner, Wiegers. De Invloed van
88 See Kemp (op. cit. n. 76) 275-82, for a summary of this litera- Goethe’s Kleurenleer, Groningen Museum, 1982.
ture. For Testa, see Cropper (op. cit. n. 12 above). 99 Most recently Heinz Matile has represented the view that
89 J. C. Bell 1985, “The Life and Works of Matteo Zaccolini (1574- Runge’s and Goethe’s views on colour were closely related: P. O.
1630)’, Regnum Dei, XLI, 227-58; idem 1993, ‘Zaccolini’s theory of Runge, Farben-kugel, Neudruck der Ausgabe Hamburg 1810 mit einem
color perspective’, Art Bulletin, LXXV, 91-112. Janis Bell is prepar- Nachwort von Heinz Matile, 1977, Nachwort 11-1; Matile (op. cit. n.
ing an edition of Zaccolini’s writings on colour, part of which 93 above) 148, and espec. 224-7 on Runge’s links with Goethe’s
appeared in her dissertation, ‘Color and Theory in Seicento Art. earlier Beitrage zur Optik; on p. 231 Matile points to some important
Zaccolini’s ‘Prospettiva del Colore’ and the Heritage of Leonardo’, differences between Goethe’s and Runge’s views, and on pp. 235-41
PhD diss., Brown University 1983. to their very similar approach to harmony. For a more sceptical
90 B. Teyssédre 1965, Roger de Piles et les débats sur le coloris au siecle de treatment, see below Chapter 13.
Louis XIV. For a brief English summary, see A. Soreil 1963, ‘Poussin 100 This was, however, only published in recent times: S. A. Forsius,
versus Rubens: The Conflict between Design and Colour in France’, Physica, ed.J.Nordstrém 1952, Uppsala Universitets Arsskrift, X, 316-
Palette, XII, 3-12; and for some Roman antecedents to this debate, 19. Forsius’s colour-space is not three-dimensional in the modern
see M. Poirer 1979, ‘Pietro da Cortona e il dibattito disegno-colore’, sense, as Runge’s is, since the Swede sought to incorporate black and
Prospettiva, XVI, 23-30. white into the two-dimensional section of the sphere. On Forsius,
g1 M. Rzepitska 1986, “Tenebrism in Baroque Painting and Its see R. L. Feller and A. S. Stenius 1970, ‘On the Color-Space ofSigfrid
Ideological Background’, Artibus et Historiae, XIII, 91-112. Forsius’, Color Engineering, VIII, 48-51.
92 Kemp (op. cit. n. 76 above) 286-90. tor H. Matile (op. cit. n. 93 above) has related Runge’s metaphysics
93 Colour-systems have been investigated by F. Gerritsen 1979, to Jacob Boehme’s colour-theory, 130-42; and to German Romantic
‘Evolution of the Color Diagram’, Color Research and Application, thought, ‘Runges Farbenordnung und die “unendliche Kugel” in
IV, 33ff C. Parkhurst and R. L. Feller 1982, “Who Invented the H. Hohl (ed.) 1979, Runge Fragen und Antworten, 269-72. The most
Color Wheel?’, ibid., VI, 219ff; M. Richter 1984, ‘The Develop- coherent account of Lomazzo’s colour-theory is now Kemp (op.
ment of Color Metrics’, ibid., IX, 69-83; S. Hesselgren, “Why cit. n. 76 above) 66-77.
Color-Order Systems?’ ibid., 220-28; H. Matile, Die Farbenlehre 102 Matile (op. cit. n. 93 above) 202-3.
Phillipp Otto Runges, and ed. 1979. 58-83; and Kemp (op. cit. n. 76 103 See M. Kemp, ‘Yellow, Red and Blue. The Limits of Colour
above) 289-92. ae Science in Painting, 1400-1730’ in A. Ellenius (ed.) 1985, The Natural
94 J. E. Purkinje 1918, Beobachtungen und Versuche zur Physiologie der Sciences and the Arts (Actua Universitatis Upsaliensis, XXII), 98-105.
Sinne, IL (1825), Opera omnia, Prague, I, 118f and P. de la Hire 104 The German context has been outlined by B. Rehfus-Dechéne
(1685), Dissertations sur les differens accidens de la Viie I, V, in Baxandall 1982, Farbengebung und Farbenlehre in der deutsche Malerei um 1800. For
(op. cit. n. 20 above) 90. For some later painterly examples, see England, see G. Finley 1967, ‘Turner: An Early Experiment with
above, ch. 1. . Colour Theory’, Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes,
XXX, 357-66; P. D. Schweitzer 1982, ‘John Constable, Rainbow
95 On Meyer's contribution, see Strauss (op. cit. n. 23 above) 335.
NOTES TO THE TEXT
Science, and English Color Theory’, Art Bulletin, XLIV, 424-45; also in Hess (op. cit. n. 31 above), 64-9. See also C. Boyle-Turner
and Gage (op. cit. n. 4 above), 12-28. A study of the French litera-
1983, Paul Sérusier, espec. 84.
120 R. Shiff 1978, ‘Seeing Cézanne’, Critical Inquiry, IV, 786ff and
ture is one of the most urgent tasks of the colour historian. See now
‘The problem with colour: three theorists, Goethe, idem 1978, ‘The End of Impressionism: A Study in Theories of
B. Howells,
Artistic Expression’, Art Quarterly, new ser. I, 347ff.
Schopenhauer, Chevreul’ in P. Collier and R. Lethbridge (eds)
121 For extreme perceptualist views see G. J. R. Frankl (1951),
1994, Artistic Relations: Literature and Visual Arts in Nineteenth Century
France, 76-93.
‘How Cézanne Saw and Used Colour’ in J. Wechsler (ed.) 1975,
105 Matile (op. cit. n. 93 above) 185-91. Cézanne in Perspective, 125-30; H. Damisch, ‘La Géometrie de la
couleur’ in C. de Peretti (ed.) 1982, Cézanne, ou la peinture en jeu, 42.
106 J. Gage 1969, Colour in Turner: Poetry and Truth, espec. chap. 1 I;
and idem 1984, ‘Turner’s Annotated Books: Goethe’s Theory of 122 L. Gowing, ‘The Logic of Organized Sensations’ in W. Rubin
Colours’, Turner Studies, IV, 2, 34-52. G. Finley 1973 has pointed to (ed.) 1977, Cézanne: The Late Work, 55-71; E. Strauss (1980), “Nach-
Tumer’s positive evaluation of Newton about 1818: ‘A “New betrachtungen zur Pariser Cézanne-Retrospective 1978’ in Strauss
Route” in 1822: Turner’s Colour and Optics’, Journal ofthe Warburg (op. cit. n. 23 above) 164, 183. Both Gowing and Strauss seek to
and Courtauld Institutes, XXXVI, 380, n. 33. See also U. Seibold analyse the painter’s idiosyncratic terminology, but neither of them
1987, Zum Verstandis des Lichts in der Malerei J.M. W. Turners, PhD looks at its immediate context in French philosophy and psychol-
diss., Heidelberg, 101-11, and G. Finley, ‘Pigment into Light’: ogy. I have tried to make a start in ‘Constancy and Change...’ (cit.
Turner and Goethe’s “Theory of Colours” in F. Burwick and n. 118 above).
J. Klein (eds) 1996, The Romantic Imagination: Literature and Art in 123 Matisse (op. cit. n. 14 above) notable for its detailed index;
England and Germany, 357-76. D. Fourcade 1976, ‘Autres Propos de Henri Matisse’, Macula, 1;
107 L. Johnson 1963, Delacroix, 63-72, based on idem 1958, ‘Colour J. Flam (ed.) 1973, Matisse on Art (a shorter selection than the
in Delacroix: Theory and Practice’, PhD diss., Cambridge Univer- French, but with some pieces not in Fourcade); H. Roethel and
sity. See also J. B. Howell 1982, ‘Eugéne Delacroix and Color: H. Hahl-Koch 1980, Kandinsky: Die Gesammelte Schriften, 1; W.
Practice, Theory and Legend’, Athanor, I, 37-43. Kandinsky, Complete Writings on Art, ed. K. Lindsay and P. Vergo
108 For the note and the triangle, see Kemp (op. cit. n. 76 above) 1982; idem, Ecrits, ed. P. Sers 1975 (Vol. III of this edition includes
308;J.F .L. Mérimée (1830), De la Peinture a l’huile, 1981, ill. facing the unpublished notes for his Bauhaus lectures); F. Marc, Schriften,
272 and 274-5. For the date of the note, see below p. 297, col. 2, n. ed. K. Lankheit 1978; F. Kupka, La Création dans les arts plastiques,
15. Delacroix and Mérimée were both members of agovernment ed. and trans. E. Abrams 1989; R. Delaunay, Du Cubisme a l'art
committee on the arts in 1831 (L. Rosenthal 1914, Du Romantisme au abstrait, ed. P. Francastel 1957; R. and S. Delauney, The New Art
réalisme, 5). For Mérimée’s career, Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, of Color, ed. and trans. A. A. Cohen 1978; P. Klee, Schriften Rezen-
214-15. zionen und Aufsaze, ed. C. Geelhaar 1976; idem, The Diaries, ed. F.
109 For the lecture notes, now in the Cabinet de Dessins of the Klee 1965; J. Spiller, ed. 1964, Paul Klee: The Thinking Eye; idem
Louvre, see Kemp (op. cit. n. 76 above) 310, and for Delacroix’s 1973, Paul Klee, The Nature of Nature (both extracts from Klee’s
proposed visit to the chemist, see Signac (op. cit n. 62 above) 76. Bauhaus lectures); P. Mondrian, The New Art -The New Life: The
110 For Blanc’s interpretation of Delacroix, see Johnson (op. cit. Collected Writings, ed. and trans. H. Holzmann and M. S. James
n. 28 above) 63-72; G. Roque 1996, ‘Chevreul and Impressionism: a 1986; T. van Doesburg, Scritti di arte di architettura, ed. S. Polano
reappraisal’, Art Bulletin, LX XVIII, 26-39. 1979; J. Baljeu 1974, Theo van Doesburg; W. Nicholson 1987,
111 M. Song,1984, Art Theories of Charles Blanc, 1813-1882. Unknown Colour, H. Hofmann, The Search for the Real, 2nd ed. 1967;
112 The colour-star in Grammaire des arts du dessin (1867), 599, K. Malevich, Essays on Art, ed. and trans. T. Andersen 1969-78;
derives fromJ. Ziegler 1850, Etudes céramiques, 199, repr. in idem idem, Ecrits, ed. A. Nakov, 2nd ed., 1986; and V. Knight (ed.) 1988,
1852, Traité de la couleur et de la lumiere, 16. Patrick Heron.
113 R. L. Herbert ef al.. 1991, Georges Seurat 1859-1891, 397-8. The 124J. E. Bowlt 1976, Russian Art of the Avant-Garde: Theory and
fullest account of the papier de Gauguin is in M. Roskill 1960, Van Criticism, 1902-1934; N. Watkins 1984, Matisse, drawing on his 1979
Gogh, Gauguin and the Impressionist Circle, 267-8. Roskill inclined to dissertation, ‘A History and Analysis of the Use of Colour in the
think that the text, printed conveniently in L. Nochlin (ed.) 1966, Work of Matisse’, M.Phil. thesis, London, Courtauld Institute; V.
Impressionism and Post-Impressionism, 1874-1904, 166-7, was authenti- Spate 1979, Orphism; W. Rotzler, Johannes Itten: Werke und Schriften,
cally Turkish, but parts of it seem too close, e.g., to Blanc, Gram- 2nd ed. 1978; C. Lodder 1983, Russian Constructivism. A. Doig 1986,
maire, 606, not to arouse our suspicions. Theo van Doesburg: Painting into Architecture, Theory into Practice. C.
114 R. A. Weale 1972, ‘The Tragedy of Pointillisme’, Palette, XL, Blotkamp et al. 1986, De Stijl: The Formative Years. W. Venzmer
16ff; A. Lee 1987, ‘Seurat and Science’, Art History, X, 203-26. See 1982, Adolf Hoelzel: Leben und Werk.
also below Ch. 16. 125 H. B. Chipp 1958, ‘Orphism and Color Theory’, Art Bulletin,
115 A. Laugel 1869, L’Optique et les arts, 151. For Delacroix’s circle, XL, 55-63;J.E. Bowlt 1973-4, ‘Concepts of Color and the Soviet
see Johnson (op. cit. n. 28 above), 56, pl. 34. For Seurat’s, see below, Avant-Garde’, The Structurist, XIII/XIV, 20-9; C. Douglas, ‘Colors
pl. 106. without Objects: Russian Color-Theories (1908-1932) in ibid., 30-
116 Herbert (op. cit. n. 115 above);J.Arguélles 1972, Charles Henry 41; J. F. Moffitt, ‘Fighting Forms: The Fate of the Animals: The
and the Formation ofaPsychophysical Aesthetic. Occultist Origins of Franz Marc’s “Farbentheorie’”’, Artibus et Histo-
117 Badt (op. cit. n. 31 above). nae, XII, 1985, 107f R. Wankmiiller 1960, ‘Zur Farbe bei Paul Klee’,
118 E. van Uitert, “De toon van Vincent van Gogh: Opvattingen Studium generale, XI, 427-35; M. Huggler 1967, ‘Die Farbe bei Paul
over Kleur en zijn hollandse Periode’, Simiolus, Il, 1966-7, 106, 108-9 Klee’, Palette, XXII, 13-22; E. Strauss (1970), ‘Paul Klee: Das Licht und
(with English summary), has made a careful study of Vincent's early Etliches’ (op. cit. n. 33 above) 219-26; idem, ‘Zur Helldunkellehre
use of Fromentin and Blanc. See B. Welsh-Ovcharov 1976, Vincent Klees’, ibid. 227-39; L. Nochlin, ‘Picasso’s Color: Schemes and
van Gogh; His Paris Period, 1886-1888, 65-6;J.A. Walker 1981, “Van Gambits’, Arts in America, Dec. 1980, 105-23; 177-83; R. Bothner
Gogh’s Colour Theories and Their Relevance to the Paintings of 1987, ‘Mark Rothkos Modulationen’, Pantheon, XLV, 172ff. I have
the Arles Period’ in Van Gogh Studies; Five Critical Essays, 7, n. 6. I taken the discussion of Rothko rather further in ‘Rothko: Color as
have touched on Vincent's use of A. Cassagne, Traité d’aquarelle Subject’, an essay for the catalogue of the Rothko exhibition, Wash-
(1875) in ‘Constancy and Change in Late Nineteenth-Century ington, DC, National Gallery of Art, 1998.
French Painting’ in United Kingdom Instititute for Conservation 126 For example, C. C. Bock 1981, Henri Matisse and Neo-
Reprints, Appearance, Opinion, Change: Evaluating the Look of Paint-
Impressionism, 1898-1908; S. Buckberrough 1982, Robert Delaunay:
ings, 1990, 32-5. The Discovery of Simultaneity; G. Levin 1978, Synchromism and Ameri-
119 P. Séruster (1921), ABC de la peinture, 3rd ed. 19$0, 29, 94-5;
can Color Abstraction, 1910-1925; N. G. Parris 1979, ‘Adolf Hoelzel’s
278
NOTES TO THE TEXT
279
NOTES TO THE TEXT
Gebrauch der Edelsteinallegorese vom friihen Christentum bis ins 18 Jahrhun- example, P. Mitchell 1990, “Wright’s Picture Frames’ in J. Edgerton,
Wright of Derby, London, Tate Gallery.
dert, Bk I, 152. . ;
160 B. H. Crawford 1960, ‘Colour rendition and Museum Light-
152 For example, see Meier (op. cit.) 147ff, on the sard. See also her
ing’, Studies in Conservation, V, 41-51: H. Ruhemann 1961, ‘Experi-
general discussion of the problems of symbolic interpretation (I 974)
ences with the Artifical lighting of Paintings’ in ibid., IV, 83-85
in ‘Das Problem der Qualitatenallegorese’, Frihmittelalterliche Studien,
(repr. in The Cleaning ofPaintings, 1968, 344-8); G. Thomson 1961,
VIII, espec. 387ffon colour; also F. Ohly 1977, Schriften zur mittelal-
terlichen Bedeutungsforschung, XVI-XXI. For the ill-fated dictionary
‘A New Look at Colour-Rendering, Level of Illumination, and
Protection from Ultraviolet Radiation in Museum Lighting:, in
of medieval colour symbolism, C. Meier and R. Suntrup 1987, “Zum
ibid., VI, 46-70; B. H. Crawford and D. A. Palmer, ‘Further Inves-
Lexikon der Farbenbedeutungen im Mittelalter’, Frii/mittelalterlichen
Studien, XXI, 390-478 (including a sample entry on ‘red).
tigations of Colour Rendering, and the Classification of Light
153 See, for example, M. Bornstein 1976, ‘Name Codes and Color Sources’ in ibid., 71-82; R. A. Weale 1973, ‘La Lumiére dans les
Memory’, American Journal of Psychology, LXX XIX, espec. 274. Musées’, Chronique des Arts, suppl. to Gazette des Beaux-arts, July-
154 The classic treatment ofJ.B. Weckerlin 1905, Le Drap ‘escarlate’ Aug., 1-2; H. Lank 1984, “The Function of Natural Light in Picture
au Moyen Age, has now been subject to revision by J. H. Munro, Galleries’, Burlington Magazine, CXXVI, 4f& R. S. Berns and F.
‘The Mediaeval Scarlet and the Economics of Sartorial Splendour’ Grum 1987, ‘Exhibiting Art Work: Consider the Illuminating
in N. B. Harte and K. G. Ponting (eds) 1983, Cloth and Clothing in Source’, Color Research and Application, X11, 63-72.
Mediaeval Europe, 13f€ but there is no doubt that the documents 161 Schone (op. cit. n. 25 above) 260, n. 448.
record ‘scarlets’ of many hues. A similar case is the obsolete colour 162 The modern literature differs considerably in estimating this
term perse, which comprised many colours, and may also refer to a figure: for ‘some ten million colours’, see K. Nassau 1983, The
quality of cloth (below p. 68). Physics and Chemistry of Color, 7; for seven million, C. A. Padgham
155 M. Pastoureau 1979, Traité d’hérvaldique; and idem 1983, Armor- andJ.E. Saunders 1975, The Perception of Light and Colour, 104; for
ial des chevaliers de la Table Ronde. Arthurian heraldic blazon has also one million, H. Terstiege, ‘The CIE Colour-Coding System’ in J.
been treated in detail by G. J. Brault 1972, Early Blazon, Heraldic D. Mollon and L. T. Sharpe (eds) 1983, Colour- Vision: Physiology and
Terminology in the Twelfth and Thirteenth Centuries with Special Refer- Psychophysics, 563.
ence to Arthurian Literature. Many of Pastoureau’s essays have been 163 The standard study is now B. Berlin and P. Kay, Basic Color
gathered in L’Hermine et le sinople, 1982; Figures et couleurs: Etudes sur Terms, 2nd ed. 1991, but see also n. 183 below. On trichromacy
la symbolique et la sensibilité médiévales, 1986; and Couleurs, images (cit. in colour vision, see J. D. Mollon, ‘Colour Vision and Colour
n. 5 above). Pastoureau’s insistence on the abstract character of Blindness’ in Barlow and Mollon (op. cit. n. 17 above), 165ff. To
heraldic colour, restated recently in ‘Vers une histoire sociale des my knowledge, only one modern artist, Gerrit Rietveld, has related
couleurs’ (Couleurs, images, 43) seems to me to overlook the history his use of ‘primary’ colours (implausibly) to the mechanics ofvision.
and concrete character of heraldic language, which he has also noted For the notion of ‘primary colours’ in aesthetics, see E. E. Gloye
in passing (Couleurs, décors, emblémes’ in Figures et couleurs, 52). 1957-8, ‘Why are There Primary Colours?’ Journal of Aesthetics and
156 ‘Farbe (Liturgisch)’, Reallexikon zur deutschen Kunstgeschichte, V1, Art Criticism, XVI, 128ff.
1981, cols 54-139. 164 P. Trevor-Roper, The World Through Blunted Sight, 2nd ed.
157 On Rubens, see C. Parkhurst 1961, ‘Aguilonius’ Optics and 1988, chaps I, III. See also R. W. Pickford 1965, “The Influence of
Rubens’ Color’, Nederlands Kunsthistorisch Jaarboek, XII, 35-49; M. Colour-Vision Defects on Painting’, British Journal of Aesthetics, LI1,
Jaffé 1971, ‘Rubens and Optics: Some Fresh Evidence’, Journal of 211ff idem, ‘Colour Defective Students in Colleges of Art’ in ibid.
the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes, XXXIV, 326-66; and Kemp 1967, 132ff; ‘The Artist’s Eye’, British Medical Journal, 19 Aug. 1972,
(op. cit. n. 76 above) 275-7. On Poussin, see O. Batschmann, ‘Farb- 434 (cf. also correspondence in ibid., 586, 702, 826): P. Lanthony
genese und Primirfarbentrias in Nicholas Poussins “Die Heilung 1982, ‘Daltonisme et peinture’, Journal francais d'ophthalmologie, V,
der Blinden”’ in M. Hering-Mitgau et al. (n. 139 above), 329-36; 373-85, idem 1994, ‘J. J. Peintre Daltonien’, ibid., XVII, 596-602:
idem, Dialektik der Malerei von Nicholas Poussin, 1982 (English trans. R. W. Pickford and J. Bose 1987, ‘Colour Vision and Aesthetic
1990), chaps I, III; and Kemp (op. cit. n. 76 above) 278-81. On Problems in Pictures by Rabindranath Tagore’, British Journal of
Turner, seeJ.Gage, Colourin Turner (cit. n. 106 above), chap. 11. Aesthetics, XXVII, 70-5; G. H. Hamilton, ‘The Dying ofthe Light:
158 Fora structural analysis ofthis series, seeJ.Albrecht 1974, Farbe The Late Work of Degas, Monet and Cézanne’ in J. Rewald and
als Sprache: Robert Delaunay, Josef Albers, Richard Paul Lohse, 60-113. F. Weitzenhofter (eds) 1984, Aspects of Monet: A Symposiuim on the
159 The study of frames and hanging conditions has blossomed in Artist’s Life and Times, 223-37; O. Sacks 1995, “The case of the
recent years: seeJ.Foucart 1987, ‘Bibliographie du cadre’, Revue de colour-blind painter’ in An Anthropologist on Mars, 1-38; and P.
l'art, LX XVI, 60-62. This issue of the review also contains a number Lanthony 1989, Les Effets de cataracte sur les oeuvres picturales.
of important articles on framing from the Renaissance to the roth 165 I. M. Siegel and G. B. Arden, ‘The Effects of Drugs on Colour
century, including J. Foucart, ‘Etude critique de l’encadrement’, Vision’ in A, Herxheimer (ed.) 1968, A Symposium on Drugs and
7-14; C. Grimm, ‘Histoire du cadre: Un Panorama’, 15-20. See Sensory Functions, 210-28, espec. 217 on alchohol and tobacco.
also the number of The International Journal of Museum Management, 166 A. von Wattenwyl and H. Zollinger 1981, “Color Naming by
IV, 1985, devoted to framing; and the Cahiers du Musée National Art Students and Science Students’, Semiotica, XX XV, 303-15.
d’Art Moderne, XVII/XVIII, 1986, ‘L’Ocuvre et son accrochage’, 167 For the early history of chromotherapy, see R. D. Howat 1938,
which included two important essays on Matisse’s frames: D. Four- Elements of Chromo-Therapy, 1ff. The classic text is C. Féré 1887,
cade, ‘Crise du cadre: A Propos d’un tableau de Matisse, Le Peintre Sensation et mouvement. Kandinsky knew of the subject at least
dans son atelier’, 68-76; and J. C. Lebensztejn, “Constat amiable’, through the article by Karl Scheffler. ‘Notizen iiber die Farbe’,
84-91. There have also been a number of recent exhibitions on Dekorative Kunst, 1V, 1901: see below 251. See also B. D. Prescott
framing: Italienische Bilderrahmen des 14-18 Jahrhunderts, Munich, 1942, ‘The Psychological Analysis of Light and Color’, Occupational
Alte Pinakothek, 1976; La Cittd degli Uffizi, Florence, Uffizi, 1983; Therapy and Rehabilitation, XX1, 142-6; K. Goldstein, ‘Some Experi-
Prijst de Lijst, Amsterdam, Riksmuseum, 1984; The Art of the Edge:
mental Observations Concerning the Influence of Colors on the
European Frames 1300-1900, Chicago Art Institute, 1986; Oretcouleur:
Function of the Organism’ in ibid., 147-51. The article by E. and
Le Cadre dans la seconde moitié du dix-neuvieme siecle, Paris, Musée
P. Gruss 1982, ‘Der Einfluss des Farbsehens auf die Motorik bei
d’Orsay, 1989 (see the book of the exhibition, I. Cahn, Cadres de Gesunden, und Hirnkranken’, Festschrift
fiirH. Roosen-Runge, 277f,
peintres, 1989); Amsterdam, Van Gogh Museum, In Perfect Harmony:
is little more than a repetition of Goldstein’s experiments. For a
Picture and Frame, 1850-1920, 1995. Just as exhibitions of paintings survey of the hitherto meagre results in this branch of experimental
now encourage studies of problems of technique and conservation,
psychology, see P. K. Kaiser 1984, ‘Physiological response to color:
so scholars are beginning to take more notice of frames: see, for A Critical Review’, Color Research and Application, IX, 29-36.
280
NOTES TO THE TEXT
168 The Liischer Colour Test, trans. and ed. I. Scott, 1971, 50.
181 W. Waetzoldt 1909, ‘Das theoretische und praktische Problem
169 The most extensive study seems to be H. J. Eysenck 1941, ‘A
der Farbenbenennung’, Zeitschrift
fiirAsthetik und allgemeine Kunst-
Critical and Experimental Study of Color Preferences’, American
wissenschaft, 1V, espec. 384 P. Coremans, ‘La Notation des couleurs.
Journal of Psychology, LIV, 388: blue, red, green, violet, orange, yellow.
Essai d’application aux Primitifs flamands’ in M. Meiss (ed.) 1961,
A slightly divergent scheme, apparently based on much the same
De Artibus Opuscula, XL: Essays in Honor of Erwin Panofsky, 76-81.
earlier literature, is R. W. Burnham, R. M. Haines, C. J. Bartleson
182 See the exemplary bibliography by M. Grossmann 1988, Colori
1963, Color: A Guide to Basic Facts and Concepts, 209-10. Some more
e lessico: Studi sulla struttura semantica degli aggettivi di colore in catalano,
recent tests, in which, for example, blue remains the preferred
castigliano, italiano, romano, latino ed ungherese, 320-9. Perhaps the
colour in most European countries, except Spain (and Peru), are most useful studies for the art historian are: D. G. Hays et al. 1972,
mentioned by Pastoureau, ‘Vers une Histoire sociale des couleurs’
‘Color Term Salience’, American Anthropologist, LX XIV, 1107ff; M.
(cit. n. § above), 13-14, but unfortunately he gives no references. Durbin 1972, “Basic Terms — Off Color?’, Semiotica, VI, 257-78;
See also I. C.McManus, A. L.Jones,J.Cottrell 1981, ‘The Aesthetic N. B. McNeil 1972, ‘Colour and Colour Terminology’, Journal
of Colour’, Perception, X, 651-66. of Linguistics, VIII, 21ff; H. C. Conklin, ‘Colour Categorization’,
170 For a Constructivist artist who has used the Liischer system American Anthropologist, LXXV, 931-42; H. Zollinger, ‘A Correla-
(as well as those of Aristotle, Goethe, and G. Wyszecki), see H. tion between the Linguistics of Colour-naming and Colour percep-
Stierlin (ed.) 1981, The Art of Karl Gerstner, which includes (1644) an tion’, Colour 73 (cit. n. 171 above), 38off, R. Kuschel and T. Monberg
appreciation by Liischer himself. 1974, ‘We don’t talk much about color here’. A Study of Colour
171 Heimedahl (op. cit. n. 43 above), 165ff; R. W. Pickford 1971, Semantics on Bellona Island’, Man, [X, 213-42; C. B. Merrin et al.
‘The Liischer Test’, Occupational Psychology, XLV, 151-4; and R. 1975, Development ofthe Structure of Color Categories’, Develop-
Lakowski and P. Melhuish 1973, “Objective Analysis ofthe Liischer mental Psychology, XI, 54-60; M. Sahlins 1976, ‘Colors and Cultures,’
Colour Test’ in International Colour Association, Colour 73, 486-9. Semiotica, XVI, 1ff; F. Ratliff 1976, ‘On the Psycho-Physiological
172 For example, C. E. Osgood, G. J. Suci, P. H. Tennenbaum Bases of Universal Color Terms’, Proceedings of the American Philo-
1957, The Measurement of Meaning, Ul, 292ff: and G. Cerbus and sophical Society, CXX, 311-30; B. Lloyd, “Culture and Colour
R. C. Nichols 1963, ‘Personality Variables and Response to Colour’, Coding’ in G. Vesey (ed.) 1977, Communication and Understanding
Psychology Bulletin, LX, 566-75. (Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures), 141ff H. Zollinger 1979,
173 For a short critical survey of these types of theory, see R. “Correlations between the Neurobiology of Colour Vision and
Arnheim 1974, Art and Visual Perception: A Psychology of the Creative the Psycholinguistics of Colour Naming’, Experientia, XXV_ 1-8;
Eye: The New Version, 346ft. Carl Loef has recently sought to recon- idem, ‘Farben-gesehen, erkannt und erlebt’ in Hering-Mitgau et al.
cile the value-based theory with the musical octave: ‘Die Bedeu- (op. cit. n. 139 above) 9-12; W. D. Wright 1984, ‘The Basic Con-
tung der Musik-Oktave im optischen-visuellen Bereich der Farbe’ cepts and Attributes of Colour Order Systems’, Color Research and
in Hering-Mitgau et al., 227-36. Application, IX, 229-3; U. Eco 1985, ‘How Culture Conditions the
174 V. K. Ball 1965, ‘The Aesthetic of Color: A Review of Fifty Colors We See’ in M. Blonsky, On Signs, 157-75.
Years’ Experimentation’, Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, XXII, 183 Several fundamental studies of colour-terminology relevant to
44rft. the history of Western art are now available: for Ancient Egypt, J.
175 I. W. A. Whitfield and P. E. Slatter 1978, ‘Colour Harmony: Baines 1985, ‘Color Terminology and Color Classification: Ancient
An Evaluation’, British Journal ofAesthetics, XVII, 1890ff. Egyptian Color Terminology and Polychromy’, American Anthropol-
176 See, for example, H. Zeishold 1944, “Philosophy of the Ostwald ogist, LXXXVII, 282-97; for Hebrew, A. Brenner 1982, Colour
Color System’, Journal of the Optical Society of America, XXXIV, Terms in the Old Testament; for Greek, C. Mugler 1964, Dictionnaire
355f& Hesselgren (op. cit. n. 94 above); and R. S. Berns and F. W. historique de la terminologie optique des Grecs; P. G. Maxwell-Stuart
Billmeyer,Jr (op. cit n. 128 above). 1981, ‘Studies in Greek Colour Terminology, I, Glaucos, II, Karopos,
177 See the extensive bibliography in F. Mahling 1926, “Das Mnemosyne, suppl. LXV; for Latin,J.André 1949, Etude sur les termes
Problem der “Audition Colorée’”’, Archiv fiir die gesamte Psychologie, de couleur dans la langue latine; for Coptic, W. C. Till 1959, ‘Die Far-
LVII, 165ff. For some effects on painterly research and practice, see benbezeichnungen im Koptischen’, Analecta biblica (Oriens antiquus),
below pp. 192, 247, 251, ch. 21. XII, 331-42; for Anglo-Saxon, N. Barley 1974, ‘Old English Colour
178 L. E. Marks, 1978, The Unity of the Senses; S. Baron-Cohen,J. Classification: Where Do Matters Stand?’ Anglo Saxon England, III,
E. Harison (eds) 1997, Synaesthesia; Classic and Contemporary Read- 15-28; IV, 1975, 145-54; for Old German, J. Konig 1927, “Die
ings; M. Dériberé 1978, ‘ The Relationship between Perfumes and Bezeichnung der Farben’, Archiv fiir die gesamte Psychologie, LX,
Colours’, Color Research and Application, WI, 115f; S. Baron-Cohen, 145ff; for Old French, A. G. Ott 1899, Etudes sur les couleurs en vieux
M. A. Wyke, C. Binnie 1987, ‘Hearing Words and Seeing Colours: frangais (repr.1977); for Slavic languages, G. Herne 1954, Die slavis-
An Experimental Investigation of aCase of Synaesthesia’, Perception, chen Farbenbenennungem (Publications de l'Institut Slave d’Upsal,
XVI, 761-7. This study examines the case of an elderly female IX), 24ff P. M. Hill 1972, Die Farbworter der russischen und bulgar-
painter. See also below ch. 21. ischen Schriftsprache der Gegenwart; for Catalan, Spanish, Italian,
179 G. T. Fechner, Vorschule der Aesthetik, 2nd ed. 1897-8, I, 176; U, Romanian and Hungarian, see Grossmann (op. cit. n. 182 above).
3 15 ff. 184 R. Byron 1985, First Russia, Then Tibet (1933), 99-100.
180 Kandinsky, Complete Writings (cit. n. 123 above), I, 193. For 185 For example, W. Voge 1891, Eine deutsche Malerschule um die
Kandinsky and Schoenberg, see J. Hahl-Koch (ed.) 1984, Arnold Wende des ersten Jahrtausends, 165, who found the information gath-
Schoenberg — Wassily Kandinsky: Letters, Pictures and Documents. The ered from his ‘systematisch geordneten Farbentafel’ too difficult
more or less close interest of many 20th-century artists in musical to convey in language; E. H. Zimmermann 1916, Vorkarolingische
aesthetics has been documented in a number of studies, notably Miniaturen, UX, used a commercial colour-maker’s chart; O. Graut-
Kunsthaus, Zurich, Stadtische Kunsthalle, Diisseldorf, Museum des off 1914, Nicholas Poussin: Sein Werk und sein Leben, included his
20. Jahrhunderts, Vienna, Der Hang zum Gesamtkunstwerk: Europais- own table of 62 samples prepared by a painter.
che Utopien seit 1800, 1983; K. von Mauer (ed.) 1985, Vom Klang der 186 H. Fuerstein, ed., Fiirstlich Fiirstenbergische Sammlungen zu
Bilder: Die Musik in der Kunst des 20. Jahrhunderts. Paul Klee has been Donaueschingen: Verzeichnis der Gemiilde, 3rd ed. 1921, XI, and, for
particularly well served by studies of his musical interests and activi- example, 15, no. 98. Ostwald’s system was applied only in a few
ties: R. Verdi 1968, ‘Musical Influences on the Art of Paul Klee’, instances; for a later recourse to it, see H. Chorus 1933, Gesetzmas-
Museum Studies (Chicago), UI, 81f& A. W. Kagan 1983, Paul Klee: sigkeit der Farbgebung in der ottonischen Buchmalerei, PhD diss.,
Art and Music; Paris, Centre Georges Pompidou, Klee et la musique, Cologne, 8f, 54.
1985-86 (German ed. 1986). But none ofthese studies devotes much 187 M. Saltzman’s paper, ‘Color Terminology: Can We Talk with
attention to the question of
colour. Each Other?’ given at the 1980 Temple University conference,
281
NOTES TO THE TEXT
‘Color and Technique in Renaissance Painting’, and advocating frequently in the Swiss pharmaceutical journals CIBA Review and
the Munsell system, is mentioned by Hall (op. cit. n. 71 above) XXI. Palette. :
1961, Uber das Licht in der Malerei, espec. 5, 68.
One ofthe first scholars to use the Munsell Book of Color was proba- 2 Wolfgang Schéne
Schéne’s terms derive from the Eigenwert and Darstellungswert of
bly Joy Thornton (diss. cit. n. 86 above); for recent examples, see
1983, The Sculpture of Palenque, Princeton, I, xvul,
colour proposed by H. Jantzen in 1913 (‘Uber Prinzipien der
M. G. Robertson
97; 1985, Il, 69-72; 1985, II, 99-103; A. W. Epstein 1986, Tokali Farbengebung in der Malerei’, reprinted in Uber den gothischen
Kirchenraum, 1951, 61-7). His view ofthe irrelevance of contempo-
Kilise:. Tenth-Century Metropolitan Art in Byzantine Cappadocia,
Washington, DC, s8f. rary theory was contested by A. Neumayer 1955 in his review (Art
Bulletin, 37, 302-3), which also provides a useful English summary of
188 O. M. Lilien 1985, Jacob Christophe Le Blon, 1667-1741, Inventor
of Three and Four Colour Printing; also see the review by J. Gage 1986 a difficult book. Something like a development from Eigenlicht to
in Print Quarterly, II, 65-7. See alsoJ. Friedman 1978, Color Printing Beleuchtungslicht has indeed been traced in the medieval philosophy
in England, 1486-1870, Yale Center for British Art, New Haven; of light between the 13th and the 15th centuries by G. F. Vescovini
S. Lambert 1987, The Image Multiplied: Five Centuries of Reproduction 1965, Studi sulla Prospettiva Medievale. For Koloritgeschichte, see above,
of Paintings and Drawings, 87-99; F. Rodin (ed.) 1996, Anatomie de Chapter 3.
la Couleur: l’Invention de l’Estampe en Couleurs. 3 B. Berlin and P. Kay 1969, Basic Color Terms, 2nd ed. 1991.
189 For example, the processes desribed by E. Robinson and K. 4 For critiques of Berlin and Kay, see especially the survey in M.
R. Thompson 1970, ‘Matthew Boulton’s Mechanical Paintings’, Grossmann 1988, Color e Lessico: Studi Sulla Struttura semantica degli
Burlington Magazine, CXII, 497¢f. aggettivi di color in Catalano, Castigliano, Italiano, Romano Latino ed
190 On the early lithographic facsimiles and their technical prob- ungherese, 16-17, and Chapter 2 above. E. Irwin 1974, Colour Terms
lems, see C. Nordenfalk 1976, Color of the Middle Ages, A Survey of in Greek Poetry, espec. 220ff. For Latin: J. André 1949, Etudes sur les
Book Illumination Based on Color Facsimiles of Medieval Manuscripts, Termes de Couleur dans la langue Latin; for Anglo-Saxon, N. F. Barley
Pittsburgh, University Art Gallery; also E. Spalletti 1979, ‘La docu- 1974, ‘Old English Colour Classification: where do matters stand?’,
mentazione figurativa dell’ opera d’arte, la critica e l’editoria nell’ Anglo-Saxon England, Il, espec. 17.
epoca moderna (1750-1930)’ in Storia dell’arte italiana, II, 415-484; 5 Although J.J. G. Alexander’s 1975 article ‘Some Aesthetic Princi-
and T. Fawcett 1986, ‘Graphic versus Photographic in the Nine- ples in the Use of Colour in Anglo-Saxon Art’, Anglo-Saxon
teenth-Century Reproduction’, Art History, LX, 195-200. England, IV, 145f§, was ostensibly linked to Barley’s linguistic study
191 B. Coe 1978, Colour Photography. The First Hundred Years. (cit. n. 4 above), it did not make use of these findings, but inter-
192 For Warburg’s use of a coloured ‘Lumiére-Lichtbild’ at the preted colour-usage chiefly in terms ofnaturalism.
1912 International Congress of Art History, see T. Fawcett 1983, 6 See espec. P. Toynbee 1902, Dante Studies, 307-14; also M. Mann
‘Visual Facts and the Nineteenth-Century Art Lecture’, Art History, 1923 in Romania, XLIX, 186ff and E. Hoepfiner in ibid. $92ff.
VI, 457. Berenson, who had, of course, pioneered the use of black- 7 The oth-century inventory of the monastery of S. Riquier refers
and-white photography in the 1890s, seems by 1921 to have consid- to persae sericae in a list of coloured vestments (J. Wickham Legg
ered coloured slides to be superior to black-and-white ones for 1882, ‘Notes on the History of the Liturgical Colours’, Transactions
lecturing (A. K. McComb (ed.) 1965, The Selected Letters of Bernard of the St Paul’s Ecclesiological Society, 1, iii, 99), and in the 11th-century
Berenson, 90). gift of Robert Guiscard to Monte Cassino was Tunicam unam de
193 Colour, Oct. 1920, 43. panno perso inaurato (O. Lehmann-Brockhaus 1938, Schriftquellen zur
194 E. Diez and O. Demus 1931, Byzantine Mosaics in Greece: Hosios Kunstgeschichte des 11 und 12 Jh.f.Deutschland, Lothringen und Italien,
Lukas and Daphni, VU-VII. I, no. 2844). For Persia as the chief intermediary of the silk trade,
195 H. Ruhemann (1951), ‘The Masters’ Methods and Colour O. von Falke, Kunstgeschichte der Seidenweberei 2nd ed. 1921, 2f.
Reproduction’, repr. in The Cleaning ofPaintings, 1968, 353. 8 H. Roosen-Runge 1967, Farbgebung und Technik Frithmittelalter-
196 For example, J. Widman 1958, “Die Colorphotographie im licher Buchmalerei, U1, 66f€.
Dienste der Kunstpflege und Forschung’, Festschrift Johannes Jahn, 9 H.B. Gottschalk 1964, ‘The De Coloribus and its Author’, Hermes,
223-4. XCII, 59, proposes Theophrastus as the author; E. Franceschini
197 R. Longhi 1952, ‘Pittura-Colore — Storia e una domanda’, 1955, ‘Sulle versioni latine medievali del mept YPM@LOTOV, in Autour
Paragone, XX XIII, 3-6. See also the editorial in the Burlington Maga- @’Aristote: Recueil d'études offerta M. A. Mansion, 451, reports more
zine, CV, 1963. 47f; R. Longhi 1964, ‘Il critico accanto al fotografo, than eighty codices of the Latin translation attributed to Bartolomeo
al fotocolorista e al documentarista’, Paragone, CLXIX, 29-38. See also da Messina (1258/66).
Kudielka, op. cit. n. 137 above. Now of course computers and videos to R. D’Avino 1958, “La Visione del Colore nella Terminologia
have changed the whole future picture of colour documentation. Greca’, Richerche Linguistiche, IV, espec. 101, 103ff, 108f: P. Zancani
198 P. C. Beam 1942-3, “The Color Slide Controversy’, College Art Montuoro, ‘Colore’, in Encyclopedia dell’Arte Antica, Classica, e Ori-
Journal, 11, 35-8;J.M. Carpenter, ‘The Limitations of Color Slides’, entale, Il, 1959, 770ff C. Mangio 1961, “Cenni sulle teorie cro-
ibid., 38-40. matiche dei Greci e loro applicazioni architettoniche’, Studi Classici
199 See E. Wind 1963, Art and Anarchy, 165f: ‘Since the ordinary e Orientali, X, espec. 214; Irwin (op. cit. n. 4 above), 213ff.
photographic plate is sensitive to a larger range of shades than can be 11 Johannes Philoponus 1959, In Aristotelis Meteorologicorum librum
recorded in colour, the best black-and-white reproduction of a primum commentarium, 47, 18. Urso of Salerno, De Coloribus, ed.
Titian, Veronese or Renoir is comparable to a conscientious piano Thorndyke, Ambix, VU, 15.
transcription of an orchestral score, whereas the colour print, with 12 The most comprehensive recent study is in Pauly-Wissowa,
some exceptions, 1s like a reduced orchestra with all the instruments Real-Enzyklopadie d. Klass. Altertumswissenschaft, Supp. Il, cols 461ff,
out of tune.’ sv ‘Farbung’.
200 For example, R. G. W. Hunt, ‘Problems in Colour Reproduc- 13 A.J. Hopkins 1934, Alchemy Child of Greek Philosophy, 117. For
tion’, Colour 73 (cit. n. 171 above), 53ff. the medieval developments, J. Read, Prelude to Chemistry, 2nd ed.
1939, 14sft.
14 Eraclius De Coloribus et Artibus Romanorum, Ul, vii (13th century),
4 Colour in History — Relative and Absolute ed. C. G Romano 1996. For a modern account, M. G. Chesneau
1933, “Contribution a l’Etude de la technique des Vitraux du
1 S. Skard 1946, “The Use of Color in Literature: a Survey of Moyen-Age’, Bulletin Monumental, XCU.
Research’, Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, XC, 181. 15 F. Haeberlein 1932/3, ‘Zur Farbenikonographie des Mittelal-
Skard’s list could now be much expanded: see above Chapter 3. ters’, Annales Institutorum, V, 103-4, where it is claimed that a fixed
Essays on colour of special interest to historians of art have appeared canon of Farbvokabeln obtained until the period of High Scholasti-
282
NOTES TO THE TEXT
283
NOTES TO THE TEXT
41 Mesarites (op. cit. n. 33 above) 872. Weitzmann (op. cit. n. 39 hauer 1969, Die Architektur der Pariser Oper, 168f), opposed this atti-
tude (C. Garnier 1869, A Travers les Arts, 179f), as, later, did scholars
above) 14-15 accounts for the absence of Mount Tabor in the St
like E. Didron 1875 (‘La Peinture en Mosaique’, Gazette des Beaux-
Catherine’s mosaic by referring to St John Crysostom’s Homily on
Arts, ser. I, vol. XI, 449f) and E. Gerspach 1880 (‘La Mosaique
the Metamorphosis, “not with a cloud over his head, but surrounded
Absidale de Saint-Jean de Lateran’, ibid., XXI, 141ff) who discussed
by Heaven’, but since no earlier version of the subject including
Tabor has come to light, the point does not seem to be a crucial one the rendering of Christ’s hair in terms of Chevreul’s law ofsimulta-
neous and successive contrast (146-7).
(see ‘Verklirung Christi’ in Lexikon der Christlichen Ikonographie, ed.
Kirschbaum 1972, IV). 55 F. Cachin 1971, Paul Signac, 85f, 88. It must, however, be said
42 The conception of God as darkness in the earlier Old Testament that he did acquire some reproductions of mosaics, and that most
tradition (until about the 6th century Bc) has been examined by of the important medieval mosaics in Constantinople were not
J. Hempel 1960, ‘Die Lichtsymbolik in Alten Testament’, Studium uncovered until after his visit.
“Generale, XIII, espec. 355-8, 367f. For the survival of some of these 56 Paul Adam, cit. Herbert (op. cit. n. 53 above) 16.
ideas in medieval Jewish mysticism, G. Scholem 1972, ‘Farben und 57 Homer (op. cit. n. 2 above) 288, n. 22.
ihre Symbolik in der judischen Uberlieferung und Mystik’, Eranos 58 Fora wide-ranging discussion ofthe scientific credentials of Neo-
Yearbook, XLI, espec. $, 23f. Impressionism, P. Smith 1997, Seurat and the Avant-Garde, ch. 2.
43 See espec. E. von Ivanka, ‘Dunkelheit, mystische’, in Reallexikon 59 The phenomenon was stressed in the first important account of
fiir Antike und Christentum. It is remarkable that in the versions ofthe Neo-Impressionism, by Felix Fénéon 1886, La Vogue, 13-20 June
‘episodes of Moses and the Burning Bush and Moses receiving the (Oeuvres plus que completes, ed. Halperin 1970, I, 36-7). In 1888 Seurat
Law later than the triumphal arch at Sinai, the first shows God’s called this article ‘the exposition of my ideas on painting’ (Homer,
hand emerging from a cloud of light, the second from a cloud of op. cit. n. 2 above, 290 n. 31).
darkness (H. Buchthal 1938, The Miniatures of the Paris Psalter, pl. X; 60 ‘Videntur autem sic propter distantiam aut velocitatem motio-
K. Weitzmann 1973, Illustrated Manuscripts at St Catherine’s Monastery nis, Cum visus in unoquoque istorum debilis fiat aspiciendi et intelli-
on Mount Sinai, pl. XXX). gendi singulas partes. Quoniam, si distantia rerum videndarum
44 Celestial Hierarchy, XV, §8, ed. Rocques 1958, 186ff, who notes quantitatem habuerit ita ut et angulus qui totam rem continet,
that there are no blue horses in the biblical accounts of the Horses of habeat ydoneam quantitatem, singuli autem anguli qui continent
the Apocalypse (Zechariah 1, 8; VI, 2-3; Revelations. VI, 3-7). On the diversos colores, fuerint insensibiles, apparebit ex comprehensione
shift in the Greek interpretation of kuaneos from ‘dark’ to ‘blue’, partium que non discernuntur, cum omnium sensibilitas congre-
Irwin (op. cit. n. 4 above) 108f. The place of darkness in Dionysian gabitur, quod color totius rei sit unus, alter quam singularum
thought has been discussed generally by H. C. Puech 1938, ‘La partium.
Ténébre mystique chez le Pseudo-Denys’, Etudes Carmelitaines, ‘Similiter etiam accidit ex motu vehementis celeritatis, ut moto
XXIII, i. troci plures colores habentis, quia non moratur unus et idem visibilis
45 The fullest account in Dictionnaire de Spiritualité, U1, 1957, ¢. radius super unum et eundem colorem, quoniam recedit color ab
240ff. eo propter celeritatem volutionis. Et sic idem radius, cadens super
46 V.E. Gardthausen 1886, Catalogus codicum graecorum siniaticorum, omnes colores, non potest dividere iter primum et novissimum, nec
nos. 319-25. inter eos qui sunt per diversa loca. Apparent enim omnes colores per
47 Some of these ideas have been conveniently summarized by totum trocum in eodem tempore quasi unus et quod sit similis
E. Panofsky 1944, ‘Note on a Controversial Passage in Suger’s De coloris qui vere fieret ex commixtis coloribus...Si linee autem
Consecratione’, Gazette des Beaux-Arts, LXXXVI. So far as I know, fuerint super trocum constitute et per axem transducte, apparebit in
the only modern discussion of the ‘negative aesthetic’ developed volutione tota superficies troci similem habere colorem...’ (A.
from Dionysius is De Bruyne (op. cit. n. 16 above), II, 21 sf, 247-8. Lejeune 1956, L’Optique de Claude Ptolémée, Il, 95, 59-61). This
48 E.g. Ignatius the Grammarian on the 9th-century mosaic of the sometimes difficult text survives only in an early 13th-century Latin
subject in the Church of the Virgin of the Pege at Constantinople translation from an Arabic version of the original Greek. Hints of
(The Greek Anthology, trans. Paton 1969, I, I, 112); J. Viellard, Le optical mixture through distance had been given tentatively by
Guide du Pelerin de Saint-Jacques de Compostelle, 3rd ed. 1963, 104: Aristotle (De Sensu, 439b, 23ff, an especially interesting text, since
‘Est enim Dominus ibi in nube candida, facie splendens ut Sol, veste it suggests the optical derivation of all colours from mixtures of
refulgens ut nix’; Alexander of Villa Dei, Ecclesiale (ed. and trans. black and white) and through motion in the Peripatetic De Audi-
Lind 1958, 34, 85): ‘a shining cloud [lucida nubes] enveloped them’. bilibus (803b, 34ff). A 1oth-century refinement of the method ofdisc
49 Otto Demus 1948, Byzantine Mosaic Decoration, 38 and fig. 29. mixture seems to lie behind Seurat’s reference to ‘the duration
50 Idem 1949, The Mosaics ofNorman Sicily, 383. of a light-impression on the retina’ in a letter of 1890 (Homer, op.
51 First reported by C. Angrand to H. E. Cross about 1891 (R. Rey cit. n. §2 above, 140f).
1931, La Renaissance du Sentiment Classique, 95); with slightly differ- 61 Lejeune, loc. cit. n, 60 above, 17*.
ent wording, Angrand in G. Coquiot 1924, Seurat, 41. 62 R. Koldewey 1884, ‘Das Bad von Alexandria-Troas’, Athenische
52 Seurat himself acknowledged a debt to Blanc, Delacroix, Mitteilungen, IX, 39f. The tesserae found here were of both stone
Chevreul, Monet, Pissaro and Rood in a letter of 1890 (W. I. Homer and glass. Literary references in Pliny, Natural History, XXXV, 64;
1964, Seurat and the Science of Painting, 17, with an analysis of these Statius, Silvae, 1, 5, 42-3; Seneca, Epistolae, LXXVI, 6f.
sources). For Lehmann, A. Boime 1970, The Academy and French 63 The only example known to me is the coarse, pebble-like vault
Painting in the Nineteenth Century, 114ff colour-photography: L. of Criptoportico D in Hadrian’s Villa at Tivoli, published by
Moholy-Nagy 1947, Vision in Motion, 158-9; Japanese prints: H. G. Lugli 1928, Bulletino della Commissione Communale di Roma, LV,
Dorra 1970, ‘Seurat’s Dot and the Japanese Stippling Technique’, 1O8fE.
Art Quarterly, XXXII; colour-printing: N. Broude, ‘New Light on 64 One 2nd-century AD example is in the distant landscapes and
Seurat’s “Dot”: its Relation to Photomechanical Color Printing in water in the small inset floor mosaics from Hadrian’s Villa now
France in the 1880s’, Art Bulletin, LVI, 1974. in the Vatican (M. Wheeler 1964, Roman Art and Architecture, figs
53 R.L. Herbert 1968, Neo-Impressionism, New Y ork, Guggenheim 473-4).
Museum, 220f. 65 Colour plate: G. Kawerau and T. Wiegand 1930, Altertumer von
54 Chevreul himself surprisingly took the view that mosaic was Pergamon, V, i, pl. VIII. The ‘rainbow’ borders found frequently in
hardly more than an imitation of painting, although it should not early medieval manuscript illumination, in which each colour-band
be too refined to tell over a distance (The Principles of Harmony and has a serrated edge, like mosaic tesserae set at an angle of45 degrees
Contrast of Colours, trans. Martel 1854, 176); Garnier, who had to the line, clearly derive from mosaic practice such as the interlace
admired medieval mosaics in Sicily and Constantinople (M.-Stein- borders in the late-Antique vault of Sta Constanza in Rome (Comp.
284
NOTES TO THE TEXT
X) (G. Matthiae 1967, Mosaici Medioevali delle Chiese di Roma, pls I, details Filarete gives (e.g. the five values of each hue, like the
II). The earliest MS example I have found is in a 6th-century Greek
6th/7th-century Byzantine mosaic palette of4 to 8 values recorded
Dioscurides, Materia Medica, (Vienna Nat. Bibl. Vindob. med. er. I,
by B. Rubin 1954, Byzantische Zeitschrift, XCVII, 439, and 4 or 5
f. 4r, repr. A. Grabar 1966, Byzantium from the Death of Theodosius to values used in the Kariye Djami, Underwood, op. cit. n. 65 above, I,
the Rise ofIslam, fig. 215). The almost contemporary mosaic of the 181), suggest the persistence of traditional methods. Five values
Virgin and Child at Lynthrankomi seems to have a similar arrange- were also the norm in wall painting (D. Winfield 1968, ‘Middle and
ment in its ‘rainbow’ mandorla (just visible to the far left in pl. II later Byzantine wall-painting methods’, Dumbarton Oaks Papers,
of A. Stylianou 1963, Cyprus: Byzantine Mosaics and Frescoes). The XXII, 136ff).
clearest example of the painter borrowing from mosaic convention 78 Lejeune (op. cit. n. 60 above), 27%.
in this context is in the 14th-century decoration of the Kariye Djami 79 Notably C. Mango 1963, ‘Antique Statuary and the Byzantine
in Istanbul (P. Underwood 1967, The Kariye Djami, Il, pl. 44, ILI, Beholder’, Dumbarton Oaks Papers, XVI, espec. 64ff; H. Maguire
pl. 411). 1974, “Truth and Convention in Byzantine Descriptions of Works
66 E.g. 4th-century Salonika, Hagios Georgios, head ofStGeorge of Art’, ibid., XXVIII, espec. 128ff D. S. Wallace-Hadrill 1968, The
(good pls in H. Torp, Mosaikkene i St Georg-rotunden, 1963); 11th- Greek Patristic View of Nature, 97£. Ekphrasis has now been studied in
century Daphni, Head of the Virgin in Crucifixion (pl. 78); 13th- relation to colour in L. James 1996, Light and Colour in Byzantine Art.
century Rome, formerly St Peter’s, Giotto’s Navicella (G. Matthiae, 80 There is a suggestion that flesh areas were sometimes left until
loc. cit., pl. LX VIII); 14th-century Istanbul, Kariye Djami (Under- last, presumably to be executed by the leading master (Underwood,
wood, loc. cit., II, pls 33, 34, 45, 69, 70, 263, 326). op. cit. n. 65 above, I, 1796).
67 E.g. sth-century Bitola (Heraclea Lyncestis) pavement (G. C. 81 A. Chastel and F. Minervino 1973, Tout l’Oeuvre Peint de Seurat,
Tomasevié 1973, Heraclea Lyncestis, Bitola figs 16-19); e7th-century pl. XLII.
Istanbul, Great Palace (Mosaic Museum) (Grabar, op. cit. n. 65 above, 82 D.C. Rich 1936, Seurat and the Evolution of ‘La Grande Jatte’, 34-5.
fig. 108 — not the best example from this pavement). 83 P. Bruneau 1972, Les Mosaiques de Delos, no. 214, Matthiae (op.
68 E.g. 8th-century Rome, Chapel of John VII (P. J. Nordhagen cit. n. 65 above), pls 91, 94. Matthiae argues (pp. 154ff) that these are
1965, ‘The Mosaics of John VII’, Acta Instituti Romani Norvegiae, II, all contemporary, and that the setter of the Apostles was in charge of
I§1). the whole scheme and probably had connections with Ravenna. He
69 E.g. sth-century Rome, Sta Maria Maggiore: Abraham visited by also identifies a third artist, responsible for S. Hyppolitus (pl. XX).
Angels (Grabar, op. cit. n. 65 above, fig.157); 12th-century Mon- 84 Fenéon (op. cit. n. 59 above) I, 74 (1887).
reale (Kitzinger, op. cit. n. 65 above, pls 2, 47); 13th-century Rome, 85 Vasari (1568), Le Vite, Milan 1965, VII, 332; Reynolds (1788),
Sta Prassede, Chapel ofS.Zeno, Tabernacle (Matthiae) (op. cit. n. Discourse XIV; Constable wrote of Count Forbin, the organizer of
65 above, pl. LXIII). For lustre, which occurs when the eye is unable the 1824 Salon: ‘He is no artist (I believe) and he thought “as the
to decide whether to distinguish or to fuse the dots, Fénéon (op. cit. colours were rough, they must be seen at a distance” — they found
n. 59 above). their mistake as they then acknowledged the richness ofthe texture
70 Some examples in Sta Maria Maggiore in Rome and S. Apol- —and the attention to the surface of objects in these pictures’ (Corre-
linare Nuovo in Ravenna are cited by G. Bovini, “Origine e tecnica spondence, ed. Beckett 1968, VI, 185).
del mosaico parietale paleocristiana’, Felix Ravenna, 2nd ser. 1954, 86 C. Mango (op. cit. n. 23 above), 197; also 205 (sermon of Leo
7. Instances in the 9th-century apse mosaic in Haghia Sophia in VI).
Istanbul have been noticed by C. Mango and E. J. Hawkins 196s, 87 Metamorphoses, I, 5. |have discussed the medieval interpretation
Dumbarton Oaks Papers, X1, 125. of this tag in Colour and Culture, 1993, 75-6.
71 E.g. the late-Antique heads of Dionysius and a Maenead, from 88 C. Mango 1958, The Homilies of Photius, 187.
Utica, in the British Museum (nos. 54 g, k). Striking medieval 89 For Empedocles, K. Freeman 1966, Ancilla to the Pre-Socratic
examples are in S. Apollinare Nuovo (col. pls in G. Bovini 1958, Philosophers, Frags. 22-3. The same conception is repeated in the De
Mosaici di S. Apollinare Nuovo di Ravenna), and in the Chapel of Mundo attributed to Aristotle, but probably composed in the second
S. Zeno at Sta Prassede (e.g. W. Oakeshott 1967, The Mosaics of century AD (396b).
Rome, pl. V). 90 Freeman, loc. cit., 92-8.
72 For example by Demus (op. cit. n. 50 above), 135; Bovini (op. 91 De Mixtione, II, 214, 18, in M. C. Nahm, Selections from Early
cit. n. 70 above), 12. Greek Philosophy, 4th ed. 1964, 164. Mango (op. cit. n. 88 above)
73 S. Lauffer 1971, Diokletians Priesedikt, 118-19, 234-5. F. Deich- unaccountably cites Aristotle, Metaphysics, 985b to illustrate Photius’s
mann 1974, Ravenna: Hauptstadt des Spatantiken Abendlandes, II, 189, point.
recognizes the irrelevance of this document, but proposes a single 92 Joannis Stobaei Eclogarum Physicarum et Ethicarum Libri Duo (Greek
designer and many executants, on grounds of style. and Latin), I, 1792, ch. XVII, 362ff. For Photius’s copy (cod. 167),
74 Kitzinger (op. cit. n. 65 above) 130, n. 106. R. Henry 1960, Photius: La Bibliotheque, I, 149ff.
75 F. Forlati 1949, ‘La Tecnica dei Primi Mosaici Marciani’, Arte 93 Theophrastus, in Stratton (op. cit. n. 27 above) 132ff. Galen and
Veneta, III, 86; Mango and Hawkins (op. cit. n. 70 above), and the Aétius in Nahm (op. cit. n. 91 above), 160, 176.
summary of research by S. H. Young 1976, ‘Relations between 94 The ‘primary’ palette is described by Angrand in Coquiot (op.
Byzantine Mosaic and Fresco Decoration’, Jahrbuch der osterreichis- cit. n. $1 above) 40, but Signac claimed that he had already intro-
chen Byzantinistik, XXXV. duced Seurat to the ‘prismatic’ arrangement in 1884 (Homer, op.
76 The text in B. Bischoff 1984, Anecdota Novissima: Texte des Vierten cit. n. 52 above, 151). Also W. I. Homer 1959, ‘Seurat’s Palette’,
bis Sechzehnten Jahrhunderts (Quellen und Untersuchungen zur urlington Magazine, Cl, 192-3.
Lateinischen Philologie des Mittelalters 7), 223. Since the rather 95 Moralia, Loeb (ed.) 1961, IX, 156-7, cf. also ibid., 247; 1962, IV,
scanty Carolingian revival of mosaic seems to have relied on spoils 47f, and especially V, 48of. Medieval usage: H. Silvestre 1954,
from Ravenna for cubes (H. E. del Medico 1943 in Monuments Piot, ‘Le MS Bruxellensis 10147-58 et son Compendium artis picturae’,
XXXIX, 85), it is not surprising that only setting is discussed here, Bulletin de la Commission Royale d’ Histoire, CXTX, 138.
although there are recipes for making green, gold and silver cubes in 96 Mappae Clavicula, op. cit. n. 29 above, ch. ix, xi, 27-8. The best
the Lucca MS (op. cit. n. 29 above), 5-6, 86-90. survey ofthe literature is W. W. Bulatkin 1954, “The Spanish word
77 The treatise Sul Modo di tagliare ed applicare il musaico (2c. 1415), ‘Matiz’: Its Origin and Semantic Evolution’, Traditio, X. Roosen-
ed. Reali 1858, 12f, leaves it an open question ‘se tu sai desegnare’. Runge (op. cit. n. 8 above) and Winfield (op. cit. n. 77 above) have
It was written by a Venetian craftsman working outside S. Marco shown that these prescriptions were widely practised. Roosen-
(cf. p. 4), but Filarete in mid-century found similar practices there Runge, Vol. II for a catalogue ofthe colour-terms.
97 Mappae, loc. cit. n. 29 above. The MS of
the De Clarea unfortu-
(Treatise on Architecture, trans. Spencer 1965, 312). Some of the other
285
NOTES TO THE TEXT
286
NOTES TO THE TEXT
287
NOTES'TO THE TEXT
Ghiberti’, Rivista di Storia Critica delle Scienze Medicale e Naturali, 1V, Ghiberti. His window in colour in Marchini (op. cit. n. 1 above)
62, although he has not taken the analysis of the contents very far. fig.54. Both Gaddi and Uccello are cited as pictori in the documents,
E. Panofsky 1955 noted that Ghiberti’s concept of proportionality, whereas Ghiberti is called sculptor (magister intagli).
24 Bergdolt (op. cit. n. 2 above) 178.
while drawing on Alhazen, altered Alhazen’s emphasis completely
25 The Opera di Prospettiva, which exists only in an early 16th-
(Meaning in the Visual Arts, 89-90 n.). For a discussion of Ghiberti’s
century MS (Florence Riccardiana 2110), but was attributed to
choice of sources, A. Parronchi, Studi su la Dolce Prospettiva, 1964,
3 18fF; cf. also 383f. f Alberti by A. Bonucci (Opere Volgari di L. B. Alberti, IV, 1847),
6 Commentari, ed. Morisani (op. cit. n. 2 above), 41f.
includes a number of remarks on the persistence of vision and on
light as at once the condition and destruction of vision (ed. cit. 104,
7 L.B. Alberti, Della Pittura, ed. Mallé, 1950, $s.
8 Bergdolt (op. cit. n. 2 above) 6. 132) which reinforce the more recent attribution to a Ghibertian
9 Commentari, ed. Morisani, 44.
milieu (G. Nicco Fasola 1942-3, ‘Lo svolgimento del pensiero
10 E.g. where Alhazen describes (Bk I, ch. i) the after-image ofa prospettico nei trattati da Euclide a Pero della Francesca’, Le Arti, V,
brightly-lit white object viewed for some unspecified time, Ghiberti 66). Parronchi has republished this MS with an attribution, based
gives precisely ‘un terzo d’ora’. Bergdolt (14-16) follows Vescovini chiefly on language, to Paolo dal Pozzo Toscanelli (Studi..., cit. n. 5
1965 (‘Contributo per la storia della fortuna di Alhazen in Italia: il above), 299.
volgarizzamento del MS Vat. 4595 e il “Commentario Terzo” del 26 As has been suggested, for example, Kris, loc. cit. (n. 12 above).
Ghiberti’, Rinascimento, ser. 2, V, 32) in pointing out that this Italian For Niccoli’s real concerns, Krautheimer (op. cit. n. 1 above) 301 f;
version specified ‘un ora’, which must have seemed a good deal too E. H. Gombrich, ‘From the revival ofletters to the reform of the
long to Ghiberti. Vescovini, in Lorenzo Ghiberti nel suo Tempo (cit. n. arts: Niccolé Niccoli and Filippo Brunelleschi’, Essays in the History
1 above, 369-73), cites parallel passages on the effect of light on ofArt presented to Rudolph Wittkower, 1967, espec. 78-81; P. Castelli
vision which also show Ghiberti’s freedom with his source. in the exhibition catalogue, Materia e Ragionamenti, Florence 1978,
11 Ghiberti’s version (Bergdolt, 22) may be roughly translated: 534-7.
27 Vespasiano da Bisticci, Renaissance Princes, Popes and Prelates, ed.
if the viewer looks at a polished body with carvings in low relief Gilmore 1963, 402; cf. 399 on the chalcedony.
on its surface, and if there be various colours in these carvings, as
28 J. von Schlosser 1910, ‘Lorenzo Ghibertis Denkwiirdigkeiten’,
there are in cha [lcedonies], which are composed of several Kunstgeschichtliches Jahrbuch der K. K. Zentral-Kommission, I-IV, 134.
colours, and if the viewer is in a moderately illuminated place 29 Ambrogio Traversari, Latinae Epistolae..., ed. Cannetus and
facing the light or some strongly-lit wall which reflects some
Mehus 1759 (repr. 1968), II, cols 411f; Krautheimer (op. cit. n. 1
light into his eyes...
above) 301. For Ghiberti and Traversari, Castelli (op. cit. n. 26
Bergdolt (23, n. 5) makes rather heavy weather of this passage and above) $31-4.
does not notice that, unlike Alhazen, Ghiberti is concerned with 30 Traversari’s letter has been usefully reprinted in M. Baxandall
parti-coloured stones. I have discussed another passage in Ghiberti’s 1971, Giotto and the Orators, 152-4, and on Traversari’s humanist
account oflooking at sculpture in Colour and Culture, 1993, 120. vocabulary, 13-14. In the shorter account of the Basilica Ursiana in
12 Bergdolt (32-6). This chalcedony passed from the Niccoli col- his book of travels (Hodeopoericon, 1681, 49) Traversari applied the
lection through that of Pope Paul II to the Medici, whose 1492 mirror image to that building rather than to S. Vitale. For a recon-
inventory described it as ‘in transparent intaglio with no foil’ (in struction ofthe basilica and illustrations of some surviving capitals in
chavo trasparente sanza fondo: E. Miintz, Les Collections des Medicis au the Museo Archivescovile at Ravenna, G. Bovini 1964, Storia e
XV Siécle, 1888, 69). As well as the version from the Medici collec- Architettura degli Edifici Paleocristiani di Culto di Ravenna, 101-25.
tion (pls 38, 39) there are many 1sth-century copies and variants 31 On the aesthetic oflight, Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, ch. 3.
(E. Kris 1929, Meister und Meisterwerke der Steinschneidekunst in der 32 For Niccoli’s approval, Traversari to Niccoli, July 1433 in Latinae
Italienischen Renaissance, I, 2of, II, pl. s). Epistolae (cit. n. 25 above), col. 414; for Pope Nicholas V’s view that
13 B. Cellini, ‘Del’ Oreficeria’ in Opere, ed. Maier 1968, 625. ‘he understood it better in his simple text than in the others with
14 On this relationship,J. R. Johnson 1964, The Radiance ofChartres, the numerous comments and notes they contained’, Vespasiano da
57-66; R. Silva 1996, ‘Il colore dell’ inganno: gemme, perle, ambra e Bisticci (op. cit. n. 27 above) so. For the earlier translations, M. de
corallo secondo un manoscritto del XIII secolo’ in Il Colore nel Gandillac (ed.) 1943, Oeuvres Completes du Pseudo-Denys |’Aréopagite,
Medioevo: Arte, Simbolo, Tecnica, 27-39. 12f.
15 Except by G. Poggi 1909, Il Duomo di Firenze, XCI n. 2, and 33 Traversari began his translations in 1431 and had completed the
E. Giusto 1911, Le Vetrate di S. Francesco in Assisi, who suggested that task by 1437 (A. Dini-Traversari, Ambrogio Traversari e i suoi Tempi,
he was the glass-painter Antonio di Giomeo da Leccio, recorded n.d. 135 ff).
in Pisa in 1386-7 and 1407. 34 De Divinis Nominibus, ch. IV, lect. v. A useful English trans. and
16 See Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, 119. S. Pezzella (ed.) 1976, Il commentary (based on the Latin of Johannes Saracenus) by A.
Trattato di Antonio da Pisa sulla Fabbricazione delle Vetrate Artistiche, Coomaraswamy, ‘Medieval Aesthetic: I. Dionysius the Pseudo-
24. Antonio shows how close the glass-painter still was to the Areopagite and Ulrich of Strasburg’, Art Bulletin, XVII, 1935, 3 1ff.
jeweler in his short section (49) on the best gemstones and crystals 35 For Suger and Pseudo-Dionysius, Gage 1993, Colour and Culture,
for cutting glass. ch. 4.
17 Van Straelen (op. cit. n. 1 above) 21, 27. 36 Krautheimer (op. cit. n. 1 above) 311f.
18 Pezzella (op. cit. n.16 above) 25; Marchini (op. cit. n. 1 above)
figs 42-6. For the date of St. Barnabas, Poggi (op. cit. n. 15 above)
docs 657, 677. 7 Color Colorado
19 Poggi (op. cit) doc. 622.
20 Pezzella (op. cit.) 25. C. Cennini, The Crafisman’s Handbook, trans. I See espec. the bibliography in M. Grossmann 1988, Colori e¢
Thompson 1933, 111f. H. Wentzel 1949, ‘“Glasmaler und Maler in Lessico: Studi sulla Struttura Semantica degli Aggettivi di Colore in
Mittelalter’, Zeitschrift des deutschen Vereins fur Kunstwissenschaft, U1, Catalano, Castigliano, Italiano, Romeno, Latino e Ungherese; and L.
54f, notes many 1sth-century German examples of glass-painters Maffi, ‘A Bibliography of Color Categorization Research, 1970-
referred to in documents simply as ‘Maler’. 1990’ in B. Berlin and P, Kay, Basic Color Terms: their Universality and
21 Poggi (op. cit.) doc. 480. Evolution, 2nd ed. 1991.
22 Marchini (op. cit.) 248 n. 53. 2 See, for example, the discussion in B. A. C. Saunders andJ.van
23 Poggi (op. cit.) doc. 757. Cf.J.Pope-Hennessy 1950, Paolo Uccello, Brakel, ‘Re-evaluating Basic Color Terms’, Cultural Dynamics, 1, 3,
145; Krautheimer (op. cit. n. 1 above), 109, for Uccello’s time with 1988, 359-78.
288
NOTES TO THE TEXT
3 Berlin and Kay, loc. cit., 6-7. In publications since 1969 Berlin
13 See D. Gonzales Holguin 1608, Vocabulario de la lengua general de
and Kay have modified some of these criteria: see, for example,
todo el Peru (repr. 1952), under allcca. In Vol. I, 11, of his dictionary,
B. Kay and C. K. McDaniel, ‘The linguistic significance of the Holguin also gives the term ficclla, which has survived as tijllaa
meaning of basic color terms’, Language, 54, 1978, 610-46. (‘bi-coloured’) in modern Quechua (J. Lara, Diccionario Qheshwa-
4 For azul, see R. M. Duncan 1968, “Adjetivos de color en el Castellano — Castellano-Qheshwa, 1971). For chequerboard designs in
Espanol medieval’, Anuario de Estudios medievales, V, 463, 466; also textiles see the Inca tunic in Munich (Levenson, loc. cit. n. 7 above),
the revisions in idem 1975, ‘Color words in medieval Spanish’, no. 449, and another at Dumbarton Oaks, no. 451. There was also a
Studies in Honor of L. A, Kasten, 62. For gris, a term for fur, i Quechua term for ‘chequerboard’ itself: golganpata (‘hill of terraces
Corominas andJ.A. Pascual, Diccionario Critico Etimologico Castellano with storehouses’), and the design seems to have had royal or mili-
e Hispanico, 1980- . The origin of anaranjado remains obscure: tary connotations.
whether, like so many medieval ‘colour’ terms (e.g. purpura, escar- 14 Hernan Cortés, Letters from Mexico, ed. and trans. A. Pagden -
lata) it referred primarily to a type of cloth, or whether it took its 1986, 104. It is notable that colours and dyes formed an jmportant
name from a fruit (English: orange) is still uncertain: see the discus- sector of the goods sold at the market of Coyocan ¢. 1550, in Mexico
sion of Naranje in J. Alfau de Solalinde 1969, Nomenclatura de los in the 1540s and 1550s, and at Tlaxcala from the mid-1540s to the
Tejidos Espaniles del Siglo XIII, 135-7. mid-1560s (J. Lockhart 1992, The Nahuas after the Conquest: a Social
5 Berln and Kay, loc. cit., 7. Daniéle Dehouve has found rather more and Cultural History of the Indians of Central Mexico, 16th through 18th
evidence of the influence of bilingualism in modern Nahuatl: see centuries, 187). It is equally striking that a document of 1610 records
‘Nombrar los colores en Nahuatl (Siglos XVI-XX)’, to be published the purchase specifically of caxtilla tlapalli, ‘Spanish colours’, as
in the papers of the 1994 El Color en el Arte Mexicano conference. opposed to local ones (ibid., 278). So far there have been few
6 Berlin and Kay, loc. cit., 12, 32. detailed studies of the pigments of Aztec painting, or indeed ofthat
7 See the Mixtec mask in Rome in J. A. Levenson (ed.) 1991, Circa of 16th-century Spain. The few tonalamtl which have been analysed
1492: Art in the Age of Exploration, no. 377; and the Aztec Tlaltoc vase technically have revealed the use of some nine hues, some of them
(c. 1470) from the Museo de Sitio del Templo Mayor in Mexico mixtures (K. Nowotny 1961, Codices Becker I/II, Introduction, 23;
City: ibid. no. 368. idem 1968, Codex Cospi: Calendario Messicano 4093, 14-16). The
8 Fray Bernardino de Sahagun, Florentine Codex: General History analysis of the painted sculpture at the Mayan site of Palenque has
ofthe Things of New Spain, ed. and trans. C. E. Dibble and A. J. O. yielded around a dozen nuances (E. Robertson 1983-91, The Sculp-
Anderson 1961, Bk X, ch. 16, 60. This passage is not in Sahagiin’s ture of Palenque, Appendices). See also L. Schele, ‘Color on Classic
own Spanish translation. Chalchiuhnamac relates to chalchiuitl, ‘emerald’ , Architecture and Monumental Sculpture of the Southern Maya
but, according to A. de Molina, Vocabulario en Lengua Castellana y Lowlands’ in E. H. Boone (ed.) 1986, Painted Architecture and Poly-
Mexicana, y Mexicana y Castellana, Mexico 1571 (repr. 1970), in the chrome Monumental Sculpture in Mesoamerica, 32-4. In the Iberian
form ofchalchiuhiximatqui (‘knowledge ofstones’) it has the conno- peninsula ofthe early 17th century around twenty painters’ colours
tation of any stone. It is notable that the earliest known reference have been listed: Z. Veliz 1986, Artists’ Techniques in Golden Age
to the colour of the turquoise in Europe, in the mid-13th-century Spain, 3, 26.
lapidary of Albertus Magnus, it is described as blavus (blue): Albertus 15 Sahagun (loc. cit. n. 8 above) 1961, Bk X, ch. 21, 77.
Magnus, The Book ofMinerals, trans. D. Wyckoff 1967, 123. See also 16 Ibid. 1952, Bk III, ch. 3, 14: chichiltic (chili-red); coztic (golden
A. Pagliaro, ‘Il nome della turchese’, Archivio glottologico italiano, 39, yellow); tlaztaleolaltic (flesh-pink); camopaltic (violet); xoxoctic (green);
1954, 142-65. Pagliaro’s 16th-century edition of Albertus Magnus, matlaltic (blue); quilpaltic (verdigris); viztecoltic (whitish, sometimes
interestingly, reads blavus as flavus (yellow). The Nahuatl term for interpreted as ‘orange’); camiltic (dark-brown); movitic coioichcatl
obsidian in this passage in Sahagtn is maztlalitzli, which is related to (coyote-coloured). For the Spanish version, Fray Bernardino de
the term for ‘fine blue’ and also ‘dark green’, matlalin. The more Sahagun, Historia General de las Cosas de Nueva Espana, ed. A. M.
usual term for blue is fexorli. See also Sahagun’s Bk XI, ch. 8, 1963, Garibay K. 1956 Mexico, I, 279: colorado, encarnado, amarillo, morado,
222-4, on the many green stones. blanquecino, verde, azul, prieto, pardo, naranjado, leonado. Note that the
9 Itzac (white object, from ‘salt’); yapalli (black); chichiltic (red object, Spanish has only one green, where the Nahuatl has two.
from ‘chili-pepper’); quilpalli (blue or green or ‘verdigris’); cuztic 17 Fora well-documented overview, F. Brunello 1968, L’Arte della
(yellow, gold); texotli (blue); quauhpachtli (brown); camopalli (purple); Tintura nella Storia dell’ Umanita, 77-87.
tlaztaleualli (Aesh-pink); xuchipalli (orange); nextic (grey, from ‘ashes’). 18 F. Boas, Primitive Art, 1955, 46-52.
These terms are taken from Molina (loc. cit. n. 8 above). For 19 L. N. O’Neale 1933, ‘A Peruvian multicolored patchwork’,
Sahagtin’s use of this source, R. J. Campbell and M. L. Clayton, American Anthropologist, New series 35, 86-94. The hues include
‘Bernardino de Sahagtin’s contribution to the lexicon of Classical blue, green-blue and turquoise. The textile is in the collection of the
Nahuatl’ in J. J. Klor de Alva, H. B. Nicholson, E. Q. Keber (eds) Phoebe Apperson Hearst Museum ofAnthropology, Berkeley, CA.
1988, The Work of Bernardino de Sahagin, 297. For a general study of 20 C. A. Romero (ed.) 1923, ‘Razon y Forma en Theoria de los
some aspects of this colour-vocabulary,J.H. and K. C. Hill, ‘A note Tintes Reales de Quito...’ (1703) in Inca, I, 455-74. The Araucan
on Uto-Aztecan color terminologies’, Anthropological Linguistics, 12, Indians of Central Chile have used more than twenty vegetable
1970, 235. Molina and Sahagun list many other nuances besides dyestuffs, and describe their effects with some ten colour names
those given above. (Brunello, op. cit. n. 17 above, 84). See also the Chilean Aymara
10 Berlin and Kay (loc. cit. n.1 above) 13. colour-vocabulary for natural and dyed wools in V. Cereceda
11 For a discussion of the history of the idea of ‘primary colours’ 1978, ‘Sémiologie des tissus Andins: les Talegas d’Isluga’, Annales,
and their largely 19th-century interpretation as intrinsic to colour- Economiques, Sociales, Culturales 33, 1023.
science, Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, 34-6, 258-9. 21 For example the colour-terms used by horse-breeders (Gage
12 Georges Roque has drawn my attention to the reconstructed 1993, Colour and Culture, 79), and for the Andean region,J.A. Flores
headdress, largely of quetzal feathers, known as the Penacho de Ochoa 1978, ‘Classification et dénomination des camélides sud-
Moctezuma in the Museo Nacional de Antropologia in Mexico City. Américains’, Annales, ESC 33, toooff.
The colours veer from blue-green to green as the feathers move. 22 See, for example, C. B. Mervis and E. M. Roth, “The internal
The blue feathers at the base were originally from the Cotinga ama- structure of basic and non-basic color categories’, Language, $7,
bilis Gould, known to the Nahua as xiuhtototl (‘turquoise bird’): see TQ81, 384-405.
K. A. Nowotny 1960, Mexikanische Kostbarkeiten aus Kunstkammern 23 For the problems of symbolism, Gage, Colour and Culture, 1993,
der Renaissance im Museum fur Volkerkunde, Wien und in der National- chs:
24 cin for example, K. A. Nowotny 1961, Tlacuilolli: die Mexicanis-
bibliothek Wein, no. 3, 44. The much-damaged original is still in
Vienna. chen Bilderhandschriften: Stil und Inhalt, 254. Nowotny also (233) notes
289
NOTES TO THE TEXT
discrepancies in the colouring of the gods in the codices. Gil Riley; ed. 1902, 11, line 6. It is notable that in Spanish Renaissance usage
‘Color-direction symbolism. An example of Mexican-South Western the traditional stigmatization of Judas and the Jews in general for
their red hair (R. Mellinkoff 1983, ‘Judas’ Red Hair and the Jews’,
contacts’, America Indigena, 23, 1963, 49-60; K. A, Nowotny 1969/70,
Journal ofJewish Art, IX, 31-46) was extended to their ostensibly
‘Beitrage zur Geschichte des Weltbildes, Farben und Weltrichtun-
‘florid complexions: F. Gonzalez Olle, ‘Fisiognomia del color rojizo
gen’, Wiener Beitrige zur Kulturgeschichte und Linguistik, XVII, espec.
en la literatura espafiola del siglo de oro’, Revista de Literatura, 43,
215. E. T. Baird, ‘Naturalistic and symbolic color at Tula, Hidalgo’,
in Boone (op. cit. n. 14 above) 124-6; H. B. Nicholson, ‘Polychrome 1981, 153-63.
41 Sahagtin, Florentine Codex, Bk X1, ch. 11, 245. Dehouve, however,
on Aztec Sculpture’, ibid. 145-6. Baird notes the intimate relation-
proposes two independent etymologies for flapalli: ‘colouring’ and
ship between ‘direction’ and the appearance of the sun, rather than
with compass-points in the modern Western sense; but although the ‘red’, The Maya word chac, ‘red’, also had the connotation ‘great’
(Schele, loc. cit. n. 14 above, 37). It is striking, too, that the dye
colours of the sun are not standard (see above p. 23), this hardly
accounts for the wide divergences of view exposed by Riley. colorado, as described in the 1703 account ofdyeing at Quito (loc. cit.
25 Riley (loc. cit. n. 24 above) 54. n. 20 above, 469), a dye made not with cochineal but with Brasil
26 Inthe case of the rather pale colours of the world-diagram in the wood, should, like the ancient ‘purple’, have shown a particular
Codex Fejervary-Meyer in Liverpool (which may be unfinished), it lustre. For dyeing with Brasil wood, Brunello (loc. cit. n. 17 above)
is notable that Nowotny (op. cit. n. 24 above, 226 f) identifies south 360.
as green and west as blue, where the more recent commentary of 42 For the problems of identifying the colours of the rainbow,
M. Leon-Portilla has ‘bluish-green’ and ‘greenish-blue’ respectively Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, ch. 6.
(Levenson, loc. cit. n. 7 above), nos 356, 540. The codex has been
reproduced in facsimile: M. Leon-Portilla, Tonalamtl de los Pochetas:
Codice Fejervary-Meyer, 1985. 8 The Fool’s Paradise
27 Sahagtin 1963, Florentine Codex, Bk XI, ch. 8, 228.
28 Duncan 1968 (op. cit. n. 4 above), 463; 1975, 57- Rojo does not I C. Merrett in A. Neri 1662, The Art of Glass, 229.
appear in Antonio de Nebrija’s Spanish-Latin dictionary of 1516, 2 D.C. Lindberg, ‘Optics in sixteenth-century Italy’ in P. Galluzzi
although roxo (rutilus, flavus) does (A. de Nebrija, Vocabulario de Romance (ed.) 1983, Novita Celesti e Crisi del Sapere (Atti del Convegno
en Latin, 1516, ed. G. J.Macdonald 1973). Internazionale di Studi Galileiani), Annuali dell’Istituto e Museo di
29 N. M. Holmer, ‘Amerindian color semantics’, International Anthro- Storia della Scienza, Supp. 2, 148. See also T. Frangenberg 1991,
poligical and Linguistic Review, Il, 3-4, 1955-6, 162. For Antiquity, ‘Perspectivist Aristotelianism: three case studies of Cinquecento
Gage, Colour and Culture, 1993, 26-7. visual theory’, Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes, LIV,
30 For 16th-century Aymara, Ludovico Bertonio, Vocabulario de la 137-38.
Lengua Aymara, 1612 (repr. 1956). Holmer, op. cit. 163, has pointed 3 For the metaphysics of light, D. Bremer 1973, ‘Hinweise zum
out that chupica is also a soup of meat and red chili-peppers. griechischen Ursprung und zur europaischen Geschichte der Licht-
31 B. Cobo, Historia del Nuevo Mundo (1653), Bk XIV, ch. xi, in metaphysik’, Archiv fiir Begriffsgeschichte, XVII; D. C. Lindberg 1986,
Obras, ed. F. Mateos 1956, II, 258. ‘The genesis of Kepler’s theory of light: light metaphysics from
32 Sahagin, ed. Garibay, III, 241. The Nahuatl version (Florentina Plotinus to Kepler’, Osiris, New series 2, 5-42.
Codex, Bk XI, ch. 11, 1963, 239) does not include this passage. For 4 C. B. Boyer 1959, The Rainbow, from Myth to Mathematics (repr.
the Spanish reception of cochineal, Brunello (loc. cit. n.17 above) 1970). For a more visually oriented discussion, Gage 1993, Colour
202-3. and Culture, ch. 6.
33 Brunello (loc. cit. n. 17 above) 85. In Peru the cinnabar face- 5 Roger Bacon, Opus Maius VI, u (ed. Bridges 1907, Il, 173);
paint called in Quechua ychima or llimpi was also used as tribute (G. Theodoric of Freiberg, De Iride et Radialibus Impressionibus, ed. 1914
Montell 1929, Dress and Ornament in Ancient Peru, 219 ft). J. Wiirschmidt (Beitrage zur Geschichte der Philosophie des Mitte-
34 Alfau de Solalinde (loc. cit. n. 4 above) 95-9, and on grana, 112-13. lalters, XII), 48, 62 (hexagonal crystal), 49-so (spherical beryll). In
For the general history ofscarlet, Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, 80. his De Coloribus, which was probably written as an adjunct to De
35 A. Castro 1921, “Unos aranceles de aduana del siglo XIIT’, Revista Iride, Theodoric used the traditional term Iris for the hexagonal
de Filologia Espariola, VII, 348 f. stone (W. A. Wallace 1959, The Scientific Methodology of Theodoric of
36 Alonso Fernandez de Palencia; Universal Vocabulario en Latin y en Freiberg, 369).
Romance, 1490 (repr. 1967), f ccclxxxvii r, describes under purpurare 6 Pliny, Natural History, XXXVII, lii (Iris); Isidore of Seville,
the process of dying with purpura to achieve, at the third dipping, Etymologiae, XVI, xiii, 6; Marbode of Rennes, De Lapidibus, XLVII
‘perfecto color quermesi’. For the earlier interpretation of purpura (ed. Riddle 1977, 82); Arnoldus Saxo, De Virtute Universali, ch. VIU:
simply as a silk cloth of any colour, Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, De Lapidibus, ed. V. Rose 1875, ‘Aristotelis de Lapidibus und
27. In what must be one of the earliest European references to the Arnoldus Saxo’, Zeitschrift
fiirdeutsches Altertum, 18, Neue Folge 6,
Mexican nochetzli, it is described as dyeing silk and wool purpuram 427, 439.
seu chermisinum (G. Cardano 1663, De Rerum Varietate, Bk 13, ch. 7 Solinus, Collectanea Rerum Memorabilium, XXXII, 22f ed. Mommsen,
Ixvi, in Opera, III, 266). and ed. 1958, 152; Thomas of Cantimpré, Liber de Natura Rerum,
37 Pedro Pizarro (1571), Relacion del Descubrimento y conquista de los XIV, xli, ed. Boese 1973, 364; R. Bacon, Opus Maius, VI, ii (1907,
Reinos del Peru, ed. E. Morales 1944, 64. For a full account of this II, 173).
audience, J. Hemming, The Conquest of the Incas, 2nd. ed. 1972, 8 Albertus Magnus, The Book of Minerals, Il, ii, ed. D. Wyckoff
33-6. Red was also an essential feature of other parts of the Inca’s 1967, OSf.
head-dress (Montell, op. cit. n. 33 above, 223). 9 Ibid. II, ii, 98f, I, ii, 30f.; Vannoccio Biringuccio, De la Pirotechnia,
38 For the adoption of Spanish colour-terms in Nahuatl docu- Venice 1540 (facs. ed. A. Carrugo 1977), IL, xiii, f 39v still calls
ments, F. Karttunen and J. Lockhart 1976, Nahuatl in the Middle crystal ‘di sustantia acquea’.
Years: Language Contact Phenomena in Texts of the Colonial Period 10 John Pecham and the Science of Optics: Perspectiva Communis, IIL, 20
(University of California Publications in Linguistics, 85) 27, 29, 67, ed. and trans. D. C. Lindberg 1970, 234-5.
71, 73- 11 Witelo, Optics, X, 83 in F. Risner, Opticae Thesaurus, 1572 (repr.
39 Molina (loc. cit. n. 8 above) I, 66v; Sahagin 1963, Florentine 1972 with intro. by D. C. Lindberg), 473-4: ‘Fit autem colorum
Codex, Bk XI, 224. distinctio a figura corporis: quoniam a qualibet alia crystallo vel
40 Duncan 1968 (loc. cit. n. 4 above) 467; see also Grossmann (loc. corpore pervio alterius figurae varii apparent, qui secundum situm
cit. n. 1 above) 170. For a Renaissance example of lips and finger- colorum iridis non sunt distincti.’ For the rainbow colours, ibid. xs
nails, Fernando de Rojas (1502), Tragicomedia de Calisto y Nemibea, 67, 400-1.
290
NOTES TO THE TEXT
12 ‘Ibid. X, 84, 474. Boyer (op cit. n. 4 above) 106 suggests that Witelo
J. J. Verdonk 1966, Petrus Ramus en de Wiskunde, 72-3. Verdonk
might have known Bacon’s distinction between the colours of the
concludes that Ramée (Ramus) provided the general concept and
bow and those of the prismatic spectrum (Opus Maius, VI, vii; 1907, framework of the book, as well as the classical material, Reisner
II, 188).
the detailed references from Alhazen and Witelo (whose optical
13 Theodoric 1914 (op. cit. n. 5 above) II, 23, 106-7: ‘Magis autem works he edited, also with help from Ramée, and published in 1572)
apparet dictorum colorum intensio et claritas, si corpus diaphanum, and the editing itself. Ramée was murdered at Paris in the St
per quod fit radiatio, esset parvae quantitatis’. Bartholomew’s massacres of 1572; Reisner died in Germany in 1580
14 R. Grosseteste, De Iride seu de Iride et Speculo, ed. L. Bauer 1912 or 1581. For Ramée’s empiricism, R. Hooykaas 1958, Humanisme,
(Beitrage zur Geschichte der Philosophie des Mittelalters, IX), 74-s. Science et Reforme: Pierre de la Ramée (1515-1572), 91-6.
See B. S. Eastwood, ‘Grosseteste’s ‘quantitative’ law of refraction:a 28 Opticae Libri Quattuor ex voto Petri Rami novissimo per Fridericum
chapter in the history of experimental science’, Journal of the History Risnerum eiusdem in mathematicis adjutorum olim conscripti, Kassel 1606,
ofIdeas, 28, 1967, 406. i 230-41.
15 P. Boehner has traced the formulation of ‘Ockham’s Razor’ to 29 M. Maylender 1929, Storia delle Accademie d’Italia, IV, 26.
the late 13th-century Franciscan theologian Odo Rigaldus, but it is 30 V. A. Scarmilionius 1601, De Coloribus Libri Duo, Marburg, 3-4.
of course best known in Ockham and Duns Scotus after 1300 31 I have found Scarmigioni’s work mentioned only in a single
(William of Ockham, Philosophical Writings, ed. P. Boehner 1957, place: Valerio Martini, Subtilitatum Proprietatum totius Substantiae
xx-xxi). See also K. Tachau 1988, Vision and Certitude in the Age of quae occultae, specificaeque sunt Patefacta, Venice 1638, I, iv, 7; xi, 20;
Ockham, 32, 132-3. For Fermat, A. I. Sabra 1967, Theories of Light XVi, 31; XVil, 32, 33, 34, 41; XXill, 43; XXvi, 46; xxxvi, 66; xxxvil,
from Descartes to Newton, ch. 5. ; 74-5, Venice 1638.
16 R. Grosseteste, Hexaemeron, ed. R. C. Dales and S. Gieben 1982, 32 Scarmilionius 1601, 112, 118-20, 166.
VIII, iv, 7, 222-3. Bacon did not link the Trinity with the rainbow 33 This medical context has been discussed briefly by A. Mugnaini
colours, which he believed to be five (Opus Maius, VI, xii; 1907, II, 1986, ‘Il colore, e il corpo nel panorama scientifico e quotidiano del
197). Cinquecento’, Annali dell’Istituto Storico Italo-Germanico in Trento,
17 Guillaume Digulleville, Le Pélerinage de l’Ame, ed. J. J. Sturzinger XII, 125-45.
1895, 349, II.10775, 10783; 350-1, II.10799-823. For ‘peacock stuffs’, 34 Phillipus Mocenicus 1581, Universales Institutiones ad’ Hominum
Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, 60-1; R. G. Kuehni, ‘Cangianti: a Perfectionum, Venice, 307; Hieronymus Capivaccius 1603, Tractatus
fabric and a coloristic device in the art of the Renaissance’, Color de Urinis, in Opera Omnia, Frankfurt, 211; Giambattista della Porta
Research and Application, 21, 1996, 326-30. 1591, Phytognomica, Frankfurt, 147. All of these texts were used by
18 ‘Quoniam idem spatium numero et totum capit quilebet de Scarmiglioni.
angulis trianguli, ut patet ad sensum, et tamen veraciter sunt anguli 35 T. da C. Kaufmann 1988, The School of Prague: Painting at the
distincti quod est mirabile et creatura, nec alibi reperitur nisi in Court of Rudolph II, 165-6.
summa trinitate’ (Opus Maius, Pt IV; 1907, 219). 36 Scarmilionius 1601, 18, with a reference to an untraced Tractatus
19 See G. Stuhlfauth 1937, Das Dreieck: Die Geschichte eines Religidsen de Temperamentis.
Symbols. For the Manichean doctrine which, curiously, used the 37 Ibid. 16-18, 106ff.
image of sunlight passing through a triangular window, A. Adam 38 Ibid. 23f. It is conceivable that coerulea here means ‘yellow’ (cf.
1954, Texte zum Manichdismus, 64. For the Scutum Fidei, Gage 1993, above, n. 20, and Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, 35).
Colour and Culture, 83. 39 Ibid. 21. Scarmiglioni did not share the Aristotelian view that
20 A. C. Crombie 1953, Robert Grosseteste and the Origins of Experi- the rainbow colours could not be painted (112).
mental Science, 199-200 n. 4. Albertus also argued for the decisive effect 40 The classic account was Bacon’s De Multiplicatione Specierum: see
of the thickness of the crystal or glass through which the light had to D. C. Lindberg 1983, Roger Bacon’s Philosophy of Nature: A Critical
pass: light red in the thinnest part, green in the thickest and yellow Edition with English Translation, Introduction and Notes of De Multipli-
(caeruleus) in the middle, although he does not appear to have had a catione Specierum and De Speculis Comburentibus, 3-7, and espec. liv-
clear idea ofthe role of refraction. lviii.
21 B. Boncompagni 1871, ‘Intorno a un manoscritto dell’ottica di 41 Scarmilionius (op. cit. n. 30 above) 19, 21.
Vitellione citato da Fra Luca Pacioli’, Bulletino di Bibliografia e di 42 Ibid. rit.
Storia delle Scienze Matematiche e Fisiche, 1V, 78-81. For Ghiberti, 43 Ibid. 25.
Bergdolt 1988 (cit. ch. 6 n. 2 above) xl, xli. For Leonardo, M. Kemp 44 Ibid. 105. The ‘lucid’ colours are candidus, flavus, puniceus, viridis
1981, Leonardo da Vinci: The Marvellous Works of Nature and Man, purpureus and coeruleus.
105, 330. 45 Ibid. 170. For Descartes on the identity of ‘real’ and ‘apparent’
22 H.S. Matsen 1974, Alessandro Achillini (1463-1572) and his doctrine colours, Sabra (op. cit. n. 15 above) 67n. For Newton on the iden-
of ‘Universals’ and ‘Transcendentals’: a Study in Renaissance Ockhamism. tity of ‘simple’ and ‘compound’ colours, A. E. Shapiro 1993, Fits,
23 J. Trutfetter 1517, Philosophie Naturalis Summa, Erfurt, IV, ii, ff Passions and Paroxysms, 10-11.
lvii verso-Ixi recto on colours; f lix recto on tonal contrast. His 46 Scarmilionius 1601 (op. cit. n. 30 above) 121; Mocenicus 1581
discussion does not seem to be related to the late scholastic treat- (op. cit. n. 34 above) 305.
ment of depth-perception through contrast studied by P. Marshall 47 Mocenicus (op. cit.) 316.
1981, ‘Two scholastic discussions of the perception of depth by 48 British Library Add. MS 6789, f 148. According to his Will of
shading’, Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes, XLIV, 170-5. 1621, Harriot apparently owned grinding and polishing apparatus
For earlier interest in Theodoric’s ideas, Wallace (op. cit. n. 5 above) (E. Rosen, ‘Harriot’s Science: the Intellectual Background’ in J. W.
249-54. Shirley (ed.) 1974, Thomas Harriot, Renaissance Scientist, 1).
24 Trutfetter (op. cit.) flix v. 49 S. Brugger-Koch 1985, “Venedig und Paris, die wichtigsten
25 Gregor Reisch 1504, Margarita Philosophica, Freiberg, [X, xxii on Zentren des hochmittelalterlichen Hartsteinschlifts’, Zeitschrift des
rainbows and haloes. For the complicated publishing history ofthis deutschen Vereins fiir Kunstwissenschaft, XX XIX, 18, 21-2. See also
encyclopaedia, R. von Sbrik, ‘Die Margarita Philosophica des Gregor H. R. Hahnloser and S. Brugger-Koch 1985, Corpus der Hartstein-
Reisch’, Akadademie der Wissenschaften in Wien (Matem.-Naturwiss. schliffe des 12-15 Jahrhunderts, nos 238, 243-4, 326 for multi-facetted
Klasse), Denkschriften, 104, 1941, 104-8. objects.
26 G. Cardano 1554, De Subtilitate Libri XXI, Leiden, 168; G. B. 50 Mocenicus 1581 (op. cit. n. 34 above) 313-14.
della Porta 1593, De Refractione Optices, Naples, espec.222f. 51 Biringuccio 1540 (op. cit n. 9 above) f 43v. For the chemistry
27 The precise role ofeach collaborator is uncertain, although they and optical quality of this glass, E. Turriére 1925, ‘Introduction a
seem to have joined forces about 1565. The fullest discussion is in Vhistoire de l’optique: le developpement de l'industrie verriére d’art
291
NOTES TO THE TEXT
depuis ’époque vénetienne jusqu’a la fondation des verreries been anticipated by Marcus Marci in 1648 (174); in one ofhis earli-
d’ optique’, Isis, VII, 77-104. ; f
est notes of 1666, Newton identified his prism as an equilateral one
52 Turriére (op. cit.) 99; K. Hettes 1963, ‘Venetian trends in, of 60 degrees (179).
Bohemian glassmaking in the 16th and 17th centuries’, Journal of
Glass Studies, V, 38-53; O. Drahtova, ‘Comments on Caspar
9 Newton and Painting
Lehmann, Central European glass and hardstone engraving’, ibid.
1981, XXIII, 34-45.
1 William Blake, Poetry and Prose, ed. G. Keynes 1956, 115. For
53 A.A. Mills, ‘Newton’s prisms and his experiments on the spec-
Blake and Newton, D. Ault 1974, Visionary Physics: Blake’s Response
trum’, Notes and Records of the Royal Society, 33, 1981, 13-36; and
espec. S. Schaffer, ‘Glass works: Newton’s prisms and the uses of to Newton, and Chapter 10 below.
2 M.H. Nicolson 1946, Newton demands the Muse; D. Greene 1953,
experiment’ in D. Gooding, T. Pinch, S. Schaffer 1989, The Uses of
Experiment: Studies in the Natural Sciences, 67-104. . ‘Smart, Berkeley, the scientists and the poets’, Journal of the History of
54 For Harriot’s experiments, J. Lohne 1959, ‘Thomas Harriot Ideas, XIV, 327-52; R. T. Murdoch 1958, ‘Newton and the French
(1560-1621): the Tycho Brahe of optics’, Centaurus, VI, 119-21. muse’, ibid. XIX, 323-34; H. Guerlac, ‘An Augustan monument:
The first extensive precise experiments with the prism are thought the Opticks of Isaac Newton’ in P. Hughes and D. Willams 1971,
to have been those by Harriot’s friends Thomas Aylesbury and The Varied Pattern: Studies in the Eighteenth Century, 131-63.
Walter Warner in 1627, but they remained unpublished (J. Lohne 3 G. Turnbull 1740, A Treatise on Ancient Painting, London, 133-4.
1963, ‘Zur Geschichte des Brechungsgesetzes’, Sudhoffs Archiv, 47, Turnbull’s notion oflandscape painting as a science was so close to
160f). Line’s experiments are described in [Kenelm Digby], Tivo Constable’s that the painter felt obliged to disclaim knowledge of
Treatises (1644), 2nd ed. London 1658, 329. For Line, C. Reilly, the book before he had delivered similar thoughts in his Royal Insti-
‘Francis Line, Peripatetic (1595-1675), Osiris, 14, 1962, 223-40. tution lectures of 1836 (C. R. Leslie (1843), Memoirs ofthe Life ofJohn
55 J. W. von Goethe 1791-2, Beitrage zur Optik (facs. 1964). Constable, ed.J.Mayne 1951, 323-4).
56 Arnoldus Saxo (op. cit. n. 6 above) 439. 4 A. Blunt 1966, The Paintings of Nicholas Poussin: A Critical Cata-
57 Albertus Magnus, Metereology II, iv, 19, in Crombie (op. cit. n. logue, no. 1. For Poussin’s access to the Zaccolini MSS see espec.
20 above), 199-200n. J. C. Bell 1988, ‘Cassiano dal Pozzo’s copy of the Zaccolini Manu-
58 Theodoric, De Iride, II, i, 1914, 60, on the colours in the bow scripts’, Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes, LI, 102-25.
which, it has been argued (Wallace, op. cit. n. 5 above, 115ff.) were Recent cleaning of the self-portrait has shown that the lettering on
an intrinsic part of the contrarieties among the four elements (cf. the spine of the book was a later addition, based on the engraving by
De Iride, Il, ii, 1914, 81-3). For the isolation of red and blue in the Jean Pesne. For Zaccolini’s ideas,J.C. Bell 1993, “Zaccolini’s theory
prismatic experiments, De Iride, II, 23 (1914, 106). In his treatise on of color perspective’, Art Bulletin, LXXV, 91-112, espec. 91.
colour, however, Theodoric identified the four rainbow colours 5 B. Teyssédre, Roger de Piles et les Débats sur le Coloris au Siécle de
in the spectrum of the hexagonal stone (De Coloribus, V1; Wallace Louis XIV, 1957.
368f). For Della Porta’s rejection of Aristotle’s mixed yellow, which 6 Roger de Piles 1672, Dialogue surleColoris, Paris, 50-1.
was the result of his experiments with coloured glass filters, and of 7 C. Kutschera-Woborsky 1919, ‘Ein kunsttheoretisches Thesen-
the experience of painters (neque pictores unquam ex viridi & puniceo blatt Carlo Marattis und seine aesthetischen Anschauungen’, Mit-
flavum colorem efficiunt), De Refractione, 1593, 195. teilungen der Gesellschaft
fiirverveilfaltigende Kunst, 9-28.
59 G. Cardano 1663, De Gemmis et Coloribus (Opera, II, 558) on the 8 R. Boyle 1664, Experiments & Considerations touching Colours
“cristallina prismata’: purpura, amethystina, punicea, candida, coerulea; (repr. 1964), 219-21. For Boyle’s crucial influence on Newton, A.
but later (566) viridem, amethystinum, puniceum, purpureumque. Moceni- Shapiro 1993, Fits, Passions and Paroxysms: Physics, method, and
cus 1581 (n. 34 above) 314: hyacinthinus, viridis, rubeus; and 316 on Chemistry and Newton’s Theories of Colored Bodies and Fits of Easy
supernumerary colours. Scarmilionius 1601 (n. 30 above), 118-19: Reflection, 99-101.
yellow-red, green, yellow (caeruleus), red, blue-violet (amethystinus); 9 Isaac Newton, Papers and Letters on Natural Philosophy, ed. 1. B.
but 121: red, green, blue (hyacinthinus /coeruleus): ‘Appellentur oculi: Cohen, 2nd ed. 1978, 47-59. See also R. S. Westfall 1962, ‘The
plane secundum nos pronunciabunt.’ development of Newton’s theory of color’, Isis, LIII, 339-58.
60 J. Lohne, Dictionary ofScientific Biography, V1, sv. “Harriot’, 125. 10 Isaac Newton, Correspondence, ed. H.W. Turnbull 1959, I, 112.
61 Della Porta 1593, 223-4; see also the red, white and blue ofthe 11 A. Shapiro 1980, “The evolving structure of Newton’s theory of
‘most pleasant and delightfull experiment we may perceive in a white light and color’, Isis, LXXI, 211-35, and Shapiro 1993 (op. cit.
three square Cristall prisme’, described by Henry Peacham 1634, n. 8 above) 98-9, 108-110 for Newton’s continuing interest in the
The Gentleman’s Exercise, 2nd ed. 139-40. complementarity of reflected and transmitted colours.
62 Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, 232, and Chapter 9 below. 12 Brook Taylor 1719, ‘A new theory for mixing of colours taken
63 The ‘prism or triangle of crystal’ illustrated in Descartes’ Les from Sir Isaac Newton’s Opticks’ in New Principles of Linear Perspec-
Meteores (1637) is, however, a right-angled prism, using the thinnest tive, London, 67-70. Newton’s own interest in colour-mixing has
part by the smallest angle, of 30 or 40 degrees (R. Descartes, Discours been discussed by A. E. Shapiro 1994, ‘Artists’ colors and Newton’s
de la Methode, ed.J.R. Armogathe et al. 1987, 293-300). This prism, colors’, Isis, LXXXV, 600-30.
the bottom side of which was masked off, with only a small opening 13 J. Byam Shaw 1967, Paintings by Old Masters at Christ Church,
to admit the sun’s rays to a white paper placed at right-angles to it, Oxford, 21.
allowed Descartes to observe six hues: ‘all the colours of the 14 Ibid. 21-6; F. Rodari (ed.) 1996, L’Anatomie de la Couleur:
rainbow’: rouge, orange, jaune, verd, ‘bleu ou le violet’, which last was L’'Invention de L’Estampe en Couleurs. O. Lilien 1985, Jacob Christophe
also perhaps ‘couleur de pourpre’. Le Blon, 1667-1741: Inventor of Three- and Four-Colour Printing, 30ft.
64 J. Cardan, The Book of My Life, trans. J. Stoner 1930, ch. 44, Also review in Print Quarterly, II, 1986, 65-7.
espec. 216 on his simplification of algebra and his reduction of the 15 Coloritto (1725), facs. in Lilien, op cit., 6.
elements to three and the humours to two. Cardano’s father, Fazio, 16 L. Gerard-Marchant 1990, ‘Les indications chromatiques dans le
had been the editor of the first printed edition of Pecham’s Perspec- De Pictura et le Della Pittura d’Alberti’, Histoire de l’Art, XI, 23-36;
tive (Prospectiva communis d. Johannis archiepiscopi Cantariensis...ed. Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, 118.
Facius Cardanus [Milan], Petrus de Cornero [?1482/3] Hain *9425), 17 G. Wildenstein 1960, ‘Jakob Christoffel Le Blon, ou le “secret
and although his work is mentioned by Gerolamo, he makes no ref- de Peindre en Gravant”’, Gazette des Beaux-Arts, LVI, 92; J. M.
erence to the prism. Friedman 1978, Color Printing in England, 1486-1870, Yale Center for
65 J. Lohne 1968, ‘Experimentum Crucis’, Notes and Records of the British Art, no. 14.
Royal Society, 23, 169-99. Newton's manipulation of two prisms had 18 J. Gautier d’Agoty 1749, Chroagenesis, ou Generation des Couleurs,
292
NOTES TO THE TEXT
contre le Systéme de Newton. The fullest account of Gautier d’Agoty’s 5 Charles de Tolnay 1945, Michelangelo, II, The Sistine Chapel, 89, has
version of Le Blon’s methods is in Rodari, op.cit. n. 14 above. characterized Abias, puzzlingly, as a ‘great and good king’.
19 H. W. Singer 1901, ‘Jacob Christoffel Le Blon’, Mitteilungen der 6 G. Schiff 1973, Johann Heinrich Fiissli (1741-1825). Text und Oeu-
Gesellschaft
ftir Vervielfaltigende Kunst, 5. G. Roque has emphasized vrekatalog, nos 471-8.
that Chevreul’s preference for the harmony of complementary 7 Cf. the characterization of E.Wind 1965, ‘Michelangelo’s Prophets
contrasts was confined to decorative art (G. Roque 1996, ‘Chevreul and Sybils’, Proceedings ofthe British Academy, li, 70f.
and Impressionism: a reappraisal’, Art Bulletin, LXX VIII, espec. 35). 8 This view seems to go back to G. Keynes 1956, The Pencil Draw-
20 F. Haskell, Patrons and Painters, 2nd ed. 1980, 319n. For Conti ings of William Blake, ii, at pl. 8; and has been restated by K. Raine
and Newton, P. Casini 1978, ‘Les débuts de Newtonianisme en 1968, Blake and Tradition, ii, 64, and A. T. Kostelanetz, ‘Blake’s 1795
Italie, 1700-1740’, Dix-Huitiéme Siecle, X, 88-90. Color Prints. An Interpretation’ in A. H. Rosenfeld (ed.) 1969, William
21 Newton, 1978, 192-3. This letter was not published until Thomas Blake, Essays forS. Foster Damon, 126. The watery appearance of some
Birch included it in The History of the Royal Society of London, 1757, of the plants is probably a result ofthe colour-printing process, and
Ill, 263. does not differ from similar features in the Nebuchadnezzar, Butlin
22 Shapiro 1993 (op. cit. n. 8 above) 91-2, 192-3. fig. 393. Blake’s convention for rendering figures under water, for
23 See Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, 231-2. example in pl. 6 of Urizen, 1794 (facs. in G. Keynes 1965, William
24 T. Christensen 1993, Rameau and Musical Thought in the Enlight- Blake: Poet, Printer, Prophet, 73) is, pace Kostelanetz, quite unlike the
enment, 109-11, 142-50, 190-3. Newton.
25 L. B. Castel 1737, ‘J. C. Le Blon, Coloritto’, Mémoires de Trévoux, 9 ‘A cave, as we learn from Porphyry...is an apt symbol of the
August. material world: since it is agreeable at its first entrance on account
26 M. Franssen 1991, “The ocular harpsichord of Louis-Bertrand ofits first participation of form, but is involved in the deepest obscu-
Castel: the science and aesthetics of an 18th-century cause célebre’, rity to the intellectual eye, which endeavours to discern its dark
Tractrix, Yearbook
for the History of Science, Medicine, Technology and foundation. So that, like a cave, its exterior and superficial parts are
Mathematics, U1, 15-77. pleasant: but its interior parts are obscure, and its very bottom dark-
27 Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, 243-6. ness itself.’ (T. Taylor 1787, The Hymns of Orpheus, 131f, cit. G. M.
28 Shapiro 1993 (op. cit. n. 8 above) 52-5, 69. Harper 1961, The Neoplatonism of W. Blake, 157.)
29 R.W. Darwin (1786), ‘On the ocular spectra of light and colours’, 10 W. Blake, Complete Poetry and Prose, ed. Keynes 1956, 344. All
repr. in E. Darwin, Zoonomia, 1794-1796 (repr. 1974), I, 548. For the page reterences are to this edition.
history of ‘complementarity’ in the 19th century, G. Roque 1994, ‘Les 11 Repr. W. Blake, Vala, or the Four Zoas, ed. Bentley, 1963, pl.
Couleurs complémentaires: un nouveau paradigme’, Revue d’ Histoire 120; for the identification of the compasses,J.Beer, Blake’s Visionary
des Sciences, XLVIII, 405-33. Universe, 1969, 351.
30 See Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, 172-3. 12 M. K. Nurmi, ‘Blake’s “Ancient of Days” and Motte’s Fron-
31 For Chevreul and Seurat, see Chapter 16 below. tispiece to Newton’s Principia’ in V. de Sola Pinto (ed.) 1957, The
32 For Kupka’s Discs, F. Kupka 1989, La Création dans les Arts Plas- Divine Vision, 205-16.
tiques, 156-7; M. Rowell, Frank Kupka: a Retrospective, New York, 13 The diagram to Bk 1, sect. i, Lemma ix (Sir I. Newton, Mathe-
Guggenheim Museum 1975, 67-76; V. Spate 1979, Orphism: the matical Principles ofNatural Philosophy, trans. Motte 1729, i, pl. ii), has
Evolution of Non-Figurative Painting in Paris, 1910-1914, 126-8, which something in common with Blake’s.
offers a different interpretation from that suggested here. 14 It is notable that other versions of the Newton design, e.g. the
33 For Goethe on Castel, Farbenlehre: Historischer Teil, ed. D. Kuhn pencil drawing in the Keynes collection (Butlin fig. 409) and the
(Leopoldina Ausgabe der Schriften zur Naturwissenschaft, I, 6) 1957, ‘Newtonian Angel’ in an illustration to Young’s Night Thoughts
328-33; for Gautier d’Agoty, 335-42. (repr. de Sola Pinto, op. cit. n. 12 above, facing 200), show either no
mathematical figure or only a simple triangle. The chord or arc may
symbolize graphically the rainbow spectrum created by the prism.
10 Blake’s Newton 15 Raine (op. cit. n. 8 above, ii, 136f) has suggested that this cloth is
the ‘woof of Locke’, but in Jerusalem (i, 15) this is described specifi-
1 David Bindman, who has generously made many corrections and cally as black (¢. also The First Book of Urizen, v, 12). She has also
amplifications to the present study, proposes a date in the early 1770s claimed (i, 420f, n. 38; ii, 158f) Blake’s direct knowledge of Newton’s
for these copies. M. Butlin 1981, The Paintings and Drawings of Opticks, on the basis of some of his language and imagery.
William Blake, nos 167-70, suggests a date ofc.1785. Ghisi’s engrav- 16 Op. cit., i, 238, of: also 239, ‘there was no example ofany philo-
ings were re-issued as Pitture dipinte nella Volta della Capella Sistina sophical inquiry conducted with more circumspection [than the
nel Vaticano presso Carlo Losi l’anno 1773; and Benjamin Heath Opticks], or in which the aid of mathematics was applied with more
Malkin, in his memoir of 1806, has Blake buying and copying prints advantage or address’.
after Michelangelo from about 1767 (G. E. Bentley, Jr, 1969, Blake 17 Op. cit., ii, 669, 663£ M. K. Nurmi, ‘Negative Sources in Blake’
Records, 422). It is not known if the British Museum series is com- (Rosenfeld, op. cit. n. 8 above, 304), has stressed the purely optical
plete; if so, Blake’s choice of the Prophet Daniel, the youthful and connotations of ‘single vision’ for an 18th-century audience, but
energetic interpreter, Butlin fig. 205, was in the light of his subse- without quoting Priestley, who specifically uses the expression,
quent career a happy one. where Newton (Opticks, Bk III, pti, query 15) does not.
2 Butlin fig. 211. This free attitude has been held to be characteris 18 ‘Having opened the points of a pair of compases somewhat
tic of Blake throughout his career (J. Burke, “The Eidetic and the wider than the interval of his eyes, with his arm extended, he held
Borrowed Image: An Interpretation of Blake’s Theory and Practice the head orjoint in his hand, with the points outwards, and equidis-
of Art’, In Honour ofDaryl Lindsay: Essays and Studies, ed. Philipp and tant from his eyes, a little higher than the joint. Then fixing his eyes
Stewart 1964, espec. 120 f). on a remote object, lying in the line that bisected the intervals of
3 A. Blunt 1938, ‘Blake’s “Ancient of Days”’, Journal of the Warburg the points, he first perceived two pairs of compasses, each leg being
and Courtauld Institutes, IL, 61, no. 6; expanded in idem 1959, The Art doubled, with their inner legs crossing each other. But, by com-
of William Blake, 35, pl. 30 a.b. The musculature and lighting of pressing the legs with his hand, the two inner points came nearer to
Blake’s copy is closer to the Abias in the large engraving by Giorgio each other, and when they united, the two inner legs also entirely
Ghisi than to the detail version by Adamo; but the genius behind coincided, and bisected the angle under the outward ones; and
him is closer to the latter source. they appeared more vivid, thicker, and longer, so as to reach from
4 Lecture II, 1800, cit. E.C. Mason 1951, The Mind of Henry Fuseli, his hand to the remotest object in view, even in the horizen itself...’
247f. (ii, 670).
293
NOTES TO THE TEXT
19 139; for Priestley and Newton, 137. Priestley, History and Present 8 above, Pencil Drawings, pl. 34) is contested by David Bindman and
State, op. cit., 11, 7o8tf. v Martin Butlin. :
20 652; Priestley, op. cit., 1, 716f. 32 Raine (op. cit. n. 8 above) i, 412, n. 37 records a rainbow in a
21 Op. cit., 11, 5901. if
version of Blake’s Ugolino and his Sons which I have not been able
22 J. Boehme, Mysterium Magnum, cit. Raine (op. cit. n. 8 above) ul, to trace. It is not recorded in the list of Ugolino designs given by
A. S. Roe 1953, Blake’s Illustrations to Dante, 132 However, the
412, n. 37, where, and at i, 6, Raine has followed Yeats in supposing
connotations given to the Ugolino design in The Gates of Paradise
that Blake’s scheme is identical, which is clearly not the case.
23 The Works ofJames Barry, 1809, 1, 525f. would support the conclusions on the materialism of the rainbow
24 Dante’s accounts are in Purgatorio XXIX, 77-8 and Paradiso
XII, discussed above. The auras and sky-modulations in the Beatrice
10-12. Neither was published in English until after 1800; but Blake’s watercolours are not strictly rainbows, although Dante refers to
later associate William Hayley was familiar with the whole Divine them as such (Purgatorio, XXIX), and Blake’s colours are in the
Comedy by 1782 (H. A. Beers 1901, A History of English Romanticism Newtonian sequence. Blake’s view of Beatrice as Rahab, the fallen
in the Nineteenth Century, 95f). His first connection with Blake, state of Vala (Roe, op. cit., 164-71), again reinforces the interpreta-
through Flaxman, seems to date from 1784 (Bentley, op. cit. n. 1 tion set out in this study.
above, 27). Both Fuseli and Flaxman knew Dante in the original by
the 1770s; but Flaxman’s rainbow in his illustration prefacing the
Paradiso, 1793, has five, not seven colour-divisions. 11 Magilphs and Mysteries
25 (a) Title-page to Visions of the Daughters of Albion, 1793; colour
reproduction of A copy (British Museum, cf. Sir G. Keynes and 1 James Barry to Sir Joshua Reynolds, 17 May 1769 (The Works of
E. Wolf 1953, William Blake’s Illuminated Books, 28) with note by James Barry, 1, 1809, 106 (the context suggests the date should be
J. Middleton Murry, 1932; C copy (Lord Cunliffe: Keynes and Wolf 1768); cf. also Barry to Burke, 30 Sept. 1768, ibid. 120. The Italian
29), facs. by Trianon Press, 1959. Copy O (British Museum: Keynes quotation, ‘good drawing and muddy colouring’, is taken from the
and Wolf 32), which was printed and illuminated after 1815, has the life of Annibale Carracci in C. Malvasia (1678), Felsina Pittrice, 1841,
same order on the title-page, which may depend upon a common I, 2. For the 18th- and 19th-century English liking for the unstable
model, but the new motif
of the rainbow-nimbus round the kneel- oil medium ‘megilp’, L. Carlyle and A. Southall, ‘No short mechanic
ing figure on p. 3 has the colours in reverse. road to fame’ in R. Hamlyn 1993, Robert Vernon’s Gift, London,
(b) Watercolour illustrating Night viii of Young’s Night Thoughts, Tate Gallery, 23-5.
c. 1797: British Museum 1929-7-13-178, Butlin no. 330/335 (our 2 W. Sandby 1862, The History of the Royal Academy ofArts, I, 386-7.
pl. 48). 3 Field’s work has been examined in J. Gage 1989, George Field
(c) Death of the Virgin, 1803: Butlin no. $72. and his Circle, from Romanticism to the Pre-Raphaelite Brotherhood,
(d) Death of
Joseph, 1803 (reproduced in colour in L. Binyon 1922, Cambridge, Fitzwilliam Museum.
The Drawings and Engravings of William Blake, 49). 4 N. Pevsner 1940, Academies ofArt, 168, 232. In 1770 the Incorpo-
26 (a) The Four and Twenty Elders, c. 1804-5: Tate Gallery, Butlin rated Society of Artists made a brief experiment with lectures on
no. §75. chemistry, apparently at the invitation of the chemist, Dr Awsiter,
(b) Noah's Sacrifice, 1805: Harvard University, Houghton Library, himself (Walpole Society, XXXII, 1946-8, 23).
repoduced in colour Butlin fig. 577. I am indebted to Miss Carol 5 For Reynolds’s secretiveness about techniques, J. Northcote,
D. Goodman for examining and reporting the colours ofthis water- Memorials of an Eighteenth-Century Painter, ed. S. Gwynn 1898, 49,
colour. 225; C. L. Eastlake 1847, Materials fora History of Oil Painting (repr.
(c) Jerusalem, pl. 14. Copy E, coloured after 1820, reproduced in 1960),
facs. by the Trianon Press, 1951. I, 539. James Ward was obliged to copy out Thomas Bardwell’s
(d) Beatrice on the Car: Matilda and Dante, c. 1825: British Museum, Treatise on Oil Painting for his own instruction (E. Fletcher, ed.,
Butlin no. 812/8, reproduced in colour Binyon (op. cit.) pl. 103. 1901, Conversations ofJames Northcote with James Ward, 100).
(e) Beatrice addressing Dante from the Car, c. 1825: Tate Gallery, 6 T. Bardwell 1756, The Practice of Painting. ..made Easy, 2.
Butlin no, 812/88, reproduced in colour fig. 973. 7 See, for example, Ozias Humphry’s notebooks of technical
27 The painting is now in the Chamberlayne-Macdonald Coll. gossip, British Library Add MS 22949-s50, and William Buchanan’s
See London, Kenwood, George Romney, 1961, no. 38. I was able to letter to Julius Caesar Ibbetson asking for his ‘gumption’ recipe and
study the spectrum colours at this exhibition. P. Fagot has also closing, ‘In writing I beg you will also communicate the grand
noticed this change in the Newtonian order of Blake’s rainbows (P. secret of varnish you mentioned... which shall be kept. .. with invi-
Fagot, “Temoignages synoptiques de William Blake et d’Emmanuel olate secrecy.’ (1801): R. M. Clay 1948, Julius Caesar Ibbetson, 85.
Swedenborg sur l’arc-en-ciel’ in P. Junod and M. Pastoureau 1904, 8 Reynolds’s curiosity is seen most strikingly in his dissection of
Couleur: regards croisés sur la couleur du Moyen Age au XX* Siecle, several Venetian pictures, ruining them (J. Northcote 1813, Memoirs
90, 93.) of Sir Joshua Reynolds, 227); for Barry, loc. cit.; for West,J.Galt 1820,
28 Bryant (op. cit) ii, 1775, 346ff, from Hesiod, Theogony, 65. Life and Studies... of Benjamin West, 1, 130-1, Il, 136-7; for Turner,
Bryant, however, in this chapter relates the etymology of Iris and A.J. Finberg 1909, Inventory of Tumer Drawings, 1, 180-91; for Haydon,
Eros, and is anxious to follow the traditional view in interpreting Diary, ed. Pope 1960, II, 430-4, and Autobiography, ed. Penrose
the bow as a symbol of Divine Love. 1927, I, 167. It does not seem possible to find this taste reflected in
29 Butlin no. 474, fig. 958. Venetian picture-prices during the period: G. Reitlinger 1961, The
30 e.g. The Marriage of Heaven and Hell, 1793: ‘Jesus Christ did not Economics ofTaste, 26 and tables.
wish to unite, but to separate them [the Prolific and the Devourer], 9 The Diary ofJoseph Farington, ed. K. Garlick, A. Macintyre, K. Cave,
as in the Parable of Sheep and goats...’, 188; Blake’s key text is 1978-84, 17 January 1797 (henceforth ‘Farington’).
Luke 12:51: ‘Suppose ye that | am come to give peace on the earth? 10 Farington, 11 January. W. T. Whitley 1928, Artists and their
I tell you, nay, but rather division.’ For a discussion of Blake’s treat- Friends in England, II, 209, gives the grandfather’s name as ‘Captain
ment of the Neo-Platonic idea of division and separation in the Morley’.
Material, see Harper (op. cit. n. 9 above) 228ff. Blunt’s interpreta- ir Ann Jemima Provis had exhibited miniatures at the Royal
tion of the compasses and set-square in terms of Redemption (art. Academy Exhibition of 1787. John Opie reported (Lectures on Paint-
cit. n. 3 above, 60) seems unlikely in view ofthese attributes of Jesus ing, 1809, 145) that Miss Provis was ‘scarce in her teens’ when she
in Blake’s mythology. offered the Secret, but his information is inaccurate in other respects,
31 Blunt, loc. cit. n. 3 above. Blake’s authorship of an apparently and cannot be credited.
related drawing formerly in the Lowinsky collection (Keynes, cit. n. 12 Farington, 13 February 1797. Dr Monro was the King’s physi-
294
NOTES TO THE TEXT
cian, and Miss Provis may have been introduced to him through
40 Whitley, Artists (cit. n. 10 above) II, 213. M. B. Amory 1882,
her father, a member of the Royal Household (Whitley, loc. cit. n.
The Domestic and Artistic Life ofJohn Singleton Copley, 230 £ For
10 above). Solomon Williams’s British School exhibit, Gage, Field (cit. n. 3
13 Royal Academy, 5172, 25A, 4. I am indebted to the Royal above) 28, and for his vehicle, Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, 213.
Academy for permission to cite this MS. Two further versions of 41 Transactions, XXIV, 1806, 85-9.
the ‘Secret’ are known: one, in the collection of Dr Jon Whiteley,
42 1821 ed. 1. The identification of the ‘Lady’ of the pamphlet with
is entitled, The Venetian manner ofPainting particularly laid down, relat- Miss Cleaver depends on a pencilled note to the Courtauld Insti-
ing to the Practice. by A. J. P., and does not yet include the ‘Titian tute’s copy of the 2nd edition, on Constable’s reference to her as
Shade’, so it may be earlier than the RA version. The copy sold to daughter of the late Bishop of Bangor and on the Brighton address
J. F. Rigaud was summarized by his son in a memoir (1854) pub- he gives (R. B. Beckett, ed., 1964, Jolin Constable’s Correspondence, IL,
lished by W. Pressly 1984, Walpole Society, L, 99-103. 347-8).
14 Farington, 1 February 1797. 43 1821 ed. 9.
15 Royal Academy MS, n. p. (notes transcribed in Farington’s hand). 44 1815 ed. 39.
16 Ibid. 8. 45 Beckett (op. cit n. 42 above) 348 (30 June and 1 July). The version
17 Pressly (op. cit. n. 13 above) 100. Cf. the watercolour manuals of in C. R. Leslie, Memoirs of the Life ofJohn Constable, ed. J. Mayne
Ibbetson (1794) andJ.Laporte (c. 1802) in P. Bicknell andJ.Munro 19§1, 126, omits much ofthis detail.
1988, Gilpin to Ruskin: Drawing Masters and their Manuals, 1800-1860, 46 1821 ed. 20.
Cambridge, Fitzwilliam Museum, nos 28, 30. 47 St James’s Chronicle in Whitley, Artists and their Friends in England
18 Farington, 18 January 1797, and notes in his hand in Royal (cit n. 10 above) 213
Academy MS (cit. n. 13 above).
19 Royal Academy MS 6, 9, and landscape section, 1.
20 Whitley (op. cit. n. 10 above) 213. Antwerp Blue appears to I2 Turner as a Colourist
have been a weaker version ofPrussian Blue, which had been devel-
oped around 1704-7 (R. D. Harley, Artists’ Pigments, c. 1600-1836, I Huysmans’ description reads in the French:
2nd ed. 1982, 70-5). “Turner... vous stupéfie, au premier abord. On se trouve en face
21 Farington, 11 January 1797; H. von Erffa and A. Staley 1986, dun brouillis absolu de rose et de terre de Sienne brilée, de bleu et
The Paintings of Benjamin West, no. 133. Other ‘Venetian Secret’ de blanc,.frottés avec un chiffon, tant6t en tournant en rond, tantdt
pictures are probably no. 22, Cicero discovering the Tomb ofArchimedes en filant en droite ligne ou en bifurquant en de longs zig-zags. On
(ll. in col. 120); no. $43: Raphael West and Benjamin WestJr. (ill. in dirait une estampe balayée avec de la mie de pain ou d’un amas de
col. 134), and possibly The Cruxifixion (no. 356). couleurs tendres étendues a l’eau dans une feuille de papier qu’on
22 Farington, 5, 6 January 1797. referme, puis qu’on rabote, 4 tour de bras, avec une brosse; cela
23 Farington, 5, 18 January. seme de jeux de nuances étonnantes, surtout si lon eparpille, avant
24 Farington, 18 January. de refermer la feuille, quelques points de blanc de gouache.
25 Farington, 13 February. A copy of the agreement is bound with ‘C’est cela, vu de trés prés, et, 4 distance, ... tout s’équilibre. Devant
the Royal Academy MS. les yeux dissuadés, surgit un merveilleux paysage, un site féerique,
26 Monthly Magazine in British Museum Print Room, Whitley Papers, un fleuve irradié coulant sous un soleil dont les rayons s’irisent. Un
XIII, 1608. pale firmament fuit a perte de vue, se noie dans un horizon de nacre,
27 Whitley, Artists and their Friends (loc. cit. n. 10 above). se revérbére et marche dans une eau qui chatoie, comme savon-
28 Farington, 3, 9 March 1797; W. Sandby, Thomas and Paul Sandby, neuse, avec la couleur du spectre coloré des bulles. Ou, dans quel
1892, 91-3. The MS of the poem is now in the Pierpont Morgan pays, dans quel Eldorado, dans quel Eden, flambent ces folie de
Library, New York. clarté, ces torrents de jour réfractés par des nuages laiteux, tachés de
29 Farington, 21 May 1797. Field’s comment on Grandi is in a note rouge feu et sillés de violet, tels que des fonds précieux d’opale? Et
to his copy ofC. L. Eastlake’s Materials, cit. 78, now 1n the Canadian ces sites sont réels pourtant; ce sont des paysages d’automne, des bois
Conservation Institute. I owe a transcript ofthese notes to the kind- rouillés, des eaux courantes, des futaies qui se déchevélent, mais ce
ness of Dr Leslie Carlyle. sont aussi des paysages volatilises, des aubes de plein ciel; ce sont les
30 Transactions of the Society of Arts, XVI, 1798, 279-99. It is clear fetes célestes et fluviales d’une nature sublimée, décortiquée, rendue
from the MS Minutes of the Committee of Polite Arts, 22 Nov. 1797, complétement fluide, par un grand poéte.’ Huysmans’ approach to
97, that Sheldrake’s communication was submitted in May 1797. colour in painting, at the same time sensual and technical, has been
A letter from Charles Smith (ibid.) assured the Society that the studied by J. Dupont, ‘La couleur dans (presque) tous ses états’, in
method, although advertised as ‘similar to that practised in the A. Guyaux, C. Heck, R. Kopp (eds) 1987, Huysmans: Une Esthétique
ancient Venetian School’, had nothing to do with the Provis process. de la Decadence, 155-66, esp. 164 for Turner. For the Louvre paint-
It did, however, stress dark absorbent grounds. I am grateful to Dr ing, M. Butlin and E. Joll, The Paintings ofJ.M. W. Turner, 2nd ed.
D. G. C. Allen for showing me the Minute Books. 1984, no. 509.
31 The Works of SirJoshua Reynolds, 1797, 1, xxxi-xxxiii n. 2 E. and J. de Goncourt, Journal, 12 Aug. 1891; R. Gimpel 1963,
32 The True Briton, 12 April. The True Briton was one of the many Journal d’un Collectionneur, 88.
newspapers supporting the Secret whose names decorate the wings 3 Turner en France, 1981, 395, no. 87 (TB CCLIX-109; W.965).
ofPegasus in Gillray’s satire. 4 Butlin and Joll (op. cit. n. 1 above) no. 390.
33. Bell’s Weekly Messenger, 30 April; Observer, 7 May (Whitley Papers, 5 G.P. Boyce, Diary, 20 June 1857 in Butlin and Joll, no, 291.
cit. n. 26 above, 1609). 6 W. Hall 1881, David Cox, Artist, 199. For the painting, Butlin and
34 Farington, 6 June, 17 July, 26 August 1797. Joll, no. 427. In the first (1977) edition oftheir catalogue, Butlin and
35 British Museum, Catalogue of Personal and Political Satires, ed. M. Joll did not refer to Cox’s story or to the vegetables.
D. George 1942, VII, no. 9085. 7 C. Tardieu 1873 in Gazette des Beaux-Arts, VII, 401; etching by
36 Farington, 9 March 1797; F. Owen and D. B. Brown 1988, G. Greux in R. Ménard 1875, Entretiens sur la Peinture, facing 156.
Collector ofGenius: a Life of Sir George Beaumont, 94-5, 101. 8 Cit. A. J. Finberg 1961, The Life ofJ.M. W. Turner R. A., 2nd
37 For Fuseli and the Secret, Farington, 29 April 1797; for Turner, ed., 200 and R. de la Sizeranne 1897, Revue des Deux Mondes, 1
Monthly MirrorinWhitley Papers (cit. n. 26 above) XII, 1513. March, 179.
38 The Works of Sir Joshua Reynolds, 1798, I, lvi-lvii n. 9 Cat. 160a, 167. For the colour-beginnings see E. Shanes 1997,
39 Courtauld Institute of Art, Newspaper Cuttings on the Fine Arts, Turner’s Watercolour Explorations, 1810-1842, Tate Gallery.
I, 182. 10 J. Gage 1969, Colour in Turner: Poetry and Truth, 206.
295
NOTES TO THE TEXT
ir Ibid., 210. ) 9 Runge to Perthes, 14 July 1810, cited from the original version in
Matile 1979 (op. cit. n. 2 above), 223.
12 Butlin and Joll (op. cit n. 1 above) nos 404-5. There isa hidden
were stolen in 1994 from 10 ‘575. Theory. How yellow pigment changes in the process of
irony in the fact that the paintings
being ground from morning to evening — not to be explained by the
a Goethe Exhibition in Frankfurt. The most extensive iconographi-
colour induced in the eye [i.e. by successive contrast], but by the
cal interpretation of these paintings is in G. Finley 1991, ‘Pigment
spreading out [Raum] [over the slab].’ From a letter from Daniel
into light: Turner and Goethe’s Theory of Colours’, European
Romantic Review 2, 44-60, although Finley is more inclined to credit
Runge to Goethe, 13 Oct. 1811 (Hinterlassene Schriften von Philipp
Otto Runge, II, 1841, 434; hereafter ‘HS’). The observation has only
Turner’s interest in symbolic and associative systems of colour than
the most tenuous connection with Goethe’s §575 in the ‘Didactic
Iam (46; cf. Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, 204). For Turner’s inter-
pretation of Goethe’s ideas, Gage (op. cit. n. 10 above) ch. 1 Gage Part’ of the Farbenlehre.
Ir Goethe to Steffens, 9 Oct. 1809 (C. Schiiddekopf and O. Walzel
1984, ‘Turner’s annotated books: Goethe’s Theory of Colours’, Turner
Studies, IV, 34-52. 1898, Goethe und die Romantik, Schriften der Goethe- Gesellschaft, 13,
13 Butlin and Joll (op. cit n. 1 above) nos 47, 334. II, 286-7). Cf. also Goethe to Zelter, 15 Aug. 1806 ((Briefwechsel
14 Gage (op. cit. n. 10 above) 169. zwischen Goethe und Zelter, 1, ed. Riemer, 1833, 241) and Goethe to
15 G. Adams, Lectures on Natural and Experimental Philosophy, 2nd Runge, 18 Oct. 1809 (von Maltzahn, 99).
ed. 1799, 424f; C. O’Brien 1795, The British Manufacturer’s Compan- 12 Matile 1979, 140, following von Maltzahn (cit n. 4 above) 36,
ion and Calico Printer’s Assistant, “General Reflections’. Turner knew suggests that colour might have been a topic on this occasion, but
both books. Goethe’s words read: ‘This agreement from a living person, who
16 J. Mitford, Notebooks, XV, British Library Add. MS 32573, f. 349. knew nothing of me and my efforts until now, gives me a new desire
17 T.S. Cooper 1890, My Life, II, 2-3. to take them further...’. Goethe had been in touch with Runge
18 ‘R’ in L’Artiste, XII, 1836, repr. in G. Finley 1979, “Turner, the since 1801.
Apocalypse and History: the “Angel” and “Undine”’, Burlington 13. Von Maltzahn 83; Matile 1979, 224.
Magazine, CXX1, 696. 14 In his autobiography, Was ich Erlebte, IV, 1841, 101, Steffens
19 Gage (op. cit. n. 10 above) 168. recalled that he already knew the Beitrage zur Optik by the tme he
20 R.S. Owen 1894, The Life ofRichard Owen, 1, 263. met Goethe for the first time in 1799.
21 For Monet, I. C. Perry 1927, ‘Reminiscences of Claude Monet 15 HSI, 504.
from 1889-1909’, American Magazine of Art, XVIII, 120. In 1900 16 For Runge’s first idea of his colour-system as a Globus, to Goethe,
Monet claimed that ‘ninety percent of the theory of Impressionism Nov. 1807, von Maltzahn 71, and for the letter of 19 April 1808 in
isin The Elements ofDrawing‘ (W. Dewhurst 1911, “What is Impres- which he referred to his connection with Steffens, ‘which could not
sionism?’, Contemporary Review 99, 296). J. Ruskin (1857), The Ele- have happened at a better time for me’, ibid. 84-5.
ments of Drawing, 1971, 27n. For the translation by Cross and Signac, 17 See Matile 1977 (cit n. 2 above).
P. Signac, De Delacroix au Néo-Impressionisme, ed. Francoise Cachin 18 See especially Steffens to Goethe, 3 Oct. 1809 (Schiiddekopf
1964, 116. and Walzel 1898, 284-6) and Runge to Goethe, 1 Feb. 1810 (von
Maltzahn 100).
19 H. Steffens, ‘Uber die Bedeutung der Farben in der Natur’ in
P. O. Runge 1810, Farben-Kugel, 35.
13 ‘Iwo Different Worlds’ — Runge, Goethe and 20 E.g. F. Schmid 1948, The Practice of Painting, 109. Schifter-
the Sphere of Colour miiller’s book has now been fully discussed by T. Lersch 1984, “Von
der Entomologie zur Kunst-theorie’, De Arte et Libris: Festschrift
1 See the brief modern bibliography Chapter 3, n. 96 above. For Erasmus, 301-16.
handbooks, see for exampleJ. Albers 1963, Interaction of Color; and 21 ‘Colours of two species which are so close on the circle that only
for philosophical studies,J.Westphal, Colour: a Philosophical Introduc- one other lies between them, are to be tolerated neither in a dress
tion, 2nd ed. 1991. nor in a painting... Blue and grass-green, olive and orange, red and
2 The fullest modern edition is the facsimile reprint with an violet are examples of such colours... When two other species lie
introduction by H. Matile, Mittenwald, 1977. Matile’s study, Die between them, they are usually adequately contrasted. Colours sep-
Farbenlehre Philipp Otto Runges, 2nd ed. 1979, is the fullest modern arated by three others are described by painters as “rather strident”,
analysis of the book; but there is also a very substantial discussion of and those separated by four are “strong and violent”, but, then,
Runge’s colour-ideas inJ.Traeger 1975, Philipp Otto Runge und sein many like the colourful...
But when, finally, the two colours are
Werk: Monographie und kritischer Katalog, 54-61 and passim. separated on each side by five other species, so that they lie opposite
3 J. W. von Goethe, Die Schriften zur Naturwissenschaft: Leopoldina each other on the circle, then their juxtaposition can generally
Ausgabe, ed. Matthaei, Troll, Wolf 1955, 1/4, 257. please those who are used to being touched only by very powerful
4 Goethe wrote to Runge on 18 Oct. 1809 that the Farben-Kugel objects... These last colours can be seen in the country on wooden
*...includes nothing that could not be appended to mine, which arm-chairs, spinning wheels and other household objects which
does not engage in one way or another with what I have intro- are painted en masse: experienced artists call such juxtapositions in
duced. Since I find my work supplemented here and there by yours, paintings poisonous and merely box-painting.’ (I. Schiffermiiller
we shall be able to start a lively correspondence.’ (Philipp Otto Runges 1771, Versuch eines Farbensystems, 15-17).
Briefwechsel mit Goethe, ed. von Maltzahn 1940, Schriften der Goethe- 22 Ibid., 12.
Gesellschaft, 51, 99; hereafter ‘von Maltzahn’). 23 J. G. Sulzer 1792, Allgemeine Theorie der Schénen Kunste, 214. Matile
5 Matile 1979 (cit. n. 2 above) 231 and n. 364 (hereafter ‘Matile’). 1979, 128 has noted Runge’s derivation of some of his early termi-
For Runge’s circle with red at the top, von Maltzahn 42; and for his nology from Sulzer, and the painter’s conception of allegory may
other painted circles, Traeger (op. cit. n. 2 above) nos 510-18. also owe something to him (see Sulzer, I, rooff).
6 Von Maltzahn (op. cit. n. 4 above) 49-51. 24 For Runge’s experiments with disc-mixture, see especially his
7 Traeger (op. cit. n. 2 above) 56, 172, 210, n.146, $01, 507. letter to Goethe of 19 April 1808 (von Maltzahn 82). Schiffermiiller’s
8 See the rainbow in the upper margin of Der Tag (Traeger no. experiments are described in Versuch (cit n. 21 above) 1-3 n. The
282b) and the diagram of ‘Monotone Wirkung’ in the Farben-Kugel problem had been taken up in Runge’s own day by M. A. F. Liidicke,
(Traeger 1975, 56 pl. 9), with its preparatory study in Hamburg who also divided his circle into twelve parts and experimented with
(Traeger no. 521). F. Burwick 1986, The Damnation of Newton, 49, harmonious juxtapositions, concluding, like Runge, that those
has reached similar conclusions about the relationship of Runge to colours which mix to a near-white (i.e. the complementaries) are
Newton’s theory. harmonious. Unlike Runge and Goethe, however, Liidicke inclined
296
NOTES TO THE TEXT
towards the newer additive primary triad of red, green and violet,
14 Mood Indigo
which had been proposed in 1792 by Wiinsch (M. A. F. Liidicke
1800, ‘Beschreibung eines kleinen Schwungrades, die Verwandlung
I K. Schwitters, Das Literarische Werk, ed. F. Lach, I (1973), 150.
der Regenbogen-Farben in Weiss darzustellen...’, Gilberts Annalen The first German version (Die Blume Anna in Der Sturm, XII/2
der Physik, V, 272£€; cf. also his ‘Versuche tiber die Mischung prisma- March 1922, 176), in ibid. (I, 292) runs:
tischer Farben’, ibid. 1810, XXXIV, 8f). ss
25 Matile 1979, 234-7. For Goethe on colour-harmony to Meadials ... Preisfrage:
Meyer in 1798, Schriften zur Naturwissenschaft (cit. n. 3 above), 1/3, ed. 1. Anna Blume hat ein Vogel.
ie) . Anna Blume ist rot.
R. Matthaei 1951, 386.
26 Steffens (op. cit. n. 19 above) 35. 3. Welche Farbe hat der Vogel?
27 Moses Harris (?1776), The Natural System of Colours, facs, with Blau ist die Farbe seines gelben Haares.
an introduction by F. Birren, 1963. On 5, Harris states that the 20 Rot ist das Girren deines griinen Vogels.
gradations of each hue run from saturation at the circumference to Du schlichtes Madchen im Alltagskleid, du
near-white at the centre of his circle. For the date of the treatise, liebes griines Tier, ich liebe dir...
J. Gage 1969, Colour in Turner: Poetry and Truth, 222, n. 13. The 2 I have traced some of the French developments in Colour and
Swedish mathematician Sigfrid Forsius had designed an eccentric Culture, 1993, 191-201, 209-12, 222; for Goethe’s immediate sup-
colour-sphere along Aristotelian lines about 1611, but it remained porters, 202-3. It is conceivable that Schwitters, who was much con-
unpublished (Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, 166). For a contempo- cerned with fundamentals, and composed a sound-poem entitled
rary criticism that Runge’s Kugel was really a two-dimensional Ur-Sonate (1922-32; Schwitters I, 1973, 214-42), was echoing Goethe’s
system, H. Nagele 1972 in Jahrbuch des Freien Deutschen Hochstifts, Ur-Farben, yellow and blue, in his poem on Anna Blume/Blossom:
espec. 286. seeJ.W. von Goethe (1810), Farbenlehre, Didaktischer Teil (Didactic
28 Steffens to Goethe, 3 Oct. 1809 (Schtiddekopf
and Walzel 1808, Part), §7os.
284). 3 Novalis, Schrifien, ed. P. Kluckhohn and R. Samuel 1960, I, 195-
29 Von Maltzahn 97. 7. Subsequent references in the text and notes are to this edition.
30 Only the beginning of this attack has been included in the 4 W. Wackenroder, ‘Die Farben’ in Phantasien uber die Kunst, ed.
reprint of the review in Traeger 1975, 501. See also Sartorius to L. Tieck 1799, repr. W. H. Wackenroder, Werke und Briefe, ed. F.
Goethe on the poor reception of the Farben-Kugel in Gottingen von der Leyen 1967, 195f.
(von Maltzahn, 115). 5 H. Steffens, ‘Uber die Bedeutung der Farben in der Natur’ in
31 Steffens (op. cit. n. 19 above) 59. P. O. Runge 1810, Farben-Kugel, repr. 1977, 59. C. K. Sprengel, Das
32 Steffens 47: *...although red and blue are seen as a lively opposi- entdeckte Geheimniss der Natur, ed. P. Knuth 1894, I: 9 (Myosotis): 89
tion, yellow is very far from being perceived as a mere difference (Iris).
between these two’. See also ibid. 48, 52. The concept seems to 6 J. W. von Goethe 1810, Farbenlehre, Didaktischer Teil (Didactic
have especially attracted Jens Baggesen in his critique of the Farben- Part), §626.
Kugel (Nagele, op. cit.n. 27 above, 289). 7 A. Leslie Willson, “The Blaue Blume: a new dimension’, Germanic
33 Runge to Daniel Runge, 7 Nov. 1802 (HS I, 17). By the end Review, 34 (1959), 57. Willson’s article reviews the earlier identifica-
of January 1803 Runge had come to see red as representative of tions of the blue flower. For a well-illustrated historical study of
morning and evening, and blue as characteristic of day (HSI, 32). In indigo, see the catalogue ofthe exhibition Sublime Indigo, Musée de
a slightly later scheme devised by the nature-philosopher Lorenz Marseille, 1987.
Oken, red stood for fire, love and the Father; blue for air, truth and 8 Novalis (op. cit. n. 3 above) HI, 7676.
belief and the Son; green for water, formative power, hope and the 9 Novalis refers to Werner’s system of classification in a note of
Holy Ghost — and yellow for Satan (L. Oken 1810, Physiophilosophy, 1799/1800 (op. cit. n. 3 above) II, 259. The Wernerian terminology
Engl. trans. 1847, 78, §378). was introduced in Von den dusserlichen Kennzeichen der Fossilien (1774;
34 Runge to Goethe, 19 April 1808 (von Maltzahn 80). This English trans. Dublin 1805), 36-72. Werner noted that flowers were
emphasis is close to Steffens’s interpretation by experiment: see his a good example of standard colours, and the majority of his blues,
conversation with Wilhelm Grimm in April 1809 (Briefwechsel zwis- the rarest colour among minerals, had pigment- or flower-names
chen Jacob and Wilhelm Grimm aus der Jugendzeit, ed. Grimm and (1805, 49ff). Novalis’s notes on colour from Werner are op. cit. IIT:
Hinrichs 1963, 86-7). A striking example of Runge’s increasing 147-56.
‘abstraction’ is the abandonment of the sea as a background to the 10 Novalis (op. cit. n. 3 above) III, 295.
Large Morning (Traeger nos 473, 478, 492, 497), which robs the 11 Goethe’s unpublished essay on coloured shadows had been
female figure of much of her identity as Venus (in the letter to composed in 1793 (Leopoldina Ausgabe der Schriften zur Naturwis-
Goethe cited above she is simply called ‘female form’ (weibliche senschaft, |Abt. 3, ed. R. Matthaei 1951, 66). A reference to Goethe’s
Gestalt), although the sea is still introduced at this stage). If this is optical work in a letter from Caroline and A. W. Schlegel to Novalis
indeed an important iconographical change, the lost oil study of of Feb. 1799, in Schriften, 1V (1975), 523, suggests that the young
a calm sea and sky (Traeger no. 494) is unlikely to have been writer was familiar with these researches.
connected with the last versions of Morning. U. Bichel has pointed 12 For Novalis’s scheme ofopposites, III, 150, and for another note
to the narrative significance of the colour of the sea in Runge’s on colour-polarity, III, 148.
fairy-tale The Fisherman and his Wife, 1805 (‘P. O. Runges Marchen 13 Jean-Paul Richter 1793, The Secret Society (Die unsichtbare Loge),
1982, “Von dem Fischer un syner Fru”, sein Aufbau und seine I. Theil, 20 Sektor, in Sdmtliche Werke, ed. E. Berend, I/2 (1927),
Farbssymbolik’, Niederdeutsches Jahrbuch 105, 983-5); and transparency 165-6. Novalis had read the novel by the end of 1795 (IV, 406).
was of course one of the keystones of his colour-theory (see espec. 14 Goethe (op. cit. n. 6 above), Didactic Part $781.
Traeger, op. cit n. 2 above, 440f and no. 435; H. Hohl in the exhibi- 15 Steffens (op. cit. n. 5 above) 48f. For Steffens and Runge,
tion catalogue Runge in seiner Zeit, Hamburg, Kunsthalle, 1977, Chapter 13 above.
220ff: S. Rehfus-Déchene 1982, Farbengebung und Farbenlehre in der 16 Goethe (op. cit. n. 3 above), Didactic Part §696.
deutschen Malerei um 1800, 1 16ff). 17 J. G. Herder (1800), Kalligone, ed. H. Begenau 1955, 32.
35 HS, U, 372. 18 F. H. Lehr 1924, Die Bliitezeit romantischer Bildkunst: Franz Pforr,
36 HS, I, 157-8. der meister des Lukasbundes, 275-7. See also the discussion in B. Rehfus-
Dechéne 1982, Farbengebung und Farbenlehre in der deutschen Maleret
um 1800, 108. For the red hair of the Jews, R. Mellinkoff 1983,
‘Judas’ Red Hair and the Jews’, Journal ofJewish Art, IX, 31-46. The
297
NOTES TO THE TEXT
298
NOTES TO THE TEXT
299
NOTES TO THE TEXT
12 Broude 16. Charles Blanc’s ‘Eugéne Delacroix’ was published Vibert, who claimed to have been teaching at the Ecole for thirty
sff, o7ff, and reprinted years, introduced this palette chiefly as a key to harmony.
1864 in the Gazette des Beaux-Arts, XVI,
1876 in his Les artistes de mon temps. | have used the later version here. 29 Rood 179-80.
30 Herbert in Sutter (op. cit. n.15 above) 26.
13 Blanc 23f. For van Gogh, see E. van Uitert 1966-7, ‘De toon van
over Kleur en zijn Hollandse 31 Letter to Fénéon, 1889, in C. de Hauke 1962, Seurat et son oeuvre,
Vincent van Gogh: Opvattingen
periode’, Simiolus, II, Lott. ; I, XX.
pl. Dy and of Le 32 Gustave Kahn 1891, in Broude 22.
14 See the detail of La Grande Jatte in Homer,
Chahut (1889-90) in A. Callen 1982, Techniques of the Impressionists, 33 Homer 171ff.
149. 34 Ibid. 294, 103.
: : 35. P. Signac, Journal, 22 Nov. 1894, inJ. Rewald (ed.) 1949, “Extraits
15 See espec. Figure and Trees on the Banks of the Seine, New York,
Marie Coll. (Dorra and Rewald 108) and Figure on the Bank of the du journal inédit de Paul Signac’, Gazette des Beaux-Arts, XXXVI,
Seine, with Sailing Boat, Washington, DC, National Gallery of Art, 108. It is an irony that from this date Signac’s brushstrokes become
Mellon-Bruce Coll. (Dorra and Rewald 109). increasingly larger, so that by the end of the 1890s fusion can no
16 C. Blanc 1867, Grammaire des arts du dessin, 608. Seurat told longer be in question.
Fénéon that he had read this book ‘at school’ (Broude 16). A. Piron 36 Ibid. 114 (29 Dec. 1894). Also see the letter of 1887 to Pissarro,
186s, Delacroix: Sa vie et ses oeuvres, 416ff. For Seurat’s notes from cited by D. Thompson 1985, Seurat, 112, and Signac to Seurat on
this source, see R. L. Herbert, ‘Seurat’s Theories’ in J. Sutter (ed.) the Grande Jatte in Brussels in 1887: Dorra and Rewald 1959, 381-s.
1970, The Neo-Impressionists, 24. 37 See, for example, the contours of the figures in the excellent
17 Rood 14 (but see 41 for ‘white sunlight’). The most detailed dis- detail in J. Russell 1965, Seurat, 164.
cussion of the colour of sunlight available to Seurat was probably 38 J. Carson Webster 1944, ‘The Techniques of Impressionism: A
that in Ernst Briicke’s Physiologie der Farben, 1866, 32, 46ff (French Reappraisal’, in Broude 99; Lee (op. cit. n. 3 above) 207-8.
trans. Des couleurs au point de vue physique, physiologique, artistique et 39 Signac 1894 (op. cit. n. 35 above). The fullest technical study of
industriel, 1866), but Briicke’s conclusion was that its yellowish or this painting is in J. Leighton and R. Thompson 1997, Seurat and the
reddish cast was essentially subjective, and could be disregarded by Bathers, espec. 76-83.
the painter. Seurat may have known the French translation of 40 The fullest study is still L. Schmeckebier 1932, ‘Die Erschein-
Briicke’s handbook, Principes scientifiques des beaux-arts, Paris, 1878, ungsweisen kleinflachiger Farben’, Archiv fiir die gesamte Psychologie,
since, as Homer 289 has suggested, a note by the painter of the Ixxxv, espec. 25-7. Schmeckebier (33) stresses the need for variable
name of Hermann von Helmholtz in the Signac Archive probably viewing distances in the case of ‘Impressionist’ pictures.
refers to that scientist’s essay, ‘On the relation ofoptics to painting’, 41 M. Schapiro in Meyerson (op. cit. n. 3 above) 25. But see now
which was published as an appendix to this edition of Briicke’s P. Smith 1990, ‘Seurat: the natural scientist?’, Apollo, CXXXIIL,
work. 381-5.
18 L. Nochlin (ed.) 1966, Impressionism and Post-Impressionism, 1874- 42 Fénéon 175.
1904 (Sources and Documents in the History ofArt), 127. 43 Nochlin (op. cit. n. 18 above) 116 (French original in De
19 Fénéon 1886 in Broude, 38. Hauke, op. cit. n. 30 above, I, xxiv, n. 27).
20 See R. L. Herbert et al. 1991, Georges Seurat 1859-1891, App. K, 44 Rey (op. cit. n. 2 above) 130f, 21.
390-1. 45 D.C. Rich 1969, Seurat and the Evolution of ‘La Grande Jatte’, 19.
21 Homer 4of; Fénéon, whose reading of Rood has been noticed, 46 Signac (op. cit. n. 24 above) 108.
made his complementaries only approximately those of this writer 47 Following Helmholtz (op. cit. n. 17 above), a number of French
in his review of 1886, but by the time ofhis article on Signac in Les theorists ofthe period argued that the relative feebleness ofthe artists’
hommes d’aujourd’hui in 1890, they had become much closer to materials meant that they must paint the effects of nature’s contrasts
Rood’s (Fénéon 174f). themselves: see G. Guéroult 1882, ‘Formes, couleurs, mouvements’,
22 R. L. Herbert 1981, ‘Parade du Cirque de Seurat et lésthetique Gazette des Beaux-Arts, XXV, and J.-G. Vibert (op. cit. n. 27 above)
scientifique de Charles Henry’, Revue de l'art, no. 50, 18, fig. 12. 47, n. 24. Seurat’s strategies in this instance serve to undermineJ. A.
Herbert ef al. (op. cit. n. 20 above), App. L, 392. Seurat’s circle Richardson’s interesting characterization of his style as aiming to
probably derives from his reading of Charles Henry, whose construct ‘a phenomenal image first hand, an image that would
summary of Chevreul in Introduction a une ésthetique scientifique, 1885, possess all the brilliance and variability of the world of light itself
is reprinted by Herbert 22. For Henry’s circle, see Homer 195. because it was constructed with regard to the laws governing the
23 It is worth noting that Blanc, Grammaire, 597ff, n. 1, character- visual mechanics of that world (J. A. Richardson 1971, Modern Art
ized his “Rose chromatique’ as ‘une image mnemonique indispens- and Scientific Thought, 67, a reference | owe to the kindness of Prof.
able’, and yet printed two slightly differing arrangements of it in his Herbert).
plate and text. 48 See, for example, the well-informed popularizations ofA.Guillemin
24 See Herbert (op. cit. n. 3 above) n. 80 (Dorra and Rewald 177). 1874, La lumieére et les couleurs (Petite encyclopaedie populaire des sciences
25 Broude 18. The statement, which Christophe used in his article et de leurs applications), espec. 258f& E. Véron 1878, L’esthétique,
on Seurat in Les hommes d’aujourd'hui, was reprinted by Signac in Paris (English ed. London 1879), chap. iv; Guéroult (op. cit. n. 47
De Delacroix au Néo-Impressionisme, ed. F. Cachin 1964, 107. Homer above), espec. 174ff, n. 43, which cite Helmholtz’s complementaries.
135 claimed that Seurat indeed used Rood’s complementaries in Guillemin’s book was in the library of Duranty (M. Marcussen
La Grande Jatte, but this seems to be a mistake, and, in any case, the 1979, ‘Duranty et les Impressionistes’, Hafnia, V1, 29), who also
well-known alteration of the pigments in this picture make a purely owned the French trans. of Briicke and Helmholtz; and Huysmans
optical analysis hazardous, to say the least. See I. Fiedler 1984, used Véron’s work in his critique ofImpressionism (O. Reutersvard
‘Materials used in Seurat’s La Grande Jatte, including color changes 1950, ‘The Violettomania of the Impressionists’, Journal of Aesthetics
and notes on the evolution ofthe artist’s palette’, American Institute and Art Criticism, IX, 108-9).
of Conservation, Preprints, May, 43-51; idem 1989, ‘A technical 49 Fenéon 72, 174; A. Thorold (ed.) 1980, Artists, Writers, Politics:
evaluation of La Grande Jatte’, Art Institute of Chicago Museum Studies, Camille Pissarro and His Friends, 38, no. 94. Pissarro did have reserva-
XIV/2, 173-9, 244-5. tions about Fénéon’s account ofreflections and solar orange.
26 W. 1. Homer 1959, ‘Notes on Seurat’s Palette’ in Broude 1 16ff. 50 Fénéon, xv, 174, n. 1. Signac warned Fénéon not to take too
27 For Signac’s notes, see Homer 151f, n. 4; also see Callen (op. cit. much notice of Henry’s views, as he was too obsessed with comple-
n. 14 above) 134, 146. Seurat had fewer yellows, blues and greens mentary contrast, an obsession very likely to commend him to
than Signac, but more reds and oranges. Seurat.
28 J.-G. Vibert (1891), The Science of Painting, 8th ed. 1892, 35-6. 51 M.-E. Chevreul (1839), The Principles ofHarmony and Contrast of
300
NOTES TO THE TEXT
Colours, trans. C. Martel, 3rd ed. 1860, 237. But for the restriction of 14 J. Christophe 1890, ‘Dubois-Pillet’, Les Hommes d’Aujourd’hui, 8,
this principle to painting in ‘flat tints’, see above Chapter 15, and no. 370, repr. in Bazalgette (op. cit. n. 14 above), 95f. For an English
G. Roque 1996, ‘Chevreul and Impressionism: a reappraisal’, Art translation of the whole passage, J. Rewald, Post-Impressionism from
Bulletin, LXXVIII, 35. Van Gogh to Gauguin, rev. ed. 1978, 109, 116. The remarks on the
52 Rood ch. xvi. application to painting are not in Rood.
53 For Seurat’s distortion of the record, see Thompson (op. cit. n. 15 Camille to Lucien Pissarro, 30 Nov. 1886, in J. Bailly-Herzberg
36 above) 97f. (ed.) 1986, Correspondence de Camille Pissarro, 11, 77.
16 G. Dulon and C. Duvivier 1991, Louis Hayet 1864-1940, Peintre et
Théoricien du Néo-Impressionisme, 61.
17 Seurat’s Silence 17 Ibid., 166-74.
18 Ibid., 62, 185, and also 148 for Hayet’s objection to Seurat’s
I For the music in Le Chahut, W. 1. Homer 1964, Seurat and the ‘system’.
Science of Painting, 296-7. 19 Ibid. 188-9. This autobiographical note was written in 1923,
2 P. Smith 1997, Seurat and the Avant-garde, 107-55. about the same time as Malevich was proposing a similar plan in
3 Seurat to Signac, 26 August 1888, in H. Dorra and R. Rewald Light and Colour: see the French edition, K. Malevich, La Lumiere et
1959, Seurat, LXV. See also M. Zimmerman 1991, Les Mondes de la Couleur, ed.J.Marcadé 1981, 87.
Seurat: Son oeuvre et le Débat artistique de son Temps, 213f. For a con- 20 Camille to Lucien Pissarro, 10 Jan. 1892 (Bailly-Herzberg, op.
trary view, that Seurat, ‘from all reports, talked obsessively about cit. n. 16 above, III, 1988, 185): A. Thorold (ed.) 1993, The Letters of
his artistic theories’, M. Ward, ‘The rhetoric of independence and Lucien to Camille Pissarro, 1883-1903, 276.
innovation’ in C. S. Moffett et al. 1986, The New Painting: Impres- 21 Pissarro to Fénéon, 21 Feb. 1889: J. U. Halperin, Félix Fénéon,
sionism 1874-1886, 436. These reports include those of Gustave Kahn Aesthete and Anarchist in Fin-de-Siecle Paris, 1988, 105 (not in Bailly-
(N. Broude 1978, Seurat in Perspective, 21), Emile Verhaeren (ibid. Herzberg). See also Fénéon to Pissarro, 18 February 1889 (Bailly-
28, 30) and Charles Angrand (ibid. 35), who also says, however, that Herzberg II, 266), Pissarro to Fénéon, ?Oct. 1886 (BH II, 73),
Seurat “was usually silent and embarrassed’. Pissarro to Signac, April 1887 (BH I, 153-4).
4 See P. Smith 1992, ““Parbleu”: Pissarro and the political colour of 22 J.-G. Vibert (1891), La Science de la Peinture, 1902 (repr. 1981),
an original vision’, Art History, XV, 225. ch. IV and 80.
5 H. von Helmholtz 1852, ‘Ueber die Theorie der zuasammengeset- 23 G. Kahn 1891, ‘Seurat’, in Broude (op. cit. n. 3 above) 22.
zten Farben’, Poggendorffs Annalen der Physik und Chemie, LXXXVII, 24 R. L. Herbert 1962, Seurat’s Drawings. For Fantin, Gage 1993,
45-66; 1852-3, ‘Sur la Théorie des couleurs composées’, Cosmos, II, Colour and Culture, 185.
112-20. I am grateful to Carol Coe for alerting me to this article. 25 See G. Roque 1992, ‘Les Symbolistes et la Couleur’, Revue de
The French version may be by Jean-Bernard Léon Foucault, since it l’Art 96, 70-6.
adds a note that he was about to produce a ‘plus rationnel et plus 26 Seurat to Signac, 25 June 1886 in Dorra and Rewald (op. cit. n. 3
simple’ method of experiment, on which he had been working above) L-LI.
for several years. This was published as ‘Sur la recomposition des 27 Vibert (op. cit. n. 22 above) 72; Bracquemond (op. cit. n. 11
couleurs du spectre en teintes plates’ (ibid. 232-3). It was a method above) 55. Blanc’s Grammaire, 1867, 612 had spoken of Delacroix’s
which had first been taught by Pouillet at the Sorbonne in 1849. technique of optical mixture in The Women of Algiers as having
6 A. Laugel 1869, L’Optique et les Arts, 150; E. Véron (1878), Aes- produced ‘un troisiéme ton indéfinissable qu’on ne peut nommer
thetics, 1879, 229. Véron, however, pointed out that the scheme avec précision...’.
“does not furnish accurate information for painters’. 28 Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, 190, 206.
7 Laugel (op. cit.) 151-2. 29 “Even when applied in the same way, one and the same stimulus
8 E. Briicke 1878, Principles Scientifiques des Beaux-Arts. Essais et may be perceived as stronger or weaker by one subject or organ than
Fragments de Théorie... Suivis de L’Optique et la Peinture de H. by another, or by the same subject or organ at one time as stronger
Helmholtz, 7. For Henry and Leonardo,J. A. Argiielles 1972, Charles or weaker than at another. Conversely, stimuli of different magni-
Henry and the Formation ofaPsycho-Physical Aesthetic, 45, 78-9. tudes may be perceived as equally strong under certain circum-
9 Helmholtz in Briicke (op. cit.) 207, here quoted from the English stances.’ (G. T. Fechner (1860), Elements of Psychophysics trans. H. E.
version, ‘On the relation of optics to painting’, Popular Lectures on Adler 1966, 38).
Scientific Subjects, trans. E. Atkinson 1goo, II, 118. The lectures were 30 Seurat to Fénéon, 20 June 1890, in Broude (op. cit. n. 23 above)
originally published as ‘Optisches tiber Malerei’, Populdre wis- 16.
senschaftliche Vortrage, 1876.
10 Helmholtz (op. cit. n. 5 above) 207-9, 1900, II, 119-21. D.
Sutter 1880, ‘Les phenomenes de la vision’, L’Art, XX, 216. 18 Matisse’s Black Light
Ir See the version of Seurat’s Esthétique (1890) in Herbert et al.
1991, Seurat 1859-1891, 381. Homer has surveyed the evidence for 1 Verve, IV, 13, 1945. In Jeune Fille devant la Fenétre: Robe Blanche et
Seurat’s knowledge of Helmholtz without reaching a conclusion Ceinture Noire (1942) the scarlet lake, light ultramarine blue and
(op. cit. n. 1 above, 288-90). One channel may have been through cobalt violet are attributed to Lefranc, and the pot-plant in Michaella
Pissarro’s friend Bracquemond, who referred to the Young- (1943) was painted with ‘Vert comp. N° 2 Lefranc’. Matisse had
Helmholtz theory of the primaries somewhat slightingly in Du been using some ofLefranc’s materials at least since the early 1920s,
Dessin et de la Couleur, 1885, 245. Pissarro, however, did not include but at that time his colours were supplied largely by the Belgian firm
Helmholtz with Chevreul and Maxwell in the important letter on of Blockx (see C. Moreau-Vauthier 1923, Comment on peint aujour-
theory to Durand-Ruel in November 1886 (A. Thorold 1980, d’hui, 30, 84, and Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, 222, 296 nn. $4,
Artists, Writers, Politics: Camille Pissarro and his Friends, Oxford, Ash- 83). The first scholar to draw attention to these ‘palettes’ was proba-
molean Museum, 2). bly Alfred Barr Jr, who reproduced that for Danseuse, Fond Noir,
12 O. Rood 1879, Modern Chromatics, 190-1 on Helmholtz’s pri- Fauteuil Rocaille, together with a black and white reproduction of the
maries, complementaries and colour-mixing. painting, in Matisse: His Art and his Public, 1951, 488.
13 Rood (op. cit) 113. Young’s work is discussed in P. D. Sherman, 2. See the long note on the painting of the red check tablecloth in
Colour Vision in the Nineteenth Century: The Young-Helmholtz-Maxwell Citrons et Saxifrages (1943), which uses the past tense: Verve, loc. cit.,
Theory, 1981. Dubois-Pillet owned a copy of Rood, which he was 49, col. ill. so.
3 H. Matisse, Ecrits et Propos sur l’Art, ed. D. Fourcade 1972, 197.
lending to Fénéon in Sept. 1887 (L. Bazalgette 1976, Dubois-Pillet, sa
Vie et son Oeuvre (1846-90), 107). Fourcade gives this text the title De la Couleur, but in Verve it was not
301
NOTES TO THE TEXT
directly associated with Matisse’s title-page, but was printed on 9- concerned to show that scientific hypotheses were no more com—
10, andJ. Flam, in his anthology of Matisse’s writings, gives it the pelling than poetic metaphors, argued that the second tendency of
more neutral title, Observations on Painting (J. D. Flam 1973, Matisse modern science was precisely the opposite, ‘towards diversity and
on Art, 101). : complication’, but that only the first made science possible: ‘the true
4 Matisse, op. cit. 202-3. Flam, op. cit 106-7, also points out that
and only aim is unity’ (177).
27 This account ofLe Bon’s work draws largely on M. J. Nye 1974,
these thoughts were recorded at the time of an exhibition, Le Noir
‘Gustave Le Bon’s Black Light: a study in physics and philosophy
est une Couleur, at the Maeght Gallery in December 1946. Matisse
told André Masson in the early 1930s that Renoir, who admired
in France in the turn of the century’, Historical Studies in the Physical
Matisse’s use of black in the first painting he showed the older Sciences, 1V, 163-95.
painter, had also demonstrated ‘par sa franchise et son honneté’ that 28 G. Le Bon (1907), The Evolution ofForces, trans. F. Legge 1908,
279. The whole of Bk IV of this work, which ran into at least three
black was a light as well as a colour (A. Masson 1974, ‘Conversations
avec Matisse’, Critique, XXX, 324, 394-5). I owe this reference to editions before 1918, is devoted to Black Light.
the kindness of Nicholas Watkins. 29 A. Dastre 1901, ‘Les nouvelles radiations: rayons cathodiques et
5 E. de Goncourt 1895, ‘Hokusai: les albums traitant de la peinture rayons rontgen’, Revue des Deux Mondes, LXXI, s* per. VI, 696. Le
et du dessin avec ses préfaces’, Gazette des Beaux-Arts, XXXVI (3° Bon was happy to quote this passage in his Evolution of Matter (1905),
per. XIV), 442. The translation here is based on A. Reinhardt 3rd. ed., trans. Legge 1907, 29.
(1967), ‘Black as Symbol and Concept’ in B, Rose (ed.) 1975, Art as 30 Le Bon (op. cit. n. 28 above) 202.
Art: the Selected Writings of Ad Reinhardt, 86. Hokusai’s book is the 31 Ibid. 284-s.
Yehon Saishiki Tsu (An Illustrated Book on the proper use of Colours), 32 Ibid. 290-291.
published in two volumes in 1848. 33 Flam (op. cit. n. 7 above) 392. The author, Xavier Pelletier,
6 Durand-Ruel had the Astruc between 1895 (or 1899) and c. 1908, seems to have been thinking of the “N-rays’ mooted in 1903-4 as
and the Breakfast between 1894 and 1898 (see Paris, Grand Palais/ emanating from animal and plant tissue, but the experiments were
New York, Metropolitan Museum of Art, Manet, 1832-1883, 1983, soon discredited (Nye, op. cit. n. 27 above, 180). For a detailed
nos 94, 109, for the fullest accounts of these paintings). Matisse will study of the ‘N-ray’ scandal, M. J. Nye 1980,’N-rays: an episode in
also have had the opportunity of studying the Breakfast at Bernheim- the history and psychology ofscience’, Historical Studies in the Physi-
Jeune’s Gallery in 1910. cal Sciences 11, 125-56, espec. 133. Carol Coe kindly directed me to
7 J. Flam 1986, Matisse: the Man and his Art, 1869-1918, 78. this article.
8 Flam (op. cit) 114. 34 Nye (op. cit. n. 27 above) 190-1.
9 Flam (op. cit) $1. 35 They include Reader on a Black Background, 1939 (Paris, Musée
10 For The Balcony, Manet, 1983, no. 115. National d’Art Moderne) and Dancer and Rocaille Armchair on a Black
11 Flam (op. cit) 394; I. Monod-Fontaine, ‘A Black Light: Matisse Background, (1942).
(1914-1918) in C. Turner and R. Benjamin (eds.) 1995, Matisse, 36 For the series of black chasubles,J.Cowart,J.Flam, D. Fourcade
Brisbane, Queensland Art Gallery/ Canberra, National Gallery of 1977,J.H. Neff, Henri Matisse: Paper Cut-Outs, nos 148-55, espec.
Australia/ Melbourne, National Gallery of Victoria, 87. no. ISS.
12 Flam (op. cit) 394.
13 On this series, see espec. Monod-Fontaine 1995, 87-8.
14 J. Eldertield 1978, Matisse in the Collection of theMuseum ofModern 19 Colour as Language in Early Abstract Painting
Art, T12:
15 D. Giraudy 1971, ‘Correspondance Henri Matisse-Charles Camoin’, 1 ‘Reminiscences’ (1913) in Kandinsky: Complete Writings on Art,
Revue de l’Art, 12, 17-18. ed. Lindsay and Vergo 1982, I, 370.
16 See R. L. Herbert ef al. 1991, Georges Seurat, 1859-1891, New 2 C. Lévi-Strauss (1964), The Raw and the Cooked, trans. Weight-
York, Metropolitan Museum of Art, nos 69, 71, 146. Other Seurat man 1970, 19f, 25. E.H. Gombrich 1963, ‘The Vogue for Abstract
drawings of this type which may have been known to Matisse Art’, Meditations on a hobby-horse.
include The Housepainter (1883-4; Herbert no. 46), which belonged 3 S. Bann 1980, ‘Abstract Art — a Language?’ in London, Tate
to Pissarro, and Scaffolding (1886-7: Herbert no. 174), which belonged Gallery, Towards a New Art: Essays on the Background to Abstract Art,
to Signac. 1910-20, 144.
17 For example, Flam (op. cit.) 405. 4 A. Besant and C. W. Leadbeater (1901), Thought-Forms, Madras
18 Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, 118; van Gogh to Bernard, June 1961, 20.
1888 in Complete Letters of Vincent Van Gogh, 1958, I, 490. 5 Kandinsky (op. cit. n. 1 above) 183.
19 I assume that this is the underlying rationale of Malevich’s 6 W. Wundt (1874), Grundztige der physiologischen Psychologie, sth
remark in 1920, ‘I consider white and black to be deduced from the ed. 1902, II, 145.
colour spectra’ (K. S. Malevich, Essays on Art, ed. T. Andersen 1969, 7 Kandinsky (op. cit. n. 1 above) 182; Wundt (op. cit.) 352 n. 1; G.
I, 126-7). T. Fechner (1877), Vorschule der Aesthetik, 1, 1898, 216.
20 N. Watkins 1984, Matisse, 139. 8 Levi-Strauss, loc. cit., n. 2.
21 Flam (op. cit.) 133 (1951). 9 See M. Foucault 1966, Les mots et les choses, ch. 1V. The fullest
22 Matisse (op. cit. n. 3 above), 94. account of the work of Schiftermiiller and Harris is now T. Lersch
23 Flam (op. cit.) 38. For Matisse’s ‘scientific’ bias in the Fauve 1984, ‘Von der Entomologie zur Kunsttheorie’ in De Arte et Libris:
period, 1904-5, Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, 211. Festschrift Erasmus, 30 1f.
24 Barr (op. cit. n. 1 above) 185; Flam (op. cit.) 21, 243-4, 388-9. 10 | am thinking especially of G. Field 1850, Rudiments of the
M. Antliff 1993, Inventing Bergson: Cultural Politics and the Parisian painter’s art; or a Granunar of Colouring; E. Guichard 1882, Grammar of
Avant-Garde, 198-9, has questioned Matisse’s direct knowledge of Colour.
Bergson before 1909. 1X Rood 1879, Modern Chromatics, 250; W. I. Homer, ‘Notes on
25 R. Escholier 1960, Matisse from the Life, 98. Poincaré does not Seurat’s Palette’ in N. Broude 1978, Seurat in Perspective, 116ff.
speak in so many words of the ‘destruction of Matter’ in Science and 12 V. Huszar 1917, ‘lets over die Farbenfibel van W. Ostwald’, De
Hypothesis, although the argument, so exciting to Matisse, is implicit Stijl, 1, 1134.
in several places, especially ch, X. Matisse was probably reporting his 13 E. A. Carmean Jr 1979, Mondrian: The Diamond Compositions,
discussion of the book with the librarian Galanis who, according to Washington, National Gallery of Art, 79-83. Rood (op. cit. n. 11
Matisse, had ‘found the origin of cubism’ in this text. above) 136, had found that spectral red could be matched in pig-
26 Poincaré (op. cit. n. 25 above) 1905, 173. Poincaré, who was ments by a glaze of carmine over vermilion.
302
NOTES TO THE TEXT
303
NOTES TO THE TEXT
7 P. Francastel (ed.) 1957, Du Cubisme a V’Art Abstrait, 184. The und Sinnesverkniipfungen: Studien und Materialien zur Vorgeschichte der
most detailed technical analysis of the Disc is in H. J. Albrecht 1974, Syniisthesie; T. Tornitore 1988, Scambi di Sensi: Preistorie delle Sineste-
sie. See also S. Baron-Cohen andJ. E. Harrison (eds.) 1996, Synaes-
Farbe als Sprache, 30ff. The Disc (private collection) is reproduced in
colour in Albrecht (pl. 1). thesia: Classic and Contemporary Readings.
9 J. Miiller, Elements of Physiology, trans. W. Baly (1833-8). For a
8 V. Huszar 1917, ‘Iets over die Farbenfibel van W. Ostwald’, De
aT useful summary of Miiller’s work and its influence, E. G. Boring
Stijl, 1, 113 ff.
1942, Sensation and Perception in the History ofExperimental Psychology,
9 See Composition VII: The Cow, 1917, and Composition in Discords,
1918 (Mrs M. Arp-Hagenbach), in J. Baljeu 1974, Theo van Does-
68-78; and for its effect on 19th-century concepts of representation,
burg, 33, 36. In his Principles of Neo-Plastic Art (1925), 1969, 15 and
J. Crary 1990, Techniques of the Observer: on Vision and Modernity in the
fig. 1, Van Doesburg opted for the three primaries, red, yellow and Nineteenth Century, ch. 3. For Elliot’s Philosophical Observations on the
blue, but it is not certain whether this represents his views in 1915
Senses (1780), J. D. Mollon 1987, ‘John Elliot MD, 1747-1787’,
and 1917, when the MS was said to have been completed. Green is Nature 329, 19-20.
not among the colours discussed in the first published version of 10 G. T. Fechner (1876), Vorschule der Aesthetik, 1, 1897, 176ff; idem
his theory: T. van Doesburg (1919), Grondbegrippen van de nieuwe (1877), Ul, 1898, 315-19.
beeldende Kunst, ed. S. V. Barbieri, C. Boekrad,J. Leering 1983, 22. 11 The fullest study of the early history of audition colorée, a term which
For a fuller discussion of Mondrian and Ostwald, Gage 1993, Colour seems to have been a French translation of the English ‘coloured
and Culture, 257-9. hearing’, but was usually cited in French, is F. Mahling 1926, “Das
to R. P. Welsh andJ. M. Joosten1969, Two Mondrian Sketchbooks, Problem der Audition colorée’, Archiv fur die gesamte Psychologie, LV,
1912-14, 21. Mondrian’s reading of Kandinsky is suggested by his 165-257. For more recent work,J.Davidoff 1991, Cognition through
phrase ‘an inner feeling of necessity’ (44). But see also n. 3 above. Color, 111-13; P. Junod 1994, ‘De Vaudition colorée ou du bon
11 See R. P. Welsh, ‘Mondrian and Theosophy’, Piet Mondrian: usage d’un mythe’ in P. Junod and M. Pastoureau, Couleur: Regards
Centennial Exhibition, New York, Guggenheim Museum, 1971, croisés sur la couleur du Moyen Age au XX° Siecle, 63-81. J. Harrison and
35ff. Thought-Forms had been translated into Dutch in 1905. S. Baron-Cohen 1994, ‘Synaesthesia: an account of coloured
12 For Mondrian’s complex relationship with Huszar, Gage 1993, hearing’, Leonardo, 27/4, 343-6. For the long history of colour-
Colour and Culture, 257-8. music analogies, Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, ch. 13.
13 De Stijl, 1, 3, 1918, 30, in H. Holtzman and M. James (eds.) 1987, 12 For Newton’s colour-musical concerns, see above Chapter 9,
The New Art— The New Life: The Collected Writings of Piet Mondrian, and espec. D. Topper 1990, ‘Newton on the number of colours in
36. Shoenmaekers’ doctrines had been published in The New Image the spectrum’, Studies on the History and Philosophy of Science, 21/2,
of the World (Het nieuwe Wereldbeeld), 1915, and Principles of Plastic 269-79.
Mathematics (Beginselen der beeldende Wiskunde), 1916. For Kandin- 13 See, for example, L. E. Marks 1975, ‘On colored-hearing
sky’s reputation in Holland, W. Kandinsky, Regards sur le Passé, ed. synaesthesia’, Psychological Bulletin, LXXXII, 303-31; S. Baron-
Bouillon 1974, 237. For Van Doesburg’s interest in Kandinsky, Cohen, M. A. Wyke, C. Binnie 1987, ‘Hearing words and seeing
Baljeu (op. cit. n. 9 above) 16, 21-4. colours: an experimental investigation of a case of synaesthesia’,
14 For Mondrian’s use of yellow-green, above Chapter 19, n. 14, Perception, XVI, 761-7.
and Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, 258 and pl. 201. 14 A. de Rochas 1885, “L’Audition colorée’, La Nature, Il, 275,
15 Holtzman and James (op cit. n. 13 above) 36. where the poem is attributed to Verlaine, who had published it
16 See R. P. Welsh 1966, Piet Mondrian, espec. no. 84, 89; and Piet for the first time in Lutéce in 1883 and again in Les Poétes Maudits in
Mondrian: Centienniel Exhibition, New York, Guggenheim Museum, 1884 (A. Rimbaud, Oeuvres Completes, ed. A.Adam 1972, 898). For
1971, nos 69, 73, 75-7, 81, 89. See also Van Doesburg’s Composition Rimbaud’s disclaimer, Un Saison en Enfer (1873) in W. Fowle (ed.
XI, 1918, and Rhythms of aRussian Dance, 1918. and trans.) 1966, Rimbaud: Complete Works, 192. It is particularly
notable that in the course of the poem Rimbaud’s rouge becomes
elided with pourpre, and his bleu with violet:: he seems to be more
21 Making Sense of Colour — the Synaesthetic concerned with the resonance of colour-ideas than with colour-
Dimension perceptions.
15 A. Binet 1892, ‘Le probléme de l’audition colorée’, Revue des
1 The mosaics have been discussed briefly by G. Delfini Filippi, ‘La Deux Mondes, CXIII, 586, 607. Rimbaud’s poem is cited as the most
Basilica dal Seicento all’Ottocento’ in C. Pietrangeli (ed.) 1989, La famous instance of the phenomenon on 609. The Symbolist theorist
Basilica di S. Pietro, 156-62; see also F. di Federico 1983, The Mosaics of language René Ghil was much concerned with audition colorée in
of St Peter’s decorating the New Basilica. the early versions of his Traité du Verbe (1885), adducing Rimbaud’s
2 J. D. Forbes 1849, ‘Hints towards a classification of colours’, poem, but attacking his rendering of the ‘simple’ vowel U with the
Philosophical Magazine, 3rd ser., XXXIV, 177-8. ‘compound’ colour green and proposing yellow instead (R. Ghil,
3 K. Pearson, The Life, Letters and Labours of Francis Galton, 1914-30, Traité du Verbe, Etats Successifs 1885, 1886, 1887, 1888, 1891, 1904, ed.
Il, 224f. T. Goruppi 1978, 60, 82, 108). Ewald Hering had of course already
4 H. Conklin 1955, ‘Hanundo color categories’, South Western Journal shown in 1874 that green is, phenomenologically, a ‘pure’ colour
of Anthropology, Il, 340, quotes estimates of perceptible nuances — (E. Hering 1878, Zur Lehre vom Lichtsinne, 107-21).
hues with variations of brightness and saturation — of between 7.5 16 Lind’s typescript of 1900, The Music of Color and the Number
and 10 million; see also R. W. Brown and E. H. Lenneberg 1954, Seven, formerly British Museum 1752 a.8, was destroyed during the
‘A study of language and cognition’, Journal of Abnormal Social Psy- 1939-45 war; an earlier version, Music of Color (1894) is in the
chology, XLIX, 457. A. Chapanis 1965, ‘Color names for color George Peabody Library, Johns Hopkins University, Baltimore, and
space’, American Scientist, LIM, 344 suggests that there are some 50 has been published in facs. by the library. Here I have used the
usable colour-names for the whole of colour-space. extracts from the British Museum version given by A. B. Klein
5 See above Chapter 3 and G. Roque 1991, ‘Portrait de la couleur 1937, Coloured Light, an Art Medium, 14-16.
en femme fatale’, Art & Fact (Revue des historiens de l’art, des 17 R. Redgrave (1853), A Manual of Colour, with a Catechism, 1884,
archaeologues, des musicologues et des orientalistes de l’Université ii; G. Field, Chromatography (1835), 2nd ed. 1841, 15, 191; D. R.
de Liege), X, 4-11. Hay, The Laws of Harmonious Colouring adapted to Interior Decoration,
6 See above Chapter 2 and B. J. Kouwer 1949, Colours and their Manufactures and other Useful Purposes, sth ed. 1844. Hay’s diagram is
Character: a Psychological Study, 526. close to several which had been published by Field since the 1st ed.
7 Kouwer, op. cit., is still the most extensive study. of his Chromatics in 1817, the 2nd ed. of which (1845) has a very
8 For the early history of synaesthetic ideas, L. Schrader 1969, Sinne extended discussion of the topic. For Redgrave’s work at the School
304
NOTES TO THE TEXT
of Design (but without reference to the colour-manual), A. Burton, 28 C. Scott (¢. 1916), The Philosophy ofModernism (and its Connection
‘Redgrave as art educator, museum official and design theorist’ in S. with Music), 111, 115. lam grateful to David Chadd for this reference.
Casteras and R. Parkinson (eds) 1988, Richard Redgrave, R.A., 1804- 29 A. Besant, “Thought-Forms’, Lucifer, a Theosophical Monthly, XIX,
1888, 48-70. Sept. 1896-Feb. 1897, 67f. For Scriabin’s synaesthesia, K. Peacock
18 F. Galton (1883), Inquiries into Human Faculty and its Development, 1985, ‘Synaesthetic perception: Alexander Scriabin’s color hearing’,
1907, 107. Galton’s principal source-book was the earliest substantial Music Perception, 1, 483-506. Peacock does not refer to Scriabin’s
gathering ofcase-histories, E. Bleuler and K. Lehmann, Zwangsinés- links with Theosophy, for which see Gage 1993, Colour and Culture,
sige Lichtempfindungen durch Schall und verwandte Erscheinungen auf dem 299 n.122. For Belyi, A. Steinberg, ‘Andrei Belyi’s experimental
Gebiete der anderen Sinnesempfindungen, 1879 (2nd ed. 1881). poetry’ in A. McMillin (ed.) 1992, Symbolism and After, 61-9. Prof.
19 Klein (op. cit. n. 16 above) 14. Robin Milner-Guilland kindly introduced me to this article. For
20 Pearson (op. cit. n. 3 above) II, 214. Cf. the discussion of the use Kandinsky and Theosophy, espec. S. Ringbom, “Transcending the
of coloured lights to treat hysterics in C. Féré 1887, Sensation et Mou- visible: the generation of the abstract pioneers’ in M. Tuchman et al.
vement, 43-6. 1986, The Spiritual in Art: Abstract Painting 1890-1985, 131-53.
21 E.A. Fletcher 1910, The Law
of theRhythmic Breath, 284-5. |have 30 Baron-Cohen et al. (op. cit, n. 24 above) 422.
been unable to trace a report of this case in Lombroso’s published 31 G. A. Reichard, R. Jackobson, E. Werth 1949, ‘Language and
work. Synaesthesia’, Word, V, 232-3.
22 See D. G. Landgrebe 1834, Ueber die Chemischen und Physiologis- 32 Cytowic (op. cit. n. 24 above) 59.
chen Wirkungen des Lichts (largely on plants and animals); R. Hunt 33 E. Downey 1929, Creative Imagination: Studies in the Psychology of
1844, Researches on Light in its Chemical Relations (on plants). Literature, 95.
23 See also The Lancet, March 29 1919, 519-22. For Germany, see 34 R. Cooke 1987, Velimir Khlebnikov, a Critical Study, 84-5;J.Padrta,
the work of the Bauhaus-trained designer Lou Scheper at the Uni- ‘Malevitch et Khlebnikov’ in J. C. Marcadé (ed.) 1979, Malevitch:
versity Clinic in Minster in 1924 (E. Neumann 1971, Bauhaus und Actes du Colloque International, 3 1-41; and see above Chapter 19
Bauhdusler, 94). For a positive evaluation of the treatment, M. Ander- 35 Gerome-Maisse (Alexis Mérodack-Jeaneau), “L’Audition colorée’,
son 1979, Colour Healing: Chromotherapy and How It Works; and for a Les Tendances Nouvelles (1907), 656.
critical survey of recent work, P. K. Kaiser 1984, ‘Physiological 36 Reichard et al. (op. cit. n. 31 above) 225f. For Jacobson’s con-
response to color: a critical review’, Color Research and Application, tinuing concern for coloured hearing, R. Jakobson 1968, Child-
IX, 29-36. Language, Aphasia and Phonological Universals, 82-4; R. Jakobson and
24 See espec. S. Baron-Cohen, J. Harrison, L. H. Goldstein, M. M. Halle, Fundamentals ofLanguage, 2nd ed. 1975, 45n.
Wyke 1993, “Coloured speech-perception: is synaesthesia what 37 Baron-Cohen ef al. (op. cit. n. 24 above) 420. This study also
happens when modularity breaks down?’, Perception, XXII, 419-26; proposes a possibly sex-linked genetic base for the faculty (423). See
R. E. Cytowic (1993), The Man Who Tasted Shapes, 1994, espec. 97, also B. Shanon 1982, ‘Color associates and semantic linear orders’,
108, 166. I am grateful to Dr Simon Baron-Cohen for this reference. Psychological Research 44, 76. There may of course be social reasons
25 W. Kandinsky, Complete Writings on Art, ed. and trans. K. C. why the response to a BBC Radio 4 programme was predominantly
Lindsay and P. Vergo 1982, I, 158. See also E. Heimendahl 1961, female, just as the reasons for the largely male sample of subjects in
Licht und Farbe: Ordnung und Funktion der Farbwelt, 210ff. Cytowic one ofthe earliest studies may have had a social origin (F. Suarez de
(op. cit. n. 24 above) 121, has emphasized the abstractness of colour- Mendoza 1890, L’ Audition Colorée. Etude sur les Fausses Sensations
synaesthetic experiences. Secondaires Physiologiques et Particuli¢rement sur les Pseudo-Sensations de
26 See Gage 1993, Colour and Culture, 209. Couleurs Associés aux Perceptions objectives des Sons, Paris: 39 female
27 Galton (op. cit. n. 18 above) 111. Many discrepancies in cases cases out of 134). Mérodack-Jeaneau (see n. 35 above) may have
recorded since 1812 have been tabulated by Schrader (op. cit. n. 8 been a patient of this Angers doctor, and quotes the book exten-
above) 37; see also L. E. Marks 1978, The Unity ofthe Senses, 87-9. sively in his 1907 article.
305
Select Bibliography
306
SELECT BIBLIOGRAPHY
Theophilus’s ‘De Diversis Artibus’ and Eraclius’s ‘De Coloribus et Alexander ofVilla Dei. 1958. Ecclesiale, ed. and trans. L. R. Lind.
Artibus Romanorum’ for Understanding the Technology and the Colors Alhazen (Ibn al-Haytham). 1989. The Optics, ed. and trans. A. I.
of Romanesque Stained Glass. PhD. diss., Cornell University. Sabra.
Ruth, U. M. 1977. Die Farbgebung in der Byzantinischen Wandmalerei [Anon.] 1932. Compositiones ad Tingenda Musiva, ed. H. Hedfors.
der Spédtpalaologischen Epoche (1341-1453). PhD diss., Rheinisch [Anon.] 1974. Mappae Clavicula, ed. C. T. Smith andJ. G. Haw-
Friedrich-Wilhelms Universitit, Bonn. thorne (Transactions of the American Philosophical Society,
Sauvaire, N. 1978. Le RéJe de la Famille Haro, Marchand de Couleurs, LXIV/4).
os l’ Oeuvre de Delacroix. Thése de Maitrise, University of Paris Anonymus Bernensis. 1932. De Clarea, ed. D. V. Thompson, Tech-
nical Studies in the Field of Fine Arts, U1.
Seibold, U. 1987. Zum Versténdnis des Lichts in der Malerei J. M. W. —. 1965. De Clarea, ed. R. Straub, Jahresbericht des Schweizerisches
Turners. PhD diss., Heidelberg University. J Institut fiir Kunstwissenschaft, 1964.
Shearman,J. 1957. Developments in the Use of Colour in Tuscan Paint- Bacon, Roger. 1907. Opus Maius, ed.J.H. Bridges:
ing ofthe Early 16th Century. PhD diss., London University. —. 1983. Roger Bacon's Philosophy of Nature: a Critical Edition with
Shiff, R. 1973. Impressionist Criticism, Impressionist Color, and Cézanne. English Translation, Introducton and Notes of De Multiplicatione
PhD diss., Yale University. Specierum and De Speculis Comburentibus, ed. D. C. Lindberg.
Siebenhiihner, H. 1935. Uber den Kolorismus der Fruhrenaissance, Baroni, S. 1996. ‘I ricettari medieval per la preparazione dei colori e
vornehmlich dargestellt an dem Trattato della Pittura des L. B, Alberti. la loro trasmissione’, in Istituto Storico Lucchese, I! Colore nel
PhD diss., Leipzig. Medioevo: Arte, Simbolo, Tecnica.
Thornton, J. A. 1979. Renaissance Color Theory and some Paintings by Bartholomeus Anglicus. 1975. On the Properties of Things: John of
Veronese. PhD diss., University of Pittsburgh. Trevisa’s Translation of Bartholomeus Anglicus De Proprietatibus
Watkins, N. 1979. A History and an Analysis of the Use of Colour in the Rerum, ed. N. Seymour, II.
Work of Matisse. M. Phil thesis, London University. Bateson, M. (ed.) 1899. Records of the Borough of
Leicester, I.
Weale, R. A. 1974. Theories of Light and Colour in Relation to the Bischoff, B. 1984. Anecdota Novissima: Texte des Vierten bis Sechzehn-
History of Painting. PhD diss., London University. ten Jahrhunderts.
Bommarito, D. 1985. ‘II MS 25 della Newbery Library: la tradizione
dei ricettarii e trattati sui colori nel medioevo e rinascimento
PRINCIPAL PRIMARY SOURCES veneto e toscano’, La Bibliofilia, LX XXVIII.
Brunello, F. 1975. De Arte Illuminandi e Altri Trattati sulla Tecnica della
Antiquity
Miniatura Medievale.
Aristotle, De Audibilibus. Caley, E. R. 1927. ‘The Stockholm Papyrus’, Journal of Chemical
—. De Sensu. Education, IV.
—. Meteorologica. Castro, A. 1921. “‘Unos aranceles de aduana del siglo XIII’, Revista de
Armuim,J. ab. 1903. Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, II. Filologia Espanola, VII.
Augustine of Hippo. The City of God, XXII, xxiv. Cennini, Cennino. 1933. The Craftsman’s Handbook, ed. and trans.
Cleomedes, Caelestia, II, i. D. V. Thompson.
Freeman, K. 1966. Anacilla to the Pre-Socratic Philosophers. —. 1971. Il Libro dell’Arte, ed. F. Brunello.
The Greek Anthology, 1969. ed. W. K. Paton. Coomaraswamy, A. 1935. ‘Medieval aesthetic, I. Dionysius the
Nahm, M. C. 1964. Selections from Early Greek Philosophy, 4th ed. Pseudo-Areopagite and Ulrich ofStrasburg’, Art Bulletin, XVII.
Ovid, Metamorphoses, I, 5. Diehl, E. 1925. Inscriptiones Latinae Christianae Veteres.
Philoponus, Johannes. 1901. In Aristotelis Meteorologicorum Librum Digulleville, Guillaume. 1895. Le Pélerinage de Ame, ed. J. J.
Primum Commentarium, ed. M. Hayduck. Sturzinger.
Philostratus. Imagines, I, 28 Dionysius of Fourna. 1974. The Painters’ Manual, ed. and trans. P.
Pliny the Elder. Natural History Hetherington.
Plotinus. Enneads, IV. Giacosa, P. 1886. ‘Un recettario del secolo XI esistente nel-
Plutarch. Moralia. l Archivio Capitolare d’Ivrea’, Memorie della Reale Accademia delle
Pollitt,J.J.1974. The Ancient View of Greek Art. Scienze di Torino, 2* ser. XX
XVII.
Pseudo-Aristotle, De Coloribus. Gregory the Great, 1971. Homiliae in Hiezechihelem Prophetam, ed.
—. De Mundo. M. Adriaen (Corpus Christianorum Series Latina, CXLII).
Ptolemy. 1956. Optique, ed. A. Lejeune. Grosseteste, Robert. 1912. De Iride seu de Iride et Speculo, ed. L. Bauer
Seneca. Epistolae, LX XVI. (Beitriige zur Geschichte der Philosophie des Mittelalters, LX).
—. Naturai Questions, I, iv, 7. —. 1982. Hexaemeron, ed. R. Dales and S. Gieben.
Solinus, 1958. Collectanea Rerum Memorabilium, ed. T.Mommsen, 2nd Haskins, C. H. 1960. ‘A list of text-books from the close of the 12th
ed. century’ in Studies in the History ofMedieval Science, 2nd ed.
Statius, Silvae, I, 5. Hunt, T. 1995. ‘Early Anglo-Norman receipts for colours’, Journal of
Stobaeus, Johannes. 1792. Eclogarum Physicarum et Ethicarum Libri the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes, LVI.
Duo, I. Isidore ofSeville, Etymologiae.
Tertullian, 1961. De Spectaculis, ed. E. Castorina. Lehman-Brockhaus, O. 1938. Schriftquellen zur Kunst-geschichte des 11
Theophrastus. 1917. De Sensu, in G. M. Stratton, Theophrastus and und 12 Jahrhunderts
fiirDeutschland, Lothringen und Italien, 1.
the Greek Physiological Psychology before Aristotle. Maier, C. and R. Suntrup, 1987. ‘Zum Lexikon der Farbenbedeu-
Vitruvius Pollio. Ten Books on Architecture. tungen im Mittelalter. Einfiihrung zu Gegenstand und Methode,
sowie Probeartikel aus dem Farbenbereich “Rot”, Friihmittelal-
terlichen Studien, XX1.
The Middle Ages Mango, C. 1972. The Art of the Byzantine Empire,
Abrahams, H. J. 1979. ‘A 13th-Century Portuguese Work on MS Marbode of Rennes. 1977. De Lapidibus, ed. B. Riddle.
Illumination’, Ambix, XXVI. Menzel, W. 1842. ‘Die Mythen des Regenbogens’ in Mythologischen
Albertus Magnus, 1967. The Book ofMinerals, trans. D. Wyckoff. Forschungen und Sammlungen.
Alessandri, L. and F. Penacchi, 1914. ‘I piu antichi inventari della Merrifield, M. (ed.) 1967. Original Treatises on the Arts of Painting.
Sacristia del Sacro Convento di Assisi (1338-1433), Archivum Mesarites, N. 1957. The Description ofthe Church of the Holy Apostles
Franciscanum Historicum, VU. at Constantinople, ed. and trans. G. Downey (Transactions of the
307
SELECT BIBLIOGRAPHY
American Philosophical Society, NS, 47/6). Bentley, G. E. Jr. 1969. Blake Records.
1863. De Naturis Rerum, eds ., Berkeley, G. 1709. An Essay Towards a New Theory of Vision.
Nequam (Neckham), Alexander.
Wright. Bertonio, Ludovico. 1956. Vocabulario de la Lengua Aymara.
Biens, C. P. (1636) 1982. ‘De Teecken-Const, een 17de eeuws
—. 1991. De Nominibus Utensilium in T. Hunt, Teaching and Learning
Latin in 13th Century England, 1. Nederlands traktaatje’, ed. E. A. de Klerk, Oud Holland, XCVI.
Birch, T. 1757. The History of the Royal Society of London, III.
Ockham, William of, 1957. Philosophical Writings, ed. P. Boehner.
Pecham, J. 1970. Perspectiva Communis, ed. and trans. D. C. Lind- Biringuccio, Vannoccio (1540). 1977. De la Pirotechnia, ed, A
berg in John Pecham and the Science of Optics. ' Carrugo.
Petzold, A. 1995. ‘De coloribus et mixtionibus: the earliest MSS ofa Blake, William. 1956. Poetry and Prose, ed. G. Keynes.
Romanesque illuminators’ handbook’ in L. Brownrigg (ed.), Boyle, Robert (1664). 1964. Experiments & Considerations touching
Making the Medieval Book. Colours, ed. R. B. Hall.
Photius. 1958. Homilies, ed. C. Mango. Cappivacius, Hieronymus. 1603. Tractatus de Urinis in Opera Omnia.
—. 1960. La Bibliotheque, ed. R. Henry, II. Cardano, Gerolamo, 1554. De Subtilitate Libri XXI.
Pseudo-Dionysius. 1943. Oeuvres Completes, ed. M. de Gandillac. —. 1570. Opus Novum de Proportionibus.
—. 1958. Hierarchie Céleste, ed. R. Rocques. —. 1663. De Gemmis et Coloribus; De Rerum Varietate, in Opera , YALA TLL
Rabanus Maurus, De Universo, XXI1, xxi (Migne, Patrologia Latina, —. 1930. The Book of My Life, trans.J.Stoner.
CXI, col. $79). Castel, Louis-Bertrand, 1737. ‘J. C. Le Blon, “Coloritto”’, Mémoires
Romano, C. G, 1996. I Colori e le Arti dei Romani e la Compilazione de Trévoux, August 1737.
Pseudo-Eracliana. Cellini, Benvenuto. 1968. Del’ Oreficeria, in Opere, ed. P. F. Maier.
Rose, V. 1875. ‘Aristotelis de Lapidibus und Arnoldus Saxo’, Zeitschrift Cobo, B. 1956. Historia del Nuevo Mundo, in Obras, ed. P. F. Mateos, II.
fiir deutsches Altertum, 18, N.F.6. Cortés, Hernan. 1986. Letters from Mexico, ed. and trans. A. Pagden.
Schlosser,J.von. 1896. Quellenbuch zur Kunstgeschichte des abendlandis- Courtauld Institute of Art. Newspaper Cuttings on the Fine Arts.
chen Mittelalters. Cropper, E. (ed.) 1984. The Ideal of Painting. Pietro Testa’s Diisseldorf
Silva, R. 1978. ‘Chimica tecnica e formole dei colori nel manoscritto Notebook.
lucchese 1939 del secolo XIV’, Critica d’Arte, XLII, facs. 160-2. Darwin, R. W. 1974. ‘On the ocular spectra of light and colours’
Silvestre, H. 1954. ‘Le MS Bruxellensis 10147-58 et son Com- (1786) in E. Darwin, Zoonomia (1794-6), I.
pendium artis picturae’, Bulletin de la Commission Royale Descartes, René. 1987. Discours sur la Méthode, ed. J.-R. Armogathe
d’ Histoire, CXIX. et al.
Suidae Lexicon. 1935. ed. A. Adler. [Digby, Sir Kenelm] 1658. Two Treatises, in the One of Which, the
Theodoric of Freiberg. 1914. De Inide et Radialibus Impressionibus, ed. Nature ofBodies... is Looked Into. 2nd ed.
Wiirschmidt (Beitrage zur Geschichte der Philosophie des Mittelalters, Du Fresnoy, C. A. 1852. The Art of Painting, trans. W. Mason in H.
XII). W. Beechey (ed.), The Literary Works of Sir Joshua Reynolds, I.
—. 1959. De Coloribus, in W. A. Wallace, The Scientific Methodology Eastlake, C. L. 1960. Materialsfora History of Oil Painting, 1.
of Theodoric of Freiberg. Euler, L. 1746. Nova Theoria Lucis et Colorum.
Theophilus. 1963. On Divers Arts, trans.J. G. Hawthorne and C. S. Even, E. van. 1898. ‘Le contrat pour l’éxécution du triptique de
Smith. Thierry Bouts de la Collégiale Saint-Pierre 4 Louvain (1464)’,
—. 1986. De Diversis Artibus, ed. C. R. Dodwell, 2nd ed. Bulletin de l’Académie des Sciences, des Lettres et des Beaux-Arts de
Thomas of Cantimpré. 1973. Liber de Natura Rerum, ed. H. Boese. Belgique, 2° ser., XXXV.
Thorndyke, L. 1959. ‘Medieval texts on colors’, Ambix, VIL. Farington, J. 1978-1984. Diary, ed. K. Garlick, A. Macintyre, K.
—. 1960. ‘Other texts on colors’, Ambix, VIII. Cave:
Tolaini, F. 1996. “Proposte per una metodologia di analisi di un Filarete, A. 1965. Treatise on Architecture, trans.J. R Spencer.
ricettario di colori medievali’ in Istituto Storico Lucchese, I/ Fiorilli, C, 1920. ‘I dipintori a Firenze nell’Arte dei Medici, Speciali
Colore nel Medioevo: Arte, Simbolo, Tecnica. e Merciai’, Archivio Storico Italiano, LXXVULI, ii.
Tosatti Soldano, B. 1978. Miniatura e Vetrate Senesi del Secolo XIII. Forsius, S. A. 1952. Physica, ed.J.Nordstrém, Uppsala Universitets
—. 1991. II Manoscritto Veneziano. Arsskrift, X.
Urso of Salerno. 1959, De Coloribus, ed. L. Thorndyke, Ambix, VII. Gautier d’Agoty, J. 1749. Chroagenesis, ou Génération des Couleurs,
—. 1976. De Commixtionibus Elementorum Libellus. ed. W. Stiirner. contre le Systéme de Newton.
Van Acker, L. (ed.) 1972. Petrus Pictoris Carmina nec non Petri de Ghiberti, Lorenzo, 1947. I Commentari, ed. O. Morisani.
Sancto Audemaro Librum de Coloribus Faciendis (Corpus Chris- —. 1988. K. Bergdolt, Der dritte Kommentar Lorenzo Ghibertis: Natur-
tianorum Continuatio Medievalis, XXV). wissenschaften und Medezin in der Kunsttheorie der Frithrenaissance,
Vieillard,J. 1963. Le Guide du Pélerin de Saint-Jacques de Compostelle, Glasser, H. 1977. Artists’ Contracts in the Early Renaissance.
3rd ed. Harris, Moses. ¢. 1776. The Natural System ofColours.
Witelo (1572). 1972. Perspectiva in F. Risner (ed.) Opticae Thesaurus Hermens, E. 1995. ‘A 17th-century Italian treatise on miniature
painting and its author(s)’ in A.Wallert, E. Hermens, M. Peek
(eds), Historical Painting Techniques, Materials and Studio Practice.
The Fifteenth to Eighteenth Centuries Hire, P. de la. 1685. Dissertations sur les différens Accidens de la Vue.
Hofmann, W. J. 1971. Uber Diirers Farbe.
Adams, G. 1799. Lectures on Natural and Experimental Philosophy. 2nd Holguin, D. Gonzales. 1952. Vocabulario de la Lengua General de Todo
ed. el Peru.
Alberti, L. B, 1960-1973. Opere Volgari, ed. C. Grayson, I, II. Hiibner, J. 1727. Curieuses Natur- Kunst- Berg- Gewerck und Hand-
—. 1966. De Re Aedificatoria, ed. G. Orlandi and P. Portoghesi. lungs-Lexicon.
[Anon.] 1858. Sul Modo di Tagliare ed Applicare il Musaico, ed. G. Kant, I. 1952. Critique ofJudgement, trans.J.C. Meredith.
Reali. Kepler,J.1858. Opera Omnia, ed. C. Frisch, I.
Antonio da Pisa.1976. Il Trattato di Antonio da Pisa sulla Fabbricazione Le Blon, J. C. (1725). 1985. Coloritto; or the Harmony of Colouring in
delle Vetrate Artistiche, ed. S. Pezzella. Painting in O. Lilien, Jacob Christophe Le Blon, 1667-1741. Inventor
Bardwell, T. 1756. The Practice of Painting Made Easy. of Three- and Four-Colour Printing.
Barry,J.1809. The Works ofJames Barry. Leonardo da Vinci. 1988. Leonardo on Painting. An Anthology of
Baxandall, M. 1971. Giotto and the Orators. Writings by Leonardo da Vinci with a Selection of Documents relating
Bellori, G. P. 1976. Le Vite, ed. E. Borea. to his Career as an Artist, ed. M. Kemp and M, Walker.
308
SELECT BIBLIOGRAPHY
Lersch, T. 1984. ‘Von der Entomologie zur Kunsttheorie’, De Arte Traversari, Ambrogio. 1968. Latinae Epistolae, ed. P. Cannetus and
et Libris: Festschrift Erasmus, 1934-1984. L. Mehus, 2nd ed.
Locke, J. 1700. An Essay on Human Understanding, 4th ed. Trutfetter, Jodocus. 1517. Philosophie Naturalis Summa.
Malone, E. (ed). 1797. The Works of SirJoshua Reynolds (2nd ed. 1798). Turnbull, G. 1740. A Treatise on Ancient Painting.
Mancini, G. 1956. Considerazioni sulla Pittura, ed. G. Marucchi. Vandamme, E. 1974. ‘Een 16e-eeuws zuid-nederlands recepten
Mander, K. van. 1973. Den Grondt der Edel Vry Schilder-Const, ed. boek’, Jaarboek van het Koninklijk Museum voor Schone Kunsten
and trans. H. Miedema. Antwerpen. :
Manzoni, L. 1904. Statuti e Matricole dell’Arte dei Pittori delle Citta di Vasari, G. 1878-1881. Le Vite, ed. G. Milanesi.
Firenze, Perugia, Siena. Veliz, Z. 1986. Artists and Techniques in Golden Age Spain.
Martini, Valerio. 1638. Subtilitatum Proprietatum totius Substantiae Vespasiano da Bisticci. 1963. Renaissance Princes, Popes and Prelates,
quae Occultae Specificaeque sunt Patefacta. ed. M.Gilmore.
Miglio, L. 1977-8. ‘Tra chimica e colori alla meta del Cinquecento; Waller, R. 1686. “A catalogue of simple and mixt colours’, Philosoph-
le ricette del MS 232 della biblioteca della citti di Arezzo’, ical Transactions ofthe Royal Society of London, XVI.
Annali della Scuola Speciale per Archivisti e Bibliotecari dell’ Universita Wallert, A. 1995. ““Libro Secondo di Diversi Colori e Sise da
di Roma, XVII-XVIIL. Mettere a Oro”, a 15th century technical treatise on manuscript
Milanesi, G. 1854. Documenti per la Storia dell’ Arte Senese. illumination’ in A. Wallert, E. Hermens, M. Peek (eds), Histori-
Mocenicus, P. 1581. Universales Institutiones ad Hominum Perfectionum. cal Painting Techniques, Materials and Studio Practice.
Molina, A. de. 1970. Vocabulario en Lengua Castellana y Mexicana, y Werner, A. G. 1774. Von den dusserlichen Kennzeichen der Fossilien.
Mexicana y Castellana. Whitley, W. T. 1928. Artists and their Friends in England.
Muiintz, E. 1888. Les Collections des Médicis au XV° Siecle. —. Notes on Artists (The Whitley Papers), British Museum Depart-
—.and A. L. Frothingham, 1883. II Tesoro della Basilica di S. Pietro. ment ofPrints and Drawings.
Nebrija, A. de. 1973. Vocabulario de Romance en Latin, ed. G. J. Mac- Wildenstein, G. 1960. ‘Jakob Christoffel Le Blon, ou le “secret de
donald. Peindre en gravant’””’, Gazette des Beaux-Arts, LVI.
Neri, A. 1662. The Art ofGlass, trans. C. Merrett.
Newton, Sir Isaac. 1730. Opticks, new ed.
The Nineteenth Century
—. 1959. Correspondence, ed. H. W. Turnbull, I.
—. 1978. Papers and Letters on Natural Philosophy, ed. 1. B. Cohen, 2nd [Anon.] 1842. ‘Cours sur le contraste des couleurs par M. Chevreul’,
ed. Artistes 3° ser: I.
—. 1984. The Optical Papers, ed. A. C. Shapiro, I. [Anon.] 1872. “Painters and the ‘accidents of sight’, The British and
Northcote,J. 1813. Memoirs of Sir Joshua Reynolds. Foreign Medico-Chirurgical Review, 50.
—. 1898. Memorials of an 18th century Painter, ed. S. Gwynn. Badt, K. 1981. Die Farbenlehre Van Goghs, 2nd. ed.
O’Brien, C. 1795. The British Manufacturer’s Companion and Calico Bahr,J.K. 860. Der Dynamische Kreis.
Printer’s Assistant. —. 1863. Vortrage tiber Newtons und Goethes Farbenlehvre.
Opie,J. 1809. Lectures on Painting. Binet, A. 1892, ‘Le probléme de !’Audition Colorée’, Revue des
Ottonelli, G. D. and P. Berrettini, 1973. Trattato della Pittura e Deux Mondes, CXIII.
Scultura: Uso et Abuso Loro, ed. V. Casale. Blanc, C. 1867. Grammaire des Arts du Dessin.
Palencia, Alonso Fernandez de. 1967. Universal Vocabulario en Latin y —. 1876. Les Artistes de Mon Temps. 2nd.ed.
en Romance. Bracquemond, F. 1885. Du Dessin et de la Couleur.
Peacham, H. 1634. The Gentleman’s Excercise, 2nd ed. Broude, N. (ed.) 1978. Seurat in Perspective.
Piles, R. de. 1672. Dialogue sur le Coloris. Briicke, E. 1866. Physiologie der Farben.
Pizarro, Pedro (1571). 1944. Relacién del Descubrimento y Conquista de —. 1878. Principes Scientifiques des Beaux-Arts.
los Reinos del Peru, ed. F. Morales. Burnet,J. 1822. Practical hints on Composition in Painting.
Poggi, G. 1909. Il Duomo di Firenze. Cassagne, A. 1875. Traité d’Aquarelle.
Porta, G. B. della. 1591. Phytognomica. Chevreul, M.-E. 1828. ‘Mémoire sur Pinfluence que deux couleurs
—. 1593. De Refractione Optices. peuvent avoir l’une sur l'autre quand on les voit simultanément’,
Priestley, J. 1772. History and Present State of Discoveries Relating to Mémoires de l’Académie des Sciences, XI.
Vision, Light and Colours. —. 1839. Les Lois du Contraste Simultané des Couleurs (2nd ed. 1889).
Ramée, Pierre de la and Friedrich Reisner, 1606. Opticae Libri —. 1854. The Principles ofHarmony and Contrast of Colours, trans. C.
Quattuor. Martel.
Reisch, Gregor. 1504. Margarita Philosophica. —. 1866. ‘Des arts qui parlent aux yeux’, Journal des Savants.
Rigaud, S. F. D. 1984. Facts and Recollections of the XVII century in —. 1879. ‘Complément des études sur la vision des couleurs’,
a Memoir ofJohn Francis Rigaud, R.A., ed. W. Pressly, Walpole Mémoires de l’Académie des Sciences, XLI.
Society, L. {Chevreul]. 1834. Le Magasin Pittoresque, Il.
Rojas, Fernando de. 1902. Tragicomedia de Calisto y Nemibea. Christophe,J. 1976. ‘Dubois-Pillet’ in J. Bazalgette, Dubois-Pillet, sa
Romero, C. A. (ed.) 1923. ‘Razon y Forma en Theoria de los Tintes Vie et son Oeuvre.
Reales de Quito (1703)’, Inca, I. [Miss Cleaver] 1815. An Account ofaNew Process in Painting by Means
Sahagun, Fray Bernardino de. 1956. Historia General de las Cosas de of Glazed Crayons; with Remarks on its General Correspondence with
Nueva Espafia, ed. A. M. Garibay K.., I. the Peculiarities of the Venetian School. (Brighton. 2nd ed. London
—. 1961. Florentine Codex: General History of the Things of New Spain, 1821).
ed. and trans. A.J.O. Anderson and C. E. Dibble, X, XI. Clerget, C. E. 1844. ‘Lettres sur la théorie des couleurs’, Bulletin de
Scarmilionius, G. A. 1601. De Coloribus. l’Ami des Arts, I.
Schiffermiiller, I. 1771. Versuch eines Farbensystems. Cohn,J. 1894. ‘Experimentelle Untersuchungen iiber die Gefiihls-
Sheldrake, T. 1798 in Transactions of the Society ofArts, XVI. betonung der Farbhelligkeiten und ihre Combinationen’,
Sulzer,J.G. 1792. Allgemeine Theorie der Schonen Kunste. Philosophische Studien, X.
Taylor, Brook. 1719. New Principles of Linear Perspective, 2nd ed. Cooper, T. S. 1890. My Life.
Telesius, B.. 1590. Liber de Coloribus, in Bernardini Telesii Varii Natural- Corot, J.-B.-C. 1946. Corot Raconté par Lui-méme.
ibus. Darwin, Charles. 1985. Correspondence, ed. F. Burkhardt and S.
Toscanelli, Paolo dal Pozzo. 1964. Opera di Prospettiva, in A. Smith, I.
Parronchi, Studi su la Dolce Prospettiva. —. 1990. Marginalia, ed. M. A. di Gregorio.
309
SELECT BIBLIOGRAPHY
Delaborde, H. 1984. Notes et Pensées de J.-A.-D. Ingres. faults of vision on painting’, Notices ofthe Proceedings of the Royal
Institution, V1.
Delf, T. (‘Charles Martel’) 1855. The Principles of Colour in Painting.
Dorra, H. andJ.Rewald, 1959. Seurat. Liidicke, M. A. F. 1800. ‘Beschreibung eines kleinen Schwun-
grades, die Verwandlung der Regenbogen — Farben in Weiss
Dulon, G. and C. Duvivier, 1991. Louis Hayet, 1864-1940, Peintre et
Théoricien du Néo-Impressionisme. darzustellen’, Gilberts Annalen der Physik, V.
—. 1810. ‘Versuche iiber die Mischung prismatischer Farben’,
Fechner, G. T. 1897-1898. Vorschule der Aesthetik, 2nd ed.
Gilberts Annalen der Physik, XXXIV.
—. 1966. Elements of Psychophysics, trans. H. E. Adler.
Fénéon, F. 1970. Ocuvres plus que Completes, ed.J.U. Halperin.
Mérimée,J.F. L. 1981. De la Peinture a Uhuile.
Féré, C. 1887. Sensation et Mouvement.
Millais,J.G. 1899. Life and Letters of SirJ. E. Millais.
Field, G. 1845. Chromatics, 2nd ed. Nochlin, L. 1966. Impressionism and Post-Impressionism, 1874-1904
—. 1841. Chromatography, 2nd ed. (Sources and Documents).
—. 1850, Rudiments ofthe Painter's art; or, a Grammar ofColouring. Novalis (Friedrich von Hardenberg). 1960-75. Schriften, ed. P.
Fletcher, E. 1901. Conversations ofJames Northcote with James Ward. Kluckhohn and R. Samuel.
Forbes, J. D. 1849. ‘Hints towards a classification of colours’, Philo- Oken, L. 1847. Physiophilosophy.
sophical Magazine, 3rd ser. XXXIV. Owen, R. S. 1894. The Life of Richard Owen.
Gage,J. 1969. Colour in Turner: Poetry and Truth. Pearson, K. 1914-30. The Life, Letters and Labours of Francis Galton,
—. 1984. ‘Turner’s annotated books: Goethe’s Theory of Colours’, Il.
Turner Studies, 1V/2. Piron, A. 1865. Delacroix: sa Vie et ses Oeuvres.
Galt, J. 1820. The Life and Studies of Benjamin West. Pissarro, C. 1986-1988. Correspondance, ed. J. Bailly-Herzberg, I,
Galton, F. 1907. Inquiries into Human Faculty and its Development. Hl.
Garnier, C. 1869. A Travers les Arts. Pissarro, L. 1993. The Letters of Lucien to Camille Pissarro, 1883-1903,
Ghil, R. 1978. Traité du Verbe, ed. T. Goruppi. ed. A. Thorold.
Goethe, J. W. von, 1833. Briefivechsel zwischen Goethe und Zelter, ed. Previati, G. 1929. Principi Scientifici del Divisionismo, 2nd. ed.
F. W. Riemer. Purkinje, J. E. 1918. Beobachtungen und Versuche zur Physiologie der
—. 1898. Goethe und die Romantik, ed. C. Schiiddekopf and O. Sinne, II (1825) in Opera Omnia, I.
Walzel (Schriften der Goethe- Gesellschaft, XIII). ‘R’. 1979. ‘Notice surJ.M. W. Turner’, L’ Artiste, XII, 1836, repr.
—. 1951- . Die Schriften zur Natunwissenschaft, ed. D. Kuhn, R. by G. Finley, Burlington Magazine, CXXI.
Matthaei, W. Troll, K. L. Wolf, I, vi; II, vi. Ratliff, F. 1990. Paul Signac and Color in Neo-Impressionism.
—. 1964. Beitrége zur Optik (facs.). Redgrave, R. 1884. A Manual ofColour, with a Catechism.
—. 1970. The Theory of Colours, trans. C. L. Eastlake, intro. D. Judd. Rewald,J. 1949. ‘Extraits du journal inédit de Paul Signac’, Gazette
Goncourt, E. de. 1895. ‘Hokusai: les albums traitant de la peinture et des Beaux-Arts, XXXVI.
du dessin avec ses préfaces’, Gazette des Beaux-Arts, 3° per. XIV, Rey, R. 1931. La Renaissance du Sentiment Classique.
XXXVI. Reynes, G. 1981. ‘Chevreul interviewé par Nadar (1886)’, Gazette
—.andJ. de, Journal. des Beaux-Arts, XCVIII.
Grandi, S. 1806 in Transactions of the Society ofArts, XXIV. Richter, Jean-Paul, 1927. Samtliche Werke, ed. E. Berend, I.
Grivell, F. 1857. Goethe im Recht gegen Newton. Rimbaud, A. 1966. Complete Works, ed. and trans. W. Fowlie.
Grimm, W. and J. 1963. Briefiechsel zwischen Jacob und Wilhelm Rochas, A. de. 1885. “L’Audition colorée’, La Nature, 1885/2.
Grimm, ed. H. Grimm and G. Hinrichs. Rood, O. 1879. Modern Chromatics.
Guéroult, G. 1882. ‘Formes, Couleurs, Mouvements’, Gazette des Runge, P. O. 1940. Philipp Otto Runges Briefwechsel mit Goethe, ed.
Beaux-Arts, 2° per. XXV. H. von Maltzahn (Schriften der Goethe-Gesellschaft, LI).
Guichard, E. 1882. Grammar of Colour. —. 1965. Hinterlassene Schriften, 1.
Guillemin, A. 1874. La Lumiere et les Couleurs. —. 1977. Farben-Kugel, ed. H. Matile.
Hauke, C. de and P. Brame, 1961. Seurat et son Oeuvre. Sand, George. 1896. Impressions et Souvenirs, 2nd ed.
Hay, D. R. 1844. The Laws of Harmonious Colouring adapted to Interior Sandby, W. 1862. History of the Royal Academy ofArts.
Decoration, Manufactures and other Useful Purposes, sth ed. Schadow, W. 1828. ‘Meine Gedanken iiber eine folgerichtige Aus-
Haydon, B. R. 1927. Autobiography, ed. A. P. D. Penrose. bildung des Malers’, Berliner Kunstblatt, 1.
—. 1960- . Diary, ed. W. B. Pope. Schrader, L. 1969. Sinne und Sinnesverkniipfungen: Studien und Materi-
Hayter, C. 1813. An Introduction to Perspective adapted to the Capacities alien zur Vorgeschichte der Syndsthesie.
ofYouth. Signac, P. 1978. De Delacroix au Néo-Impressionisme, ed. F. Cachin,
Helmholtz, H. von. 1852-3. ‘Sur la théorie des couleurs composées’, 2nd ed.
Cosmos, II. —. 1990. See Ratliff.
—. 1871. ‘L’Optique et la peinture’ in E. Briicke, 1878. Silvestre, T. 1926. Les Artistes Francais.
Henry, C. 1885. Introduction a une ésthetique scientifique. Sprengel, C. K. 1894. Das entdeckte Geheimniss der Natur, ed. P.
Herbert, R. et al. 1991. Seurat, 1859-1891. Knuth.
Herder,J.G. 1955. Kalligone, ed. H. Begenau. Steffens, H. 1841. Was Ich Erlebte.
Hering, E. 1878. Zur Lehre vom Lichtsinne. Suarez de Mendoza, F. 1890. L’Audition Colorée. Etude sur les fausses
Hunt, R. 1844. Researches on Light in its Chemical Relations. Sensations Secondaires Physiologiques et Particuliérement sur les Pseudo-
Huysmans,J.K. 1889. ‘Turner et Goya’, Certains. Sensations de Couleurs associés ause Perceptions Objectives des Sons.
Klein, A. B. 1937. Coloured Light: an Art Medium. Sutter, D. 1880. “Les phenomeénes de la vision’, L’Art, XX.
Kuhn, A. 1921. Peter Cornelius und die geistgen Strémungen. seiner Syme, P. 1821. Werner's Nomenclature of Colours, adapted to Zoology,
Zeit. Botany, Chemistry, Mineralogy, Anatomy and-the Arts, 2nd ed.
Landgrebe, D. G. 1834. Ueber die chemischen und physiologischen Thorold, A. 1980, Artists, Writers, Politics: Camille Pissarro and his
Wirkungen des Lichts. Friends. Oxford, Ashmolean Museum.
Larmor, J. (ed.) 1907. Memoir and Scientific Correspondence ofthe late Tornitore, T. 1988. Scambi di Sensi: Preistorie delle Sinestesie.
Sir George Gabriel Stokes, Bt. Twining, H. 1849. The Philosophy ofPainting.
Laugel, A. 1869. L’Optique et les Arts. Van Gogh, Vincent. 1958. Complete Letters.
Lehr, F. H. 1924. Die Bliitezeit romantischer Bildkunst: Franz Pforr, der Véron, E. 1879. Aesthetics.
Meister des Lukasbundes. Vibert, J.-G. 1981. La Science de la Peinture,
Liebreich, R. 1872. “Turner and Mulready — on the effect of certain Wackenroder, W. H. 1967. Werke und Briefe, ed. E. von der Leyen.
310
SELECT BIBLIOGRAPHY
Wundt, W. 1902. Grundziige der physiologischen Psychologie, 5th ed., II. Klee, P. 1973. The Nature of Nature, ed.J.Spiller.
Ziegler,J.1850. Etudes Céramiques. —. 1974. Beitrége zur bildnerische Formlehre, ed.J.Glaesemer.
—. 1852. Traité de la Couleur et de la Lumiere. —. 1976. Schriften, Rezensionen und Aufsitze, ed. C. Geelhaar.
Klyun, I. 1976. “The art of colour’ in J. E. Bowlt (ed. and trans),
The Twentieth Century Russian Art of the Avant-Garde: Theory and Criticism, 1902-1934.
Knight, V. 1988. Patrick Heron.
Albers,J.1963. Interaction of Color. Kupka, F. 1989. La Création dans les Arts Plastiques, ed. E. Abrams.
Allesch, G. J. von. 1925. ‘Die aesthetische Erscheinungsweise der Le Bon, G. 1907. L’ Evolution des Forces.
Farben’, Psychologische Forschung, V1. Leck, B. van der. 1976. ‘The place of modern painting in architec-
Anderson, M. 1979. Colour Healing: Chromotherapy and How it Works. ture’ (1917) in P. Hefting and A. van der Woud (eds), Bart van
Baljeu,J.1974. Theo van Doesburg. der Leck, 1876-1958.
Berenson, B. 1965. Selected Letters, ed. A. K.McComb. Liischer, M. 1949. Psychologie der Farben.
Besant, A. 1896-7. ‘Thought-Forms’, Lucifer, a Theosophical Monthly, —. 1971. The Liischer Colour Test, ed. and trans. I. Scott.
XIX Macke, W. (ed.) 1964. August Macke — Franz Marc Briefwechsel.
—. and C. W. Leadbeater, 1961. Thought-Forms. Maerz, A. and M. R. Paul, 1950. A Dictionary of Color, 2nd ed.
Brass, A. 1906. Untersuchungen iiber das Licht und die Farben, I Teil. Mahling, F. 1926. ‘Das Problem der “audition colorée””’, Archiv fiir
Brown, T. 1958. The Work of Gerrit Rietfeld, Architect. die gesamte Psychologie, LVI.
Chlebnikovy, V. 1972. Werke, trans. P. Urban, II. Malevich, K. 1962. Suprematismus: die gegenstandlose Welt, ed. W.
Cytowic, R. E. 1994. The Man who tasted Shapes. Haftman.
Delaunay, R. 1957. Du Cubisme a l’Art Abstrait, ed. P. Francastel. —. 1969-78. Essays on Art, ed. and trans. T. Andersen.
—.and S. 1978. The New Art of Color, ed. A. Cohen. —. 1981. La Lumiere et la Couleur, ed.J.Marcade.
Doesburg, T. van. 1969. Principles ofNeo-Plastic Art —. 1986. Ecrits, ed. A. Nakov.
—. 1979. Scritti di Arte e di Architettura, ed. S. Polano. Marc, F. 1978. Schriften, ed. K. Lankheit.
—. 1983. Grondbegrippen van de Nieuwe Beeldende Kunst, ed. S. V. —. and W. Kandinsky, 1979. See Kandinsky.
Barbieri, C. Boekrad,J. Leering. Masson, A. 1974. “Conversations avec Matisse’, Critique, XXX.
Downey, E. 1929. Creative Imagination: Studies in the Psychology of Matisse, H. 1972. Ecrits et Propos sur L’Art, ed. D. Fourcade.
Literature. —. 1973. Matisse on Art, ed.J.Flam.
Escholier, R. 1960. Matisse from the Life. —. 1976. ‘Autres Propos’, ed. D. Fourcade, Macula, I.
Fedorov, N. T. 1978. In Casabella, No. 435, April 1978. Mondrian, P. 1986. The New Art— The New Life: The Collected Writ-
Fioni, T. (ed.) 1968. Archivi del Divisionismo. ings, ed. H. Holzmann and M. James.
Fletcher, E. A. 1910. The Law ofthe Rhythmic Breath. —. 1969. See Welsh, R. P. and J. Joosten.
Friedlander, S. 1916. “Nochmals polaritat’, Der Sturm, VI. Moreau-Vauthier, C. 1923. Comment on Peint Aujourd’ hui.
—. 1917-18. “Das prisma und Goethes Farbenlehre’, Der Sturm, Miiller-Freienfels, R. 1907. ‘Zur Theorie der Geftihlstone der Far-
VIL. benempfindungen’, Zeitschyift fiir Psychologie, 46.
Gérome-Maésse, 1907. L’Audition colorée’, Les Tendances Nouvelles. Nicholson, W. 1987. Unknown Colour: Paintings, Letters, Writings.
Gimpel, R. 1963. Journal d’un Collectionneur. Perry, I. C. 1927. ‘Reminiscences of Claude Monet from 1889-
Giraudy, D. 1971. ‘Correspondance Henri Matisse-Charles Camoin’, 1909’, American Magazine of Art, XVII.
Revue de Il’Art, 12. Reichard, G. A., R. Jacobson, E. Werth, 1949. ‘Language and
Hahl-Koch, J. (ed.) 1984. Arnold Schoenberg-Wassily Kandinsky: Synaesthesia’, Word, V.
Letters, Pictures and Documents. Rose, B. (ed.) 1975. Art as Art: the Selected Writings of Ad Reinhardt.
Harms, E. 1963. ‘My association with Kandinsky’, American Artist, Rotzler, W. 1978. Johannes Itten: Werke und Schviften, 2nd ed.
XXVIL. Sacks, O. 1995. ‘The case ofthe colour-blind painter’ in An Anthro-
Heimendahl, E. 1961. Licht und Farbe: Ordnung und Funktion der pologist on Mars.
Farbwelt. Scheffler, K. rgor. ‘Notizen tiber die Farbe’, Dekorative Kunst, IV.
Herzogenrath, W. and P. Liska (eds), 1987. Arthur Segal, 1875-1944. Schmidt, D. 1964. Manifeste Manifeste 1905-33.
Hess, W. 1981. Das Problem der Farbe in den Selbst-Zeugnissen der Schwitters, K. 1973. Das Literarische Werk, 1.
Maler von Cézanne bis Mondrian, 2nd ed. Scott, C. c.1916. The Philosophy ofModernism (And its Connection with
Hofmann, H. 1967. The Search for the Real, 2nd ed. Music)
Huszar, V. 1917. ‘Iets over die Farbenfibel van W. Ostwald’, De Segal, A. and N. Braun, 1925. Lichtprobleme der bildenden Kunst.
Stijl, 1. Sérusier, P. 1950. ABC de la Peinture, 2nd ed.
eee R. 1968. Child Language, Aphasia and Phonological Universals. Stefanescu-Goangi, F. 1912. ‘Experimentelle Untersuchungen zur
—. and M.Halle. 1975. Fundamentals of Language, 2nd ed. Geftihlsbetonung der Farben’, Psychologische Studien, VII.
Kandinsky, W. 1975. Ecrits, ed. P. Sers, IIL. Tschudi, Hugo von. 1912. Gesammelte Schriften zur Neueren Kunst,
—. 1980. Die Gesammelte Schriften, ed. H. Roethel and J. Hahl- ed. E. Schwedeler-Meyer.
Koch. Vantongerloo, G. 1924. L’Art et son Avenir.
—. 1982. Complete Writings on Art, ed. K. Lindsay and P. Vergo. Venzmer, W. 1982. Adolf Hoelzel: Leben und Werk.
—. and F. Marc, 1979. The Blue Rider Almanac, ed. K. Lankheit, 3rd ed. Welsh, R. P. andJ.Joosten, 1969. Two Mondrian Sketchbooks, 1912-
Keller, H. G. andJ. J. R. MacLeod, 1913. “The application of the I4.
physiology of color vision in modern art’, Popular Science Wingler, H. M. 1976. The Bauhaus, 3rd ed.
Monthly, LXXXII. Wittgenstein, L. 1978. Remarks on Colour.
311
List of Illustrations
Frontispiece: The German illuminator complementary colour (after-image) of red. 30-1 Tomaso da Modena, Cardinals Hugh
Brother Rufillus, self-portrait painting the de St Cher and Nicholas de Fréauville, c.
letter ‘R’ from a shell. From a Passionale 14 Paul Klee, Crystal Gradation, 1921. 1352. Frescoes, Chapter House, S. Nicolo,
from Weissenau Abbey, ¢. 1170-1200. Bib- Watercolour on paper mounted on card- Treviso. Photo Orio Frassetto Fotografo,
liotheca Bodmeriana, Geneva, Cod. Bodm. board 24.5 x 31.5 (9% x 12%).Offentliche Treviso.
127. f. 244. Kunstsammlung, Basel. Photo Martin
Buhler (© DACS 1998). 32-3 Willem Key, Portrait of an Illuminator,
1 Johannes Itten, Colour-sphere, 1921. From 1565. Oil on panel. National Museum of
B. Adler (ed.), Utopia - Dokuments der Wirk- 15 King David window, Augsburg Cathe- Fine Arts, Valletta.
lichkeit, Weimar 1921 (O DACS 1998). dral, c. 1135. Photo AKG, London/Erich
Lessing. 34 Painting from a palette, detail of the
2 Rembrandt van Rijn, Self-portrait holding letter ‘P’. From a French Bible of ¢. 1300.
his Palette, Brushes and Maulstick, c. 1663. Oil 16 Jan van Eyck, the Virgin, the Ghent Rheims, Biblio. Municipale MS 40, f. 83v.
on canvas 114 xX 97 (45 x 38). Kenwood Altarpiece, 1432 (detail). Oil on panel 350 x
House, London, courtesy The Trustees of 461 (11°5% x 151%). Cathedral of Saint 35 James Le Palmer, painting the letter “C’.
the Iveagh Bequest. Bavo, Ghent. Photo AKG, London. From Omne Bonum, 14th century. British
Library, London. MS Royal 6E.VI f. 329r.
3 Henri Matisse, The Snail, 1952. Gouache 17 Dieric Bouts, Altarpiece of the Last
on paper 286.4 x 287.9 (112% x 113). Tate Supper, 1464-8. Oil on panel, central panel 36 Brother Rufillus, self-portrait painting
Gallery, London (© Succession H. Matisse/ 182.9 x 152.7 (72 x 60%). Church of St the letter ‘R’ from a shell. From a Passionale
DACS 1998). Pierre, Louvain (Leuven). Photo Stedelijke from Weissenau Abbey, c. 1170-1200. Biblio-
Musea, Leuven. theca Bodmeriana, Geneva, Cod. Bodm.
4 Charles Hayter, ‘Painter’s Compass’. From 127, f. 244.
Hayter, An Introduction to Perspective, London 18 Jean-Francois Millet, The Gleaners, 1857.
1813. Oil on canvas 83.8 x 111.8 (33 x 44). Musée 37 Cast of Antique cornelian carved with
du Louvre, Paris. Apollo and Marsyas, with a setting, first half
5 A. Maerz and M. R. Paul, ‘Blue’. From A of sixteenth century, by Lorenzo Ghiberti.
Dictionary of Color, 3rd ed. New York 1953. 19 Andrej Rublev, The Trinity, 1411. Staatliche Museen, Berlin. Photo BPK.
Tempera on panel 144 x 142 (56% x 55%).
6 Ignaz Schiffermiller, The Bright Colours, Tretyakov Gallery, Moscow. Photo AKG, 38-9 Antique cornelian carved with the
coloured engraving, Schiffermiiler, Versuch London. Rape of the Palladium. Museo Nazionale,
eines Farbensystems (Essay on a System of Naples. Photos DAI, Rome.
Colours), Vienna 1771. 20 Edouard Manet, The Balcony, 1868-9. Oil
on canvas 169 x 125 (66% x 49%). Musée 40 Inca poncho woven with black-and-
7 Patrick Syme, ‘Blues’. From Syme, d’ Orsay, Paris. white chequerboard motif, 1476-1534.
Nomenclature of Colours, Edinburgh 1821. Courtesy of the Museum of Fine Arts,
21 The Transfiguration, mosaic, ¢. 1100. Boston. William Francis Warden Fund.
8 Winifred Nicholson, Colour Chart, 1944, Church of Daphni. Photo Josephine
From Nicholson, Unknown Colour: Paintings, Powell. 41 Aztec cosmic map, Codex Féjérvary Mayer,
Letters and Writings of Winifred Nicholson, p. 1. Courtesy The Board of Trustees of
London 1987 (© Trustees of Winifred 22 Moses receiving the Law, mosaic, ¢. 560, the National Museums and Galleries on
Nicholson). Monastery of St Catherine, Sinai. Merseyside.
9 Winifred Nicholson, Starlight and Lamp- 23-4 Crucifixion scene, mosaic, ¢. 1180. 42 Antonio da Pisa?, after a design by
light, 1937. Oil on canvas 76.2 x 88.9 (30 x Church of Daphni. Lorenzo Ghiberti, St Barnabas window,
35). Tate Gallery, London (© Trustees of 1441, Florence Cathedral.
Winifred Nicholson). 25-6 The Covenant of Noah, mosaic, ¢. 1180-
90. Monreale Cathedral. Photo Alinari. 43 Mixtec mask, inlaid with jadeite and
10, 11 Edouard Manet, A Bar at the Folies- turquoise mosaic. Museo Nazionale
Bergere, 1881-2. Oil on canvas 96 x 130 27-8 Georges Seurat, A Sunday Afternoon Preistorico e Etmografico, Rome. Photo
(37% x §1¥%). The Courtauld Institute Gal- on the Island of La Grande Jatte, 1884-86 Scala.
leries, London. (details of divisionist technique). The Art
Institute of Chicago. Helen Birch Bartlett 44 Inca royal tunic, Late Horizon. Tapestry
12 Aribert, Crucifixion book-cover, 11th Memorial Collection. Weave 91 X 76.5 (35% X 30%). Dumbarton
century. Enamel 42.6 x 33.9 (16% x 13%),
Oaks Research Library and Collections,
Cathedral Treasury, Milan. Photo Scala. 29 Georges Seurat, Les Poseuses, 1886-7. Washington DC.
Oil on canvas 200.6 x 250.8 (79 x 98%). The
13 Red and white discs to illustrate the Barnes Foundation, Merion. 45 Giuseppe Arcimboldo, Earth, c. 1570. Oil
312
LIST OF ILLUSTRATIONS
on panel 70.2 x 48.7 (27% x 19%). Private 61 Sir Isaac Newton, Colours of Thin Plates Kugel). From Runge, Die Farben-Kugel,
collection. (‘Newton’s Rings’). From Newton, Opticks, Hamburg 1810.
Book I, Part ii, London 1704.
46 Claude Boutet, artist’s colour-circle. 80 J. M. W. Turner, Landscape with a River
From Boutet, Traité de la Peinture en Migna- 62 Frantisek Kupka, Newton’s. Wheel, and a Bay in the Distance, c. 1845. Oil on
ture, The Hague 1708. version of Newton’s colour-circle, ¢. 1910. canvas 94 X 124 (37 x 49). Musée du Louvre,
From Kupka, Tvoréni V Umént Vitvarném Paris.
47 Frantisek Kupka, Discs of Newton, 1912. (Creation in the Plastic Arts), Prague 1923 (©
Oil on canvas 100.3 x 73.7 (39% x 29). ADAGP, Paris and DACS, London 1998). 81 J.M. W. Turner, Colour-circle No. 2,
Philadelphia Museum of Art, The Louise c. 1825. Watercolour 54 x 74.3 (214 x
and Walter Arensberg Collection (© 63 William Blake after Michelangelo, Abias, 29%). Tate Gallery, London, The Turner
ADAGBP, Paris and DACS, London 1998). 1770s. Pen and grey ink, grey wash on paper Collection.
24.4 X 174 (9% x 6%). Copyright British
48 William Blake, illustration to Young’s Museum, London. 82 J.M. W. Turner, Rouen Cathedral, c. 1832.
Night Thoughts, VII, 1797. Pen and grey ink Gouache on paper 14 x 19.4 (5% x 7%).
with grey wash and watercolour 42 x 23.2 64 William Blake, Newton, c. 1795. Water- Tate Gallery, London.
(16% x 9%). Copyright British Museum, colour 46 x 60 (18% x 23%). Tate Gallery,
London. London. 83 Claude Monet, Rouen Cathedral, 1892-4.
Oil on canvas 99.7 x 65.7 (39% x 25%). The
49 John Everett Millais, The Blind Girl, 65 Henry Fuseli, Twelfth Night, 1777. Pen Metropolitan Museum of Art, New York.
1856. Oil on canvas 82.6 x 62.2 (32% x and brown ink with grey wash over graphite Bequest of Theodore M. Davis, 1915.
24%). City Museums and Art Gallery, on paper 35.5 X 20.8 (14 x 8). Copyright
Birmingham. British Museum, London. 84 Philipp Otto Runge, The Small ‘Morning’,
1808. Oil on canvas 109 x 88.5 (42% x
50 Theodoric of Freiberg, Refraction-diagram, 66 Giorgio Ghisi after Michelangelo, The 347%). Hamburg, Kunsthalle.
c. 1304, from De Iride (after Wiirschmidt). Persian Sibyl. Engraving, sixteenth century.
56.8 X 43 (22% X17). 85 Franz Pforr, Sulamith and Maria, 1811.
51 Robert Grosseteste, Scutum Fidei, before Oil on wood 34.5 x 32 (13% x 12%). Private
1231. Copyright of the Dean and Chapter 67 Sir Isaac Newton, refraction through a collection.
of Durham. MS A III.12, f. 14v. prism. From Newton, Opticks, Book I, Part
u, London 1704. 86 Franz Marc, Blue Horse I, 1911. Oil on
52 Giovanni Battista della Porta, prismatic canvas TI2 x 84.5 (44 x 33%). Stadtische
diagram. From Della Porta, De Refractione, 68 After George Romney, Newton and the Galerie im Lenbachhau, Munich. Bernhard
1593. Prism, 1803-4. From William Hayley, Life of Koehler-Stiftung.
George Romney, 1809. By permission of the
53 René Descartes, prism-diagram, 1637. Syndics of Cambridge University Library. 87 Franz Marc, The White Dog, 1910-11.
From Descartes, Opera Philosophica, 1656. Oil on canvas 62.5 x 105 (24% x 41%).
By permission of the Syndics of Cambridge 69 James Basire after -William Blake, Stadelscher Museumsverein e V. Frankfurt.
University Library. vignette of The End of the Deluge, 1774.
From Jacob Bryant, A New System...of 88 Wassily Kandinksy, Yellow-Red-Blue, 1925.
54 Thomas Harriot, crystal triangular prism, Ancient Mythology, IU, 1774. Oil on canvas 128 x 210.5 (50% x 82%).
c. 1610. By permission of The Bntish Library, Musée National d’Art Moderne, Paris.
London. Add. MS 6789, f. 148. 70 Benjamin West, Venus Comforting Cupid
(Cupid stung by a Bee), c. 1796-1802. Oil on 89 Arthur Segal, Fisherman’s House on Sylt I,
55 Sir Isaac Newton, Experimentum crucis, canvas 76.8 x 65.7 (304 x 25%). The 1926. Oil on canvas 142.5 X 133 (56xX52%).
1666-72. By permission of the Syndics of Nelson-Atkins Museum of Art, Kansas Musée Petit Palais, Geneva.
Cambridge University Library. MSS Add. City, Missouri (Purchase: Nelson Trust).
4002, f, 128a. 90 Philipp Otto Runge, Ideal and Real
71-5 James Gillray, Titianus Redivivus; or Colours, c. 1809. From Runge, Hinterlassene
56 After Carlo Maratta, The Academy of The Seven Wise-Men consulting the new Venet- Schriften, Hamburg 1840.
Design, engraving 1677/83. Ashmolean ian Oracle, 1797. Etching and watercolour
Museum, Oxford. 54.5 X 41 (21% x 16%). Copyright British gt Friedrich Overbeck, Italia and Germania,
Museum, London. 1828. Oil on canvas 94.4 x 104.7 (337% x
57 After Nicholas Poussin, Self-portrait, 41%). Neue Pinakothek, Munich.
1649. Jean Pesne, engraving, 17th-century. 76 J.M. W. Turner, Shade and Darkness: the
Evening of the Deluge, 1843. Oil on canvas 92 Wassily Kandinsky, Table I. From
58 Sir Isaac Newton, colour-circle. From 78.7 x 78.1 (31 x 30%). Tate Gallery, Kandinsky, On the Spiritual in Art, 1911-12.
Newton, Opticks, Book I, Part 11, London London. (Engl. trans ed. K. Lindsay and P. Vergo,
1704. New York 1982). (© ADAGP, Paris and
77 J.M. W. Turner, Light and Colour (Goethe’s DACS, London 1998).
59 Moses Harris, prismatic circle. From The Theory): the Morning after the Deluge — Moses
Natural System of Colours, c. 1776. T. Phillips, writing the Book of Genesis, 1843. Oil on 93 Horace Vernet, sketch of M.-E. Chevreul,
Lectures on the History and Principles of Paint- canvas 78.7 x 78.7 (31 x 31). Tate Gallery, c. 1850. Bibliotheque de l'Institut de France,
ing, London 1833. London. Paris. Photo Jean-Loup Charmet.
60 Sir Isaac Newton, Spectrum and Musical 78 J. W. von Goethe, frontispiece to Die 94 Horace Vernet, The Battle ofHanau, 1824
Scale, 1670s. From T. Birch, The History of Farbenlehre, Tiibingen 1810. (detail). Oil on canvas 174 x 289.8 (68% x
the Royal Society of London, III, London 113%). National Gallery, London. Repro-
79 Philipp Otto Runge, Colour-Sphere (Farben- duced by courtesy of the Trustees.
1757:
313
LIST OF ILLUSTRATIONS
314
Index
315
INDEX
COLOUR continued green (see also colour-terms: Giftgriin) Constable, John 26, 84, 161, 168, 292 n. 3
patronage and 35 39, 44, 69, 71, 94, 96-7, 106, 242, Constructivism, Russian 49
-perception $4, 97, 227, 261 244, 258-9, 260, 283 n. 24; 10, 11, Conti, Antonio 139
-polarity 35, 96-7, 165, 169, 187, 193, 13, 14, 15, 20, 132. contracts, artists’ 13-14, 42
195, 252, 260; 76-7, 78, 90, 92,125 grey 200, 217, 223, 226, 254, 257-8, Copley, John Singleton 160
politics and 34-5, 216, 246, 299 col. 2n.3 260; 133 Coronation Gospels 73
primary (see also basic, simple) 14, 22, purple (see also colour-terms: purpureus) Corot, Jean-Baptiste-Camille 19
31, 44, 47, 54, 73, 86, 135-6, 138, 15, 69, 72, 108, 283 n. 30 Cortés, Hernan 107
143, 164-7, 175, 212-13, 244-7, 260, red (see also colour-materials: coccinus, Cosway, Richard 160
296-7 n. 24 kermes, minium, siricum, vermilion; Courtauld Institute, the 36
-reproduction. See engraving, photog colour-terms: colorado, escarlata, Couture, Thomas 78
raphy puniceus, rubeus, sinople, vermiculus) Crawford, T. D. 29
-scales 17,19, 27, 71, 97, 129, 214, 258, 1§, 31-2, 34, 69, 71-3, 92-4, 97, Cross, Henri-Edmond 168, 216
PS ry Real I10-12, 172, 242, 246, 260, 280 n. Cubism 260, 302 n.25
‘simple’ and ‘mixed’ (see also primary) 1§2, 283 n. 28, 290 n. 37; 13-15, 46, Cureau de la Chambre, Marin 141
44, 128, 136 84, 129 Curie, Marie and Pierre 236
-solid/-sphere (see also Forsius, Munsell, hair 188, 290 n. 40 Cyriac of Ancona 103
Runge) 17, 30, 46-7, 55, 65, 169, white 30, 34, 212, 246-7, 286 n. 103
258, 297 n. 27; 79 yellow (see also colour-terms: aureus,
spectrum (see also prism, rainbow) 23, coeruleus, flavus) 15, 36, 71, 96, 242, | ee Louis 197
25-6, 112, 123, 126, 132-3, 212, 274. 252; 103 Dahl, Johan Christian Clausen 298 n. 29
227, 236, 244, 271 col. 1 n. 6; 58 cold/cool (see also colours: ‘warm’ and Damasio, A. 21
-spread (Bezold effect) 79, 191 ‘cool’) 22-3, 36, 262, 272 n. 7; 4 Dante Alighieri 25, 150
-symbolism (see also colour: as language; complementary (see also colour-polarity; darkness 195; 22, 76
Virgin Mary) 34, 36-7, 42, 52-3, 70, colours: opponent) 15, 22, 48, 55, 87, active 45-6, 190
73, 109-10, 124, 165, 175, 187, 191, 142-3, 165, 169, 172, 185, 196-7, blue as 41; 12, 21
195, 242, 260, 271 col. I n. 6, 272 n. 199, 212, 217, 224, 244, 254, 260; brown as 41
9, 297 n. 33 13, 61 mystical 30, 73-5, 284 n. 44
-technology (see also alchemy, dyestufts) of flowers 186-7, 227, 207 n. 9 Darwin, Charles 22, 26-7, 31, 265
31, 42, 69 numbers of 25, 122, 132, 136 Darwin, Robert Waring 22
and texture 29 opponent (see also colours: complemen- Dastre, Albert 236
-theory 43-50, 185; passim tary) 29, 242, 258; 125 De Boodt, Anselm 45
-therapy 31, 32, 54, 192, 251-2, 265; 103 ‘warm’ and ‘cool’/‘hot’ and ‘cold’ 22-3, decorative art (see also flat tints, oriental
and translucency 99 36; 262, 272 0. Fig) 6 cultures) 198-9, 257
and transparency 47, 99, 128, 172, 254- COLOUR-TERMS Delacroix, Eugéne 47-8, 78, 196, 199-200,
6, 2907 N. 34, 303 n. 4; 101 alurgus 123 211, 220, 226; 232; 2741. 28:05
values (brightness and darkness) 11, 36, aureus 15 de la Hire, Philippe 185
51-2, 68, 87, 200, 214, 216, 258, azurium (asure) 93 Delaunay, Robert 38-9, 49, 193, 253-57;
260; 81 bloi 30, 92 101, 130
-vision $4, 223, 236, 244-5 brun 40 Delaunay, Sonia 257
COLOUR-MATERIALS coeruleus (caeruleus) 128, 132, 291 nn. 20, Delaval, Edward Hussey 165
(see also dyestuffs) 35, 42, 69, 72, 90, 38 Delf, Thomas 299 col.1 n. 9
92-3,108, 154, 161, 214-15, 220-1, colorado 111-12, 290 n. 41 Della Porta, Giovanni Battista 121, 126 :
228, 250, 300 n. 25, 301 col. 2n 1. Darstellungswert 50 128, 130, 132; 52
atramentum, See incaustum Eigenwert 50 Democritus 72, 85-6
azurite, 13, 14; 17 escarlata 111 Demus, Otto 76-7
coccinus 96, 111 fausse rose 93 De Piles, Roger 45, 134-5
incaustum 92 flavus 96 Derain, André 234-5
indigo 187 fuscus 92 Derrida, Jacques 7-8
kermes 96, 111 Gifigriin 39; 20 Descartes, Renée 46, 121, 128-9, 132, 134;
minium 93, 96 hyacinthus 129 53
siricum 96 pandius 68 De Stijl 49, 244, 258-9
ultramarine 13, 14, 35, 93, 226, 283 n. perse 08, 9-4 Digby, Sir Kenelm 130
33; 16 puniceus (feniceus) 93, 96, 123 Digulleville, Guillaume de 124
vermilion (cinnabar) 93, 94, 110, 290 n. purpura 111, 290 n. 36 Dillis, Georg von 298 n. 29
33; 103, 115 purpureus 94. Diocletian’s Price-Edict 81
woad 94 rubeo (rubeus) 93-4, 96 Dionysius of Fourna 70
COLOURS sinople 30 directions, colours and 109-10
black 30-1, 34, 50, 92, 228-40, 246; 98 ‘solar orange’ 210, 212 disegno 35, 134-5; 56
blue (see also colour-materials: azurite, turquoise 106, 289 n. 8; 43 Dittmann, Lorenz 37-40, 45; 18
ultramarine; colour-terms: azurium, venetus 93 Doesburg, Theo van 49,244, 259
bloi, coeruleus, hyacinthus, perse, vermiculus 94 dress 36, 50-1, 70-1, 188-9, 230-1, 276 n.
venetus; green) 13, 14-16, 25, 30, 34, xanthus 123 73, 279 n. 140; 85, 91, 116
36, 40, 42, 44, 71, 73-4, 75-6, 174, Compositiones Lucenses (Lucca MS) 68, 72, Dronke, Peter 52
186-7, 192-3, 195, 242, 252, 264-5, 285 n. 76 Dubois-Pillet, Albert 223; 113
281 n.169, 283 nn. 33, 34, 284 n. 44, Congrés Internationale de Psychologie Dumezil, Georges 34
295 N. 20; 5, 6, 7, 12, 19, 86 Physiologique 247, 263 Durand-Ruel 231
brown 40 Conrad-Martius, Hedwig 37, 39, 40 Duranty, Edmond 218
gold 15, 34, 71, 79, 89, 128, 283 n. 30 conservation 40, 42, 54 Diirer, Albrecht 45
316
INDEX
dyestuffs 36, 69, 72, 108, 289 nn. 14, 20, Ghisi, Giorgio 144; 66 Husserl, Edmund 37
290 n. 41 Gillray, James 154, 157; 71-5 Huszar, Vilmos 244, 259, 260
Gimpel, René 162 Huysmans,J. K. 162, 218
Giotto’s Navicella 285 n. 66
Dre te. CHARLES LOCK 161 Gladstone, W. E. 11, 12
Eaves, A. Osborne 252 glass, optical (see also prism) 130 lepencron CAESAR 294 n. 7, 295 n.
Eco, Umberto 21-2 glass, stained 38, 40, 44, 69, 98, 101-2, 17
Ecole des Beaux-Arts 214 254-5, 303 M. 4; 15, 42 illumination, manuscript 13, 38, 42, 51, 70,
Edda, Norse 34 Goethe, Johann Wolfgang von 8, 16, 32, 73, 90-4, 107;frontispiece, 34-6, 41
Egremont, Third Earl of 163 36, 46-7, 49, 53, 55, 132, 143, 147, 165, Impressionists, French 162-3, 164, 167
Egypt, Ancient 35 169-76, 186, 194-5, 298 n. 26; 76-7, 78, Incas 107-8; 40, 44
elements, the four 29, 73, 127-8, 292 n. 87, 89 Incorporated Society of Artists 294 n. 4
583 45 Die Farbenlehre/The Theory of Colours Ingres,J.A. D. 47-8, 196, 198-9, 200; 96
El Greco 33 46-7, 185, 187, 189-90, 192-3, 195, inventories $1
Elliot, John 262 245, 249-50, 252, 260, 272 n. 24, iris (stone). See prism, quartz
Empedocles 85-6 279 n. 134, 297 n. 2; 78, 88, 92 Isidore of Seville 72, 122
engraving, coloured 138-9, 144 Gombrich, Sir Ernst 241 Itten, Johannes 16, 49, 50; 1
monochrome 36, 144 Goncoutt brothers 81
Etty, William 153 Goncourt, Edmond de 162, 302 col. 1 n. 5
Euclid 121 Gowing, Lawrence 56 AKOBSON, ROMAN 247, 267-8
Euler, Leonhard 8 Graeco-Roman art 35 antzen, Hans so
Eyck, Jan van 14; 16 Grandi, Sebastian 155, 160 Japanese prints 31, 229-30
Gravell, F 298 n. 27 Jarman, David 8
Gregory of Nyssa 75 jewelery 44, 99-100, 126, 288 n. 16, 289 n.
ee coe, jo Hi J-=1. 226 Grosseteste, Robert 90, 121, 123-4, 287 n. 8; 37-9
Farington, Joseph 154-5, 158, 160; 72 42; 51 Joachim of Flora 70
Fauves 249, 260 Groult, Camille 162 Johannes Scotus Eriugena 104
Fechner, G. T. 12, 191, 227, 247, 257; Grtinewald, Mathias 22, 45 John of Skythopolis 76
263, 267-8, 301 n. 29 Guercino (Francesco Barbieri) 161 John of Trevisa 96-7
Federov, Nikolai Fedorovich 303 n. 32 Judaism 30
Felibien, André 45
feminism 35-6 Glee. EDOUARD 252
Fénéon, Félix 84, 209, 210-12, 214-16, Harriot, Thomas 127, 130, 1323 54 Kee GUSTAV 226, 301 col. I n. 3
218-19, 225, 232-3, 284 n. 59, 300 n. Harris, Moses 137, 165, 174, 243-4; 59; 81 Kaiser, P. 32
21; 118 Haupt, G. 52 Kandinsky, Wassily 16, 32, 49-50, 54-6,
Féré, Claude 31; 136 Hay, David R. 263-4 191-3, 241, 248, 250, 252, 254, 260,
Fermat, Pierre de 123 Haydon, Benjamin Robert 153 266-7; 86, 88, 129
Ficino, Marsilio 104 Hayet, Louis 223-5; 99, 100, 112 On the Spiritual in Art 49, 55-6, 192,
Field, George 153, 155, 160-1, 244, 263-4, Hayley, William 150, 294 n. 24 250, 252, 254, 260, 266; 92, 125
304-5 n. 17; 134 Hayter, Charles 22; 4 Kant, Immanuel 8, 271 col.1 n. 6
fire, colour of 22, 25, 126; 6 Hegel, Georg Willhelm Friedrich 190 Katz, David 29, 249-50
flags, colours of35 Helmholtz, Hermann von 48, 185, 212-14, Kemp, Martin 21
flat tints 198, 200 219-20, 221-2, 226, 262, 300 n. 17, 301 Kepler, Johann 45,
Flaxman, John 294 n. 24 N. IT; 99, 106, 109, 110, 111 Key, Willem 92; 32-3
Forbes,J. D. 261 Henry, Charles 48, 213-14, 218, 220, 254, Khlebnikov, Valimir 247, 268
Forsius, Sigfrid 46-7 300 n. 22; 105 Khlesl, Melchior 127
Foucault, Michel 243 “‘Heraclius’ 42 Kiefer, Anselm 190
frames, picture §3-4, 191 heraldry 15, 30, 52-3, 66, 97, 280 n. 155 Kirby-Tally, Mansfield 42
Fraunhofer lines 234 Herbert, Robert L. 213-14, 226 Kircher, Athanasius 47, 141
Fresnel, Agustus 239 Herder, Johann Gottfried 187 Kirchner, Ernst Ludwig 193
Friedlander (-Mynona), S. 194 Hering, Ewald 12, 49, 242, 244, 258, 304 Klee, Paul 16, 30, 38-9, 49-50, 55, 191,
Fuseli, Henry 144, 158; 65, 75 Gol 2 ms 25 257, 200 ne L8O; 14
Hersent, Louis 196 Klyun, Ivan 248
Hetzer, Theodor 37-8, 50 Koloritgeschichte 8, 37-40
Gro, AGNOLO IOI-2 Hilduin, 104 Kupka, Frantisek 142, 257, 303 n. 4; 47, 62
Gaddi, Taddeo 38 Hills, Paul 56, 274 n. 25 Kuschel, R. and T. Monberg, 30
Gainsborough, Thomas 84 Hoelzel, Adolf 49
Galen 85 Hokusai 229
Galton, Francis 261-2, 264-5, 266-7; 135 Homer 12 es J. W. anp K. SEINITZ, 42
Garnier, Charles 78 Homer, William Innes 209-10, 214-15 language 267-8
Gauguin, Paul 47-8 Hooke, Robert 136 LANGUAGES
Gautier Dagoty, Jacques-Fabien 139, 143 Hopp, Gisela 39 Anglo-Norman 90, 92-3
gems. See jewelery Hoppner, John 158 Anglo-Saxon 11
Géricault, Théodore 274 n. 28 Horace 84 Aymara 110-11
Gerstner, Karl 281 n. 170 Hugh of St Cher 91; 30 French, Old 30
Hugh of St Victor 283 n. 24 Greek, Ancient 11-12
Ghiberti, Lorenzo 44, 98-107, 124; 37, 42
Ghil, René 268, 304 col. 2 n. 15 humours, the four 128, 298 n. 18 Hebrew 11
Ghirlandaio, Domenico 38 Humphrey, Nicholas 21 Latin 15, 90, 125
Ghisi, Adamo 144; 63 Humphry, Ozias 158, 294 n. 7 Mexican languages 105-6
317
INDEX
Le Bon, Gustav 235-40; 120, 121, 123 Mesarites, Nicholas 74-5 28; 34
Leenhoff, Léon 232 Metzinger, Jean 254; 131 Passavant, Johanne David 190
Lehmann, Henri 78 Meyer, Heinrich 46 Pastoureau, Michel 52, 66
Leonardo da Vinci 18, 33, 40, 44-5, 104, Michelangelo Buonarotti 144; 63-6 Pecham, John 122, 292 n. 64
121; 124, 127, 220-1 military uniforms 197-8; 94 Pedretti, Carlo. 44
Le Palmer, James 94-6; 35 Millais, John Everett 26; 49 Pelletier, Xavier 302 n. 33
Lévi-Strauss, Claude 241, 243 Millet, Jean Frangoise 37; 18 Peter Lombard $1
Liebermann, Max 190 Milton, John 149-50 Peter of St Omer 93-4
LIGHT Mocenigo, Filippo 128-9, 130, 132-3 Pforr, Franz 188-90; 85
(see also colour: value; lustre)102, 104, Moctezuma 111 phenomenology 8, 37, 249
121, 209-10 Moholy-Nagy, Lazlo 50 Philoponus, Johannes 69
autonomous (Eigenlicht )67 Molina, Fray Alfonso de 106, 112 Philostratus 72
Christ as 70, 73-5, 87; 12 Mondrian, Piet 16, 38, 49, 143, 241, 244- Photius, Patriarch 85, 88
environmental (Standortslicht) 38 §, 259-60;
133 photography 30-1, 36, 236-7, 286 n. 105:
illuminating (Beleuchtungslicht) 67 Monet, Claude 19, 29, 77, 162-4, 168; 83 121
irradiation 221 Monro, Dr Thomas 154 colour 65, 78
metaphysics of 121 Morbelli, Angelo 303 n. 4 Picasso, Pablo 49, 234, 256
sun- 212, 300 n. 17 Moreau, Gustav 162 Pissarro, Camille 78, 215, 218-19, 223-5,
Lind, E. J. 263-5; 102 mosaic 71, 73, 76-89, 106, 261; 21-4, 131 231, 300 n. 49, 302 n. 16; 99
Lindberg, David 121 Moscow Institute of Art Culture 252, 303 Pissarro, Lucien 22;
Line (Hall), Francis 130 e310 Pizarro, Francisco 111
Locke, John 8, 36 Moscow Linguistic Circle 247, 268 PLACES
Lomazzo, Giovanni Paolo 47 Moses 75-6; 22 Alexandria 79
Lombroso, Cesare 265, 267 Miiller-Freienfels, R. 249 Arta 87
Longhi, Roberto 65 Miiller, Johannes 262-3 Asinou (Cyprus), Panagia Phorbiotissa
Lorenzo Monaco 102 Munch, Edvard 192 70
Loutherbourg, P. J. de 158, 160 Munsell, Albert H. 17, 20, 29, 65, 68, 106, Assisi, S. Francesco 38
Liischer, Max 32-3, 54-5 112, 243, 262 Augsburg, Cathedral 69, 15
lustre 72, 79, 100, 255-6, 285 n. 69; 101 Murano glass 130 Bitola (Macedonia) 285 n. 67
museology 53-4 Cajamarca 108, 111
MUSIC 15, 26; 45, $5,°132, 039-41, 192-3; Chartres 40, 76
A ee AUGUST 193-4, 253, 2573 101, 251-2, 263-4, 303 n. 33; 60, 129, 134 Chios, Nea Moni 70, 71
130 Constantinople (see also Istanbul)
Macklin, Thomas 157; 72 Church of the Holy Apostles 74
MacLaury, R. E. 30, 33 INE FRITZ 192 Church of the Virgin of the Pharos
Maerz, A. and M. R. Paul 23; 5 Neo-Impressionists 77, 165, 249, 260 85
‘Magilph’. See megilp Nequam (Neckham), Alexander 90-3, 96 Imperial Palace 85
magnifying lenses 90-2; 31 Neue Psychologische Studien 49 Cuyalapa (Coyolapan) 111
Majestas Domini 70 Newton, Sir Isaac 11, 15, 22, 24-6, 29, 46, Daphni 73, 76-7; 21, 23-4
Malevich, Kasimir 29, 224, 234, 241, 246, $5, 121, 128-9, 132-3, 134-43, 147-52, Delos, House of the Masks 84
301 n. 19, 302 n. 19; 126, 127 169, 172, 190, 263, 271 col.1 n. 6, 298 Florence
Malone, Edmond 156, 158, 160; 74 n. 27; 55, 58, 60, 61,67, 68 Baptistry 98
Maltese, Corrado 44 “Newton’s Rings’ 142; 61 Orsanmichele 98
Manet, Edouard 33, 39, 229-32; 10, 11, 20, Newton, S. M. 36 Sta Croce, Baroncelli Chapel 38
98, 116 Novalis (Friedrich von Hardenberg) 186-7 Sta Maria del Fiore (Cathedral) 98,
Mappae Clavicula 42, 72, 86 Niccoli, Niccold 100, 103-4 101; 42
Maratta, Carlo 135; 56 Niccolo di Piero 102 Sta Maria Novella 38
Marbod of Rennes 72 Nicholas de Fréauville 91; 31 Hosios Loukas 71, 72
Marc, Franz 36, 49, 193-4, 257; 86, 87 Nicholson, Winnifred 27, 49; 8, 9 Istanbul (see also Constantinople)
Marci, Marco 292 n. 65 Northcote, James 16, 158 Haghia Sophia 285 n. 70
Masson, André 302 col. 1 n. 4 Karije Djami 84, 285 nn. 65, 66, 77
Matisse, Henri 9,19, 35, 38-9, $5, 228-40, Laon 255
249; 3, 98, 115, 117-18, 122, 124 Oe WILLIAM of 125 Louvain, St Pierre 14; 17
Matiushin, Mikhail Vasilevich 128 ‘Ockham’s Razor’ 123, 124-5, 136 Lynthrankomi (Cyprus) 285 n. 65
Matteoli 261 oil-painting 14, 42; 17 Milan
Matthai, Rupprecht 36 Oken, Lorenz 297 n. 33 Cathedral Treasury 73; 12
Matvejs, Waldemars 303 n. 33 O’Neale, L. M. 108 S. Lorenzo, Chapel of S. Aquilino
Maund, Barry 8 Opie, John 158, 160 81
Maurolico, Francesco 121 oriental cultures 31, 48, 198-9; 95-6 Mistra, Church of the Hodgetria 76
318
INDEX
Monreale 76 Provis, Thomas 155, 157 Ruskin, John 87, 163, 168
Nerezi (Macedonia) 70 Pseudo-Aristotle Riith, Uwe Max 39
Oaxaca 111 De Audibilibus 284 n, 60 Rzepinska, Maria 37
Palermo, Martorana 76 De Mundo 285 n. 89
Paracas 108 Problems 96-7
Paris Pseudo-Dionysius 30, 75-6, 103-4; 21 rae FrAY BERNARDINO DE 106-7,
Louvre, Salle d’Apollon 200 psychology 31-2, $4, 96-7, 249-60, 262 rie
Musée du Luxembourg (former) 231 experimental 31, 191-92, 252, 253; 105 Sahlins, Marshall 29-30
Opéra 78 Gestalt 195 St Peter 70-1, 73
Palais Bourbon 200 Ptolemy 78-9, 82 Sand, George 199
Palais du Luxembourg 200 Purkinje, Jan-Evangelista 16, 46 Sandby, Paul 155, 158
Saint-Séverin 255 Sandby, William 153
Pergamon 79 Sarto, Andrea del 51
Quito 108 UARTZ 122, 124-5, 130, 132, 290 n, 9; Scarmiglioni, Guido Antonio 45, 127-30,
Ravenna 50, 54 1)
Basilica Ursiana 103 Schadow, Wilhelm 190
S. Apollinare Nuovo 73, 89, 285 nn. Schapiro, Meyer 196, 209, 216
70. gis ie Rave. Maurus 72 Scheffler, Karl 192, 249, 251
Sta Maria in Porta 103 radio-activity 236 Schelling, Freidrich Wilhelm Josef von 176
S. Vitale 77, Tos Rameau, Jean-Philippe 141 Scheper, Lou 305 n. 23
Rome Rameée, Pierre de la (Ramus) 126 Schiffermiiller, Ignaz 23-4, 173-4, 243; 6
Sta Costanza 284-5 n. 65 rainbow 17, 24, 26, 34, 70,-79, 112, 121-3, Schiller, Friedrich 32
S. Lorenzo fuori le Mura 84 125-7, 149-52, 291 n.16, 292 nn. 58, Schmid, F. 42
Sta Maria Maggiore 81, 89, 285 n. 70 63; 25-6, 48, 69 Schoenmaekers,M. H. J. 245, 260
Sta Prassede, Chapel ofS.Zeno 81, Raphael 261 Schoenberg, A. 55, 251
84, 285 n. 71 recipe books (see also technical literature) Schone, Wolfgang 12, 37-8, 53, 67
Vatican, Chapel of John VII 285 n. 13-14, 42-3, 68, 72, 93, 285 n- 76, 285- Schopenhauer, Arnold 190
68 6n. 97 Schwitters, Kurt 185
Capella Paolina 144 Redgrave, Richard 263 Scott, Cyril 267
St Peter’s 261 Redon, Odilon 226 Scriabin, Alexandr 267
Sistine Chapel 35, 144; 63, 65, 66 refraction (see also prism, quartz, rainbow) scriptorium (see also illumination) 90-4.
Salonika, Hagios Georgios 84, 285 n. 66 L533, 200 ms 20: sculpture, Greek 31
Sinai, Monastery ofSt Catherine 70-1, Reinhardt, Ad 232, 302 col. In. § Scutum Fidei 124; 51
73> 75-6; 22 Reisch, Grigor 125 Sedlmayr, Hans 37
Sopoéani 71 Reisner (Risner), Friedrich 126 Segal, Arthur 195; 89
Temixtitlan 107 Rembrandt van Rijn 19, 162; 2 Seneca 125-6
Tivoli, Hadrian’s Villa 284 nn. 63, 64 Renoir, Pierre-Auguste 163, 302 n. 4 Sérusier, Paul 48
Trebizond 86 reproduction: colour 13, 65 Seurat, Georges 9,16, 47, 77-8, 87, 142,
Vence, Chapel of the Rosary 240 monochrome 30-1 200, 209-27, 232, 244, 250, 254, 256,
Venice, S. Marco 71 Reutersward, Patrick 73 284 nn. $9, 60, 299 col. I n. 1; 99
Mascoli Chapel 89 Reynolds, Sir Joshua 84, 134, 153, 160; 75 Bathers at Asniéres 215, 219; 107
Plato 69, 104 Ribera, Jusepe 40 drawings 216, 221, 226, 233, 235; 106,
plein-air painting 190 Rich, Daniel Catton 216 108, 111, 119
Pliny the Elder 35, 43-4, 72, 103, 126 Richter, Jean-Paul 187 Evening, Honfleur 97
Plutarch 86 Rietveld, Gerrit 244 La Grande Jatte 78, 209, 212, 216, 219;
Poincaré, Henri 235 : Rigaud, John Francis 154-5, 158 27-9, 104, 108
Pollaiuolo, Antonio and Piero 40 Rigaud, Stephen 154 Les Poseuses 82; 29
Pollux, Julius 69 Riley. Gales ETO Shakespeare Gallery, Boydell’s 154
POPES Rimbaud, Arthur 247, 263, 304 col. 2 nn. Shearman, John $1, 56, 273 n. 2
Eugene IV 99-100 14, 15 Sheldrake, Timothy 156
Gregory I 70 Romney, George 150; 68 Shiff, Richard 48
Gregory XIII 261 Rood, Ogden 78, 209-10, 212-13, 218, Siebenhihner, Herbert 51
Innocent III 71 222-3, 244, 250, 255-6, 300 n. 21 Signac, Paul 78, 87, 168, 196, 212, 214,
Nicholas V 288 n. 32 Roosen-Runge, Heinz 38, 42 216-19, 223, 226, 251, 284 n. 55, 285 n.
Pius VI 261 Rosenstiehl, Auguste 185 94, 300 nn. 35, 50, 302 n. 16
Srxtus IV 35 Rosselli, Cosimo 35 Signorelli, Luca 40
porphyry 293 n. 9 Rothko, Mark 49 Silvéstre, Théophile 198
Porterfield, William 148 Rubens, Peter Paul 45, 53, 226 Skira 65
Poussin, Nicholas 45, 53, 134; 57 Rublev, Andrej 56; 19 Smirke, Robert 155-6, 158
Pre-Raphaelites (see also Millais) 153. Rudolph II, Emperor 45, 127, 130 Smith, R. 148
Previati, Gaetano 303 n.4 Rufillus, Brother 96; frontispiece, 36 Snow White 245
Priestley, Joseph 147-9 Ruisdael, Jacob van 154 Society of Arts 153, 156
‘primitive’ art 108, 253 Runge, Daniel 173 Solinus 122
‘primary shapes’ 252 Runge, Gustav 175 species 128
printing 92, 138 Runge, Philipp Otto 8, 35-6, 46-7, 169- spectacles 90-2; 30, 32
prism (see also glass: optical; quartz) 15, 76, 186, 303 n. 3; 79, 84, 90 Sprengel, C. K. 186
121-33, 152, 194, 290 N. §, 292 nn. $9, Farben-Kugel, Die/Colour-Sphere, The Stefanescu-Goanga, F. 192-3, 250, 252
46, 195; 79 Steffens, Henrik 169, 173-6, 186-7
63; 52-5, 67-8, 87
Provis, Ann Jemima 153-60, 156; 70-1 Times of Day, The 47, 175, 186, 187; 84 Steiner, Rudolf 250, 303 n. 3
319
INDEX
Stobaios, Johannes 85 Titian 19, 40, §0, 84, 161, 282 n.199, 299 Wagner, Richard 219, 226
Stockholm Papyrus 72 n. 03s 7a Walden, Herwath 194
Stokes, Adrian 56 ‘Titian Shade’ 154, 157 Walt Disney 26
Stothard, Thomas 156, 158 Tomaso da Modena 91; 30- 1 Walter-Karydi, E. 39
Strauss, Ernst 37-8 Transfiguration, The 70, 74, 76; 21 Warburg, Aby 65
Stuck, Franz 191 Traversari, Ambrogio 103 Ward, James 16
Sturm Gallery 194 Tresham, Henry 155-6, 158 watercolour-painting 165, 190
Sturm, Der 194-5 Trevor-Roper, Patrick 54 Webster, J. Carson 215
Suger, Abbot 104 triangle, the 124 Werner, A. G. 26, 187, 297 n. 9
Suidas (Suda) 71 Trinity, colours of the 70, 124, 175, 187, Werth, E. 268
Sulzer,J.G. 174 297 n. 33 West, Benjamin 153, 154, 156, 157, 160;
Suprematism 247; 126-7 Trutfetter, Jodocus 125, 130 70, 72
Sutter, David 221 Tschudi, Hugo von 298 n. 44 Westall, Richard 157-8
symbolism 226, 247, 263, 268 Turner,J.M. W. 19, 33, 47, 53, 153, 158- Wiegers, Jan 277 n. 98
Syme, Patrick 26; 7 60, 162-8; 75, 76, 77, 80-2 Wierzbicka, A. 22
synaesthesia 55, 192, 247, 252, 261-8; 88, Twining, Henry 297 col.2 n.14 Wijnants, Jan 154
135, 136 Wilkie, David 153
William of Auvergne 71
No) ere PAOLO 102 Williams, Solomon 160
Wise 34 BROOK 137-8 Urso of Salerno 42 Wilson, Richard 158
Taylor, Thomas 146 Utitz, Emil 249 Wind, Edgar 66
technical treatises (see also Alberti, Anonymus Winfield, David 42
Bernensis, Antonio da Pisa, Bardwell, Witelo 99, 121, 122-4, 126
Beringuccio, Boutet, Cellini, Cennini, {Vie DER LECK, BART 244, 259 Wittgenstein, Ludwig 8,14, 30
Cleaver, Compositiones Lucenses, Couture, Van de Velde, Henry 190 Wolfflin, Heinrich 36
Dionysius of Fourna, Field, Grandi, Van Dyck, Anthony138, 163 World Color Survey 29
‘Heraclius’, Ibbetson, Kirby-Talley, Le Van Gogh, Vincent 31, 47-8, 211 Wulff, Oskar 50
Begue, Le Blon, Mappae Clavicula, Vantongerloo, Georges 245, 260 Wundt, Wilhelm 12, 191-2, 242-3, 250,
Mérimée, Peter of St Omer, Provis, ‘Varnishing days’ 168 252
recipe books, Roosen-Runge, Sheldrake, Vasari, Giorgio 35, 84 Wiinsch, Christian Ernst 143
Society of Arts, Stockholm Papyrus, Velasquez, Diego 40
Theophilus, Urso of Salerno, Vibert, ‘Venetian Secret’, the 153-61; 70-1
Williams, Winfield) 42, 101, 153-4, Vermeer, Jan 33
214 Vernet, Horace 197, 198; 93, 94 Dates (INVISIBLE RADIATION) 235-6
Tériade, E. 228-9 Veronese, Paolo 226
Testa, Pietro 45 Vespasiano da Bisticci 103
textiles (see also dress, dyestuffs) 51, 68, 97, Vibert, J.-G. 214, 226, 300 n. 28 Yuwe EDWARD 151; 48
107-8, ITI, 196, 200, 257, 279 n. 139, Vienna Genesis 70
Young, Thomas 143, 223, 226; 113
280 n. 154, 289 n. 4, 299 n. 7; 40, 44 Virgin Mary 13, 15, 42, 76, 84, 87; 16, 23-4
Theodoric of Freiberg 121-3, 125, 132; 50 Vitruvius 35, 43
Theophilus 17-18, 43, 81, 86-7
Theophrastus 69, 72, 85 fae MATTEO 45, 134
Theosophy 242, 250, 260, 267 VV ACKENRODER, WILHELM HEINRICH Zelter, K. F. 173
Tieck, Ludwig 174, 186, 187 186 Ziegler, Jules-Claude 48, 199, 227
320
‘
’ ~
" b
-< ,
G
; *
+ )
en) i
Atl $4
. be S : me
ably
w ’
oe ? <
“F vr
a ; ‘
“ : 4 n us ’
we » ’ 7 I *
ye, i» ~ » .
ye a4 ; .
J *
139 3 " : i
) en .
y ’ ‘ ;
‘ Mad an e ' Px
‘ be oh ; n+
'+ = as A
,
s
‘ om F
4 : . >
P i
hn ‘
lite) 4 ae
e
be *
fy
> m 1 <j
John Gage, a graduate of Oxford University and the
Courtauld Institute of Art, has taught at the University
of East Anglia and the Yale Center for British Art. He has
been Paul Mellon Senior Visiting Fellow at the Center
for Advanced Research in the Visual Arts, Washington
D.C., and Head of the Department of History of Art at
Cambridge University, where he is presently Reader in
the History of Western Art. An authority on colour and
on Turner, in 1997 John Gage won the Sikkens Prize,
awarded since 1959 by the Sikkens foundation, ‘to
stimulate social, cultural and scientific developments in
which colour plays a specific part’. John Gage’s most
recent book, Colour and Culture, was winner of the
1994 Mitchell Prize for the History of Art, and was
hailed as ‘a book of extraordinary erudition and beau-
ty’ (Noel Malcolm, Sunday Telegraph), ‘In its wonder-
fully lucid command of detail, as well as in many other
ways... exemplary’ (Richard Wollheim, Times Literary
- Supplement), ‘of enormous scope, learned, lucidly writ
ten... indispensable for any scholar of the history of
Western Art’ (Richard Brettell, Apollo), ‘packed with
outof-the way information which, one readily believes,
took thirty years to assemble... enticing to browse in’
(Sir Ernst Gombrich, The Burlington Magazine).
Printed in Singapore
. 2
ee
| ISBN 0-500-23767-0
—al 9"780500"237670
|