We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 20
The Road to ‘Gender’
Gender history grew out of women’s history. In what follows, it may soem
as if women’s and gendor history are not just different things altogether, but
that one ~ gender ~ in flowing from the other ~ women ~ superseded it
That's only because of the order I am going to impose on the material
Remember in the Introduction, when I said that there isn’t any ‘past” out
there for us to faithfully recover? Well, here’ a perfect example of that: my
choices about what to include in this chapter will eeate a narrative ~ tell a
story ~ that appears seamless and complete. Let me assure you that itis not
Others would choose different characters and different turning pointsthey'd
focus on different subjects;and as a result, they'd tell it differently. My
version tres to be accurate in its representations, but itis made up of how I
see the process unfolding, not necessarily how everyone sees if, and you
need to know that up frat.
‘Women's and gender history do indeed have much in common with one
another, Women’s historians study women as subjects, and have been doing
so for a very long time, at least since the Renaissance.' Gender historians
study the relationship of women to men in the context of various societies,
paying particular attention to the interplay of male and female identities,
Both of these sets of practitioners address subjects and use methods that
overlap with one another, and women’s and gender histories inform one
another as a matter of course, I'S not that gender history is better than
women’s history, or vice versa, although, as you'll also see in the next
chapter, the debates that grow up between them certainly suggested that that
was So. Infact, neither women's nor gender historians could do what we do
these days without the other, Not only are they historically linked, but
without women’s history, no. gender history would have been possible
Gender history depends heavily on women’s history for the material it
analyzesand women’s history could only provide a partial view of women’slives if it did not take gender ~ the interrelationships of male and female —
into account,
‘Hidden from history’: recuperating women for history
The decade of the 1960s spawned the emergence of protests against and
radical challenges to the status quo in the West. In western Europe and the
English-speaking countries, New Left, civil rights, antiwar, and then, when
women found themselves largely unwelcome in these groups, feminist
movements sprang up, issuing calls for dramatic changes in virtually every
realm across their societies. The demands for change found especial
resonance within colleges and universities, formerly the repository of elite
persons and of a pedagogy that perpetuated their values. The influx of non-
elite white men and women and people of color into post-secondary
educational institutions transformed the humanities and social science
disciplines within a short period of time, and ultimately reached the natural
and physical scienc well. History departments, the object of our
concern, felt the impact immediately, as calls for a ‘new social history’ that
would focus on the lives of ordinary people rather than on the exploits of an
elite few led to the development of a vital and burgeoning new sub-field.
Initially it seemed to many women that the new social history would
provide just the place for the lives of women to be explored as well. That
didn’t happen, In fact, many of the radical historians and the histories they
wrote exhibited the same kinds of misogyny and discrimination against
women that earlier generations of historians had practiced.
The women’s liberation movements of the 1970s galvanized an entire
generation of feminist historians across the western world. These brave
souls — you have to imagine how hard it might have been for a lone woman
in a department consisting otherwise entirely of men to challenge their
practices — insisted not only that women should not have to deal with the
often crippling discrimination against them but that the histories being
written should include women in them. Some of the earliest works produced
by these women carried titles like Hidden from History (1973) and
Becoming Visible (1977), testimony to the overriding need to bring women
in the past into the spotlight, to resurrect them from posterity so that they
might serve as role models for the present and future. In Australia, for
example, a number of biographies treating a variety of white womenappeared;in the United States, women who had participated in the
abolitionist, feminist, and social welfare campaigns found their historians.
In Britain, feminist historians influenced by Marxist historiography tended
to focus on the lives of ‘ordinary’ rather than elite women;while in France,
women’s histories drew upon the anthropological traditions of the Annales
school and treated cultural themes that bore on women like sexuality or
motherhood.?
The search for women’s past rested in large part on two related
assumptions: first, that if women were to be regarded as historical actors,
historians would have to regard them as partaking of a collective identity;
and secondly, a conviction that women shared a collective set of
experiences on the basis of which they formed a collective identity.
Women’s historians, feminists themselves in virtually every instance, shared
the underlying belief in much of feminist thinking that women, as both
subject and object of feminism’s program, share common natures, common
needs, common wants, common desires, and a common oppression. Their
histories sought to uncover these aspects of women’s lives, and their earliest
efforts at theorizing tried to explain how that oppression operated.
The outpouring of feminist histories of women stimulated the
establishment of the Berkshire Conference on the History of Women in the
United States, the first meeting of which was held at Douglass College,
Rutgers University, in 1973. Conveners expected maybe a hundred people,
but 300 showed up;another conference was planned for the following year
at Radcliffe College, where over 1000 women participated. Having grown
so large, the conference could not be held every year, so members decided
that it would meet every three years instead, and thus Berkshire conferences
met at Bryn Mawr in 1976, Mount Holyoke in 1978, Vassar in 1981, Smith
in 1984, Wellesley in 1987, Douglass again in 1990, and Vassar again in
1993. With participants from all over the world, men and women alike, now
reaching into the many thousands, the small women’s colleges of the US
east coast could no longer accommodate such crowds, and beginning in
1996, ‘the Berks,’ as it was called, was relocated to larger universities
across the country (North Carolina, California, Connecticut, Minnesota,
Massachusetts).
The successes of the Berkshire Conferences spoke unmistakably of the
immense energies unleashed by women’s historians. The conferences
themselves, along with a number of historical journals dedicated to thestudy of women that emerged in the 1970s and 1980s in Britain, Australia,
and the United States, also served as the sites where some of the most
contentious, exciting, and fruitful debates taking place within women’s
history were aired. One of the earliest of those debates concerned the notion
of ‘patriarchy’ — literally, ‘rule of the father’ — to explain the systems and
means by which men dominate and exploit women. Depending upon their
orientation, historians turned to the theories we laid out in the preceding
chapter, incorporating analyses of kinship systems, capitalism, or
psychoanalysis to advance their arguments.
Much good work came out of these efforts, but patriarchy as a theory
tended to become ahistorical — that is, it reduced to a single cause all of
women’s oppression without allowing for alliances between men and
women, change over time or place, or women’s resistance to it. It became a
monolithic force, this power derived from biological difference, suggesting
that men and women were forever and everywhere locked in antagonism to
one another. Sheila Rowbotham made this argument in a 1979 forum in The
New Statesman, in which she and responders Sally Alexander and Barbara
Taylor debated the relative merits of the concept. Alexander and Taylor
countered that patriarchy need not be viewed as biologically based, and
therefore as an unchanging entity. But more importantly, they insisted, the
concept provided a theoretical framework within which women’s lives
could be examined and analyzed. Patriarchy served as a vital tool for
historians of women, they urged, for ‘history only answers questions which
are put to it.’ Judith Bennett added both strength and nuance to the
argument in favor of patriarchy as ‘feminism’s central theoretical
problematic’ when she observed that the system that oppressed women was
not exclusively that of ‘male oppressor/female victim.’ Men weren’t only
oppressors, women only victims. Rather, she pointed out, ‘women ... have
also colluded in, undermined and survived patriarchy.’>
One aspect of western patriarchal systems, at least, took on enormous
significance in the work of women’s historians over the next 30 years or so
— that of ‘separate spheres’ for men and women. In one of its earliest
iterations, Barbara Welter regarded the private sphere of home and family
for American women as a veritable prison, locking them into a domestic
role that demeaned and devalued them and even made them ill.4 In 1975,
Carroll Smith-Rosenberg published one of her most famous essays, ‘The
Female World of Love and Ritual,’ in which she turned Welter’s position onits head by bringing the most cherished principles of the feminist movement
— ‘the personal is political’ — to bear on her subjects. Rather than seeing the
private sphere of home and family as an entirely negative space and place
for women, Smith-Rosenberg posited it as the site where positive bonds
between women were forged. Sharing the private, personal experiences of
marriage, childbirth, child-rearing, religion, and family life, the women in
the nineteenth-century American home developed a distinctly female
culture from which men were absent. This shared, female-only culture
fostered in women a sense of worth and a belief in themselves; it
empowered them, in other words, rather than oppressed them, as Welter had
claimed.> Subsequent historians expanded upon this new valorization of
women’s distinct culture to explain how and why women ventured out from
their private sphere to engage in social and political reform activities in the
public realm. Nancy Cott’s 1977 The Bonds of Womanhood: Woman’
Sphere in New England, 1780-1835, was followed by Blanche Wiesen
Cook’s ‘Female Support Networks and Political Activism: Lillian Wald,
Crystal Eastman, Emma Goldman’ (1979), Estelle Freeman’s ‘Separatism
as Strategy: Female Institution Building and American Feminism’ (1979);
Nancy Sahli’s ‘Smashing: Women’s Relationships Before the Fall’ (1979),
Mary Ryan’s ‘The Power of Women’s Networks’ (1983), and Kitty Sklar’s
“Hull House in the 1980s: A Community of Women Reformers’ (1985).
The strengths of this approach were many. First, it brought to light the
activities of women in a wide array of both private and public activities that
conventional histories simply ignored. It tied the personal to the political,
showing how public, political activity arose from the experiences of private
life. And it demonstrated just how historical entities like sex and gender
were — that is, that they were not static categories, but changed over time.
But although the models of separate spheres and of a distinct women’s
culture proved long-lasting in women’s history, they were not without their
critics. In the United States in 1980, Ellen DuBois decried the depoliticising
of feminist history, as she saw it, that the emphasis on women’s culture
brought about. Others pointed out that the separate sphere that produced a
distinctly female culture could not be said to apply to the lives of working
women or women of color, or of many groups outside of America.
Another group of women’s historians turned to the practices developed
within the ‘new social history’ to bring women into history. Because social
history emphasized not great men as the movers and shakers of history, butfocused on large societal processes such as the development of capitalism;
because it set its sights on such non-traditional subjects as family
relationships, fertility, demography, and sexuality, and borrowed heavily
from a number of disciplines in order to study them; and because it
legitimated the study of groups not normally found in history books —
peasants, slaves, workers, for example ~ the field looked to be a promising
site for the entry of women onto its terrains. As indeed it was: the studies
done by women’s historians resist counting at this point;suffice it to say that
many, many hundreds of articles and books appeared in which the lives of
women figured prominently.
Gender
But as Joan Scott pointed out in 1983, neither the women’s culture nor the
social history approach had the effect its practitioners had sought — to
rewrite conventional history as it had been practiced in the West for the past
100 years. The first, she argued, while replacing men with women as the
subject of historical study, nonetheless continued to separate women out
from history as traditionally written. The second — adding women to social
history — didn’t change the story that social history told. Social history may
well have rewritten conventional political history, but the addition of
women to it had not made an appreciable difference. ‘Women are a
department of social history,’ Scott pointed out, too integrated within it to
offer productive insights or provocative questions. The solution, she
suggested, for feminist historians who hoped to transform history as a
practice was to incorporate ‘gender’ into their studies, an analytic category
that derived from and expanded upon the abundance of studies already
produced by historians of women.°
Scott was certainly not the first to introduce the concept of gender. In
the 1970s, two historians, Joan Kelly and Natalie Zemon Davis, began to
call for a new approach to women’s history that implied, if they did not
always explicitly utilize, the term. Rather than try to study women in
isolation from men, they argued, women’s historians needed to study them
in relation to men. At the 1975 Berkshire Conference, Davis told her
audience
that we should be i sd in the history of both women and men, that we should not be
working only on the subjected sex any more than an historian of class can focus exclusively on71 of 178
peasants. Our goal is to understand the significance of the sexes, of gender groups in the
historical past. Our goal is to discover the range in sex roles and in sexual symbolism in
different societies and periods, to find out what meaning they had and how they functioned to
maintain the social order or to promote its change.”
She believed that such an approach, which we would identify as a gendered
history, promised to compel whole new ways of thinking about many of the
issues that concerned historians — power, social structure, property,
symbols, and periodization.
Davis’s call resonated with Joan Kelly, who had been thinking along the
same lines already. Her 1976 Signs article, ‘The Social Relations of the
Sexes’, echoed Davis in claiming that ‘the activity, power, and cultural
evaluation of women simply cannot be assessed except in relational terms:
by comparison and contrast with the activity, power, and cultural evaluation
of men, and in relation to the institutions and social developments that
shape the sexual order.’® Davis and Kelly asserted not only that placing
women in relation to men enabled historians to understand women more
comprehensively, but it placed gender — the relations of the sexes — smack
in the center of any study of society. It would no longer be possible, they
were confident, to study society and its many institutions and offshoots
without incorporating gende
By 1985, History Workshop, the British socialist journal established in
1976 as an outlet for scholarship carried out outside of Britain’s
conservative history departments, had arrived at much the same conclusion.
It noted that ‘while rediscovering the worlds that women have inhabited is
important ... it can lead to a ghettoisation of women’s history and to its
presentation in forms which historians working in different fields find easy
to ignore.’ It urged feminists to continue to write women’s histories, but to
include in their works the ‘reconstructing of men as social group and gender
category [sic]’ so that a fuller reading of the historical record might be
possible.”
In one of the most influential treatments utilizing gender, Family
Fortunes: Men and Women of the English Middle Class (1987), Leonore
Davidoff and Catherine Hall sought to demonstrate how gender stood at the
very core of class identity, how it organized and structured middle-class
society in Britain. At the core of their arguments stood the practice of
separate spheres for men and women, which, they claimed, functioned to
provide both an individual identity for men and women and a social identitySusan Kingsley.
for the class they were a part of creating. An arrangement in which men
went out to work while their wives remained at home to maintain a decent,
moral, disciplined, and well-regulated domestic life — these, in the minds of
evangelicals and political economists, provided the building blocks upon
which a stable, hierarchical, deferential social order could be constructed
and sustained in the midst of industrial transformation and political
revolution. And the families that could afford to adopt this system, who
would become the bourgeois middle class of industrial Britain, drew upon
the qualities they saw as inherent in it to distinguish themselves from the
aristocracy above them and the working people below them. Class identity,
thus, was founded upon gender.
‘amily Fortunes took off in the Anglophone world, garnering a broad
audience and deep appreciation for its detailed, comprehensive, and
innovative effort to tie gender to class formation. But it also generated a fair
bit of criticism. In Britain, Amanda Vickery noted that historians’ conflation
of the prescriptions put forth by separate-sphere ideology with the actual
behavior of men and women had grievously distorted the picture. Public
and private realms never fully contained their putative inmates: men
regularly and habitually acted and participated in the private sphere of home
and family; women engaged in civic, political, and social activities that took
them far outside the home. The book also tended to paint the relationships
of men and women within the framework of separate spheres as harmonious
and unproblematic, ignoring the inequalities of power that were inherent in
it. These critiques ultimately took their toll on separate spheres as the
dominant trope of women’s history, though they never fully dislodged it,
especially in Italian and German scholarship, which continues to utilize it
heavily to this day.!°
In 1986, Joan Scott published the article that would inform virtually all
scholarship on gender from that moment on, ‘Gender: A Useful Category of
Historical Analysis.’ I was in the audience the night she gave her first
presentation of the paper, in December 1985 at the American Historical
Association’s Annual Meeting. Not many of us could grasp fully what she
laid out in her talk, but I would guess that nearly all of us knew that
something powerful was taking place. As it turned out, Scott’s article
aroused heated controversy among historians, generating fierce debate
between those who found her use of postmodern theories exciting and fullSusan Kingsley
of possibilities, and those who saw it as a threat to the very existence of
feminist history and even feminism itself.
Scott set out to find a useable theory for historians of gender. Current
theories about gender, she argued, just couldn’t work for historians, for
whether they posited a materialist analysis of patriarchy like Shulamith
Firestone’s, a marrying of Marxism with feminism, an anthropological
explanation like Gayle Rubin’s, or a psychoanalytic theory such as Jacques
Lacan’s, Nancy Chodorow’s, or Carol Gilligan’s, they limited our capacity
to incorporate differences based on race, class, or culture or to trace change
over time. ‘The challenge,’ she pointed out, ‘was to reconcile theory, which
was framed in general or universal terms, and history, which was committed
to the study of contextual specificity and fundamental change.’!!
Those who tried to find an explanation for patriarchy, Scott noted, had
placed gender at the center of their analyses of all social organization, and
in doing so had brought to our attention important inequalities between men
and women. They had not, however, been able to show how inequalities of
gender worked to organize social life or how gender made an impact on
realms of our existence that seemed not to have any relationship with it,
such as politics or war. Moreover, the reliance on physical sexual difference
to put forward these explanations tended to imply a universality and
naturalness of the body that gave it — and therefore gender — an unchanging,
inherent meaning. Gender became inaccessible to history in the sense that it
never changed across cultures or over time. Put another way, history could
only describe the ways different cultures and different societies dealt with
gender inequalities that were fixed by the physical differences of men and
women. Boring.
Within a Marxist tradition, gender, Scott argued, lost its ability to serve
as any kind of analytic category, for it was always subsumed within the
processes of dialectical materialism. That is, economic systems determined
gender relationships and gender roles, and in this way of thinking, although
economic systems change over time (in Marx’s formulation, from
feudalism, to capitalism, to socialism), gender ends up being a result, a
consequence, of those changes.
In taking on psychoanalysis, Scott differentiated between the Anglo-
American embrace of object-relations theory and the French preference for
Lacanian analysis. Object-relations theorists, she cautioned, relied too
literally on the small, concrete interactions of children with their parents to74 of 178
|
produce their explanations for gender identity and to open up possibilities
for change. Limited to the family within the household, object-relations
theories offered no means of tying the concept of gender or the individual
person to larger social, economic, or political structures in which power
resided. In focusing on the asymmetries produced by parent-child
interactions, these theories neglected to discuss the issue of inequalities
between men and women. How, Scott asked, can we account for the
ongoing, seemingly ever-present association of masculinity with power, and
the greater value consistently placed on men than women? How do children
learn that men are powerful and women weak;that men are worth more than
women?
We cannot understand these vital aspects of taking on gender identity,
she asserted, unless we pay attention to the ways various cultures and
societies represent gender; how they use gender to make evident the rules of
social interaction; how they enable us to make meaning out of our
experiences. Here she found Lacan’s interpretation of Freud helpful, though
his thinking, too, was not without its problems for historians. Think back
again to our treatment of Lacan — to his stress on the key role played by
language in the creation of gender identity. Lacan argued that the
unconscious is structured like a language; where Freud saw infants taking
on gender identity through the oedipal conflict, Lacan regarded the process
as occurring when the child left what he called the ‘imaginary’ realm (an
unconscious space of bisexual impulses unmediated by the existence of
language, laws, institutions, or social processes) to enter into the conscious
‘symbolic’ realm of society, structured by gender norms, laws, institutions,
and processes.
Lacan adopted poststructuralists’ ideas about language — by which they
mean systems of meaning, symbolic orders, not merely words, speech, or
writing — to assert that children learn a gender identity on the basis of their
relationship to the phallus. The phallus stands as the metaphor for sexual
difference, and the threat of castration serves as the symbol of the (father’s)
law. The child imagines an identification with masculinity or femininity
based upon his or her relationship to the phallus, and fantasizes a
relationship to the law, or the rules of society, on the same basis. Because
the male and female child have necessarily different relationships with the
phallus, the rules of society are gendered from the start.This sounds like absolute, unchanging sexual difference, i 75 of 178
it? What is different in Lacan’s thinking is that although geuua sucuuy
seems fixed and coherent, it is not. It’s very unstable, in fact, he argued,
here again using poststructuralism to make his case. We need to back up a
little bit in order to understand this, to explain the structuralism that then
becomes poststructuralism, and then relate it to Lacan.
Structuralism!? derives from semiotic analysis, that is, the linguistic
practice of the analysis of signs. It is based on the idea that words in a
language are arbitrary and relative, that there is no innate connection
between a word and the thing to which it refers. The spoken sound ‘cat’ is
simply a sound. We’ve assigned it to a furry, four-legged creature, but we
could just as easily have called it something else — ‘gato,’ for instance.
That’s the arbitrary part of it. The relative part posits that ‘cat’ gets its
meaning relative to the other words in the closed system that is a language.
That is, we assign meaning to ‘cat’ by understanding that it is not ‘bat’ or
‘rat’ or ‘mat.’ Nor is it ‘car’ or ‘cab’ or ‘cap.’ Nor is it ‘cut’ or ‘cot.’ ‘Cat’
takes on meaning only in a closed system, in this case, the English
language, which (like all languages) is full of little segments of sound, able
to be combined in a nearly infinite variety of patterns.
Structural linguists asked themselves how words like ‘cat’ functioned in
our communication. They split up a word like ‘cat’ into two functioning
parts: a signifier and a signified. The spoken word ‘cat’ is the signifier. The
idea that comes into your mind (furry, four-legged, not dog) when you hear
the word is the thing that is signified. When you take these two functions
and put them together, you have the communicative act we call a sign.
Semiotics, then, deals with the meanings that come together in the form of
signifiers and signifieds to form signs. Think of a sign not as a thing, but as
an act or a near-instantaneous moment of process.
Structuralists argue that the meaning of words in a language is purely
arbitrary. That is to say, there is no reason why we call a large, green leafy
thing a ‘tree’ rather than a ‘snarompf.’ Signs only get their meaning relative
to other words in a finite language system, not because there is any direct
correspondence between the word (the signifier) and the thing it stands for
(the signified). The meaning of signs is not intrinsic, in other words, but
relative; signs get their meaning on the basis of their difference from all the
other signs in a language chain. This insight — that meaning is relative to
that which surrounds it in a closed system — powered the semiotic analysesSusan Kingsley...
of the linguist Ferdinand de Saussure, the ideological analyses of the
literary theorist Roland Barthes, and the narrative and social analyses of the
anthropologist Claude Lévi-Strauss, among others. Lévi-Strauss and
Saussure, the two great figures in the history of structuralist analysis, would
go much further. They would argue that language (in the case of Saussure)
and narrative (in the case of Lévi-Strauss) do not represent meaning so
much as they create it. That is, as humans, we only see the world through
the structures we create, namely language and — in Lévi-Strauss’s
adaptation — social behaviors, institutions, and stories, which he tried to see
in linguistic terms. Here, Lévi-Strauss’s suggestion that ‘classificatory
systems’ operate as ‘systems of meaning’ translates into the conviction that
we literally create meaning as we categorize our world. Simple dualisms —
good/bad; old/new; ours/theirs — function as categories that structure the
ways we perceive and understand. Indeed, the simplest categories — like
male and female — are often the most powerful. In the process of parsing
and naming differences and similarities, we create the world — not as a
physical thing, but as a thing capable of being known in certain ways and
not in others. Language — meaning systems — not only represents the world;
it creates it.
Poststructuralists go further, claiming that the meaning created in a sign
is never fixed. It always depends upon the historically particular discourse
or text in which it is present, and, following the thought of Jacques Derrida,
meaning is produced by differentiating the signifier (‘man’) from its binary
opposite (‘woman’). ‘Woman’ is not present in the text necessarily, but it
serves to provide the meaning, through difference, of ‘man.’ But how do we
know what ‘woman’ signifies? That word itself is defined by reference to
another term, that other term defined by yet another. What all this amounts
to is the idea that meaning is fashioned not just by means of difference, but
by means of constant deferral as well, a continual slipping down a chain of
signifiers. Finally, the absent term that defines the signifier ‘man’ —
‘woman’ — is the negative of the signifier, and not of equal value to it. It is
absent and lesser than the concept it defines.
Now back to Lacan. Just as words gain their meaning through
differentiation from their binary opposite, gender identity is formed on the
basis of differentiation and distinction. But just as meaning is constantly
being deferred in language, the appearance of a coherent, fixed gender
identity requires that its opposite be repressed. The bisexual elementsee
77 of 178
existing in Lacan’s pre-symbolic child of the unconscious ‘imaginary’
constantly intrude upon the gendered subject, promising to interrupt the
stability, unity, and coherence that he or she presumably enjoys. Repression
of these unconscious impulses — the effort to present a coherent gender
identity to oneself and to the world — sets up an antagonism between the
masculine and feminine elements of the potentially bisexual subject. This
battle implies that what we regard as masculine or feminine are no more
than constructions we create; moreover, gender identity is constantly under
construction, and therefore, presumably, subject to change.
‘Change,’ that holy grail of the historian’s task. But as Scott pointed out,
the meanings of gender in Lacan’s psychoanalysis are tied to a single
signifier, the phallus. And there are but two possibilities for one’s
relationship to that signifier. In other words, sexual difference seems, once
again, to be tied to one universal element. If that’s so, Scott lamented, the
process of constructing the gendered subject is always the same. No change,
after all: that binary opposition of male and female once again appeared
eternal.
There was nothing for it, Scott determined, but to insist on the
deconstruction of that binary opposition of male/female and the implication
of antagonism that accompanied it. Here she turned to Derrida,
appropriating his poststructuralist theories of language to call for placing
these binaries in their historical context and analyzing how they operated
instead of accepting them as the way things were. That analysis would
involve reversing the binary opposition to reveal the hidden term that
defined the signifier — in our instance ‘masculine’ — and exposing the
hierarchical valuation placed on the two terms. Scott was quick to
acknowledge that feminists had been doing something of the same thing for
many years now; what was different was her embrace of poststructuralism
and postmodernism.
Postmodernism. Isn’t that something we should dread? And what is it,
anyway? In this section, I hope to explain what postmodernism is, and in
doing so, both put to rest the fears critics of it have raised and show how we
can use it effectively to do gender history.
Postmodernism refers to a lot of things, because all kinds and varieties
of postmodernists exist — in art, architecture, literature, anthropology,
politics, philosophy, psychology — you name it, they’re there, and they don’t
necessarily embrace the same ideas.!? But what all practitioners ofes
78 of 1784
postmodernists have in common is a deep skepticism of the belief system
by means of which westerners have ordered our thoughts and our practices
since the time of the Scientific Revolution and the Enlightenment of the
seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. These two momentous movements
ushered in the ‘modern’ against which ‘post’modernists position
themselves.
The ways of doing things we've inherited from the Enlightenment are
so ingrained in us that we don’t even think about them — they provide, quite
simply, the mental framework within which we walk around in the world.
Chief among the principles of the Enlightenment is the conviction that man
(and it’s important to understand that women were not included under this
rubric until the last 50 years or so, as we've seen in the theories laid out in
chapter 1, nor were men of color) possesses a stable, coherent self. This
Enlightenment self enjoys the capacity to reason — he is rational — and by
means of the exercise of his reason, he may know the ‘laws of nature’ that
govern not simply the physical universe but the behavior of human beings
in society as well. Through the process of the scientific methods advanced
by men like Francis Bacon, René Descartes, and Isaac Newton, he may
arrive at truths that hold good for all people and phenomena, that are, in
other words, objective and universal. The knowledge accumulated through
the uncovering of these truths is self-evidently real; it is out there to be
discovered by men using their reasoning faculties; and it can be expressed
through a language that faithfully corresponds to the objects being
articulated. Because man may know these things in this way, he can free
himself from forces that have limited his activities or capacities; that is, he
may become an autonomous actor in the world, free. The ‘laws of nature’
that Enlightenment philosophers appropriated from the scientific revolution
to describe how human societies and polities came to be and explain how
they work demonstrated to all rational thinkers that history has a purpose.
That is, what unfolds over time is not merely the unstructured flow of
random events;instead, history develops according to a driving principle
which seeks the perfectibility of human beings. Because we can know, we
will better ourselves. If we’re white, adult men, that is. Finally, the ways of
thinking put forth by the Scientific Revolution and the Enlightenment have,
ever since, compelled philosophers, scientists, historians, anthropologists,
psychologists, and political scientists to search for and produce theories thatee
79 of 178
purport to explain everything succinctly in a grand sweep: a ‘unified theory
of the “whole,” ’ as one critic put it.'*
Postmodernists challenge these fundamental tenets of Enlightenment
thought. They see the worldview thrown up by the Enlightenment as a story
westerners tell ourselves about the way the world works in order to justify a
certain social, political, and economic ordering. They contend that there is
no world out there just waiting for us to discover it, just as there is no
independent human being who operates freely in and autonomously of that
world. Those are fictions. Rather, human beings are always embedded in
their surroundings, embedded by language, by history, by our social and
economic relations. The knowledge we create cannot be set apart from
conditions of life in which we create it: it is a product not of a pure
discovery of what exists out there entirely independent of us, but of the
kinds of questions we ask, which are themselves a reflection of the
conditions of our lives. And because our lives are so different across time,
geography, ethnicity, race, class, gender, and culture, there can be no
universal truths, only partial ones. Let me say that again: there can be no
universal truths. This is not to say that there is no truth; it is important to
follow up that first scary assertion with the second — that there are partial
truths. Truths that hold good for certain people or phenomena in certain
places at certain times under certain conditions.
Oh, you protest, but what about gravity? That’s got to be a universal
truth. It was, until Einstein found that it wasn’t and put forth his general
theory of relativity. Or when quantum mechanics showed that general
relativity itself couldn’t account for all the forces in the universe. The
discoveries of Newton, Einstein, and hundreds of thousands of other
scientists, humanists, and social scientists have changed our lives in untold
ways, there is no question about that. These specific or partial truths — this
knowledge we possess — are wonderful in and of themselves, but somehow
they are not enough for us. We persist in trying to bring everything and
everybody under a universalizing ‘law’; we don’t seem to be able to tolerate
contradiction, insufficiency, partiality, difference, conflict, ambiguity, or
ambivalence. So we come up with these unified field theories as a way to
compensate for the anxieties such anomalies create in us; we insist on
ordering them in such a way — in linear, binary, hierarchical, holistic, or
teleological fashion — as to compel them to fit.But they don’t. Because they can’t, given that we are creatures who live
not in an abstract world devoid of power, meaning systems, or material
inequalities. We live in specific relations of power with one another, in the
context of meaning systems — culture — and material systems that are
incomplete, messy, and particular.
Postmodernists ask us to acknowledge these specificities;to appreciate
that we do not possess a coherent, stable, ever-reliable ‘self? that operates
above the fray of that messy world;to recognize that the Enlightenment
narrative is a fiction that helps us to organize that messy world, from whose
ensnarements we can never be sprung, however much we insist otherwise.
They ask us to ‘deconstruct’ these fictions in order to show them for what
they are and what they are not.
This is the context within which Joan Scott offered her new theory of
gender. She did not accept the position of some postmodernists that the
discipline of history was just one more of those fictional narratives that
came out of the Enlightenment. But she did argue that we ought to take a
good look at the way we practice history and to be upfront about the
assumptions we make in doing it. She shared the conviction that the search
for a single origin of things — in this case the inequalities between men and
women — was not merely futile but misleading. Rather, she insisted, ‘we
have to conceive of processes so interconnected that they cannot be
disentangled.”!5 And we had to understand how those processes worked if
we were to understand what they produced. The object of history should no
longer be the search for universal, general causation but an explanation of
the meanings attached to any variety of activities, events, identities,
experiences. Explaining meaning should take place at the level of both the
individual and society, and it must incorporate the relationship of one to the
other if an understanding of how gender worked and how change took place
were to be achieved. Lastly, she urged historians to approach the notion of
power in new ways, singling out Michel Foucault’s treatment of it as a
promising possibility.
Foucault argued that power in modern society (by which he meant the
West since the end of the eighteenth century) inheres in a variety of
practices and institutions though which the human subject is constituted.!°
He suggested that the human subject was made through a proliferation of
practices and institutions and techniques that together constitute what he
calls ‘discourse.’ Discourse is a sophisticated term for something as|
81 of 178
seemingly simple as conversation, discussion, and communication. It often
connotes serious speech, writing, or conversation, distinguishing it from the
casual speech of everyday language. In particular, Foucault used the term to
refer to technical speech used by ‘experts’ in the fields of the social and
human sciences — physicians, scientists, prison administrators, educators,
psychiatrists, and the like.
But Foucault used the term ‘discourse’ to mean more than simply
speech. It incorporated the institutions inhabited by such experts and all the
things that they did there. Discourses about crime, madness, or sexuality,
for instance, involved the ways prisons, asylums, and hospitals were
conceptualized and operated.
For Foucault, discourses enabled the exercise of power through the
creation and mobilization of expert knowledge. When a medical doctor at
an asylum created knowledge, that doctor also created power. When a
school headmaster figured out ways to gather statistics about the school’s
students, that headmaster was creating knowledge — and creating a kind of
power that could be put to work upon the students. Surely, you have
experienced such things yourself: automated grading systems, standardized
texts, online paper submission systems, and surveillance cameras in the
American high school, for example. Scientists, educators, physicians,
psychologists, and the institutions within which they worked created
knowledge and used it to ‘normalize’ and thereby police behavior. In doing
so, they created and wielded power.
In this sense, power did not emanate from some central location. Indeed,
Foucault made his argument by drawing a distinction between the old days,
when people thought that power was centralized. It came from God, passed
through the figure of the king, and then spread through a hierarchy of
officials across the land. The ‘new’ kind of power that Foucault hoped to
explain was not like that at all. It was made over and over again, in small
ways, and differently, in every school, prison, hospital, military training
ground, and asylum.
Foucault conceived of power not simply as decentralized; he also saw it
as diffuse. Power in pre-modern western regimes derived from the king’s
authority — that is, the authority of the state — to punish by taking human
life. Power in the modern world operates at the farthest reaches of society
and it does not rely on such a threat as death. Using the metaphor of the
human heart and circulatory system, Foucault described this new power asel
82 of 178
‘capillary’ power, a working of power at the farthest remove from the heart
and the center. Capillary power affects people in the living of their everyday
lives, in the practices they participate in as they go about the business of
living. Moreover, this kind of power operates continuously and in this it is
also different from the pre-modern power of the king. The king’s power was
imposed through an agent of the state, who was usually not around. Rather
than being continuous, then, the king’s power was occasional and
intermittent, exercised when one of his lords or sheriffs dropped by for the
annual visit.
This modern power, you will have observed, is both a lot more difficult
to grasp and to understand — and a lot more effective than that of the poor
king. The king’s power was, in essence, a negative force, denying or
censoring the expressions, needs, wishes, and desires of people. This new
modern kind of power actually produces those expressions, needs, wishes,
and desires. It is a productive power, in other words, rather than repressive
or prohibiting power. Because it operates at so local a level — so diffuse, so
decentralized, so omnipresent and everyday — Foucault’s power can be
thought of as being both broad and intimate. It is as large as the world itself,
and as small as a gesture made by a particular individual on a particular
second of a particular day. It is everywhere in what he referred to as ‘micro-
practices’; that is, the social practices that make up peoples’ everyday lives.
And it is this kind of power — micro, capillary, everyday, working through
discourses — that produces you and me as subjects.
Gendered subjects, which brings us back to Joan Scott. She laid out
what she meant by gender in two separate but interrelated parts. First, she
explained, gender is ‘a constitutive element of social relationships based on
perceived differences between the sexes.’ Secondly, she continued, ‘gender
is a primary way of signifying relationships of power.’ Both these assertions
need to be unpacked, which she proceeded to do. The first part of her
definition comes down to this: we organize our societies and the
relationships we have in them on the basis of what we believe are the
differences between men and women and the valuations we place on them.
We arrive at those beliefs — we create knowledge about sexual difference
in a number of ways. First, our cultures create and utilize symbols in a
variety of often contradictory representations. Scott’s example is the
prevalence of the Eve/Mary symbol in the Christian West to represent
woman. So, is woman Eve or Mary? When, why, how, and in what contextsee
83 of 178
is she one or the other? That’s what historians should ask about the use of
this symbolic representation, Scott contended.
Secondly, these symbols carry with them ‘norms’ for particular kinds of
behavior, and those norms are usually articulated through the establishment
of binary oppositions that insist upon a single meaning for male and female,
masculine and feminine. These norms appear natural and unproblematic in
our cultures when, in fact, as poststructuralists would argue, they depend
upon the repression or negation of other possibilities. How those other
possibilities became obscured, Scott urged, should be the object of
historical inquiry. So, in her example, we shouldn’t accept uncritically the
assumption in a lot of women’s or gender history that separate sphere
ideology appeared in whole cloth in the late eighteenth and early nineteenth
centuries. Rather, we should uncover the contests and conflicts that it
aroused as it came into being. In other words, we should not let those
apparently fixed gender binaries stand without interrogating them — what
was the nature of the debates over ‘ate-sphere ideology? Who engaged
in them? Where did they take place?
The third aspect of Scott’s definition insisted that as we go about
deconstructing those fixed binaries, we must include the political in our
sights. We can’t simply look at the family or the houschold to sce how
gender has worked; we have to broaden our scope to take in such arenas as
the labor market, education, and the polity or state. Yes, indeed, the home
and family still serve as important areas in which gender relationships are
produced, but if we are ever to understand gender in all its depth and
breadth, we must give up the outmoded belief that what takes place in
kinship systems to construct gender is enough. It’s not. What goes on in the
economy and in the state has enormous impact on the fashioning of gender.
And finally, we have to come back to the gendered identity of the
individual subject. As we've seen, psychoanalysis offers important concepts
about how we become gendered subjects, but, Scott observed, ‘if gender
identity is based only and universally on fear of castration, the point of
historical inquiry is denied.’!” Not only that, but many men and women in
real life don’t live up to the gendered and sexual norms prescribed for them,
or don’t always, at any rate, We've got to ask how gender identities are
constructed in particular historical contexts — to place the individuals and
even larger collectivities within the framework of the social, political, and
cultural milieus in which they came up.The four elements traced above offer a way to see how gender
relationships are built, and all of them are necessary to understand that
process. The second part of Scott’s formulation — that ‘gender is a primary
way of signifying relationships of power’ — lets us watch gender operating
in arenas where women themselves are absent. She was quick to admit that
gender is not the only field on which or through which power is represented
and articulated — class and race are obvious others — but in the West at any
rate and in the religious traditions of Judaism, Islam, and Christianity it has
played a vital role. Concepts about and symbols of gender, regarded as
objective, natural, and fixed, structure power;they legitimate differential
distributions of power such as material or cultural resources by providing a
way to represent those differentials as if they were natural and fixed.
Gender becomes an intrinsic part of both the conception and the
establishment of power relationships. Gender and power, in other words, if
we take the two aspects of Scott’s proposition, construct each other. They
do so in many different ways, depending upon the historical context in
which they are operating.
Back to that sine qua non of history, change. How does change take
place within this framework of gender and power? In lots of ways. Wars,
revolutions, famines, economic depressions, epidemics — all of these may
cause such great upheaval in the lives of people and states that the concepts
and representations that cultures have used to depict gender have to be
altered to make sense under a new order. But it’s important to note that
gender representations in these instances may not change — they might be
rendered even more inflexible in order to legitimate a new regime. Whether
they change or not will be determined by a contest over power — over access
to material and other resources — and that’s what historians should
investigate. By bringing gender and power in all its manifestations under
their microscopes, to ask questions about how each works to inform and
establish the other, Scott contended, historians can’t help but transform the
discipline of history, as the practitioners of women’s history had hoped all
along.