analysis2
analysis2
Basic point-set topology; metric spaces; Hölder-Minkowski Inequalities; compactness; series, series of functions, uniform
and pointwise convergence.
Contents
1 Introduction 3
1.1 Metric Spaces . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3
2 Point-Set Topology 7
2.1 Definitions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 7
2.2 Basis . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 9
2.3 Subspaces . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10
2.4 Continuous Functions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11
2.5 Product Spaces . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 12
2.6 Metrizability . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 15
2.7 Compactness, Connectedness . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 16
2.8 Path Components, Connected Components . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 21
2.8.1 Cantor Staircase Function . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 22
3 𝐿 𝑝 Spaces 23
3.1 Review of ℓ 𝑝 Norms . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 23
3.2 ℓ 𝑝 Norms, Hölder-Minkowski Inequalities . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 23
3.3 Complete Metric Spaces, Completeness of ℓ 𝑝 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 27
3.4 Contraction Mapping Theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 29
3.5 Equivalent Notions of Compactness in Metric Spaces . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 32
4 Derivatives 35
4.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 35
4.2 Chain Rule . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 35
4.3 Critical Points . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 36
4.4 Aside: Continued Fractions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 37
4.5 Back To Derivatives . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 38
4.6 L’Hopital’s Rules . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 38
4.7 Taylor’s Theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 39
4.8 Convex Sets . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 40
5 Riemann Integral 40
5.1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 40
5.2 Cauchy Criterion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 41
5.3 Squeeze Theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 42
5.4 Fundamental Theorem of Calculus . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 44
5.5 Upper and Lower Riemann Sums . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 45
5.6 Indefinite Integral . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 45
5.7 Lebesgue Integrability Criterion . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 46
5.8 Integration by Parts . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 47
7 Appendix 55
7.1 Notes from Tutorials . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 55
7.2 Miscellaneous . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 58
7.3 Class Midterm Solutions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 59
8 List of Theorems 63
1 Introduction
2. 𝑑(𝑥, 𝑦) = 0 ⇐⇒ 𝑥 = 𝑦
Remark 1.1. If 1., 3. are satisfied but not 2., 𝑑 can be called a “pseudo-distance”.
1. ||𝑥|| ⩾ 0
2. ||𝑥|| = 0 ⇐⇒ 𝑥 = 0
If 𝑋 is a normed vector space over R, we can define a distance 𝑑 on 𝑋 by 𝑑(𝑥, 𝑦) = ||𝑥 − 𝑦||.
↩→Proposition 1.1
If 𝑋 is a normed vector space over R, a distance 𝑑 on 𝑋 by 𝑑(𝑥, 𝑦) = ||𝑥 − 𝑦|| makes (𝑋 , 𝑑) a metric space.
Proof
Proof.
Proof 1. 𝑑(𝑥, 𝑦) = ||𝑥 − 𝑦|| ⩾ 0
3. 𝑑(𝑥, 𝑦) + 𝑑(𝑦, 𝑧) = ||𝑥 − 𝑦|| + ||𝑦 − 𝑧|| ⩾ ||(𝑥 − 𝑦) + (𝑦 − 𝑧)|| = ||𝑥 − 𝑧|| := 𝑑(𝑥, 𝑧)
■
1
||𝑥|| 𝑝 := (|𝑥1 | 𝑝 + |𝑥2 | 𝑝 + · · · + |𝑥 𝑛 | 𝑝 ) 𝑝 .
𝑝1
||𝑥|| 𝑝 = |𝑥 1 | 𝑝 + |𝑥2 | 𝑝
𝑝 𝑝1
𝑥2
𝑝
= |𝑥1 | 1+
𝑥1
𝑝 𝑝1
𝑥2
= |𝑥1 | 1 +
𝑥1
1
If |𝑥1 | > |𝑥2 |, this goes to |𝑥 1 |. If they are instead equal, then ||𝑥|| 𝑝 = |𝑥 1 | · 2 𝑝 → |𝑥1 | · 1 as well.
Hence, lim𝑝→∞ ||𝑥|| 𝑝 = max{|𝑥1 | , |𝑥2 |}. Thus, the unit ball will approach max{|𝑥1 | , |𝑥2 |} ⩽ 1, that
is, the unit square.
↩→Proposition 1.2
Let 𝑥 ∈ R𝑛 . Then, ||𝑥|| 𝑝 → max{|𝑥1 | , . . . , |𝑥 𝑛 |} as 𝑝 → ∞.
Remark 1.2. This is an extension of the previous example to arbitrary real space; the proof follows nearly identically.
{𝑡 · 𝑥 + (1 − 𝑡) · 𝑦 : 0 ⩽ 𝑡 ⩽ 1}.
(𝑡 · 𝑥 + (1 − 𝑡) · 𝑦) ∈ 𝐴 ∀ 0 ⩽ 𝑡 ⩽ 1.
Remark 1.3. Think of this as saying “a set is convex iff every point on a line segment connected any two points is in
the set”.
↩→ Definition 1.5: ℓ 𝑝
The space ℓ 𝑝 of sequences is defined as
∞
|𝑥 𝑛 | 𝑝 < +∞}
Õ
{𝑥 = (𝑥 1 , 𝑥2 , . . . , 𝑥 𝑛 , . . . ) : ∗.
𝑛=1
𝑝 𝑝1
Then, ∗ defines the ℓ 𝑝 norm on the space of sequences; that is, ||𝑥|| 𝑝 :=
Í∞
𝑛=1 |𝑥 𝑛 | .
. Let 𝑥 𝑛 = 𝑛1 . For which 𝑝 is 𝑥 ∈ ℓ 𝑝 ? We have, raising the norm to the power of 𝑝 for ease:
𝑝
||𝑥|| 𝑝 = |𝑥1 | 𝑝 + |𝑥2 | 𝑝 + · · · + |𝑥 𝑛 | 𝑝 + · · ·
𝑝
𝑝 1
=1 + + · · · < ∞ ⇐⇒ 𝑝 > 1.
2
∫ 𝑏 𝑝1
𝑝
|| 𝑓 || 𝑝 = | 𝑓 (𝑥)| 𝑑𝑥 .
𝑎
Remark 1.4. Triangle inequality for ||𝑥|| 𝑝 or || 𝑓 || 𝑝 is called Minkowski inequality; ||𝑥|| 𝑝 + ||𝑦|| 𝑝 ⩾ ||𝑥 + 𝑦|| 𝑝 . This
will be discussed further.
𝑑(𝐴, 𝐵) := Area(𝐴△𝐵),
where
𝐴△𝐵 : (𝐴 \ 𝐵) ∪ (𝐵 \ 𝐴) = (𝐴 ∪ 𝐵) \ (𝐴 ∩ 𝐵).
More generally, we have that ||2 𝑘 || 2 = 2−𝑘 ; coversely, ||2−𝑘 || = 2 𝑘 . That is, the closer to 0, the
larger the distance, and vice versa, contrary to our notion of Euclidean distance.
↩→Proposition 1.3
||𝑥|| 𝑝 as defined above is a well-defined norm over Q.
2 Point-Set Topology
2.1 Definitions
1. ∅ ∈ 𝜏, 𝑋 ∈ 𝜏
2. Consider {𝐴 𝛼 } 𝛼∈𝐼 where 𝐴 𝛼 an open set for any 𝛼; then, 𝐴 𝛼 ∈ 𝜏, that is, it is also an open set.
Ð
𝛼∈𝐼
In other words, 2.: arbitrary unions of open sets are open, and 3.: finite intersections of open sets are
open.
1.* 𝑋 , ∅ closed;
1 𝑑1 (𝑥, 𝑦)
< < 𝐶.
𝐶 𝑑2 (𝑥, 𝑦)
𝑟
𝐵 𝑑1 (𝑥, ) ⊆ 𝐵 𝑑2 (𝑥, 𝑟) ⊆ 𝐵 𝑑1 (𝑥, 𝐶 · 𝑟).
𝑐
Hence, 𝑑1 , 𝑑2 define the same open/closed sets on 𝑋 thus admitting the same topologies. We write
𝑑1 ≍ 𝑑2 .
𝑥 ∈ Int(𝐴).
𝑥 ∈ Int(𝐴𝐶 ).
𝐴 is closed; 𝐴 is the smallest closed set that contains 𝐴, that is, 𝐴 = 𝐵 where 𝐵 closed and 𝐴 ⊆ 𝐵. We
Ñ
↩→Proposition 2.3
1. 𝐴 is open ⇐⇒ 𝐴 = Int(𝐴)
2. 𝐴 is closed ⇐⇒ 𝐴 = 𝐴
2.2 Basis
↩→Proposition 2.4
Let ℬ be a collection of open sets in 𝑋. Then, ℬ is a basis ⇐⇒
1. ∀ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 , ∃𝑈-open ∈ ℬ s.t. 𝑥 ∈ 𝑈.
1“Requires” proof.
↩→Proposition 2.5
In a metric space, a basis for a topology is a collection of open balls,
Proof We prove via proposition 2.4. Property 1. holds clearly; 𝑥 ∈ 𝐵(𝑥, 𝜀)-open ⊆ ℬ.
Proof
Proof.
For property 2., let 𝑥 ∈ 𝐵(𝑦1 , 𝑟1 ) ∩ 𝐵(𝑦2 , 𝑟2 ), that is, 𝑑(𝑥, 𝑦1 ) < 𝑟1 and 𝑑(𝑥, 𝑦2 ) < 𝑟2 . Let
△≠
𝑑(𝑧, 𝑦1 ) ⩽ 𝑑(𝑧, 𝑥) + 𝑑(𝑥, 𝑦1 ) < 𝛿 + 𝑑(𝑥, 𝑦1 ) ⩽ 𝑟1 − 𝑑(𝑥, 𝑦1 ) + 𝑑(𝑥, 𝑦1 ) = 𝑟1 ,
2.3 Subspaces
↩→ Definition 2.7
Let 𝑋 be a topological space and let 𝑌 ⊆ 𝑋. We define the subspace topology on 𝑌:
Suppose 𝑋 a metric space. Then, 𝑌 is also a metric space, with the same distance.
↩→Proposition 2.7
Let 𝑌 ⊆ 𝑋- a metric space. Then, the metric space topology for (𝑌, 𝑑) is the same as the subspace
topology.
Ø Ø
𝑌∩( 𝐵(𝑥 𝛼 , 𝑟 𝛼 )) = (𝑌 ∩ 𝐵(𝑥 𝛼 , 𝑟 𝛼 ))
𝛼∈𝐼 𝛼∈𝐼
↩→ Lemma 2.1
Let 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑋-open, 𝐵 ⊆ 𝐴; 𝐵-open in subspace topology for 𝐴 ⇐⇒ 𝐵-open in 𝑋.
↩→ Lemma 2.2
𝐴𝑌 = 𝐴𝑋 ∩ 𝑌.
↩→Proposition 2.8
This definition is consistent with the normal 𝜀-𝛿 definition on the real line.
Proof Let 𝑓 : R → R, continuous; that is, ∀ 𝜀 > 0, ∀ 𝑥 ∈ R∃𝛿 > 0 s.t. |𝑥 1 − 𝑥| < 𝛿, then | 𝑓 (𝑥1 ) − 𝑓 (𝑥)| < 𝜀.
Proof
Proof.
Let 𝑉 ⊆ R open. Let 𝑦 ∈ 𝑉. Then, ∃𝜀 : (𝑦 − 𝜀, 𝑦 + 𝜀) ⊆ 𝑉. Let 𝑦 = 𝑓 (𝑥), hence 𝑦 ∈ 𝑓 −1 (𝑉). Now, if
𝑑(𝑥, 𝑥1 ) < 𝛿, we have that 𝑑( 𝑓 (𝑥1 ), 𝑓 (𝑥)) < 𝜀 (by continuity of 𝑓 ), hence 𝑓 (𝑥1 ) ∈ (𝑦 − 𝜀, 𝑦 + 𝜀) ⊆ 𝑉; moreover,
(𝑥 − 𝛿, 𝑥 + 𝛿) ⊆ 𝑓 −1(𝑉), thus 𝑓 −1 (𝑉) is open as required.
The inverse of this proof follows identically. ■
↩→Proposition 2.9
Suppose ℬ forms a basis of topology for 𝑌. Then, 𝑓 : 𝑋 → 𝑌 is continuous if 𝑓 −1 (𝑈) open ∀ 𝑈 ∈ ℬ.
Proof If 𝑈-open set in 𝑌, then ∃𝐼-index set and a collection of open sets {𝐴 𝛼 } 𝛼∈𝐼 , 𝐴 𝛼 ∈ ℬ, s.t. 𝑈 = ∪𝛼∈𝐼 𝐴 𝛼 .
Proof
Proof.
Then, we have
↩→Proposition 2.10
If 𝑓 : 𝑋 → 𝑌 continuous and 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑋, 𝐴 has subspace topology, then 𝑓 | 𝐴 : 𝐴 → 𝑌 is also continuous.2
By the definition of subspace topology, this is an open set and hence 𝑓 | 𝐴 is continuous. ■
(𝑋1 × 𝑋2 × · · · × 𝑋𝑛 ),
and aim to define a product topology; a basis of which consists of cylinder sets.
𝑓𝑗 = 𝜋𝑗 ◦ 𝑓 ; 𝑓 𝑗 = 𝑥 𝑗 (𝑦).
↩→Proposition 2.11
𝑓 : 𝑌 → 𝑋 = 𝑋1 × · · · × 𝑋𝑛 continuous ⇐⇒ 𝑓 𝑗 : 𝑌 → 𝑋 𝑗 continuous.
Proof Its enough to show that ∀ 𝑈 ∈ ℬ-basis for 𝑋-product space, 𝑓 −1 (𝑈)-open in 𝑌. Take 𝑈 = 𝐴1 × · · · 𝐴𝑛 -
Proof
Proof.
open. Then, we claim that
If this holds, then as each 𝑓𝑖 continuous (being a composition of continuous functions) and each 𝐴 𝑖 open in
𝑋𝑖 , then each 𝑓𝑖−1 (𝐴 𝑖 ) open in 𝑌 and hence ★, being the finite intersection of open sets in 𝑌, is itself open in 𝑌.
■
2𝜋
1
∫
𝑓ˆ(𝑛) = 𝑓 (𝑥)𝑒 −𝑖𝑛𝑥 d𝑥
2𝜋 0
2𝜋 2𝜋
1 1
∫ ∫
= 𝑓 (𝑥) cos(𝑛𝑥) d𝑥 − 𝑖 𝑓 (𝑥) sin(𝑛𝑥) d𝑥 .
2𝜋 0 2𝜋 0
Now, let 𝑓 : R → R. Suppose 𝑓 (𝑥) → 0 “fast enough” as |𝑥| → ∞ and 𝑓 continuous. Then, we
can define the Fourier coefficients
∞
1
∫
𝑓ˆ(𝑡) = 𝑓 (𝑥)𝑒 −𝑖𝑡𝑥 d𝑥 ,
2𝜋 −∞
𝑓 ↦→ { 𝑓ˆ(𝑡)} 𝑡∈R .
That is, there exists a finite set 𝐽 = (𝛼1 , . . . , 𝛼 𝑘 ) ⊆ 𝐼, such that we can write 𝐴 = 𝐴𝛼 × 𝑋𝛼
Î Î
𝛼∈𝐽 𝛼∉𝐽
(where 𝐴 𝛼 open in 𝑋𝛼 ).
↩→Proposition 2.12
Given 𝑓 : 𝑌 → 𝑋𝛼 = 𝑋, then (taking 𝑓𝛼 = 𝜋 𝛼 ◦ 𝑓 as before) we have that 𝑓 is continuous in 𝑋 ⇐⇒
Î
𝛼∈𝐼
𝑓𝛼 : 𝑌 → 𝑋𝛼 continuous in 𝑋𝛼 ∀ 𝛼 ∈ 𝐼.
Ù
𝑓 −1 (𝑈) = 𝑓𝛼−1 (𝐴 𝛼 )
𝛼∈𝐽
2.6 Metrizability
↩→Proposition 2.13
Different metrics can define the same topology.
⊛ Example 2.5
1. Different ℓ 𝑝 metrics in R𝑛 (PSET 1)
˜ 𝑑(𝑥, 𝑦)
𝑑(𝑥, 𝑦) :=
𝑑(𝑥, 𝑦) + 1
is also a metric (the first two axioms are trivial), and defines the same topology. Note, moreover,
˜
that 𝑑(𝑥, 𝑦) ⩽ 1 ∀ 𝑥, 𝑦; this distance is bounded, and can often be more convenient to work
with in particular contexts.
↩→ Question 2.1
Suppose (𝑋 𝑘 , 𝑑 𝑘 ) are metric spaces ∀ 𝑘 ⩾ 1. Then, we can define the product topology 𝜏 on
∞
Ö
𝑋 := 𝑋𝑘 .
𝑘=1
Does the product topology 𝜏 come from a metric? That is, is 𝜏 metrizable?
Remark 2.6. There do indeed exist examples of non-metrizable topological spaces; this question is indeed well-founded.
𝑑 𝑘 (𝑥 𝑘 , 𝑦 𝑘 )
𝑑˜ 𝑘 (𝑥 𝑘 , 𝑦 𝑘 ) =
1 + 𝑑 𝑘 (𝑥 𝑘 , 𝑦 𝑘 )
∞ ˜
Õ 𝑑 𝑘 (𝑥 𝑘 , 𝑦 𝑘 )
𝐷(xx, yy) = ,
𝑘=1
2𝑘
1
noting that 𝐷(xx, yy) ⩽ ∞𝑘=1 2 𝑘 = 1 (by our construction, “normalizing” each metric), hence this is a valid,
Í
converging metric (which wouldn’t otherwise be guaranteed if we didn’t normalize the metrics). It remains to
show whether this metric omits the same topology as 𝜏. ■
Ð𝑛
then ∃{𝛼1 , . . . , 𝛼 𝑛 ∈ 𝐼} such that 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑖=1 𝑈 𝛼 𝑖 .
↩→Proposition 2.14
A closed interval [𝑎, 𝑏] is compact.
Proof If3 𝑎 = 𝑏, this is clear. Suppose 𝑎 < 𝑏, and let [𝑎, 𝑏] ⊆ 𝑈 𝑖 =: 𝒰 be an arbitrary cover. Then, we
Ð
Proof
Proof. 𝑖∈𝐼
proceed in the following steps:
1. Claim: Given 𝑥 ∈ [𝑎, 𝑏], 𝑥 ≠ 𝑏, ∃𝑦 ∈ [𝑎, 𝑏] s.t. [𝑥, 𝑦] has a finite subcover.
Let 𝑥 ∈ [𝑎, 𝑏], 𝑥 ≠ 𝑏. Then, ∃𝑈 𝛼 ∈ 𝒰 : 𝑥 ∈ 𝑈 𝛼 . Since 𝑈 𝛼 open, and 𝑥 ≠ 𝑏, we further have that
∃𝑐 ∈ [𝑎, 𝑏] s.t. [𝑥, 𝑐) ⊆ 𝑈 𝛼 .
Now, let 𝑦 ∈ (𝑥, 𝑐); then, the interval [𝑥, 𝑦] ⊆ [𝑥, 𝑐) ⊆ 𝑈 𝛼 , that is, [𝑥, 𝑦] has a finite subcover.
• 𝐶 ≠ ∅; taking 𝑥 = 𝑎 in Step 1. above, we have that ∃𝑦 ∈ [𝑎, 𝑏] such that [𝑎, 𝑦] has a finite step cover,
so this 𝑦 ∈ 𝐶.
• 𝐶 bounded; by construction, ∀ 𝑦 ∈ 𝐶, 𝑎 < 𝑦 ⩽ 𝑐.
Thus, we can validly define 𝑐 := sup 𝐶, noting that 𝑎 < 𝑐 ⩽ 𝑏. Ultimately, we wish to prove that 𝑐 = 𝑏,
completing the proof that [𝑎, 𝑏] has a finite subcover.
3. Claim: 𝑐 ∈ 𝐶.
Let 𝑈𝛽 ∈ 𝒰 : 𝑐 ∈ 𝑈𝛽 . Then, by the openness of 𝑈𝛽 , ∃𝑑 ∈ [𝑎, 𝑏] s.t. (𝑑, 𝑐] ⊆ 𝑈𝛽 .
3This proof is adapted from that of Theorem 27.1 in Munkre’s Topology, an identical theorem but applied to more general ordered
topologies.
But this is a finite subcover of [𝑎, 𝑐], contradicting the fact that 𝑐 ∉ 𝐶. We conclude, then, that 𝑐 ∈ 𝐶
after all.
4. Claim: 𝑐 = 𝑏.
Suppose not; then, since we have 𝑐 ⩽ 𝑏, then assume 𝑐 < 𝑏. Then, applying Step 1. with 𝑥 = 𝑐 (which
we can do, by our assumption of 𝑐 ≠ 𝑏!), then we have that ∃𝑦 > 𝑐 s.t. [𝑐, 𝑦] has a finite subcover, call
this 𝑈 𝑦 ⊆ 𝒰.
Moreover, we had 𝑐 ∈ 𝐶, hence [𝑎, 𝑐] has a finite subcover, call this 𝑈 𝑐 ⊆ 𝒰.
Then, this gives us that
[𝑎, 𝑦] = [𝑎, 𝑐] ∪ [𝑐, 𝑦] ⊆ 𝑈 𝑐 ∪ 𝑈 𝑦 ,
that is, [𝑎, 𝑦] has a finite subcover, and so 𝑦 ∈ 𝐶. But recall that 𝑦 > 𝑐; hence, this a contradiction to 𝑐
being the least upper bound of 𝐶. We conclude that 𝑐 = 𝑏, and thus [𝑎, 𝑏] has a finite subcover, and is
thus compact.
■
Remark 2.7. A similar proof shows that [𝑎, 𝑏] is connected; we cannot cover it by two disjoint open sets.
↩→Proposition 2.15
If 𝑋 , 𝑌 are compact topological spaces, then 𝑋 × 𝑌 is compact.
Î𝑛
Remark 2.8. By induction, if 𝑋1 , . . . , 𝑋𝑛 compact, so is 𝑖=1 𝑋𝑖 .
↩→Proposition 2.16
A closed subset of a compact topological space is compact in the subspace topology.
is an open cover for the set 𝐴. 𝐴 being compact implies that 𝑈 has an finite subcover such that 𝐴 ⊂
𝑈𝑟1 ∪ 𝑈𝑟2 ∪ · · · ∪ 𝑈𝑟𝑁 . Let 𝑟0 = min𝑁
𝑖=1 𝑟 𝑖 . Then, 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑈 𝑟0 , and 𝐴 ∩ 𝐵(𝑥, 𝑟0 ) = ∅; but this is a contradiction to the
definition of a limit point, hence any limit point 𝑥 is contained in 𝐴 and 𝐴 is thus closed by definition. ■
↩→Proposition 2.17
Compact =⇒ sequentially compact; that is, every sequence in a compact set has a convergent subse-
quence.
↩→ Theorem 2.3
Let 𝑋 be a connected topological space. Let 𝑓 : 𝑋 → 𝑌 be a continuous function. Then, 𝑓 (𝑋) is also
connected.
Proof Suppose, seeking a contradiction, that 𝑋 is connected, but 𝑓 (𝑋) is not. Then, we can write 𝑓 (𝑋) ⊆ 𝑌 as
Proof
Proof.
𝑓 (𝑋) ⊆ 𝑈 ∪ 𝑉, such that 𝑈 , 𝑉 open in 𝑌 and 𝑈 ∩ 𝑉 = ∅. Then,
(𝑈 ∩ 𝑓 (𝑋)) ∩ (𝑉 ∩ 𝑓 (𝑋)) = ∅.
𝑓 −1 (𝑈) ∩ 𝑓 −1 (𝑉) = ∅ (that is, they are disjoint) by our assumption; this is a contradiction to the connectedness
of 𝑋, as we are able to write it as a subset of two disjoint open sets. Hence, 𝑓 (𝑋) is indeed connected. ■
Proof
Proof.
Proof ■
More precisely, let 𝑎 = 𝑓 (𝑥), 𝑏 = 𝑓 (𝑦) for 𝑥, 𝑦 ∈ 𝑋. Assume 𝑎 < 𝑏. Then, ∀ 𝑎 < 𝑐 < 𝑏, ∃𝑧 ∈
𝑋 s.t. 𝑓 (𝑧) = 𝑐.
Proof Suppose, seeking a contradiction, that ∃𝑐 : 𝑎 < 𝑐 < 𝑏 s.t. 𝑐 ∉ 𝑓 (𝑋) (that is, there exists an intermediate
Proof
Proof.
value that is “not reached” by the function).
Let 𝑈 = (−∞, 𝑐) and 𝑉 = (𝑐, +∞); note that these are disjoint open sets. Then, we have that
𝑋 = 𝑓 −1 (𝑈) ∪ 𝑓 −1 (𝑉),
by our assumption of 𝑐 ∉ 𝑓 (𝑋). But this gives that 𝑋 is not connected, as the union of two open (by
continuity), disjoint, nonempty ( 𝑓 (𝑥) = 𝑎 ∈ 𝑈 =⇒ 𝑥 ∈ 𝑓 −1 (𝑈), and 𝑓 (𝑦) = 𝑏 ∈ 𝑉 =⇒ 𝑦 ∈ 𝑓 −1 (𝑉)) sets, a
contradiction. ■
↩→ Theorem 2.5
Suppose 𝑋 is compact, 𝑌-topological space, 𝑓 : 𝑋 → 𝑌 is a continuous function. Then, 𝑓 (𝑋) is also
compact.
Proof. 𝑓 (𝑋) ⊆ R is compact by theorem 2.5, and so by theorem 2.2, 𝑓 (𝑋) is closed and bounded. Let, then,
Proof
𝑚 = inf 𝑓 (𝑋) and 𝑀 = sup 𝑓 (𝑋); these necessarily exist, since 𝑓 (𝑋) is bounded. Both 𝑚 and 𝑀 are limit
points of 𝑓 (𝑋). But 𝑓 (𝑋) is closed, and hence contains all of its limit points, and thus 𝑚 ∈ 𝑓 (𝑋) and 𝑀 ∈ 𝑓 (𝑋),
and thus ∃𝑦𝑚 : 𝑓 (𝑦𝑚 ) = 𝑚 and 𝑦 𝑀 : 𝑓 (𝑦 𝑀 ) = 𝑀. ■
Proof Suppose, seeking a contradiction, that 𝐴 is path connected, but not connected. Then, we can write
Proof
Proof.
𝐴 ⊆ 𝑈 ∪ 𝑉 , for open, disjoint, nonempty subsets 𝑈 , 𝑉 ⊆ 𝑋.
Let 𝑥 ∈ 𝑈 ∩ 𝐴 and 𝑦 ∈ 𝑉 ∩ 𝐴. Then, ∃ 𝑓 : [𝑎, 𝑏] → 𝐴 s.t. 𝑓 (𝑎) = 𝑥, 𝑓 (𝑏) = 𝑦, and 𝑓 ([𝑎, 𝑏]) ⊆ 𝐴, by the path
connectedness of 𝐴. Then,
[𝑎, 𝑏] ⊆ 𝑓 −1 (𝐴) ⊆ 𝑓 −1 (𝑈 ∩ 𝐴) ∪ 𝑓 −1 (𝑉 ∩ 𝐴) =: 𝑈1 ∪ 𝑈2 ,
| {z } | {z } |{z} |{z}
open open 𝑎∈ 𝑏∈
that is, [𝑎, 𝑏] is contained in a union of open, nonempty, disjoint sets, contradicting [𝑎, 𝑏] the connectedness
of [𝑎, 𝑏] by lemma 2.3. Thus, 𝐴 is connected. ■
Remark 2.10. A counterexample to the opposite side of the implication is the Topologist’s sine curve, the set
1
{(𝑥, sin ) : 𝑥 ∈ (0, 1]} ∪ {0} × [−1, 1].
𝑥
↩→Proposition 2.18
For open sets in R𝑛 , path connected ⇐⇒ connected.
Remark 2.11. Remark that if a metric space 𝑋 is not connected, then we can write 𝑋 = 𝑈 ∪ 𝑉 where 𝑈 , 𝑉 are open,
nonempty and disjoint. It follows, then, that 𝑈 = 𝑉 𝐶 (and vice versa) and hence 𝑈 , 𝑉 are both open and closed.
⊛ Example 2.6
Let 𝑋 = (0, 1) ∪ (1, 2). Here, we have two connected components, (0, 1) and (1, 2)
↩→Proposition 2.19
𝑃(𝑥) = {𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 : ∃ conintuous path 𝛾 : [0, 1] → 𝑋 : 𝛾(0) = 𝑥, 𝛾(1) = 𝑦}.
Remark 2.12. Where we “start” a path does not matter. We write 𝑥 ∼ 𝑦 if ∃𝛾 from 𝑥 to 𝑦; this is an equivalence
relation on the elements of 𝑋.
Remark 2.13. The choice of [0, 1] here is arbitrary; any closed interval is homeomorphic.
↩→ Lemma 2.4
If 𝑃(𝑥) ∩ 𝑃(𝑦) ≠ ∅, then 𝑃(𝑥) = 𝑃(𝑦).
↩→ Lemma 2.5
↩→ Lemma 2.6
Suppose 𝐴 ⊆ 𝑋 is both open and closed. Then, if 𝐶 ⊆ 𝑋 is connected and 𝐶 ∩ 𝐴 ≠ ∅, then 𝐶 ⊆ 𝐴.
↩→Proposition 2.20
Let {𝐶 𝛼 } 𝛼∈𝐼 be a collection of nonempty connected subspaces of 𝑋 s.t. ∀ 𝛼, 𝛽 ∈ 𝐼, 𝐶 𝛼 ∩ 𝐶𝛽 ≠ ∅. Then,
∪𝛼∈𝐼 𝐶 𝛼 is connected.
↩→Proposition 2.21
Suppose each 𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 has a path-connected neighborhood. Then, the path components in 𝑋 are the same
as the connected components in 𝑋.
0
Let 𝑥 ∈ 𝐶 : 𝑥 = 0.𝑎1 𝑎 2 𝑎 3 . . . (base 3), ie 𝑎 𝑗 = . Define
2
𝑎 𝑗 /2 𝑥∈𝐶
Í
2𝑗
𝑓 (𝑥) =
extend by continuity 𝑥 ∉ 𝐶.
Remark 2.14. Wikipedia’s explanation of this is far better than whatever this definition is trying to say.
Remark 3.1. Recall that for 1 ⩽ 𝑝 ⩽ +∞, we define for 𝑥 = (𝑥1 , . . . , 𝑥 𝑛 ) ∈ R𝑛 the norm
1 𝑛
||𝑥|| 𝑝 = (|𝑥1 | 𝑝 + · · · + |𝑥 𝑛 | 𝑝 ) 𝑝 , ||𝑥|| ∞ = max |𝑥 𝑖 | .
𝑖=1
Similarly, for infinite vector spaces, we had, for 𝑥 = (𝑥1 , . . . , 𝑥 𝑛 , . . . ), the norm
∞
! 𝑝1
|𝑥 𝑖 | 𝑝
Õ
||𝑥|| 𝑝 = , ||𝑥|| ∞ = sup |𝑥 𝑖 | .
𝑖=1 𝑖 ⩾1
Here, we define
ℓ 𝑝 := {𝑥 = (𝑥1 , . . . , 𝑥 𝑛 ) : ||𝑥|| 𝑝 < +∞}.
1 1
+ = 1.
𝑝 𝑞
Remark 3.2. We refer to these simply as “conjugates” throughout as no other conception of conjugate numbers will be
discussed.
1
Further, we take by convention ∞ = 0.
𝑛
Õ
⟨𝑥, 𝑦⟩R𝑛 := 𝑥 𝑖 𝑦 𝑖 ⩽ ||𝑥|| 𝑝 · ||𝑦|| 𝑞
𝑖=1
⊛ Example 3.1
For the case 𝑝 = 1 or ∞ (functionally, the same case):
𝑥𝑝 𝑦𝑞
𝑥𝑦 ⩽ + .
𝑝 𝑞
1 1
Remark 3.3. If the inequality holds, then, for some 𝑡 > 0, let 𝑥˜ = 𝑡 𝑝 · 𝑥, 𝑦˜ = 𝑡 𝑞 𝑦. Substituting 𝑥 for 𝑥˜ and 𝑦 for 𝑦,
˜ we
have
1 1 1
+ 1𝑞
LHS: 𝑥˜ 𝑦˜ = 𝑡 𝑝 𝑥 · 𝑡 𝑞 𝑦 = 𝑡 𝑝 · 𝑥𝑦 = 𝑥𝑦
𝑥𝑝 𝑦𝑞
RHS: · · · = 𝑡( + .)
𝑝 𝑞
Proof If 𝑥 = 0 or 𝑦 = 0, then the entire LHS becomes 0 and we are done; assume 𝑥, 𝑦 > 0; by the previous
Proof
Proof.
remark, assume wlog 𝑦 = 1. Then, we have
𝑥𝑝 𝑦𝑞 𝑥𝑝 1
𝑥·𝑦⩽ + ⇐⇒ 𝑥 · 1 ⩽ +
𝑝 𝑞 𝑝 𝑞
𝑥 𝑝 1
⇐⇒ − 𝑥 + =: 𝑓 (𝑥) ⩾ 0.
𝑝 𝑞
𝑝𝑥 𝑝−1
′
𝑓 (𝑥) = − 1 = 𝑥 𝑝−1 − 1
𝑝
𝑛
Õ 𝑛
Õ
𝑥 𝑖 𝑦𝑖 ⩽ |𝑥 𝑖 𝑦 𝑖 | (by triangle inequality)
𝑖=1 𝑖=1
𝑛 𝑝 𝑞
Õ 𝑥𝑖 𝑦𝑖
⩽ + (by lemma 3.1)
𝑝 𝑞
𝑖=1
𝑛 𝑛
! !
1 Õ 1 Õ
= |𝑥 𝑖 | 𝑝 + |𝑦 𝑖 | 𝑞
𝑝 𝑞
𝑖=1 𝑖=1
1 𝑝 1 𝑞
= ||𝑥|| 𝑝 + ||𝑦|| 𝑞 (by staring)
𝑝 𝑞
1 1 1 1
= · 1 𝑝 + · 11 = + = 1 (by assumption)
𝑝 𝑞 𝑝 𝑞
= ||𝑥|| 𝑝 · ||𝑦|| 𝑞 ,
0 · 𝑦1 + · · · + 0 · 𝑦𝑛 ⩽ 0,
𝑝
|𝑥 𝑖 | 𝑝
Í𝑛
𝑝 𝑖=1
||𝑥|| 𝑝
|| 𝑥||
˜ 𝑝 = 𝑝 = 𝑝 = 1 =⇒ || 𝑥||
˜ 𝑝 = 1.
||𝑥|| 𝑝 ||𝑥|| 𝑝
𝑛
Õ
𝑥˜ 𝑖 𝑦˜𝑖 ⩽ 1
𝑖=1
But by definition of 𝑥,
˜ 𝑦,
˜ we have
𝑛 𝑛 𝑛
Õ 1 Õ Õ
𝑥˜ 𝑖 𝑦˜𝑖 = 𝑥 𝑖 𝑦 𝑖 ⩽ 1 =⇒ 𝑥 𝑖 𝑦 𝑖 ⩽ ||𝑥|| 𝑝 · ||𝑦|| 𝑞 ,
||𝑥|| 𝑝 ||𝑦|| 𝑞
𝑖=1 𝑖=1 𝑖=1
𝑛 𝑛
𝑝 𝑝 𝑝−1
Õ Õ
||𝑥 + 𝑦|| 𝑝 = 𝑥 𝑗 + 𝑦𝑗 = 𝑥 𝑗 + 𝑦𝑗 𝑥 𝑗 + 𝑦𝑗
𝑗=1 𝑗=1
∞
𝑝−1
Õ
𝑥 𝑗 + 𝑦𝑗 · 𝑥 𝑗 + 𝑦𝑗
⩽
𝑗=1
:=𝐵
z }| {
𝑛 𝑛
𝑝−1 𝑝−1
Õ Õ
= 𝑥 𝑗 · 𝑥 𝑗 + 𝑦𝑗 + 𝑦𝑗 · 𝑥 𝑗 + 𝑦𝑗 ⊛
𝑗=1 𝑗=1
| {z }
:=𝐴
𝑛
! 𝑝1
(|𝑥 𝑖 | 𝑝 )
Õ
|| 𝑢® || 𝑝 = = ||𝑥|| 𝑝
𝑖=1
𝑛
! 1𝑞
𝑞
|𝑥 𝑖 + 𝑦 𝑖 | 𝑝−1
Õ
𝑣 || 𝑞 =
||®
𝑖=1
" 𝑛 𝑝
# 𝑝−1
𝑝
𝑝−1
|𝑥 𝑖 + 𝑦 𝑖 | 𝑝−1
Õ
=
𝑖=1
" 𝑛
# 𝑝−1
𝑝
|𝑥 𝑖 + 𝑦 𝑖 | 𝑝
Õ
=
𝑖=1
𝑝−1
= ||𝑥 + 𝑦|| 𝑝
𝑝
where the second-to-last line follows from 𝑝, 𝑞 being conjugate, hence 𝑞 = 𝑝−1 . Thus, by Hölder’s Inequality,
we have that
𝑝−1
𝐴 = ⟨®
𝑢 , 𝑣® ⟩ ⩽ ||𝑢|| 𝑝 · ||𝑣|| 𝑞 = ||𝑥|| 𝑝 · ||𝑥 + 𝑦|| 𝑝 .
By a similar construction, we can show that
𝑝−1
𝐵 ⩽ ||𝑦|| 𝑝 · ||𝑥 + 𝑦|| 𝑝 .
𝑝
||𝑥 + 𝑦|| 𝑝 ⩽ 𝐴 + 𝐵
𝑝−1 𝑝−1
⩽ ||𝑥|| 𝑝 · ||𝑥 + 𝑦|| 𝑝 + ||𝑦|| 𝑝 · ||𝑥 + 𝑦|| 𝑝
=⇒ ||𝑥 + 𝑦|| 𝑝 ⩽ ||𝑥|| 𝑝 + ||𝑦|| 𝑝 ,
↩→ Theorem 3.1
The sequence of centers of balls with monotonically decreasing radii is a Cauchy sequence in 𝑋.
|𝑥 𝑖 | 𝑝 < +∞}, 1 ⩽ 𝑝 ⩽ +∞
Í∞
2. ℓ 𝑝 = {𝑥 = (𝑥 𝑖 )∞
𝑖=1
: 𝑖=1
3. ℓ∞ = {𝑥 = (𝑥 𝑖 ) : sup∞
𝑖=1 |𝑥 𝑖 |
< +∞}.
↩→Proposition 3.3
Hölder’s Inequality and Minkowski Inequality inequalities hold for infinite sequences. that is,
1 1
1. if 𝑥 = (𝑥 𝑖 ) ∈ ℓ 𝑝 and 𝑦 = (𝑦 𝑖 ) ∈ ℓ 𝑞 with 𝑝 + 𝑞 = 1, then
∞
Õ
𝑥 𝑖 𝑦 𝑖 ⩽ ||𝑥 𝑖 ||ℓ 𝑝 ||𝑦 𝑖 ||ℓ 𝑞 .
𝑖=1
2. if 𝑥, 𝑦 ∈ ℓ 𝑝 , then
||𝑥 + 𝑦|| 𝑝 ⩽ ||𝑥|| 𝑝 + ||𝑦|| 𝑝 .
𝑝 𝑝 𝑝
Proof (of 2.) If 𝑥, 𝑦 ∈ ℓ 𝑝 , we have that ∞ ∞
𝑖=1 |𝑥 𝑖 | < +∞, 𝑖=1 |𝑦 𝑖 | < +∞, so ∃𝑁 > 0 :
∞
𝑖=𝑁+1 |𝑥 𝑖 | <
Í Í Í
Proof
Proof.
𝑝 (𝑛)
𝜀, ∞𝑖=𝑁+1 |𝑦 𝑖 | < 𝜀. Let 𝑥 𝑖 = (𝑥 1 , . . . , 𝑥 𝑛 , 0, 0, . . . ) be (𝑥) truncated after 𝑛 (finite) coordinates. This gives
Í
(𝑛) (𝑛)
||(𝑥 𝑖 + 𝑦 𝑖 )(𝑛) || 𝑝 ⩽ ||𝑥 𝑖 || 𝑝 + ||𝑦 𝑖 || 𝑝 ⩽ ||𝑥|| 𝑝 + ||𝑦|| 𝑝
by Minkowski on finite spaces. Taking 𝑛 → ∞ (ie, “detruncating”), we have (𝑥 + 𝑦) ∈ ℓ 𝑝 , and thus ||𝑥 + 𝑦|| 𝑝 ⩽
||𝑥|| 𝑝 + ||𝑦|| 𝑝 .
1. left as an exercise. ■
↩→Proposition 3.4
Let 1 ⩽ 𝑝 ⩽ +∞, and ||𝑥|| ∞ = sup∞
𝑖=1 |𝑥 𝑖 |
= 𝐴 < +∞, ||𝑦|| ∞ = sup∞
𝑖=1 |𝑦 𝑖 |
= 𝐵 < +∞. Then, the triangle
inequality ||𝑥 + 𝑦|| ∞ ⩽ ||𝑥|| ∞ + ||𝑦|| ∞ holds.
Proof We have
Proof
Proof.
∞ ∞ ∞ ∞
sup |𝑥 𝑖 + 𝑦 𝑖 | ⩽ sup (|𝑥 𝑖 | + |𝑦 𝑖 |) ⩽ sup |𝑥 𝑖 | + sup |𝑦 𝑖 | = ||𝑥|| ∞ + ||𝑦|| ∞ .
𝑖=1 𝑖=1 𝑖=1 𝑖=1
↩→Proposition 3.5
||𝑥|| ∞ := sup∞
𝑖=1 |𝑥 𝑖 |
is a well-defined norm on ℓ∞ .
Proof. The triangle inequality is prove in proposition 3.4. The remainder of the requirements are left as an
Proof
exercise. ■
↩→Proposition 3.6
ℓ 𝑝 ⊆ ℓ 𝑞 if 𝑝 < 𝑞.
|𝑥 𝑖 | 𝑞 ⩽ |𝑥 𝑖 | 𝑝 < ∞
Õ Õ
𝑖 ⩾𝑁 𝑖 ⩾𝑁
∞
|𝑥 𝑖 | 𝑞 < +∞ =⇒ 𝑥 ∈ ℓ 𝑞
Õ
=⇒
𝑖=1
=⇒ ℓ 𝑝 ⊆ ℓ 𝑞
■
↩→ Lecture 08; Last Updated: Thu Mar 28 09:13:10 EDT 2024
Remark 3.6. The “functional construction” of the Cantor set is an example of a contraction mapping, with 𝑓1 (𝑥) =
𝑥 𝑥+2
3 , 𝑓2 (𝑥) = 3 . The first has a fixed point of 0, and the second a fixed point of 1.
Remark 3.7. This is a generalization of this proof done in Analysis I, an equivalent claim over the reals.
Proof Fix 𝑥 ∈ 𝑋. Consider the sequence {𝑥 0 , 𝑥1 , 𝑥2 , . . . , 𝑥 𝑛 , . . . } := {𝑥, 𝑓 (𝑥), 𝑓 ◦ 𝑓 (𝑥), · · · , 𝑓 [𝑛] (𝑥), . . . } (we call
Proof
Proof.
𝑓 [𝑛] the orbit of 𝑥 under iterations of 𝑓 ). We claim that this is a Cauchy sequence. Let 𝑛 ∈ N arbitrary, then
we have, by the property of the contraction mapping,
𝑑( 𝑓 [𝑛+1] (𝑥) − 𝑓 [𝑛] (𝑥)) ⩽ 𝑐 · 𝑑( 𝑓 [𝑛] (𝑥) − 𝑓 [𝑛−1] (𝑥)) ⩽ 𝑐 2 𝑑( 𝑓 [𝑛−1] (𝑥) − 𝑓 [𝑛−2] (𝑥)).
𝑑( 𝑓 [𝑚] , 𝑓 [𝑚+𝑘] (𝑥) ⩽ 𝑑( 𝑓 [𝑚] )(𝑥), 𝑓 [𝑚+1] (𝑥)) + 𝑑( 𝑓 [𝑚+1] (𝑥), 𝑓 [𝑚] (𝑥)) + · · · + 𝑑( 𝑓 [𝑚+𝑘−1] (𝑥), 𝑓 𝑚+𝑘 (𝑥))
★
⩽ 𝑑(𝑥, 𝑓 (𝑥))[𝑐 𝑚 + 𝑐 𝑚+1 + · · · + 𝑐 𝑚+𝑘−1 ]
𝑐 𝑚 𝑑(𝑥, 𝑓 (𝑥))
⩽ 𝑐 𝑚 𝑑(𝑥, 𝑓 (𝑥))[1 + 𝑐 + · · · + 𝑐 𝑘 + 𝑐 𝑘+1 + · · · ] =
1−𝑐
𝑐 𝑁 𝑑(𝑥, 𝑓 (𝑥))
Now, given 𝜀 > 0, choose 𝑁 such that 1−𝑐 < 𝜀. It follows, then, that { 𝑓 [𝑛] (𝑥)} 𝑛∈N a Cauchy sequence,
and thus converges, 𝑓 [𝑛] (𝑥) → 𝑧 as 𝑛 → ∞ for some 𝑧.
We further have to show that 𝑓 (𝑧) = 𝑧. It is easy to show that 𝑓 continuous due to the contraction mapping
(it is clearly Lipschitz with constant 𝑐), and it thus follows that
implying 𝑑(𝑦1 , 𝑦2 ) ⩽ 𝑐 · 𝑑(𝑦1 , 𝑦2 ). This is only possible if 𝑑(𝑦1 , 𝑦2 ) = 0, and thus 𝑦1 = 𝑦2 and the fixed point is
indeed unique. ■
Proof (Sketch) We suppose first 𝑝 < +∞. Consider an arbitrary number of Cauchy sequences in ℓ 𝑝 :
Proof
Proof.
(1) (1)
𝑥 (1) = (𝑥 1 , . . . , 𝑥 𝑛 , . . . )
(2) (2)
𝑥 (2) = (𝑥 1 , . . . , 𝑥𝑛 , . . . )
.. .. ..
. . .
(𝑘) (𝑘)
𝑥 (𝑘) = (𝑥1 , . . . , 𝑥 𝑛 , . . . ) ∈ ℓ 𝑝
(𝑛)
We claim that, for any 𝑘 ∈ N, the (𝑥 𝑘 )𝑛∈N is a Cauchy sequence; note that in this definition we are taking a
fixed-index (namely, the 𝑘th) element from different sequences (namely, the 𝑛th sequence).
∞ 𝑝
𝑝
Õ
(𝑛) 𝑝
< 𝜀𝑝
(𝑚) (𝑚) (𝑚) (𝑛)
𝑑 𝑝 (𝑥 ,𝑥 ) = ||𝑥 − 𝑥 (𝑛) || 𝑝 = 𝑥𝑖 − 𝑥𝑖
𝑖=1
𝑝 ∞
Õ 𝑝 𝑝
− 𝑥 𝑛𝑘 − 𝑥 𝑛𝑘 < 𝜀𝑝
(𝑚) (𝑚) (𝑛) (𝑚)
𝑥𝑘 ⩽ 𝑥𝑖 − 𝑥𝑖 =⇒ 𝑥 𝑘
𝑖=1
(𝑚) (𝑛)
=⇒ 𝑥 𝑘 − 𝑥𝑘 < 𝜀,
(𝑛)
since we are taking “less of the summands in the second line”. It follows, then, that for each 𝑘, ∃𝑧 𝑘 : 𝑥 𝑘 → 𝑧 𝑘
as 𝑛 → ∞. Let 𝑧 = (𝑧 1 , . . . , 𝑧 𝑛 , . . . ). We claim that 𝑥 (𝑛) → 𝑧 ∈ ℓ 𝑝 as 𝑛 → ∞.
First, we show that 𝑑 𝑝 (𝑥 (𝑛) , 𝑧) → 0 as 𝑛 → 0 (that is, 𝑥 (𝑛) → 𝑧 as 𝑛 → ∞). Fix 𝜀 > 0, and choose 𝑁 ∈ N for
which 𝑑 𝑝 (𝑥 (𝑚) , 𝑥 (𝑛) ) < 𝜀 ∀ 𝑚, 𝑛 ⩾ 𝑁 (by Cauchy). Fix 𝐾 ∈ N, 𝐾 > 0.
∞ 𝑝
𝑝 𝑝
Õ
(𝑛)
𝑑 𝑝 (𝑥 (𝑛) , 𝑧) = ||𝑥 (𝑛) − 𝑧|| 𝑝 = 𝑥𝑖 − 𝑧𝑖
𝑖=1
𝐾 𝑝
𝑝
Õ
||𝑥 (𝑚) − 𝑥 (𝑛) || 𝑝 < 𝜀 𝑝 =⇒ ⩽ 𝜀𝑝
(𝑚) (𝑛)
𝑥𝑖 − 𝑥𝑖
𝑖=1
(𝑚)
Let 𝑚 → ∞; then 𝑥 𝑖 → 𝑧 𝑖 (note that 𝑖 fixed!), and we have
𝐾
Õ 𝑝
𝑧𝑖 − 𝑥𝑖
(𝑛)
⩽ 𝜀𝑝 .
𝑖=1
Let 𝐾 → ∞; then,
∞
Õ 𝑝
𝑧𝑖 − 𝑥𝑖
(𝑛)
⩽ 𝜀 𝑝 =⇒ ||𝑧 − 𝑥|| 𝑝 ⩽ 𝜀 =⇒ 𝑑 𝑝 (𝑧, 𝑥 𝑛 ) ⩽ 𝜀,
𝑖=1
and thus 𝑥 𝑛 → 𝑧 as 𝑛 → ∞.
It remains to show that 𝑧 ∈ ℓ 𝑝 , ie ||𝑧|| 𝑝 < +∞. We have:
For sufficiently large 𝑛, ||𝑧 − 𝑥 (𝑛) || ⩽ 1 (for instance); 𝑥 (𝑛) ∈ ℓ 𝑝 , hence ||𝑥 (𝑛) || 𝑝 < +∞ (say, ||𝑥 (𝑛) || 𝑝 ⩽ 𝑀). Thus:
||𝑧|| 𝑝 ⩽ 1 + 𝑀 < +∞ =⇒ 𝑧 ∈ ℓ 𝑝 ,
↩→ Theorem 3.4
Let (𝑋 , 𝑑) be a metric space. TFAE:
2. 𝑋 is compact;
Proof (1. =⇒ 2.) Suppose 𝑋 complete and totally bounded. Assume towards a contradiction that 𝑋 not
Proof
Proof.
compact, ie there exists an open cover {𝑈 𝛼 } 𝛼∈𝐼 of 𝑋 with no finite subcover.
𝑋 being totally bounded gives that it can be covered by finitely many open balls of radius 12 . It must be
that at least one of these open balls cannot be finitely covered, otherwise we would have a finite subcover.
Let 𝐹1 be the closure of this ball. 𝐹1 closed, with diameter diam(𝐹1 ) ⩽ 1. 𝑋.
We also have that 𝑋 can be covered by finitely many balls of radius 14 ; again, there must be at least one
ball 𝐵1 such that 𝐵1 ∩ 𝐹1 cannot be covered by finitely many open sets from the cover. Let 𝐹2 = 𝐵1 ∩ 𝐹1 -closed,
with diam(𝐹2 ) ⩽ 41 + 14 = 12 .4
Arguing inductively, at some step 𝑛, 𝑋 can can be covered by finitely many balls of radius 21𝑛 ; at least one
of these balls 𝐵 cannot be covered by a finite subcover hence 𝐵 ∩ 𝐹𝑛−1 cannot be covered by finitely many 𝑈 𝛼 ’s.
1
Let 𝐹𝑛 = 𝐵 ∩ 𝐹𝑛−1 -closed, with diam(𝐹𝑛 ) ⩽ 2𝑛−1 .
1
As such, we have a nested sequence 𝐹1 ⊇ 𝐹2 ⊇ · · · ⊇ 𝐹𝑛 ⊇ · · · of closed sets, where diam(𝐹 𝑘 ) ⩽ 2 𝑘−1
→0
as 𝑘 → ∞.
Ñ∞
↩→ Lemma 3.1 (Cantor Intersection Theorem). 𝑘=1 𝐹 𝑘 ≠ ∅.
1
𝑑(𝑥 𝑛 , 𝑥 𝑛+𝑘 ) ⩽ diam(𝐹𝑛 ) + · · · + diam(𝐹𝑛+𝑘 ) ⩽ ,
2𝑛−1
by the nested property, which can be made arbitrarily small for sufficiently large 𝑛, 𝑘. Hence, 𝑥 𝑛 → 𝑦 ∈ 𝑋
for some 𝑦, as 𝑋 complete. The tail of 𝑥 𝑛 lies in 𝐹𝑛 for all sufficiently large 𝑛, and as each 𝐹𝑛 closed, the limit
must lie in 𝐹𝑛 for all sufficiently large 𝑛. We conclude the intersection nonempty. ■
1
4𝐵1 has radius 4 and hence diameter 12 . The intersection of 𝐵1 with a set with a larger diameter must have diameter leq 1
2
(2. =⇒ 3.) Suppose 𝑋 compact. Let {𝑥 𝑛 } 𝑛∈N ∈ 𝑋. Let 𝐹𝑛 = we have too that
Ð
𝑘 ⩾ 𝑛 {𝑥 𝑘 }-closed;
𝐹1 ⊇ 𝐹2 ⊇ · · · ⊇ 𝐹𝑛 ⊇ · · · .
Proof
Proof.
Proof ■
This lemma directly gives that ∞ 𝑛=1 𝐹𝑛 ≠ ∅, {𝐹𝑛 } 𝑛∈N being a collection of closed subsets with any subset
Ñ
having nonempty intersection (by the nestedness). Let 𝑦 ∈ ∩∞ 𝐹 . Take 𝐵(𝑦, 1𝑘 ), which thus has nonempty
𝑛=1 𝑛
intersection with {𝑥 𝑘 } 𝑘 ⩾ 𝑛 ∀ 𝑛, ie ∃𝑛1 : 𝑑(𝑦, 𝑥 𝑛1 ) < 1 and ∃𝑛2 > 𝑛1 : 𝑑(𝑦, 𝑥 𝑛2 ) < 12 . Arguing inductively,
∃𝑛 𝑗 > 𝑛 𝑗−1 : 𝑑(𝑦, 𝑥 𝑛 𝑗 ) < 1𝑗 for any given 𝑛 𝑗−1 . It follows that lim 𝑗→∞ 𝑥 𝑛 𝑗 = 𝑦, and thus {𝑥 𝑛 𝑗 } is a convergent
subsequence of {𝑥 𝑛 } that converges within 𝑋, and thus 𝑋 is sequentially compact.
(3. =⇒ 1.) Suppose 𝑋 sequentially compact. Let {𝑥 𝑛 } ∈ 𝑋 be a Cauchy sequence in 𝑋, which thus have a
convergent subsequence {𝑥 𝑛 𝑘 } → 𝑦.
Proof
Proof.
Proof ■
This contradicts our assumption that 𝑋 sequentially compact, and we conclude 𝑋 must be totally bounded. ■
∫ 𝑏 𝑝1
|| 𝑓 || 𝑝 := | 𝑓 (𝑥)| 𝑝 d𝑥 .
𝑎
As desired, || 𝑓 || 𝑝 ⩾ 0; || 𝑓 || 𝑝 = 0 ⇐⇒ 𝑓 ≡ 0; ||𝑐 · 𝑓 || 𝑝 = 𝑐 · || 𝑓 || 𝑝 .
1 1
Hölder’s and Minkowski’s inequalities for functions also hold; for 𝑝 + 𝑞 = 1, 1 ⩽ 𝑝, 𝑞 ⩽ ∞,
∫
| 𝑓 𝑔| ⩽ || 𝑓 || 𝑝 · || 𝑔|| 𝑞 ; || 𝑓 + 𝑔|| 𝑝 ⩽ || 𝑓 || 𝑝 + || 𝑔|| 𝑞 ,
respectively.
|| 𝑓 || ∞ = sup | 𝑓 (𝑥)| ,
𝑥∈[𝑎,𝑏]
Let 𝑓𝑛 → 𝑓 in 𝐶([𝑎, 𝑏]), wrt || · · · || ∞ , where { 𝑓𝑛 } 𝑛∈N a sequence of functions. Namely, we say that
We say that 𝑓𝑛 (𝑥) → 𝑓 (𝑥) pointwise on [𝑎, 𝑏] if ∀ 𝑥 ∈ [𝑎, 𝑏], 𝑓𝑛 (𝑥) → 𝑓 (𝑥). Note that uniform
convergence implies pointwise convergence, but not the converse.
↩→ Theorem 3.5
Suppose 𝑓𝑛 (𝑥) continuous, and 𝑓𝑛 (𝑥) → 𝑓 (𝑥) uniformly on [𝑎, 𝑏]. Then, 𝑓 (𝑥) also continuous on [𝑎, 𝑏].
Proof Fix 𝜀 > 0, 𝑥0 ∈ [𝑎, 𝑏]. We have that ∃𝑁 : 𝑛 ⩾ 𝑁 , | 𝑓𝑛 (𝑥) − 𝑓 (𝑥)| < 3𝜀 , ∀ 𝑥 ∈ [𝑎, 𝑏].
Proof
Proof.
Let 𝑛 ⩾ 𝑁. 𝑓𝑛 (𝑥) continuous at 𝑥0 , hence ∃𝛿(𝑥0 ) > 0 : |𝑦 − 𝑥 0 | =⇒ | 𝑓𝑛 (𝑦) − 𝑓𝑛 (𝑥0 )| < 3𝜀 . We have
4 Derivatives
4.1 Introduction
Remark 4.1. For 𝑥 close to 𝑐, then 𝑓 (𝑥) ≈ 𝑓 (𝑐) + 𝑓 ′(𝑐)(𝑥 − 𝑐); this is a linear approximation of 𝑓 at 𝑐.
↩→ Definition 4.2
The derivative, d𝑥, is a linear map 𝐶 1 ([𝑎, 𝑏]) → 𝐶 0 ([𝑎, 𝑏]).
𝑓 (𝑥) − 𝑓 (𝑐)
lim 𝜑(𝑥) = lim = 𝑓 ′(𝑐) = 𝜑(𝑐).
𝑥→𝑐 𝑥→𝑐 𝑥−𝑐
5If not stated otherwise, sets named 𝐼 or 𝐽 are intervals.
𝑓 (𝑥) − 𝑓 (𝑐)
∃𝜑(𝑐) = lim 𝜑(𝑥) = lim
𝑥→𝑐 𝑥→𝑐 𝑥−𝑐
Proof Using Caratheodory’s Theorem, ∃𝜑 : 𝑓 (𝑥) − 𝑓 (𝑐) = 𝜑(𝑥)(𝑥 − 𝑐) with 𝜑(𝑐) = 𝑓 ′(𝑐). Let 𝑑 = 𝑓 (𝑐), then
Proof
Proof.
similarly ∃𝜓 : 𝑔(𝑦) − 𝑔(𝑑) = 𝜓(𝑦)(𝑦 − 𝑑) with 𝜓(𝑑) = 𝑔 ′(𝑑), with 𝜑, 𝜓 continuous at 𝑐, 𝑑 resp. Then,
𝑔( 𝑓 (𝑥)) − 𝑔( 𝑓 (𝑐))
lim = lim (𝜓 ◦ 𝑓 )(𝑥) · 𝜑(𝑥) = 𝜓( 𝑓 (𝑐))𝜑(𝑐) = 𝑔 ′( 𝑓 (𝑐)) · 𝑓 ′(𝑐),
𝑥→𝑐 𝑥−𝑐 𝑥→𝑐
by construction. ■
↩→ Definition 4.3
𝑓 : 𝐼 → R has a max/min 𝑐 if ∃𝐽 ⊆ 𝐼 : 𝑥 ∈ 𝐽 s.t. max𝑥∈𝐽 𝑓 (𝑥)/min𝑥∈𝐽 𝑓 (𝑥) = 𝑓 (𝑐).
𝑓 (𝑏)− 𝑓 (𝑎)
Proof Let 𝜑(𝑥) = 𝑓 (𝑥) − 𝑓 (𝑎) =
Proof
Proof. (𝑏−𝑎)
(𝑥 − 𝑎), where 𝜑(𝑎) = 0 = 𝜑(𝑏). By Rolle’s theorem, ∃𝑐 ∈ (𝑎, 𝑏) :
𝑓 (𝑏)− 𝑓 (𝑎)
𝜑′(𝑐) = 0 = 𝑓 ′(𝑐) − (𝑏−𝑎)
, as desired. ■
We have that, for any 𝑥 ∈ R, 𝑥 = ⌊𝑥⌋ + {𝑥}, with {𝑥} ∈ (0, 1); ⌊𝑥⌋ and {𝑥} are the integral and fractional parts
of 𝑥 respectively.
Fix 𝑥 ∈ R, assuming 𝑥 ≠ 0.
1
Let 𝑥1 := {𝑥}
. We can write
1
𝑥 = ⌊𝑥⌋ + .
𝑥1
1
If {𝑥1 } ≠ 0, let 𝑥 2 := {𝑥 1 }
and write
1
𝑥 = ⌊𝑥⌋ + 1
.
⌊𝑥1 ⌋ + 𝑥2
1
𝑥= 1
.
1+ 1
1+ 1+···
1
𝑥 = 𝑎0 + 1
.
𝑎1 + 1
𝑎2 +
..
𝑎3 + .
We notate, accordingly, 𝑥 := (𝑎1 , 𝑎2 , 𝑎3 , . . . ); in this case, the Golden Ratio can be notated (1, 1, 1, . . . ).
𝑝
We denote 𝑞 𝑛𝑛 as the 𝑛th continued fraction of a given 𝑥. It turns out that this is the best possible rational
approximation for 𝑥 ∉ Q.
↩→ Theorem 4.6
𝑓 : 𝐼 → R, differentiable. 𝑓 is increasing (resp decreasing) iff 𝑓 ′(𝑥) ⩾ 0 ∀ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐼 (resp 𝑓 ′(𝑥) ⩽ 0 ∀ 𝑥 ∈ 𝐼).
↩→Proposition 4.1
Let 𝑓 continuous on 𝐼 = [𝑎, 𝑏]. Let 𝑎 < 𝑐 < 𝑏 and suppose 𝑓 differentiable on (𝑎, 𝑐) and (𝑐, 𝑏). Suppose
𝑓 ′(𝑥) ⩾ 0 on (𝑐 − 𝛿, 𝑐) and 𝑓 ′(𝑥) ⩽ 0 on (𝑐, 𝑐 + 𝛿) for some 𝛿 > 0. Then, 𝑓 has local max at 𝑥 = 𝑐.
↩→ Lemma 4.1
Let 𝐼 ⊆ R, and assume 𝑓 : 𝐼 → R is differentiable at 𝑥 = 𝑐 ∈ 𝐼.
↩→Proposition 4.2
Suppose 𝑓 (𝑥), 𝑔(𝑥) : [𝑎, 𝑏] → R with 𝑓 (𝑎) = 𝑔(𝑎) = 0, and 𝑔(𝑥) ≠ 0 ∀ 𝑎 < 𝑥 < 𝑏. Suppose 𝑓 , 𝑔 are
𝑓 (𝑥) 𝑓 ′ (𝑎)
differentiable at 𝑥 = 𝑎 and 𝑔 ′(𝑎) ≠ 0. Then, lim𝑥→𝑎 + 𝑔(𝑥)
exists, and moreover, it is equal to 𝑔 ′ (𝑎)
.
Proof
Proof.
Proof
𝑓 ′ (𝑎)
but the original line is simply 𝑔 ′ (𝑎)
. ■
⊛ Example 4.2
sin 𝑥 cos(0)
lim𝑥→0 𝑥 = 1 = 1.
𝑓 ′ (𝑥) 𝑓 (𝑥)
1. If ∃𝐿 := lim𝑥→𝑎 + 𝑔 ′ (𝑥)
where 𝐿 some real number, then lim𝑥→𝑎 + 𝑔(𝑥)
= 𝐿 as well.
𝑓 ′ (𝑥) 𝑓 (𝑥)
2. If ∃𝐿 := lim𝑥→𝑎 + 𝑔 ′ (𝑥)
where 𝐿 = +∞ or −∞, then lim𝑥→𝑎 + 𝑔(𝑥)
= 𝐿 as well.
↩→Proposition 4.4
Let −∞ ⩽ 𝑎 < 𝑏 ⩽ +∞, 𝑓 , 𝑔 differentiable on (𝑎, 𝑏) and 𝑔 ′(𝑥) ≠ 0 ∀ 𝑥 ∈ (𝑎, 𝑏). Suppose lim𝑥→𝑎 + 𝑔(𝑥) = ±∞.
𝑓 ′ (𝑥) 𝑓 (𝑥)
1. If lim𝑥→𝑎 + 𝑔 ′ (𝑥)
=: 𝐿 exists and is some finite real number, then lim𝑥→𝑎 + 𝑔(𝑥)
= 𝐿 as well.
𝑓 ′ (𝑥) 𝑓 (𝑥)
2. If lim𝑥→𝑎 + 𝑔 ′ (𝑥)
=: 𝐿 exists and is ±∞, then lim𝑥→𝑎 + 𝑔(𝑥)
= 𝐿 as well.
Proof If 𝑛 := 2𝑚-even and 𝑓 (2𝑚) (𝑥0 ) > 0, then 𝑓 (𝑛) (𝑐) > 0 so 𝑓 (𝑥) − 𝑓 (𝑥 0 ) = 𝑓 (2𝑚) (𝑐)(𝑥 − 𝑥0 ) > 0.
Proof
Proof. ■
5 Riemann Integral
5.1 Introduction
𝒫 = {𝑎 = 𝑥0 , 𝑥1 , . . . , 𝑥 𝑛−1 , 𝑥 𝑛 = 𝑏}.
¤ < 𝜀.
That is, ∀ 𝜀 > 0, ∃𝛿 : if diam(𝒫) < 𝛿, then for any choice of 𝑡 𝑖 ∈ [𝑥 𝑖 , 𝑥 𝑖+1 ] we have 𝐿 − 𝑆( 𝑓 , 𝒫)
↩→Proposition 5.1
1. If 𝐿 exists, it is unique.
∫𝑏 ∫𝑏 ∫𝑏 ∫𝑏
2. The integral is linear in 𝑓 (𝑥); if 𝑎
𝑓 (𝑥) d𝑥 and 𝑎
𝑔(𝑥) d𝑥 exist, then 𝑎
(𝑐1 𝑓 + 𝑐 2 𝑔) d𝑥 = 𝑐1 𝑎
𝑓 d𝑥 +
∫𝑏
𝑐2 𝑎
𝑔 d𝑥.
∫𝑏 ∫𝑏
3. If 𝑓 ⩽ 𝑔 are Riemann integrable on [𝑎, 𝑏], then 𝑎
𝑓 (𝑥) d𝑥 ⩽ 𝑎
𝑔(𝑥) d𝑥.
↩→Proposition 5.2
If 𝑓 (𝑥) integrable on [𝑎, 𝑏], the 𝑓 (𝑥) is bounded on [𝑎, 𝑏].
∫𝑏
¤ < 𝛿 then 𝐿 − 𝑆( 𝑓 , 𝒫)
Proof Suppose 𝑎 𝑓 exists. Let 𝜀 > 0, and 𝛿 such that if diam(𝒫)
Proof.
Proof ¤ . Let 𝜀 = 1. Then,
¤ ⩽ |𝐿| + 1.
𝑆( 𝑓 , 𝒫)
Let 𝑄 = {𝑎 = 𝑥0 , . . . , 𝑥 𝑛 = 𝑏} be a partition of [𝑎, 𝑏] such that diam(𝑄) < 𝛿. Suppose towards a
contradiction that 𝑓 is not bounded on [𝑎, 𝑏]. Then, 𝑓 is unbounded on at least one interval [𝑥 𝑖 , 𝑥 𝑖+1 ],
say,
Í on [𝑥 𝑘 , 𝑥 𝑘+1 ]. Let 𝑡 𝑖 = 𝑥 𝑖 for 𝑖 ≠ 𝑘 and choose 𝑡 𝑘 ∈ [𝑥 𝑘 , 𝑥 𝑘+1 ] such that | 𝑓 (𝑡 𝑘 )| (𝑥 𝑘+1 − 𝑥 𝑘 ) > |𝐿| + 1 +
𝑖≠𝑘 𝑓 (𝑡 𝑖 )(𝑥 𝑖+1 − 𝑥 𝑖 ) (which we can do by assumption of 𝑓 being unbounded).
contradiction. ■
↩→ Theorem 5.1
∫𝑏
Let 𝑓 : [𝑎, 𝑏] → R. Then 𝑎
𝑓 exists ⇐⇒ ∀ 𝜀 > 0, ∃𝛼 𝜀 (𝑥), 𝜔 𝜀 (𝑥) ∈ ℛ[𝑎, 𝑏], 𝛼 𝜀 ⩽ 𝑓 ⩽ 𝜔 𝜀 , and
∫ 𝑏
(𝜔 𝜀 − 𝛼 𝜀 ) < 𝜀
𝑎
∫ 𝑏 ∫ 𝑏
¤ ⩽ 𝑆( 𝑓 , 𝑃)
𝛼 𝜀 − 𝜀 < 𝑆(𝛼 𝜀 , 𝑃) ¤ ⩽ 𝑆(𝜔 𝜀 , 𝑃)
¤ < 𝜔 𝜀 + 𝜀.
𝑎 𝑎
∫𝑏
Let 𝑄¤ be any other tagged partition with diam 𝑄¤ < 𝛿; then, the same inequality holds ie 𝑎
¤ <
𝛼 𝜀 − 𝜀 < 𝑆( 𝑓 , 𝑄)
∫𝑏
𝑎
𝜔 𝜀 + 𝜀. Subtracting one from the other, we see that
∫ 𝑏 ∫ 𝑏
¤ − 𝑆( 𝑓 , 𝑄)
𝑆( 𝑓 , 𝑃) ¤ < 𝜔𝜀 − 𝛼 𝜀 + 2𝜀 < 3𝜀,
𝑎 𝑎
1 𝑥 ∈ 𝐽
𝜑 𝐽 (𝑥) := .
0 𝑥 ∉ 𝐽
∫𝑏
Then, 𝜑 𝐽 ∈ ℛ[𝑎, 𝑏] and 𝑎
𝜑 𝐽 = 𝑑 − 𝑐.
7Note that ℛ[𝑎, 𝑏] is the set of all real-valued functions integrable on the interval [𝑎, 𝑏].
↩→ Theorem 5.3
𝑓 continuous on [𝑎, 𝑏] implies 𝑓 ∈ ℛ[𝑎, 𝑏].
Proof (Sketch) 𝑓 uniform continuous; use this to construct step functions that “bound” 𝑓 from above and
Proof
Proof.
below. Apply the squeeze theorem. ■
Proof We show only for increasing. Let 𝑓 : [𝑎, 𝑏] → R be monotone increasing. If 𝑓 constant, then it is a step
Proof
Proof.
function and we are done.
𝑓 (𝑏)− 𝑓 (𝑎) 𝜀
Otherwise, 𝑓 (𝑏) − 𝑓 (𝑎) > 0. Let 𝜀 > 0 and 𝑞 ∈ N such that ℎ ..= 𝑞 < 𝑏−𝑎 , effectively subdividing the
𝑦-axis into 𝑞 equal-sized parts. Then, let
𝑦 𝑖 ..= 𝑓 (𝑎) + 𝑖 ℎ, 0 ⩽ 𝑖 ⩽ 𝑞,
and take
∅
𝐴 𝑘 ..= 𝑓 −1 ([𝑦 𝑘+1 , 𝑦 𝑘 )) = {𝑥} .
𝐼𝑖
We disregard each 𝐴 𝑘 : 𝐴 𝑘 = ∅, and adjoin the isolated points {𝑥} to the 𝐼 𝑖 ’s, and hence have a partition
∪ 𝑘 𝐴 𝑘 = [𝑎, 𝑏]. Letting 𝛼(𝑥) = 𝑦 𝑘−1 and 𝜔(𝑥) = 𝑦 𝑘 for 𝑥 ∈ 𝐴 𝑘 , then 𝛼(𝑥) ⩽ 𝑓 (𝑥) ⩽ 𝜔(𝑥) ∀ 𝑥 ∈ [𝑎, 𝑏] (effectively,
we are created a “series of squeezes”). Then,
∫ 𝑏 𝑞
Õ
𝜔(𝑥) − 𝛼(𝑥) d𝑥 = (𝑦 𝑘 − 𝑦 𝑘−1 )(𝑥 𝑘 − 𝑥 𝑘−1 ) = ℎ(𝑏 − 𝑎) < 𝜀,
𝑎 𝑘=1
Proof See book. Remark that this holds for finite summations of integrals as such by induction.
Proof
Proof. ■
↩→ Definition 5.4
Call 𝐹(𝑥) a primitive of 𝑓 (𝑥) if 𝐹 differential and 𝐹′(𝑥) = 𝑓 (𝑥).
1. 𝐹 continuous on [𝑎, 𝑏]
2. 𝐹′(𝑥) = 𝑓 (𝑥) ∀ 𝑥 ∈ [𝑎, 𝑏] \ 𝐸; ie they agree for all but finitely many points
3. 𝑓 ∈ ℛ[𝑎, 𝑏]
∫𝑏
Then, 𝑎
𝑓 (𝑥) = 𝐹(𝑏) − 𝐹(𝑎).
Proof (Sketch) Remark first that it suffices to prove for 𝐸 ..= {𝑎, 𝑏}; using additivity, we can subdivide any
Proof
Proof.
other such 𝐸 into such subsets of 1 or 2 elements.
∫𝑏
Fix 𝜀 > 0 and take 𝛿 > 0 such that for any 𝑃¤ of [𝑎, 𝑏] s.t. diam 𝑃¤ < 𝛿, 𝑆( 𝑓 , 𝑃)
¤ −
𝑎
𝑓 (𝑥) < 𝜀. Applying the
¤
mean value theorem to 𝐹 on each [𝑥 𝑖−1 , 𝑥 𝑖 ] of 𝑃:
𝐹(𝑎) 𝐹(𝑏)
𝐹(𝑥 1 ) −
𝐹(𝑥 ) + 𝐹(𝑥2 ) − 𝐹(𝑥1 ) + · · · +
𝐹(𝑥
𝑛) − 𝐹(𝑥 𝑛−1 ) = 𝑓 (𝑢1 )(𝑥 1 − 𝑎) + · · · + 𝑓 (𝑢𝑛 )(𝑥 𝑛 − 𝑥 𝑛−1 )
*
*
0
𝑛
Õ
=⇒ 𝐹(𝑏) − 𝐹(𝑎) = 𝑓 (𝑢𝑖 )(𝑥 𝑖 − 𝑥 𝑖+1 ) =: 𝑆( 𝑓 , 𝑃¤1 )
𝑖=1
∫𝑏
by construction, diam(𝑃¤1 ) < 𝛿 since the only change we have made from 𝑃¤ is the tags, hence 𝑆( 𝑓 , 𝑃¤1 ) − 𝑎
𝑓 (𝑥) <
𝜀. Thus,
∫ 𝑏 ∫ 𝑏
𝑆( 𝑓 , 𝑃¤1 ) − 𝑓 (𝑥) = 𝐹(𝑏) − 𝐹(𝑎) − 𝑓 (𝑥) < 𝜀
𝑎 𝑎
∫ 𝑏
=⇒ 𝐹(𝑏) − 𝐹(𝑎) = 𝑓 (𝑥) as 𝜀 → 0.
𝑎
■
↩→ Lecture 18; Last Updated: Thu Mar 28 09:07:47 EDT 2024
Í𝑛
• 𝑆( 𝑓 , 𝑃) ..= 𝑖=1 (sup𝑡∈[𝑥 𝑖−1 ,𝑥 𝑖 ] 𝑓 (𝑡)) · (𝑥 𝑖 − 𝑥 𝑖−1 )
Í𝑛
• SS( 𝑓 , 𝑃) ..= 𝑖=1 (inf𝑡∈[𝑥 𝑖−1 ,𝑥 𝑖 ] 𝑓 (𝑡)) · (𝑥 𝑖 − 𝑥 𝑖−1 )
↩→Proposition 5.4
¤
For any tagged partition 𝑃,
SS( 𝑓 , 𝑃) ⩽ 𝑆( 𝑓 , 𝑃)
¤ ⩽ 𝑆( 𝑓 , 𝑃).
Proof (Sketch) Remark that this is a similar idea to saying that inf = sup =⇒ limit exists.
Proof
Proof. ■
↩→Proposition 5.5
Let 𝑃1 , 𝑃2 be partitions of [𝑎, 𝑏], and let 𝑃3 be the common refinement of 𝑃1 , 𝑃2 . Then
SS( 𝑓 , 𝑃𝑖 ) ⩽ SS( 𝑓 , 𝑃3 ) ⩽ 𝑆( 𝑓 , 𝑃3 ) ⩽ 𝑆( 𝑓 , 𝑃𝑖 ), 𝑖 = 1, 2,
↩→ Definition 5.6
For 𝑓 ∈ ℛ[𝑎, 𝑏] and any 𝑧 ∈ [𝑎, 𝑏], define
∫ 𝑧
..
𝐹(𝑧) = 𝑓 (𝑥) d𝑥 .
𝑎
↩→ Theorem 5.7
𝐹(𝑧) continuous on [𝑎, 𝑏].
Proof 𝑓 ∈ ℛ[𝑎, 𝑏] =⇒ 𝑓 bounded =⇒ ∃𝑀 s.t. | 𝑓 (𝑥)| ⩽ 𝑀 ∀ 𝑥 ∈ [𝑎, 𝑏], so (assuming 𝑧 < 𝑤),
Proof
Proof.
∫ 𝑧 ∫ 𝑤 ∫ 𝑤
|𝐹(𝑧) − 𝐹(𝑤)| = 𝑓 (𝑥) d𝑥 − 𝑓 (𝑥) d𝑥 = 𝑓 (𝑥) d𝑥 ⩽ 𝑀 · |𝑧 − 𝑤| ,
𝑎 𝑎 𝑧
↩→ Corollary 5.1
If 𝑓 (𝑥) continuous on [𝑎, 𝑏] 𝐹′(𝑥) = 𝑓 (𝑥) ∀ 𝑥 ∈ [𝑎, 𝑏].
⊛ Example 5.1
∫ 4 sin(√𝑡 )
Compute 1
√ d𝑡 using the previous theorem.
𝑡
For some set 𝑆 ⊆ R and statement 𝑃, we say “𝑃 holds for almost every 𝑥 ∈ 𝑆” if {𝑥 ∈ 𝑆 : 𝑃 false } has
Lebesgue measure 0.
⊛ Example 5.2
1. Any countable set is a null set.
Remark 5.1. The proof is rather involved, but is in the appendix of Bartle. Its important to remark that this is a necessary
and sufficient condition.
⊛ Example 5.3
1 𝑥 ∈ Q
..
1. Let 𝑓 : [0, 1] → R, 𝑓 (𝑥) = . 𝑓 discontinuous everywhere, so 𝑓 ∉ ℛ[𝑎, 𝑏].
0 𝑥 ∉ Q
𝑏1 𝑥= 𝑎
∈ Q s.t. (𝑎, 𝑏) = 1
𝑏
..
2. Let 𝑓 (𝑥) = . One can show that 𝑓 continuous on 𝑥 ∈ R \ Q and
𝑥∉Q 0
only discontinuous on Q. But this is a countable set so certainly has Lebesgue measure 0 and
so 𝑓 ∈ ℛ[0, 1].
Proof
Proof
Proof.
{𝑥 s.t. 𝜑 ◦ 𝑓 discontinuous at 𝑥} ⊆ {𝑥 : 𝑓 discontinuous at 𝑥}
since 𝜑 continuous. The RHS has Lebesgue measure 0, and thus so does the LHS, hence the proof. ■
Proof 𝑓 · 𝑔 = 41 ( 𝑓 + 𝑔)2 − ( 𝑓 − 𝑔)2 . 𝑓 ± 𝑔 ∈ ℛ[𝑎, 𝑏] and so so is ( 𝑓 ± 𝑔)2 by taking 𝜑(𝑥) ..= 𝑥 2 as in the
Proof
Proof.
previous theorem. It follows that 𝑓 · 𝑔 ∈ ℛ[𝑎, 𝑏]. ■
and so
∫ 𝑏 ∫ 𝑏
𝐹(𝑥)𝐺(𝑥)| 𝑏𝑎 = 𝑓 𝐺 d𝑥 + 𝐹 𝑔 d𝑥
𝑎 𝑎
∫ 𝑏 ∫ 𝑏
=⇒ 𝑓 (𝑥)𝐺(𝑥) d𝑥 = 𝐹(𝑥)𝐺(𝑥)| 𝑏𝑎 − 𝐹(𝑥)𝑔(𝑥) d𝑥 ,
𝑎 𝑎
8Remark that this is a weaker condition than continuity as was used in our previous statement of Taylor’s theorem.
⊛ Example 6.1
2𝑛𝑥 0 ⩽ 𝑥 ⩽
1
2𝑛
. Show that 𝑓𝑛 → 0 pointwise but not uniformly (hint: 𝑓𝑛 ( 21𝑛 ) = 1 ∀ 𝑛).
..
Let 𝑓𝑛 =
0 1
𝑥 > 2𝑛
↩→ Theorem 6.1
The space of functions 𝐶([𝑎, 𝑏]) equipped with the sup norm is complete.
Proof This is a rather painful proof; one needs to make use of the “multiple epsilons” from each given
Proof
Proof.
continuity/convergence/differentiability statement. ■
↩→ Lecture 20; Last Updated: Wed Apr 10 13:31:53 EDT 2024
↩→ Theorem 6.3
∫𝑏 ∫𝑏
Let 𝑓𝑛 ∈ ℛ[𝑎, 𝑏], 𝑓𝑛 → 𝑓 uniformly on [𝑎, 𝑏]. Then, 𝑓 ∈ ℛ[𝑎, 𝑏] and 𝑎
𝑓𝑛 (𝑥) d𝑥 → 𝑎
𝑓 (𝑥) d𝑥.
∞
Õ ∞
Õ
𝑥 𝑗 converges absolutely ⇐⇒ ||𝑥 𝑗 || < +∞.
𝑗=1 𝑗=1
↩→ Theorem 6.6
Any rearrangement of absolutely convergent series given the same sum.
↩→ Theorem 6.7
Í∞
If 𝑖=1 𝑎 𝑖 ∈ R conditionally convergent, you can change the order of summation such that ∀ 𝑥 ∈ R,
Í∞
∃𝜎-permutation such that 𝑖=1 𝑎 𝜋(𝑖) = 𝑥.
Proof (Sketch) Separate 𝑎 𝑖 into positive, negative parts. Since conditionally convergent, 𝑎 𝑗 >0 𝑎 𝑗 = +∞ and
Í
Proof.
Proof
𝑎 𝑗 <0 𝑎 𝑗 = −∞. Add positive 𝑎 𝑖 ’s until the partial sum ⩾ 𝑥, then add negative 𝑎 𝑖 ’s until the partial sum ⩽ 𝑥,
Í
and repeat. The final rearrangement will converge as desired. ■
↩→ Lecture 22; Last Updated: Thu Mar 28 12:14:46 EDT 2024
↩→ Theorem 6.8
𝑣® 𝑖 ∈ R𝑛 , converges, but
Í∞ Í∞ Í∞
Suppose 𝑖=1 𝑣
®𝑖 , 𝑖=1 𝑣 𝑖 || = +∞. Then, the set of rearranged sums
||® 𝑖=1 𝑣
® 𝜎(𝑖) for
each 𝜎 : N ↔ N permutation form an affine subspace of R𝑛 .
↩→Proposition 6.1
𝑥𝑛
Let 𝑥 𝑛 , 𝑦𝑛 be sequences and 𝑟 ..= lim𝑛→∞ 𝑦𝑛 .
Í∞ Í∞
1. If 𝑟 ≠ 0, 𝑛=1 𝑥 𝑛 converges absolutely iff 𝑛=1 𝑦𝑛 converges absolutely. In addition, if 0 < 𝑟1 ..=
𝑥𝑛 𝑥𝑛
lim inf 𝑦𝑛 ⩽ lim sup 𝑦𝑛 =: 𝑟2 < +∞, this still holds.
𝑥 𝑛+1
If ⩾ 1 for 𝑛 ⩾ 𝐾, 𝑥 𝑛 diverges.
Í
𝑥𝑛
𝑥 𝑛+1
1. Suppose ∃𝑎 > 1 s.t. ⩽ 1 − 𝑛1 , 𝑛 ⩾ 𝐾. Then 𝑥 𝑛 converges absolutely.
Í
𝑥𝑛
𝑥 𝑛+1
2. If ∃𝑎 ⩽ 1 s.t. ⩾ 1 − 𝑛1 , 𝑛 ⩾ 𝐾. Then 𝑥 𝑛 does not converge absolutely.
Í
𝑥𝑛
↩→ Corollary 6.1
𝑥 𝑛+1
Let 𝑎 ..= lim 𝑛(1 − ), if such a limit exists. Then, if 𝑎 > 1, 𝑥 𝑛 converges absolutely, and if 𝑎 < 1,
Í
𝑥𝑛
𝑥 𝑛 does not.
Í
𝑚
Õ 𝑚
Õ
𝑥 𝑘 𝑦 𝑘 = 𝑥 𝑚 𝑠 𝑚 − 𝑥 𝑛+1 𝑠 𝑛+1 + (𝑥 𝑘 − 𝑥 𝑘+1 )𝑠 𝑘
𝑘=𝑛+1 𝑘=𝑛+1
𝑚
Õ 𝑚−1
Õ
𝑥 𝑘 𝑦 𝑘 ⩽ |𝑥 𝑚 𝑠 𝑚 − 𝑥 𝑛+1 𝑠 𝑛 | + 𝑠 𝑘 (𝑥 𝑘 − 𝑥 𝑘+1 )
𝑘=𝑛+1 𝑘=𝑛+1
𝑚−1
Õ
⩽ 𝑥 𝑚 𝐵 + 𝑥 𝑛+1 𝐵 + (𝑥 𝑘 − 𝑥 𝑘+1 )𝐵
𝑘=𝑛+1
| {z }
telescopes
= 2𝑥 𝑛+1 𝐵 → 0.
𝑛→∞
■
Remark 6.2. What is red and commutes? An abelian grape!
We say the convergence 𝑛 𝑓𝑛 (𝑥) → 𝑔(𝑥) is uniform if the convergence is uniform for any 𝑥 ∈ 𝐸; that
Í
∫ 𝑏 ∞ ∫
Õ 𝑏
𝑔(𝑥) d𝑥 = 𝑓𝑛 (𝑥) d𝑥 .
𝑎 𝑛=1 𝑎
That is, the integral of the limit is equal to the limit of the integral.
↩→Proposition 6.8
Let 𝑓𝑛 : [𝑎, 𝑏] → R where 𝑓𝑛′ ∃ on [𝑎, 𝑏]. Suppose 𝑛 𝑓𝑛 (𝑥) converges for some 𝑥 ∈ [𝑎, 𝑏] and 𝑛 𝑓𝑛 (𝑥)
′
Í Í
converges uniformly on [𝑎, 𝑏]. Then there exists some 𝑔 : [𝑎, 𝑏] → R such that 𝑛 𝑓𝑛 → 𝑔 uniformly on
Í
of the derivatives.
Í𝑚 Í𝑚
Proof. Suffices to look at the tail:
Proof 𝑗=𝑛+1 | 𝑓𝑛 (𝑥)| ⩽ 𝑗=𝑛+1 𝑀𝑗. ■
1/𝑛
Proof Directly apply the root test; assume 𝑐 = 0. Then |𝑎 𝑛 𝑥 𝑛 |
Proof
Proof. = |𝑎 𝑛 | 1/𝑛 |𝑥|. If |𝑥| < 𝜌, then lim sup |𝑎 𝑛 | 1/𝑛 |𝑥| <
𝜌 𝜌1 = 1 so ∀ 𝜀 > 0, ∃𝑁 s.t. ∀ 𝑛 ⩾ 𝑁, |𝑎 𝑛 | 1/𝑛 |𝑥| < 1 − 𝜀 =⇒ |𝑎 𝑛 | |𝑥| 𝑛 < (1 − 𝜀)𝑛 . It follows that
|𝑎 𝑛 𝑥 𝑛 | < 𝑗 ⩾ 𝑁 (1 − 𝜀) 𝑗 . But this RHS is a geometric series with 𝑟 < 1 so thus converges. The con-
Í Í
𝑗 ⩾𝑁
verse follows similarly (well, backwards). ■
⊛ Example 6.3
1. 1 + 𝑥 + 𝑥 2 + · · · converges absolutely for |𝑥| < 1.
𝑥2 𝑥3
2. 1 + 𝑥 + 2 + 3 + · · · converges for −1 ⩽ 𝑥 < 1.
𝑥𝑛
3. with 𝑘 ⩾ 2 converges for −1 ⩽ 𝑥 ⩽ 1 (check the 𝑥 = 1 case by comparison test, then the
Í
𝑛 𝑛𝑘
𝑥 = −1 test follows by alternating series test.)
↩→ Theorem 6.13
Let 𝐽 be a closed and bounded interval strictly contained in the interval of convergence of ⊛ . Then 𝑓 (𝑥)
converges uniformly in 𝐽.
↩→ Theorem 7.1
Let (𝑋 , 𝑑) be a compact metric space.9 Let 𝐶(𝑋) := { 𝑓 : 𝑋 → R : 𝑓 continuous} be a vector space. Take
the uniform norm || 𝑓 || := sup𝑥∈𝑋 | 𝑓 (𝑥)| on 𝐶(𝑥). Then, (𝐶(𝑥), || • ||) is complete.10
Define, for this fixed 𝑥, a sequence in R { 𝑓𝑛 (𝑥)} 𝑛∈N . By ∗1 , we have that this sequence is Cauchy in R, but as R
complete, 𝑓𝑛 (𝑥) hence converges, to some limit we call 𝑓 (𝑥) := lim𝑛→∞ 𝑓𝑛 (𝑥). Note that 𝑥 is still fixed at this
point; these are but real numbers we are working with here.
Now, as 𝑥 was completely arbitrary, we can repeat this process for all of 𝑋, and define a function 𝑓 : 𝑋 → R
where 𝑓 (𝑥) := lim𝑛→∞ 𝑓𝑛 (𝑥).
For a fixed 𝑥, we have that 𝑓𝑚 (𝑥) → 𝑓 (𝑥) as 𝑚 → ∞. This implies:
=⇒ | 𝑓𝑛 (𝑥) − 𝑓 (𝑥)| ⩽ 𝜀 ∀ 𝑛 ⩾ 𝑁
=⇒ 𝜌( 𝑓𝑛 , 𝑓 ) = sup | 𝑓𝑛 (𝑥) − 𝑓 (𝑥)| ⩽ 𝜀 =⇒ 𝑓𝑛 → 𝑓
𝑥∈𝑋
It remains to show that 𝑓 ∈ 𝐶(𝑋). Let 𝑐 ∈ 𝑋 and 𝜀 > 0, and the corresponding 𝑁 ∈ N : 𝜌( 𝑓𝑛 , 𝑓 ) < 3𝜀 ∀ 𝑛 ⩾ 𝑁.
By construction, 𝑓𝑁 ∈ 𝐶(𝑋), and is thus continuous at 𝑐. This gives that ∃𝛿 > 0 : | 𝑓𝑁 (𝑥) − 𝑓𝑁 (𝑐)| < 3𝜀 whenever
𝑑(𝑥, 𝑐) < 𝛿. 11
Hence, if 𝑑(𝑥, 𝑐) < 𝛿, we have
↩→ Theorem 7.3
Let (𝑋 , 𝑑)-complete, and 𝑓 : 𝑋 → 𝑋 an “expanding map”, such that 𝑑(𝑥, 𝑦) ⩽ 𝑑( 𝑓 (𝑥), 𝑓 (𝑦)) ∀ 𝑥, 𝑦 ∈ 𝑋.
Then, 𝑓 is a surjective isometry, ie, 𝑓 (𝑋) = 𝑋 and 𝑑( 𝑓 (𝑥), 𝑓 (𝑦)) = 𝑑(𝑥, 𝑦) ∀ 𝑥, 𝑦 ∈ 𝑋.
↩→ Lemma 7.1
Differentiable =⇒ Continuous.
𝑓 (𝑥)− 𝑓 (𝑐)
Proof Let 𝑓 : 𝐼 → R, and 𝑐 ∈ 𝐼 arbitrary. Notice that ∀ 𝑥 ≠ 𝑐 ∈ 𝐼, 𝑓 (𝑥) − 𝑓 (𝑐) = (𝑥 − 𝑐)
Proof
Proof. 𝑥−𝑐 . Hence,
𝑓 (𝑥) − 𝑓 (𝑐)
lim ( 𝑓 (𝑥) − 𝑓 (𝑐)) = lim (𝑥 − 𝑐)
𝑥→𝑐 𝑥→𝑐 𝑥−𝑐
𝑓 (𝑥) − 𝑓 (𝑐)
= lim (𝑥 − 𝑐) · lim
𝑥→𝑐 𝑥→𝑐 𝑥−𝑐
′
= 0 · 𝑓 (𝑥) = 0
=⇒ lim 𝑓 (𝑥) = 𝑓 (𝑐),
𝑥→𝑐
hence 𝑓 continuous, noting that the splitting of the limits is valid as both are defined. ■
𝑥2 𝑥∈Q
Let 𝑓 : R → R, 𝑓 (𝑥) :=
0
𝑥∉Q
Claim: 𝑓 discontinuous at all 𝑥 ≠ 0.
Claim:
lim 𝑓 (𝑧 𝑛 ) = lim 0,
𝑛→∞
Claim: 𝑓 ′(0) = 0.
Claim:
Proof Let 𝜀 > 0 and 𝛿 = 𝜀. Notice that 𝑓 (𝑥) ⩽ 𝑥 2 ∀ 𝑥. Then, we have that ∀ |𝑥| < 𝛿,
Proof
Proof.
↩→ Definition 7.1
Let 𝑓 : 𝐼 → R. A point 𝑐 ∈ 𝐼 is a local max (resp min) if ∃𝛿 > 0 s.t. 𝑓 (𝑥) ⩽ 𝑓 (𝑐) (resp 𝑓 (𝑥) ⩾ 𝑓 (𝑐))
∀ 𝑥 ∈ (𝑐 − 𝛿, 𝑐 + 𝛿) ∩ 𝐼.
↩→ Lemma 7.2
Let 𝑓 : 𝐼 → R be differentiable at 𝑐 ∈ 𝐼 ◦ . If 𝑐 a local extrema of 𝑓 , then 𝑓 ′(𝑐) = 0.
Proof Assume wlog that 𝑐 a local max; if a local min, take 𝑓˜ := − 𝑓 and continue.
Proof
Proof.
Since 𝐼 ◦ open, ∃𝛿1 > 0 : (𝑐 − 𝛿 1 , 𝑐 + 𝛿 1 ) ⊆ 𝐼 ◦ ⊆ 𝐼. We also have that ∃𝛿 2 > 0 : 𝑓 (𝑥) ⩽ 𝑓 (𝑐) ∀ 𝑥 ∈
(𝑐 − 𝛿2 , 𝑐 + 𝛿2 ) ∩ 𝐼, by 𝑐 an extrema.
Let 𝛿 := min{𝛿1 , 𝛿2 }. Then, we have both (𝑐 − 𝛿, 𝑐 + 𝛿) ⊆ 𝐼 and 𝑓 (𝑥) ⩽ 𝑓 (𝑐) ∀ 𝑥 ∈ (𝑐 − 𝛿, 𝑐 + 𝛿).
𝑓 (𝑥)− 𝑓 (𝑐) 𝑓 (𝑥)− 𝑓 (𝑐)
Since 𝑓 ′(𝑐) exists, lim𝑥→𝑐 + 𝑥−𝑐 = lim𝑥→𝑐 − 𝑥−𝑐 . But we have from the property of being a maximum
hence, as these two limits must agree, they must equal 0 and thus 𝑓 ′(𝑐) = 0. ■
7.2 Miscellaneous
𝑓 (𝑥) − 𝑓 (𝑦)
| 𝑓 (𝑥) − 𝑓 (𝑦)| ⩽ (𝑥 − 𝑦)2 =⇒ ⩽ 𝑥 − 𝑦 = |𝑥 − 𝑦| → 0 as 𝑦 → 𝑥
𝑥−𝑦
𝑓 (𝑥) − 𝑓 (𝑦)
=⇒ →0
𝑥−𝑦
This implies, then, that 𝑓 ′(𝑥) is defined ∀ 𝑥 ∈ R, and moreover, that 𝑓 ′(𝑥) = 0 ∀ 𝑥 ∈ R. We
conclude, then, that 𝑓 (𝑥) constant ∀ 𝑥 ∈ R. ■
2. Suppose 𝑓 ′(𝑥) > 0 in (𝑎, 𝑏). Prove that 𝑓 is strictly increasing in (𝑎, 𝑏), and let 𝑔 be its inverse
function. Prove that 𝑔 is differentiable, and that
1
𝑔 ′( 𝑓 (𝑥)) = (𝑎 < 𝑥 < 𝑏).
𝑓 ′(𝑥)
𝑓 (𝑥)− 𝑓 (𝑦)
Proof Fix 𝑥 > 𝑦 ∈ (𝑎, 𝑏). Then, by the mean value theorem, ∃𝑧 ∈ (𝑥, 𝑦) : 𝑓 ′(𝑧) =
Proof
Proof. 𝑥−𝑦 .
Since 𝑓 ′(𝑧) > 0, it follows that
𝑓 (𝑥) − 𝑓 (𝑦)
> 0 =⇒ 𝑓 (𝑥) − 𝑓 (𝑦) > 𝑥 − 𝑦 > 0 =⇒ 𝑓 (𝑥) > 𝑓 (𝑦),
𝑥−𝑦
12Note that this means that 𝑓 Hölder continuous with constant 𝛼 = 2. Indeed, Hölder continuous functions with 𝛼 > 1 are always
constant by a similar proof. For 0 < 𝛼 ⩽ 1, we have the inclusion continuously differentiable =⇒ Lipschitz =⇒ 𝛼−Hölder =⇒
uniformly continuous =⇒ continuous.
↩→ Question 7.1
Let 𝑋 be a topological space, and let 𝑓 , 𝑔 : 𝑋 → R be two continuous functions. Show that the set
{𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 : 𝑓 (𝑥) > 𝑔(𝑥)} is an open subset of 𝑋.
Proof Let 𝐴 ..= {𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 : 𝑓 (𝑥) > 𝑔(𝑥)}. Letting 𝜑(𝑥) ..= 𝑓 (𝑥) − 𝑔(𝑥) = ( 𝑓 − 𝑔)(𝑥), then remark that
Proof
Proof.
𝐴 ≡ {𝑥 ∈ 𝑋 : 𝜑(𝑥) > 0}, and since differences of continuous functions are continuous, 𝜑 continuous.
Letting 𝐵 ..= (0, ∞) ⊆ R, then, we have that 𝐴 = 𝜑−1 (𝐵). But 𝐵 an open set, and the inverse images of
open sets by continuous functions are open, hence 𝐴 open. ■
↩→ Question 7.2
(a) List three equivalent properties (definitions) of compact sets in metric spaces; you don’t need to
prove anything.
(b) Is the unit ball13 in the space ℓ 2 of infinite sequences compact? Prove or disprove. You may use any
of the properties from (a).
Proof
Proof.
Proof (a) Every open cover admits a finite subcover ⇐⇒ sequentially compact ⇐⇒ complete and
totally bounded.
(b) Denote the closed unit ball centered at (0, 0, . . . ) in ℓ 2 , 𝐵 ..= {𝑥 ∈ ℓ 2 : 𝑑22 (0, 𝑥) =
Í∞
𝑖=1 |𝑥 𝑖 | ⩽ 1}.
Consider the sequence of “unit sequences”
{𝑒 𝑛 } 𝑛∈N ∈ 𝐵, 𝑒 𝑖𝑛 ..= 𝛿 𝑖𝑛 .
√
Then, for any 𝑖 ≠ 𝑗, 𝑑2 (𝑒 𝑛 , 𝑒 𝑚 ) = 2 > 1. It follows that, although 𝑒 𝑛 ∈ 𝐵 for any 𝑛, there cannot exist
a subsequence of 𝑥 𝑛 that converges within 𝐵 (verify why this is!). Thus, 𝐵 cannot be sequentially
compact and thus not compact.
(d) Does 𝑓 have a fixed point in the open interval 𝐼 = (0, 1)? Does that contradict the contraction
mapping theorem?
Proof
Proof. (a) A complete metric space is a metric space in which every Cauchy sequence converges within
that space.
(b) Let (𝑋 , 𝑑) be a complete metric space, and let 𝑓 : 𝑋 → 𝑋 be a contraction mapping, ie for any
𝑥, 𝑦 ∈ 𝑋, 𝑑( 𝑓 (𝑥), 𝑓 (𝑦)) ⩽ 𝑐 · 𝑑(𝑥, 𝑦) for some 𝑐 ∈ (0, 1). Then, the contraction mapping states that 𝑓
has a unique fixed point 𝑧 ∈ 𝑋, ie 𝑓 (𝑧) = 𝑧 and lim𝑛→∞ 𝑓 (𝑛) (𝑥) = 𝑧 for any 𝑥.
𝑥−𝑦 1
𝑑( 𝑓 (𝑥), 𝑓 (𝑦)) = | 𝑓 (𝑥) − 𝑓 (𝑦)| = = |𝑥 − 𝑦| = 𝑐 · 𝑑(𝑥, 𝑦),
2 2
𝑥 𝑥 𝑥
(d) We have that for any 𝑥 ∈ 𝐼, 𝑓 (𝑛) (𝑥) = 2𝑛 so 𝑥 a fixed point iff 2𝑛 = 2𝑛−1
for some 𝑛, which is only
possible if 𝑥 = 0, but 0 ∉ 𝐼, so indeed 𝑓 has no fixed point in 𝐼. This is not a contradiction to the
1 1
contraction mapping theorem since 𝐼 ..= (0, 1) not complete (indeed, 𝑛 ∈ 𝐼 ∀ 𝑛 but 𝑛 → 0 ∉ 𝐼).
Proof
Proof.
Proof (a) Holder’s inequality: for 𝑝, 𝑞 Holder conjugates and 𝑥 ∈ ℓ 𝑝 , 𝑦 ∈ ℓ 𝑞 we have
Õ
𝑥 𝑖 𝑦 𝑖 ⩽ ||𝑥|| 𝑝 ||𝑦|| 𝑞 .
𝑖=1
(b) For 𝑥, 𝑦 as given; by Holders, 𝑥 · 𝑦 ⩽ ||𝑥|| 𝑝 ||𝑦|| 𝑞 = 2 · 3 = 6, and by Minkowski’s, ||𝑥 + 𝑦|| ⩽
||𝑥|| + ||𝑦|| = 2 + 3 = 5, so 6, 5 are upper bounds for 𝑥 · 𝑦, ||𝑥 + 𝑦|| respectively.
(b) Let 𝑓 ∈ 𝐶 4 ([0, 2]), and let 𝑓 ′(1) = 𝑓 ′′(1) = 𝑓 ′′′(1) = 0 while 𝑓 (4) (1) = 2. Use (a) to show that 𝑓 (𝑥) has
a local extremum at 𝑥 = 1, and determine its type.
Proof
Proof.
Proof (a) Let 𝐼 ..= [𝑎, 𝑏] ⊆ R and let 𝑓 : 𝐼 → R such that 𝑓 ∈ 𝐶 𝑛 (𝐼), and 𝑓 (𝑛+1) (𝑥) exists on (𝑎, 𝑏). Then,
for 𝑥0 ∈ [𝑎, 𝑏], there exists some 𝑐 ∈ (min(𝑥, 𝑥0 ), max(𝑥, 𝑥0 )) such that
(b) By Taylor’s, for any 𝑥 ∈ [0, 2], there exists some 𝑐 between 𝑥 and 1 such that
𝑓 (4) (𝑐)
𝑓 (𝑥) = 𝑓 (1) + 𝑓 ′(1)(· · · ) + 𝑓 ′′(1)(· · · ) + 𝑓 ′′′(1)(· · · ) + (𝑥 − 1)4
| {z } 4!
=0
𝑓 (4) (𝑐)
= 𝑓 (1) + (𝑥 − 1)4
4!
𝑓 (4) (𝑐)
=⇒ 𝑓 (𝑥) − 𝑓 (1) ⩾ (𝑥 − 1)4 ∀ 𝑥 ∈ [0, 2]
4!
By continuity of 𝑓 (4) , there exists some neighborhood 𝑉 of 𝑥0 = 1 such that 𝑓 (4) (𝑐) has the same
𝑓 (4) (𝑐) 𝑓 (4)(1) 2
sign of 𝑓 (4) (1). So, for any 𝑥 ∈ 𝑉, 4! ⩾ 0, since 4! = 4! ⩾ 0. Thus, since (𝑥 − 1)4 ⩾ 0, we have
that for such 𝑥 in 𝑉,
𝑓 (𝑥) − 𝑓 (1) ⩾ 0 =⇒ 𝑓 (𝑥) ⩾ 𝑓 (1).
Hence, we have a neighborhood of 1 such that for all 𝑥 in the neighborhood 𝑓 (𝑥) ⩾ 𝑓 (1). It follows
that 1 a local minimum of 𝑓 .
63
↩→ Lemma 2.3 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 19
↩→ Theorem 2.4 (“Intermediate Value Theorem”) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 19
↩→ Theorem 2.5 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 19
↩→ Theorem 2.6 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 20
↩→ Definition 2.16 (Path Connected) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 20
↩→ Theorem 2.7 (Path connected =⇒ connected) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 20
↩→Proposition 2.18 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 20
↩→ Definition 2.17 (Connected Component) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 21
↩→ Definition 2.18 (Path Component) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 21
↩→Proposition 2.19 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 21
↩→ Lemma 2.4 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 21
↩→ Lemma 2.5 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 21
↩→ Lemma 2.6 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 21
↩→Proposition 2.20 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 22
↩→Proposition 2.21 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 22
↩→ Definition 2.19 (An Explicit Definition) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 22
↩→ Definition 2.20 (Complement Definition) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 22
↩→ Definition 3.1 (Hölder Conjugates) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 23
↩→Proposition 3.1 (Hölder’s Inequality) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 23
↩→ Lemma 3.1 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 24
↩→Proposition 3.2 (Minkowski Inequality) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 26
↩→ Theorem 3.1 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 27
↩→ Definition 3.2 (Complete Metric Space) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 27
↩→Proposition 3.3 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 27
↩→Proposition 3.4 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 28
↩→Proposition 3.5 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 28
↩→Proposition 3.6 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 28
↩→ Definition 3.3 (Contraction Mapping) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 29
↩→ Theorem 3.2 (Contraction Mapping Theorem) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 29
↩→ Theorem 3.3 (ℓ 𝑝 complete) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 30
↩→ Definition 3.4 (Totally Bounded) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 32
↩→ Theorem 3.4 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 32
↩→ Lemma 3.1 (Cantor Intersection Theorem) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 32
↩→ Definition 3.5 (Finite Intersection Property) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 33
↩→ Lemma 3.2 (Finite Interesection Formulation of Compactness) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 33
↩→ Lemma 3.3 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 33
↩→ Lemma 3.4 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 33
↩→ Theorem 3.5 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 34
↩→ Definition 4.1 (Differentiable) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 35
↩→ Definition 4.2 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 35
↩→ Theorem 4.1 (Caratheodory’s Theorem) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 35
↩→ Theorem 4.2 (Chain Rule) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 36
↩→ Definition 4.3 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 36
↩→ Theorem 4.3 (Rolle’s) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 36
↩→ Theorem 4.4 (Gauss-Lucas) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 36
↩→ Definition 4.4 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 37
↩→ Theorem 4.5 (Mean Value) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 37
↩→ Theorem 4.6 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 38
↩→Proposition 4.1 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 38
↩→ Lemma 4.1 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 38
64
↩→ Theorem 4.7 (Darboux) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 38
↩→Proposition 4.2 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 38
↩→ Theorem 4.8 (Cauchy Mean Value) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 39
↩→Proposition 4.3 (More General L’Hopital) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 39
↩→Proposition 4.4 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 39
↩→ Theorem 4.9 (Taylor’s Theorem) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 39
↩→ Theorem 4.10 (Relative Extrema) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 40
↩→ Definition 4.5 (Convex Set) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 40
↩→ Definition 4.6 (Convex Function) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 40
↩→ Definition 5.1 (Partitions) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 40
↩→ Definition 5.2 (Riemann Sum) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 41
↩→ Definition 5.3 (Riemann Integrable) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 41
↩→Proposition 5.1 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 41
↩→Proposition 5.2 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 41
↩→Proposition 5.3 (Cauchy Criterion for Integrability) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 42
↩→ Theorem 5.1 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 42
↩→ Lemma 5.1 (BS-7.2.4) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 42
↩→ Theorem 5.2 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 43
↩→ Theorem 5.3 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 43
↩→ Theorem 5.4 (BS-7.2.7) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 43
↩→ Theorem 5.5 (Additivity; BS-7.2.8) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 43
↩→ Definition 5.4 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 44
↩→ Theorem 5.6 (Fundamental Theorem of Calculus) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 44
↩→ Definition 5.5 (Upper/Lower Riemann Sums) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 45
↩→Proposition 5.4 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 45
↩→Proposition 5.5 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 45
↩→ Definition 5.6 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 45
↩→ Theorem 5.7 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 45
↩→ Theorem 5.8 (Another Fundamental Theorem of Calculus) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 46
↩→ Corollary 5.1 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 46
↩→ Theorem 5.9 (Substitution/Change of Variables) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 46
↩→ Definition 5.7 (Lebesgue Measure 0) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 46
↩→ Theorem 5.10 (Lebesgue Integrability Criterion) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 47
↩→ Theorem 5.11 (Composition) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 47
↩→ Theorem 5.12 (Product Theorem) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 47
↩→ Theorem 5.13 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 48
↩→ Theorem 5.14 (Taylor’s Theorem, Remainder’s Version) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 48
↩→ Definition 6.1 (Pointwise vs Uniform Convergence) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 49
↩→ Theorem 6.1 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 49
↩→ Theorem 6.2 (Interchange of Limits) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 49
↩→ Theorem 6.3 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 49
↩→ Theorem 6.4 (Bounded Convergence Theorem) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 49
↩→ Theorem 6.5 (Dimi’s Theorem/Monotone Convergence) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 49
↩→ Definition 6.2 (Absolute Convergence) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 50
↩→ Theorem 6.6 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 50
↩→ Definition 6.3 (Conditional Convergence) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 50
↩→ Theorem 6.7 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 50
↩→ Theorem 6.8 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 50
↩→Proposition 6.1 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 50
↩→Proposition 6.2 (Root Test) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 51
65
↩→Proposition 6.3 (Ratio Test) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 51
↩→Proposition 6.4 (Integral Test) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 51
↩→Proposition 6.5 (Raube’s Test) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 51
↩→ Corollary 6.1 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 51
↩→Proposition 6.6 (Alternating Series) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 51
↩→ Lemma 6.1 (Abel’s Lemma) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 51
↩→ Theorem 6.9 (Dirichlet’s Test) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 52
↩→ Theorem 6.10 (Abel’s Test) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 52
↩→ Definition 6.4 (Convergence) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 52
↩→Proposition 6.7 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 53
↩→Proposition 6.8 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 53
↩→ Theorem 6.11 (Cauchy Criterion) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 53
↩→Proposition 6.9 (Weierstrass M-Test) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 53
↩→ Definition 6.5 (Power Series) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 53
↩→ Definition 6.6 (Radius of Convergence) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 53
↩→ Theorem 6.12 (Cauchy-Hadamard) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 54
↩→ Theorem 6.13 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 54
↩→ Theorem 7.1 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 55
↩→ Theorem 7.2 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 56
↩→ Theorem 7.3 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 56
↩→ Lemma 7.1 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 56
↩→ Definition 7.1 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 57
↩→ Lemma 7.2 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 57
↩→ Question 7.1 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 59
↩→ Question 7.2 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 59
↩→ Question 7.3 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 60
↩→ Question 7.4 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 61
↩→ Question 7.5 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 62
66