Complete Download Young Thomas More and The Arts of Liberty 1st Edition Gerard Wegemer PDF All Chapters
Complete Download Young Thomas More and The Arts of Liberty 1st Edition Gerard Wegemer PDF All Chapters
https://ebookultra.com/download/utopia-thomas-more/
ebookultra.com
https://ebookultra.com/download/an-analysis-of-keith-thomas-s-
religion-and-the-decline-of-magic-1st-edition-simon-young/
ebookultra.com
https://ebookultra.com/download/the-prophet-and-the-reformer-the-
letters-of-brigham-young-and-thomas-l-kane-1st-edition-matthew-j-grow/
ebookultra.com
https://ebookultra.com/download/cultivating-demand-for-the-arts-arts-
learning-arts-engagement-and-state-arts-policy-1st-edition-laura-
zakaras/
ebookultra.com
Deconstructing Digital Natives Young People Technology and
the New Literacies 1st Edition Michael Thomas
https://ebookultra.com/download/deconstructing-digital-natives-young-
people-technology-and-the-new-literacies-1st-edition-michael-thomas/
ebookultra.com
https://ebookultra.com/download/the-tradition-of-ethics-2nd-edition-
gerard-pacillo/
ebookultra.com
https://ebookultra.com/download/the-constitutional-systems-of-the-
australian-states-and-territories-gerard-carney/
ebookultra.com
https://ebookultra.com/download/the-letters-of-robert-frost-1st-
edition-donald-gerard-sheehy/
ebookultra.com
Young Thomas More and the Arts of Liberty 1st Edition
Gerard Wegemer Digital Instant Download
Author(s): Gerard Wegemer
ISBN(s): 9780521196536, 0521196531
Edition: 1
File Details: PDF, 3.57 MB
Year: 2011
Language: english
Young Thomas More and the Arts of Liberty
GERARD B. WEGEMER
University of Dallas
cambridge university press
Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town,
Singapore, São Paulo, Delhi, Tokyo, Mexico City
Cambridge University Press
32 Avenue of the Americas, New York, ny 10013-2473, usa
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521196536
C Gerard B. Wegemer 2011
A catalog record for this publication is available from the British Library.
Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy of urls
for external or third-party Internet Web sites referred to in this publication and does not
guarantee that any content on such Web sites is, or will remain, accurate or appropriate.
Contents
v
vi Contents
vii
Acknowledgments
Gratitude for assistance from numerous friends over the past decade is
a joy to express. Without the vision and support of Steven A. Bennett,
Joseph Coleman, Myles Harrington, Charles LiMandri, Thomas Spence,
Glen Thurow, and codirector Stephen W. Smith, the Center for Thomas
More Studies would never have been founded, and therefore the many
fruitful conferences and research projects that made this book possi-
ble would not have occurred. No scholar could have asked for better
conversationalists than these colleagues, as well as Clarence H. Miller,
Elizabeth McCutcheon, Seymour House, John Boyle, Travis Curtright,
Michael Foley, Louis Karlin, Joseph Koterski, Jeff Lehman, Tamara
Kuykendall, David Oakley, and the faculty and students at the Univer-
sity of Dallas, especially John Alvis and Scott Crider, and Josh Avery
and Matthew Mehan. Special thanks go to Mary Pawlowski for her
help with Greek texts and with compiling the indices of terms at
www.thomasmorestudies.org/IndicesofLatinTerms; to Paul Weinhold for
the index; to Lewis Bateman, senior editor of Cambridge University Press;
and to Brian MacDonald, production editor, for their patience and good
advice through the long process of this book.
Thanks to the following institutions for permission to use their materi-
als: the President and Fellows of Harvard College for permission to quote
from the Loeb Classical Library, Yale University Press for permission to
quote from The Complete Works of St. Thomas More, HarperCollins
Publishers for permission to quote from C 2008 David Starkey’s Henry,
xi
1
[Wisdom is] the skilled artisan of life . . . , her voice is for peace, and she
summons all mankind to concord.
Seneca, Epistulae 90.26–27
[Liberal] arts were devised for the purpose of fashioning [fingerentur]1 the
minds of the young according to humanitas and virtue.2
Cicero, De Oratore 3.58
Humanitas, or the idea of man, [is that] according to which man is fashioned
[effingitur] . . . as Plato says.3
Seneca, Epistulae 65.7
“Work out your own ideas and sift your thoughts so as to see what concep-
tion and idea of a good person they contain”; otherwise you can end up as
a “Caesar [who] overturned all the laws, human and divine, to achieve for
himself a principate fashioned [finxerat] according to his own erroneous
opinion.”4
Cicero, De Officiis 3.81, 1.26
1
2 Young Thomas More and the Arts of Liberty
In 1515, as part of their plan for international peace, Thomas More and
Erasmus both called for a renaissance – a “rebirth” – of the “so-called
liberal studies.”5 That “so-called” referred to Seneca’s famous state-
ment: “Hence you see why ‘liberal studies’ are so called: because they are
studies worthy of the free. But there is only one really liberal study, that
which gives a person his liberty. It is the study of wisdom, and that is
lofty, brave, and great-souled.”6 In calling for this renaissance, they were
agreeing with their classical predecessors that education in the “liberal
arts,”7 or what Cicero often called the studia humanitatis, is the best
path “to lead the state in peace,”8 because “the fostering of a virtuous
and educated citizenry provides the key” to peace and liberty.9 But what
did they mean, and were they and their fellow humanists not woefully
misguided as critics such as Machiavelli would later claim?10
In 1515 More wrote book 2 of Utopia with its provocative promises
of liberty, peace, and humanitas;11 in the same year, Erasmus “dreamt
of an age truly golden,” only to discover “the severity of that worse than
iron age we live in.”12 The iron age of war rather than the golden age
of peace was also portrayed in The History of King Richard III, which
More had been writing since 1513 but never published in his lifetime.
Did the shattering of this golden dream prove to More and Erasmus that
the fashionings of humanitas lacked the power they hoped?
In 1515 the playful “Triumph of Humanitas” (Illustration 1) deco-
rated Erasmus’s newly published edition of Seneca’s collected works, the
edition that Erasmus had worked on during his stay in England from
1509 through 1514, using manuscripts from English libraries. The figure
Humanitas in the top of the frame is pushed by the Latin authors Cicero
(Tully) and Virgil and pulled by the Greek authors Demosthenes and
Homer – all four of whom wrote on war in ways that deeply affected
their cultures. Lady Humanitas is peacefully reading, even while riding in
her triumphal chariot pushed and pulled by these laurel-crowned poets
and bareheaded statesmen, all under a triumphal canopy held by plump,
happy cherubs. On the left side of the engraving is the figure of a child,
and lest there be any doubt after one sees the sickle in his hand or the
wings at his feet, a sign in Greek identifies this figure as “Time.” On the
right, another label in Greek identifies “Nemesis,” who is holding her
traditional measure and spool of fate. Erasmus, in his Adages (II.vi.38),
describes Nemesis as “a goddess, the scourge of insolence and arrogance,
whose province is to forbid excessive hopes and punish them,” possessing
“a general power of supervising the fates, surveying above all human
affairs as queen and arbiter of all things.”13 In this frontispiece, however,
the triumphal march that takes place above Time and Nemesis seems
to present Humanitas as the greater queen and arbiter. This reading is
confirmed by the comparative-genitive constructions, which lead us to
read the text in this frame as “Humanitas greater than Time, greater
than Nemesis.”14
But how could humanitas ever have such power? Cicero was mur-
dered, and Seneca’s death was ordered by the Roman princeps he loyally
served.15 Cicero’s head and hands were nailed to the rostra in the Roman
forum where he had served as lawyer, senator, and consul of the Roman
Republic.16 He lived to see the Roman Republic become an empire,
ruled by one despotically powerful princeps instead of many principes
17 For the changing use of this term from the late Republic to Augustan’s conception of
princeps, see Ogilvie 392.
18 See Seneca’s masterful appeal to Emperor Nero for humanitas in De Clementia, and
especially Seneca’s praise of Augustus Caesar as “mitis princeps” (9.1), echoing Cicero’s
similar praise of Julius Caesar at Epistulae ad Familiares 6.6.5.
19 For the central importance of leges-libertas, see Wirszubski 1954 and 1968.
20 “To Thomas Ruthall,” CWE 3, Letter 325, 7 March 1515. In this letter, Erasmus
expresses his gratitude for use of the manuscripts of Seneca provided by King’s College
at Cambridge and by Archbishop Warham of Canterbury.
21 This volume is 665 large folio pages and contains Seneca’s twelve moral essays, 124
moral letters, ten books of natural questions, ten books of declamations, six books of
suasoriae and controversiae, St. Jerome’s praise of Seneca, and the pseudocorrespon-
dence between Seneca and St. Paul. It concludes with a seven-page listing of “Senecae
Proverbia,” a twenty-one-page “Index Locorum,” and another snake-and-dove device
(more elaborate and elegant than the one on the frontispiece) with the Hebrew, Greek,
and Latin quotations that appear in the Utopia version of this device.
22 See St. Jerome, On Illustrious Men 26–27.
23 CWE 3, Letter 325/81–83, 109–10.
24 Quintilian, Institutio Oratoria 10.1.112.
25 CWE 10, Letter 100.
6 Young Thomas More and the Arts of Liberty
26 CW 15, 143.
27 Ius gentium is a fundamental theme in De Oratore, De Re Publica, and De Legibus and
throughout his speeches. As an introduction to the complexity of Cicero’s thought, see
Nicgorski 1993 and Frank.
28 De Legibus 1.30, 23.
29 See especially 1.1 on “Justice and Law,” 1.5 on “Human Status,” and the treatment of
ius gentium throughout.
30 Seneca’s Oedipus appears in the portrait Sir Thomas More and His Family, and selections
from the important choral ode of the fourth act can be read in this near life-size painting.
See also the quotations from Seneca’s tragedies in the sixteenth-century play Sir Thomas
More as noted in TMSB 134ff.
31 For example, De Otio 6.4 and its reference to “leges . . . toti humano generi.”
Young Thomas More 7
As he develops this analogy, he points out again that the parts of the
human community need to be united by bonds of love:
What if the hands should desire to harm the feet, or the eyes the hands? As all
the members of the body are in harmony one with another because it is to the
advantage of the whole that the individual members be unharmed, so mankind
should spare the individual man, because all are born for a life of fellowship, and
society can be kept unharmed only by the mutual protection and love [amore] of
its parts. (2.31.7–8)
Although Seneca is the first to say explicitly that the body politic should
be bound by love, he is simply advancing the concepts already developed
by Aristotle and Cicero.33
One of Seneca’s longest explanations of humanitas occurs in Epistulae
88, “On Liberal Studies”:34
Seneca insists in this letter that liberal arts can only “prepare the soul
for virtue.”35 Because virtue is the “art to become good” (90.44), it
“does not enter a soul unless that soul has been trained and taught,
and by unremitting practice brought to perfection” (90.46) through free
choice.36 Seneca insists that our “primary art is virtue itself” (92.10) and
that virtue is “nothing else than a soul in a certain condition” (113.2).
What condition? The “perfected condition” of wisdom, which is “the
greatest of all the arts” (104.19). In the last letter, Seneca explains that
the highest human good is the free use of one’s godlike power of reason
to forge “a pure and corrected soul” (124.23).37 Such a soul, as we will
see, is most capable of leading the “sound deliberation” that prudent first
citizens foster to achieve peace, prosperity, and liberty.
Thomas More will paraphrase this same Senecan language in his own
letters on education. For example, in his 1518 Letter to Oxford, More
argues that liberal education “prepares the soul for virtue” and helps in
acquiring “prudence in human affairs,” which “can nowhere be drawn
so abundantly as from the poets, orators, and historians.”38 This view
of education accords with Cicero’s that the liberal “arts were devised for
the purpose of fashioning [fingerentur] the minds of the young according
to humanitas and virtue.”39 Thomas More consistently affirmed a view
of freely acquired virtue and well-trained reason based on “the inner
knowledge of what is right” or “right conscience” (recti conscientia) that
gives rise to “solid joy”40 – a view that would bring More in radical
conflict with Luther.
But why would poets, orators, and historians be superior sources of
“prudence in human affairs”? Eleven years later, More would repeat and
[R]eason is by study, labour, and exercise of logic, philosophy, and other liberal
arts corroborate [strengthened] and quickened, and the judgement both in them
and also in orators, laws, and [hi]stories41 much rip[en]ed. And albeit poets
[have] been with many men taken but for painted words, yet do they much help
the judgement and make a man among other things well furnished of one special
thing without which all learning is half lame . . . a good mother wit.42
Proper study of oratory, law, history, and poetry, More explains, will
“much ripen” and “help the judgment” by making one “among other
things well furnished of one special thing without which all learning is
half lame.” Lucian, as Chapter 4 will indicate, is a master at revealing
in most entertaining and effective ways what that “one special thing” is:
prudence, clear-sighted practical wisdom; or, put in Chaucerian language,
“a good mother wit.”
Why these particular arts or areas of study? Oratory is an art that
requires a thorough knowledge of human nature and a thorough, detailed
knowledge of a people and its culture. The same is true of law, poetry,
and history. All require an expertise in humanitas if they are to move and
affect their audience.43
This expertise in humanitas gave rise to Seneca’s and Cicero’s view
that all should be treated equal before the law and be subject, before that
law, to equal rights.44 Cicero forcefully argued that human flourishing
required “liberty in law,” and he used his rhetorical powers to attempt to
persuade his fellow citizens that “we are servants of the law that we might
be free.”45 Seneca, however, given the imperial despotism and ambitions
for world domination of his time, had to use persuasion of another kind,
but he artfully and powerfully reminded all of their common humanity
and of the importance of peace.46 Seneca’s most famous essays – “On
letters to Francis Cranevelt [22 February 1526] and [8 November 1528] in Moreana
103:63 and 117:47 as well as More’s Letter to Wolsey 21 September [1521] in Corr.
263/41–44.
54 See Robert P. Adams’s classic study, The Better Part of Valor.
55 On 3 November 1929.
56 Tudor historian Edward Hall and Spanish ambassador Eustace Chapuys give the only
extended accounts of this speech, and they are in general agreement with the official
Parliament Roll’s summary (Hall 2.164–65; Great Britain, CSPS no. 211, 8 November
1529; Letters and Papers of Henry VIII 4, no. 6043, 3 November 1529).
57 See Chapter 7; on Henry’s leadership as a danger to England, see Scarisbrick 35, 37–38.
On Henry VIII’s crafted imitation of Henry V, see Chapter 6 and Herman 1995 220.
58 See the sources in note 56 and their many references to the need for “reform” and
“reformation.”
59 See the analysis of More epigrams on the good princeps as a shepherd in Chapter 6.
Young Thomas More 13
67 On the epitaph of his tombstone, More includes integrity among the qualities he admired
in his father: “homo ciuilis, suauis, innocens, mitis, misericors, aequus et integer” (EE
2831/96). These qualities are quite close to those required by Cicero’s and Seneca’s
humanitas. A sampling of More’s other uses of “integrity” are CW 1, 64/14 (claimed to
be the first use in English as indicated at CW 1, L, note 1, but the Medieval Dictionary
points out one earlier use: in the 1425 translation of Paul’s Letter to Titus 2.7 – I
thank H. A. Kelly for this earlier reference); CW 4, 102/11; CW 15, 358/23, 392/2; EE
2831/42, 46. Erasmus uses the term to describe More at EE 999/209, 221 or TMSB
10. For More’s earliest recorded concern that word and deed should harmonize and
not be in “dispute,” see TMSB 177, SL 5, or Corr. 3/47, but also CW 3.1, 29/20–22,
172.
68 EE 2831/41–42: “arbitrabar oportere me integritatem nominis mei defendere.”
69 See CW 4, 56/24.
70 EE 2831/46–47: “nec adhuc quisquam prodiit qui de mea integritate quereretur”
71 One indication of this early concern is that More wrote of various characters’ “reputation
for integrity”; see, for example, in Richard III, the power of “integritatis opinionem”
(CW 15, 358/23; also 393/2).
72 See Muller, catalog entries 124 and 124a: “Druckermarke von Johannes Froben.”
Young Thomas More 15
“those of us who follow Christ’s command [are to] become wise as serpents (CW 14,
617/1); Christ “wished His followers to be brave and prudent,” not “senseless and
foolish” (CW 14, 59/3).
76 For example, St. Basil the Great refers to Socrates’ quote in How to Profit from Pagan
Literature, sec. 6. Basil’s document was so important to the renaissance of Florence that
“it was the first Greek text translated by Leonardo Bruni,” who used it “as a defense
of humanism” (Basil 371–72). Bruni dedicated his translation to the city’s fourteenth-
century lord chancellor Coluccio Salutati.
77 Cicero refers to these passages in De Officiis 2.43.
78 De Officiis 1.72, 3.5 and see Chapter 3.
79 For “sure deliberation” (certum consilium), see More’s Epigram 198/13, especially in
light of Aristotle’s discussion of deliberation and “deliberate choice” at Nicomachean
Ethics 1112a19–1113a14 and Aquinas’s use of consilium as the term for deliberation
in his commentary. For the importance of a “sure” conscience, see SL 242, 242, 221,
TMSB 332, or Corr. 528/550, 552; see also the ironic use at CW 2, [English] 18/17
and the power of conscience at CW 2, [English] 68/31–34 and 87/11–12, 16–21 as
so dramatically portrayed in Shakespeare’s Richard III. In his first work published in
English, More adds to the text he translates: “Of virtue more joy the conscience hath
within / Than outward the body of all his filthy sin” (CW 1, 108/7–8; compare with
378). This idea is expressed again at the end of his life when he writes in prison that
“the clearness of my conscience hath made my heart hop for joy” (SL 235). For the
obligation of training the conscience “surely by learning and good counsel,” see SL
242, 229. More stated that “for the instruction of my conscience . . . , I have not slightly
looked, but by many years studied and advisedly considered” the matters at hand (Corr.
516 or TMSB 320). For the danger of “framing one’s conscience” according to one’s
own desire, see More’s comments at Corr. 521, 527, CW 13, 112, or TMSB 325, 331,
214. For achieving “surety,” consider also CW 1, 40/250 and More’s early argument
against Lady Fortune, as will be seen in Chapter 4. That More is deliberately provocative
in the use of “certum consilium,” see note 5 of Chapter 7.
80 Cicero, Pro Murena 3: “Catoni, gravissimo atque integerrimo viro”; Sallust, Catiline
54.2: “integritate vitae Cato” as well as 10.5 with its condemnation of hypocrisy whereby
18 Young Thomas More and the Arts of Liberty
and why Cicero claimed that Cato could improve by having greater edu-
cation in humanitas.81 Cato illustrates the dangers associated with one
who is rigidly concerned about an appearance of integrity; his unbending
and doctrinaire Stoicism presented a grave danger to the republic.82 While
More leaves no doubt that he is committed to consistency of word and
deed,83 he also leaves no doubt that he is well aware of the many ethical
complexities and the demands of “true virtue.” True virtue, consistency
between word and deed,84 is a necessary condition of Cicero’s princeps,
who must be well educated in the full range of studia humanitatis.85
Aristotle expressed this same thought in different ways, noting that
“the end appears to each man in a form answering to his character”86
and, for this reason, “it is impossible to be practically wise without being
good.”87 Popularly put, “As a person is, so does he judge.”88 Experience
shows that persons enslaved by uncontrolled anger or burning ambition
one’s public face does not reflect one’s true character. In English, More may use the word
only once in this sense (CW 1, 64/4). The Latin uses at CW 15, 358/23 and 392/2, CW
4, 102/11 show the ambiguities and dangers involved. When More describes his father
as “integer,” that adjective is the last of a list of seven qualities: “civilis, suavis, innocens,
mitis, misericors, aequus et integer” (EE 2831/96).
81 Pro Murena 65.
82 After strongly disagreeing with Cato’s overly rigid behavior and judgments, Cicero
praises “my master, the schools of Plato and Aristotle, men who do not hold violent
or extreme views” (Pro Murena 63). Cicero goes on to address Cato: “If some happy
chance, Cato, had carried a man of your character off to these masters, you . . . would
be a little more disposed to kindness” (64). However, much more than kindness was at
stake in Cicero’s long battle with the extremes of Roman Stoicism and Epicureanism.
See Nicgorski 1984 and 2002. The best study of Sallust’s exploration of these issues is
Batstone.
Reflection on these reasons provide a context for Morus’s criticism of Hythlodaeus’s
“uncivil” approach at CW 4, 98; in response to Morus, Hythlodaeus invokes a rigid
dichotomy between corruption and integrity (102/10–11).
83 From one of his earliest letters, More states his concern for the consistency of vita with
verba (TMSB 177, Corr. 7/47).
84 Cicero often uses the word constantia for this quality; see De Officiis 1.69, 72, 119.
85 On the necessity of an unwavering fides and love for truth and justice, see De Officiis
1.15, 61–65, 153. See also Cicero’s frequent insistence that the true statesman must have
the full range of learning, as in De Oratore 3.122 especially, but also 1.20, 1.53–54,
1.71–73, 2.5–6, 3.20–21, 3.54; Pro Archia 15–16; De Legibus 1.59–62; De Republica
1.28–28, 2.24–25.
86 Nicomachean Ethics 1114a33. Rhetoric is essential because, Aristotle observes, all are
“so much influenced by feelings of friendship or hatred or self-interest that they lose any
clear vision of the truth and have their judgment obscured by considerations of personal
pleasure or pain” (Rhetoric 1354b.). More makes a similar point at CW 6, 262.
87 Nicomachean Ethics 1144a36–37.
88 A free rendering of Nicomachean Ethics 1114a33. See also Rhetoric 1388b32–1391a19.
Young Thomas More 19
or blinding greed cannot judge clearly; they lack the integrity of self-
government that human beings need for consistent sharp-sightedness,
humanitas, and, consequently, prudent action. Hence, we can understand
why More would write with his typical wit, “I would rather be good than
practically wise.”89
These views about character, perception, and self-government are
expressed in two classic images: the ship’s captain at sea and the shep-
herd protecting his flock, images that More used throughout his life.90 As
these examples indicate, it is one thing to think or even to boast of facing
dangers; it is another to do so in fact, especially in the face of death.
The captain or the shepherd might perceive clearly what must be done in
times of danger, but each must also have a character so disciplined over
time that the leader can act courageously in obedience to that perception,
at the cost of one’s own life if necessary.
Sir Thomas used such examples not only in his earliest publications91
but also before the king in the 1529 Parliament and right up to the months
preceding his own death. In his last book, he warned that the weight and
difficulties of duties could “drown and oppress” the mind with sorrow
unless such sorrow is “ruled and governed by reason.” If reason does
not rule, then reason freely “gives over her hold and government,”92 like
“a cowardly ship’s captain who is so disheartened by the furious din of
a storm that he deserts the helm, hides away cowering in some cranny,
and abandons the ship to the waves.”93 More goes on to indicate in no
uncertain terms that such a captain could never be called good or just. As
More used this image, he showed that the captain’s character, his ethos,94
is at least as important as his intellect or his skill. He showed that a certain
kind of character is needed to free the intellect to utilize the very skills it
has acquired.
89 Thomas More’s prefatory letter to Utopia: “malim bonus esse quam prudens,” CW 4,
40/29.
90 For example, see the Republic 341c and 488d, 345c and 440d, and the references to
Homer in note 65.
91 CW 4, 98/27–28; guarding sheep: CW 3.2, no. 115; sarcastic play on protecting sheep:
CW 15, 358/25, the lamb entrusted to the wolf (agnus certe consulto in lupi fidem
creditus).
92 CW 14, 263, but I follow here Mary Basset’s translation given at CW 14, 1113. The
verb used is “infrenet,” alluding to Plato’s famous image of the charioteer governing his
two powerful horses at Phaedrus 246, 254.
93 CW 14, 265.
94 This Greek word for character is the root of our word “ethics.”
20 Young Thomas More and the Arts of Liberty
Despite his own fear, the effective captain must have the character
and clarity of perception to do as Morus says in Utopia, “You must not
abandon the ship in a storm because you cannot control the wind.”95
As More implies here and explains in his later writings, not only must
the captain know when to lower his sails and carefully supervise his
crew, especially during storms, but also the captain must have the tested
skills and virtues needed to do so.96 That is precisely why special care
must be taken beforehand to acquire all the arts of the captain’s trade:
good captains need sufficient knowledge of the ship, the sea, the winds,
and their own crews; they need sufficient skill in the many arts required
for piloting, for gubernans (the root of our word “govern”). Just as
important, however, they need proven strength of character to fulfill
their duty in the face of grave dangers.
Why did More join Erasmus in calling for “the renascence of good let-
ters”? How could a “rebirth” of old books be of any help in the face
of new and pressing contemporary problems? Those “good letters” –
that is, those classical, biblical, and patristic texts in Latin and especially
Greek97 – he considered to be not only the basis for but also the best-
fashioned exercises to achieve the prudence that is a prerequisite for all
the other arts needed by “the leading citizens” or principes. More and his
fellow humanists were convinced of this truth because liberal education
gives access to the time-tested truths and also to the intellectual train-
ing of the highest, most effective, and most profitable kind.98 One such
intellectual exercise is More’s famous Utopia, which raises the funda-
mental issues about humanitas, and hence about the soul and the nature
of happiness, justice, virtue, wisdom, and government. True, Raphael’s
report leaves the reader uncertain whether Utopia is really a tyranny or a
free republic and whether the common Utopians are enslaved and broken
subjects, or wise and virtuous citizens. But for More, “good letters” or
the “liberal arts” are not just entertaining pastimes; they are the very
95 CW 4, 98/27–28.
96 Some of the uses of this piloting metaphor can be found at CW 1, 45/7–8 and SL 233; CW
4, 98/27–28 and negatively at 52/18; CW 5, 270/28–29; CW 12, 6/13, 29/6, 57/30–31;
CW 14, 265/1–3; CW 15, 476/12, and the text from Seneca’s Oedipus shown in portrait
Sir Thomas More and His Family (Illustration 5). The image is used in abbreviated form
at CW 3.2, Epigram 19/184.
97 CW 15, 139ff.; SL 100ff.
98 In reflection upon the title and theme of St. Basil the Great’s How to Profit from Pagan
Literature, one can appreciate why Bruni’s translation from Greek to Latin was dedicated
to the chancellor of Florence, Coluccio Salutato (Basil 371).
Young Thomas More 21
means to achieve the strength of mind and character needed for free
self-government rather than enslavement to passion, false ideas, or other
persons. They are the means to become free and effective citizens.
In this context, one can appreciate why Thomas More disagreed fun-
damentally with Martin Luther’s denial of free choice of the will,99 belief
in a class of “pure elect,”100 and claim that human nature was so cor-
rupt that the reason and will were powerless either to find truth or to
live justice.101 These doctrines were, in More’s judgment and in the judg-
ment of Christian principes then in Europe, false and seditious opinions
sure to lead to war and social chaos.102 The greatest evidence for this
view – from their perspectives – was the Peasants’ Revolt of 1525, which
ended with the slaughter of sixty thousand to eighty thousand peasants
in one summer.103 Luther’s ideology – claiming that he and some few
were the “pure elect” unable to lose salvation by sin and saved by their
faith alone – went against the entire humanist project advanced by More,
Erasmus, and their fellow advocates of international unity, peace, and
reform based on the development of law, virtue, public deliberation, and
education.
When in conversation with one of Luther’s followers who claimed
that personal inspiration from reading the Bible was sufficient education,
More made this reply:
Now in the study of scripture, in devising the sentence, in considering what you
read, in pondering the purpose of diverse commentaries, in comparing together
diverse texts that seem contrary and are not, although I deny not but that grace
and God’s special help is the great thing therein, yet he uses for an instrument
man’s reason thereto. God helps us to eat also but yet not without our mouth.
Now as the hand is the more nimble by the use of some feats, and the legs and
feet more swift and sure by custom of going and running, and the whole body
the more wieldy and lusty by some kind of exercise, so is it no doubt but that
reason is by study, labour, and exercise of logic, philosophy, and other liberal
arts corroborate [strengthened] and quickened.104
Later in life, More put this view even more strongly, stating that no virtue
is possible without well-trained judgment – that “strength of heart and
courage in a reasonable creature can never be without prudence.”105
Plato, Aristotle, Cicero, Seneca, Erasmus, and More’s fellow humanists
agreed on this view of reason, of a humanitas of free and self-governing
citizens. Luther did not, and in contrast, More emphasized throughout his
life the importance of a well-fashioned reason, a well-fashioned character,
and a substantial body of well-fashioned laws, resulting from many gen-
erations of prudent citizens and rulers guiding human affairs. Therefore,
More followed Plato, Aristotle, Cicero, and Seneca in affirming wisdom
and virtue to be the proper ends of education and of life because they
alone could equip the individual and the nation to fashion the integrity
of thought and action needed to be just, happy, and free. This is a quality
we would call “integrity” today, and it is significant that Thomas More is
one of the first to use that English word.106 And like Socrates and Cicero,
he died in a deliberate attempt to live it.
Along with these mentors, More agreed that such an education is the
most useful education precisely because it best equips human beings to
pilot their ships through uncharted waters and through those mighty
storms that always come. And in this prudent piloting, More emphasized
the absolute necessity of the legislator’s expertise in the art of law making.
More saw law as itself an ongoing work of prudence, yet despite
his respect for it, More had modest expectations because even the best
laws cannot protect every innocent person. This view More learned from
history and from his own experience: that often laws are, in words More
quoted from Plutarch, “just like spiders’ webs; they would hold the weak
and the delicate who might be caught in their meshes, but would be torn
in pieces by the rich and powerful.”107 More was acutely aware from
his earliest days that even the best laws could be manipulated unless
learned, prudent, and courageous principes exercised constant vigilance
and prudent care.
That such prudence is best fashioned with the help of good letters or
studia humanitatis or the “liberal arts” was a conviction that arose from
an understanding of art.
[M]ost principes apply themselves to the arts of war . . . instead of the good
arts of peace.
Thomas More, Utopia 56/22–24
The princeps’ art of rule . . . is easily seen in our faces and is made conspic-
uous in the prosperity of the people.
Thomas More, Epigram 19/82–85
[A]rt produces nothing without reason. . . . When you see a statue or a paint-
ing, you recognize the exercise of art; when you observe from a distance
the course of a ship, you do not hesitate to assume that its motion is guided
by reason and by art.
Cicero, De Natura Deorum 2.87
23
24 Young Thomas More and the Arts of Liberty
at the expense of the ruler. To act as a good shepherd, for example, the
guardian of the flock must be willing to endure pain and possible death.8
And in each case, the master artisan must reason a great deal about all
factors involved in that art.
Like Plato, Aristotle develops the Socratic analogies between well-
known arts and the less-known political art: just as each art has an
activity or function proper to it as seen in its perfection, such as the
well-made shoe or well-made chair,9 so the art of politics has an activity
proper to human beings, an activity that orders groups of people to their
particular excellence, which for Plato and Aristotle is synonymous with
“virtue.”10 As Aristotle puts it, “every virtue or excellence both brings
into good condition the thing of which it is the excellence and makes
the work of that thing be done well.” Two classic examples he gives
are these: “[T]he excellence of the eye makes both the eye and its work
good; . . . the excellence of the horse makes a horse both good in itself and
good at running and at carrying its rider and at awaiting the attack of the
enemy. Therefore, if this is true in every case, the virtue of man also will
be the state of character which makes a man good and which makes him
do his own work well.”11
Aristotle explains that art “exists to aid nature and to fill up its defi-
ciencies.” Just as flourishing harvests depend on the art of the farmer,
so flourishing lives of human beings require “many arts for preservation,
both at birth and in the matter of nutrition later.”12 Because this nutrition
is both physical and educational, Aristotle notes that “all art and educa-
tion wish to supply the element that is lacking in nature.”13 Ultimately,
8 This common truth about art Socrates used to counter Thrasymachus’s claim that the
artful ruler seeks his own good rather than the good of the ones ruled in book 1 of the
Republic. See Thrasymachus and Socrates’ exchange on the shepherd at 343a–345e, and
consider Thomas More’s Epigram 115. In his Apology, Socrates defends himself before
the city, saying: “I have neglected all my own affairs . . . , approaching each one of you as
a father or an elder brother to persuade you to care for virtue.” He explains that he has
endured poverty in exercising his distinctive art, rather than seeking his own advantage
by charging fees (31b–c). See also Chapter 1 for More’s comparison of Henry VIII to a
shepherd.
9 Nicomachean Ethics 1097b21 ff.
10 Nicomachean Ethics 1097b23, 1101a18, 1102a1–2, 1153b17.
11 Nicomachean Ethics 1106a15–17, 1106a18–24.
12 Protrepticus xi; Parts of Animals 639b15–19; Physics 2.2 and 13; Nicomachean Ethics
1140a10 ff.; Metaphysics 981a, 1034a8 ff. Compare these with Cicero’s De Natura
Deorum 2.57–28 and Seneca’s Epistulae 65.3 and 17.
13 Politics 1337a2.
26 Young Thomas More and the Arts of Liberty
the art of arts or the science of sciences is wisdom, that is, “knowledge
about principles and causes that are certain.”14 In the human sciences,
the master or architectonic art of that wisdom is political philosophy.15
In the field of politics, Aristotle’s master artisans have as their aim
the happiness of their people, which in turn requires obedience to good
laws.16 Such laws are in a special way “the ‘product’ of the political
art,”17 because they are those dictates of reason18 which look to the good
of the whole without reference to personal or special interests.19
Because these laws look to the true good of citizens, the legislator
must “have studied virtue above all things,” and he must know “the
facts about the soul” because “legislators make the citizens good by
forming habits in them.”20 To develop these habits of “excellence,” to
develop the “best state” of the human soul,21 Aristotle explains that “it
is from the same causes and by the same means that every virtue is both
produced and destroyed, and similarly every art.”22 Just as builders or
harpists become good artisans by repeatedly doing their arts well, so
souls develop excellences or virtues by repeatedly doing human actions
well. The reverse is true regarding poor artistry and vice. In this way art
and virtue are analogous:23 both require habits guided by knowledge and
deliberation about the best and most appropriate means to the best and
most appropriate end.24
Therefore, any artisan, Aristotle explains, whether a physician or a
builder or a political ruler, “starts by forming for himself a definite pic-
ture . . . of his end – the physician of health, the builder of a house”25 –
or, in the case of the political ruler, a definite picture of happiness for his
people, that is, “the best way of life” for human beings, or what Cicero
14 Metaphysics 982a1.
15 Nicomachean Ethics 1094a14.
16 Nicomachean Ethics 1102a9–10.
17 Nicomachean Ethics 1181a24.
18 Nicomachean Ethics 1134a36 and Aquinas’s commentary no. 1009.
19 See Aristotle’s discussion of political justice and rule by law rather than rule by individ-
uals at Nicomachean Ethics 1134a24 ff.
20 Nicomachean Ethics 1102a17, 1103b3–4.
21 Nicomachean Ethics 1106a16, 1139a15.
22 Nicomachean Ethics 1103b7–8.
23 See, for example, Cicero, De Finibus 4.4.
24 Nicomachean Ethics 1103a16.
25 Aristotle, Parts of Animals 639b15–19. See also Metaphysics 981a: “[A]rt arises when,
from many notions gained by experience, one universal judgment about a class of objects
is produced.” Consider again the importance of “sure deliberation” in such judgments.
See also Nicomachean Ethics 1140a 9–14.
Fashioning Peace and Prosperity 27
33 Nicomachean Ethics 1106a14–15 and Aquinas’s commentary no. 308. See also Cicero’s
De Legibus 1.19 and 2.11 where he defines law in terms of choice.
34 Nicomachean Ethics 1112a7–8.
35 Nicomachean Ethics 1113a5, 1112a15–17, 1135b10–12, 1139a22–26.
36 See Aristotle’s perceptive analysis of counsel and deliberation at Nicomachean Ethics
1112a13–1113a14 and Aquinas’s commentary, especially no. 457.
37 See Sparshott 387n58 and his commentary for Nicomachean Ethics 1109b30 ff., where
he points out that Aristotle’s term for what is often called “voluntary” is hekousion, and
he supports the argument that the best translation is “intended.” Aquinas uses the term
will throughout his commentary on these sections; see his Summa Theologica I.83.1 ff.
for his defense of free will and his interpretation of Aristotle’s analysis of choice.
38 See the extended discussions of this point in Cicero’s De Oratore.
39 De Oratore 1.33, but at 1.35–40 Scaevola immediately refutes this exaggerated claim.
Even as a youth, Cicero’s claims for rhetoric were more moderate than in this mythic
account (De Inventione 1.1–3).
Fashioning Peace and Prosperity 29
40 De Oratore 1.30.
41 Cicero gives Plato and Aristotle high praise when he says they “had developed a teaching
that left nothing to be desired either in fullness or finish” (De Finibus 4.3).
42 De Finibus 4.4.
43 Notice that even here, in his “popularization” of the Stoic position (De Finibus 4.24),
Cicero indicates his own preference for “innate” rather than “implanted.”
44 Tusculanae Disputationes 5.108; De Legibus 1.23, 61; De Officiis 3.26, 28; De Finibus
3.64; De Natura Deorum 2.133, 154; Seneca, Otio 4.1, 6.4.
45 Seneca, in Epistulae 65.7, attributes his understanding of humanitas “or the idea of
man” to Plato; he maintains that humanitas is, along with congregationem, the “first
thing which philosophy undertakes to give” (5.4) because the alternative is demens or
madness (5.4 and 95.31–32). See Cicero, De Legibus 1.33 and 42.
46 De Finibus 4.16–17.
30 Young Thomas More and the Arts of Liberty
teaches the way of good living.”47 This same position Thomas More held
from his earliest published work.48
This “true and refined philosophy,” this “art of living” (vivendi ars),
helps human beings to “guard the gifts that nature has bestowed and
to obtain those that are lacking.”49 Because it is based on the careful
study of the “nature” of the body and of the soul, philosophy can be “the
guardian and protector of the whole person, as being the comrade and
helper of nature.”50
The emphasis on guarding and protecting is given special attention by
Cicero, who claims that the Romans both understood and cared for this
dimension of life more effectively than did the Greeks. The accomplished
statesman-orator-general-lawyer-philosopher Crassus, arguably Cicero’s
greatest princeps,51 makes this case in both subtle and confrontationally
forceful ways in Cicero’s De Oratore. Cicero gives, for example, a vivid
report of Crassus’s greatest and final speech in the Senate when he stands
against the tyrannical and illegal actions of “a consul whose duty it
was to be [the Senate’s] fostering parent and faithful guardian [but who
instead] was plundering like some unprincipled brigand” (3.3). With a
“superlative energy of spirit, intellect, and force,” Crassus fearlessly stood
against the consul Philippus, challenging him in the name of Roman
libertas if he insisted on continuing his injustice: “[Y]ou must cut out this
tongue of mine – although even when this has been torn from my throat,
my breath of itself will serve my liberty [libertas] for the refutation of
your licence [libido]” (3.4).
This same Crassus – successful general in foreign wars, consul and
honored leader in peace at home – is the one who insists on the position
47 Tusculanae Disputationes 4.5–6. That Seneca follows in this same Socratic tradition can
be seen in Epistulae 92.10, 44, 46; 88.28; 90.1–2; 104.19; 117.12, 16.
48 SL 4–6, 103–7 or TMSB 175–77, 197–200, and More’s humanist letters (CW 15). See
also his introduction to Pico della Mirandola’s “Letter to Andrew Corneus,” where,
contrary to Pico’s own opinion, More states that one reason to study philosophy is “for
the instruction of [the] mind in moral virtue” (CW 1, 85/10–11).
49 De Finibus 3.4, 4.16, 19; Tusculanae Disputationes 4.15; Seneca, Epistulae 88.28, 33;
90.27, 95.7, 117.12; Augustine, City of God 9.4.
50 De Finibus 4.16–18, where Cicero explains that careful study of the soul reveals “in the
first place . . . seeds of justice [iustitiae semina],” which provide the “origin and growth
of all the virtues.” “Innate love of knowledge” is another seed that gives rise to “the
contemplation of the secrets of nature.”
51 As Mitchell explains, Crassus is, “for Cicero, the great exemplar of the arts of peace,
the civilian statesman par excellence.” Crassus’s “position as a princeps of the highest
auctoritas in a dominant Senate was Cicero’s own fondest ambition” (1991 47). For
Cicero’s own high praise of Crassus, see De Oratore 2.1–4, 6; 3.2–7, 74–77.
Fashioning Peace and Prosperity 31
that Cicero himself affirms:52 that the princeps needs a full and complete
education in studia humanitatis – that “wide domain of science” not
“split up into separate departments” (3.132). Otherwise, leaders come “to
office and to positions in the government quite naked and unarmed, not
equipped with any acquaintance with affairs or knowledge” (3.136). Only
such a well-educated leader can “win freedom for his native land,” having
been “equipped . . . with weapons for the task” (3.139). The dangers of
a partial education are seen by two extremes: those Cynics and Stoics
who “in the Socratic discourse had been captivated chiefly by the ideal of
endurance and hardness”; and those Epicureans “who had taken delight
rather in the Socratic discussions on the subject of pleasure” (3.62). This
second extreme “that has undertaken the championship of pleasure”53
is especially unfit, Crassus argues, “to be the author of public counsel
[consilii] . . . pre-eminent for wisdom and eloquence in the Senate, in the
assembly of the people, and in public causes” (3.63).
But the first extreme, pride in personal endurance and hardness, is
also an unfatherly, uncivil, and “inept” hindrance to social harmony, as
Crassus points to in the beginning of De Oratore, where the superiority of
Romans’ wearing shoes and holding chaste conversation in the safety of a
walled household is contrasted implicitly to the primitiveness of barefoot
Socrates’ conversations about illicit loves, conversations held in the midst
of nature under the noonday sun, outside home or city.54
Cicero also compares the educational work of the true and artful
princeps to the farmer’s task of proper cultivation, of bringing all “its
parts into the most thriving condition.”55 In an analogous sense, the wise
philosopher-statesman’s “office and duty” is “entirely centered in the
work of perfecting man.”56 When artfully cultivated, human beings come
to “full flower and perfection,” marked by honestas57 and humanitas.58
In determining the “nature” of this full flowering, Cicero says that he
52 In De Oratore, see Cicero’s own comments in the prefaces to each day of his Crassus
dialogues, especially 1.5 and 16, 2.5–6, and 3.15.
53 This same phrase occurs in Utopia, CW 4, 160/25, in direct opposition to this passage
and to De Officiis 2.27.
54 Consider the parallels and contrasts of the settings of De Oratore and Plato’s Phaedrus,
especially at De Oratore 1.28–29, in light of these later comments of 3.62 and 138–39,
as well as More’s use of Lucian’s dialogues as seen in Chapter 4. I am grateful to Scott
Crider for his illuminating reflections on these contrasts.
55 De Finibus 4.38.
56 De Finibus 4.36.
57 De Finibus 4.18 and throughout De Officiis.
58 See Chapter 1.
Discovering Diverse Content Through
Random Scribd Documents
l'embargo, et arrestation de tous les navigateurs de
l'Union dans les ports de l'Empire. — Mesures de
Napoléon pour fermer à l'Angleterre les rivages du
continent. — Ses exigences à l'égard de la Hollande,
des villes anséatiques, du Danemark, de la Suède, de
la Russie. — Résistance de la Hollande. — Tout en se
livrant à ces divers travaux, Napoléon s'occupe de
mettre fin aux querelles religieuses. — Faute de
quelques cardinaux à l'occasion de son mariage, et
rigueurs qui en sont la suite. — Situation du clergé et
du Pape. — Efforts pour créer une administration
provisoire des églises, et résistance du clergé à cette
administration. — Caractère et conduite du cardinal
Fesch, du cardinal Maury, et de MM. Duvoisin et
Émery. — Établissement que Napoléon destine à la
papauté au sein du nouvel empire d'Occident. — Envoi
de deux cardinaux à Savone pour négocier avec Pie
VII, et, en cas de trop grandes difficultés, projet d'un
concile. — Suite des affaires avec la Hollande. —
Napoléon veut que la Hollande ferme tout accès au
commerce britannique, et qu'elle lui prête plus
efficacement le secours de ses forces navales. — Le roi
Louis se refuse à tous les moyens qui pourraient
assurer ce double résultat. — Ce prince songe un
moment à se mettre en révolte contre son frère, et à
se jeter dans les bras des Anglais. — Mieux conseillé, il
y renonce, et se rend à Paris pour négocier. — Vaines
tentatives d'accommodement. — Napoléon n'espérant
plus rien ni de la Hollande ni de son frère, est disposé
à la réunir à l'Empire, et s'en explique franchement. —
Cependant arrêté par le chagrin de son frère, il
imagine un plan de négociation secrète avec le cabinet
britannique, consistant à proposer à ce dernier de
respecter l'indépendance de la Hollande s'il consent à
traiter de la paix. — M. Fouché intervient dans ces
diverses affaires, et indique M. de Labouchère comme
l'intermédiaire le plus propre à remplir une mission à
Londres. — Voyage de M. de Labouchère en
Angleterre. — Le cabinet britannique ne veut point
agiter l'opinion publique par l'ouverture d'une
négociation qui ne serait pas sérieuse, et renvoie M. de
Labouchère avec la déclaration formelle que toute
proposition équivoque restera sans réponse. — La
négociation, à demi abandonnée, est reprise
secrètement par M. Fouché sans la participation de
Napoléon. — Le roi Louis se soumet aux volontés de
son frère, et signe un traité en vertu duquel la
Hollande cède à la France le Brabant septentrional
jusqu'au Wahal, consent à laisser occuper ses côtes
par nos troupes, abandonne le jugement des prises à
l'autorité française, et s'engage à réunir une flotte au
Texel pour le 1er juillet. — Retour du roi Louis en
Hollande. — Voyage de Napoléon avec l'Impératrice en
Flandre, en Picardie et en Normandie. — Grands
travaux d'Anvers. — Napoléon découvre en route que
la négociation avec l'Angleterre a été reprise en secret
et à son insu par M. Fouché. — Disgrâce et destitution
de ce ministre. — Conduite du roi Louis après son
retour en Hollande. — Au lieu de chercher à calmer les
Hollandais, il les excite par l'expression publique des
sentiments les plus exagérés. — Son opposition
patente à la livraison des cargaisons américaines, à
l'établissement des douanes françaises, à l'occupation
de la Nort-Hollande, et à la formation d'une flotte au
Texel. — Fâcheux incident d'une insulte faite à
l'ambassade française par le peuple d'Amsterdam. —
Napoléon, irrité, ordonne au maréchal Oudinot d'entrer
à Amsterdam enseignes déployées. — Le roi Louis,
après avoir fait de vains efforts pour empêcher l'entrée
des troupes françaises dans sa capitale, abdique la
couronne en faveur de son fils, et place ce jeune
À
prince sous la régence de la reine Hortense. — À cette
nouvelle Napoléon décrète la réunion de la Hollande à
l'Empire, et convertit ce royaume en sept
départements français. — Ses efforts pour rétablir les
finances et la marine de ce pays. — Vaste
développement du système continental à la suite de la
réunion de la Hollande. — Nouveau régime imaginé
pour la circulation des denrées coloniales, et
permission de les faire circuler accordée à tous les
détenteurs moyennant un droit de 50 pour 100. —
Perquisitions ordonnées pour les soumettre à ce droit.
— Invitation aux États du continent d'adhérer au
nouveau système. — Tous y adhèrent, excepté la
Russie. — Immenses saisies en Espagne, en Italie, en
Suisse, en Allemagne. — Terreur inspirée à tous les
correspondants de l'Angleterre. — Rétablissement des
relations avec l'Amérique à condition que celle-ci
interrompra ses relations avec l'Angleterre. — Situation
du commerce général à cette époque. — Efficacité et
péril des mesures conçues par Napoléon. 1 à 199
LIVRE TRENTE-NEUVIÈME.
TORRÈS-VÉDRAS.
LIVRE QUARANTIÈME.
FUENTÈS D'OÑORO.
Pages
1. Le maréchal Suchet 214
2. Heureuse découverte du général Montbrun 375
3. Bataille de Fuentès d'Oñoro 670
Notes
10: Nous citons ici une dépêche de Napoléon qui prouve son état
d'exaspération, mais dont il ne faut pas prendre toutes les
expressions au pied de la lettre, car dans ses colères, sincères à un
certain degré et au delà calculées, il menaçait de plus de mal qu'il
n'en voulait faire.
12: Il est peu de sujets sur lesquels les auteurs de mémoires aient
débité plus de fables que sur celui-ci. On a prétendu notamment que
M. Fouché fut disgracié pour avoir refusé de rendre les lettres de
Napoléon, et des lettres fort compromettantes. Il n'y a rien de vrai
dans cette assertion. Les lettres de Napoléon à M. Fouché étaient
peu nombreuses, et pas plus compromettantes que celles qu'il
écrivait à tous ses agents, et dans lesquelles, se livrant à son
impétuosité naturelle, il disait souvent: Je ferai couper la tête à tel
ou tel, sans songer à le faire. Il se souciait d'ailleurs fort peu de ce
qu'il avait écrit, et ne songeait guère à en rougir, étant déjà si peu
embarrassé de ce qu'il avait fait, même de la mort du duc d'Enghien.
La vérité est qu'il s'était fort échauffé l'esprit sur l'envoi de M. Fagan
à Londres, et qu'il croyait avoir été plus compromis qu'il ne l'était
véritablement. Ses ordres et sa correspondance prouvent que la
seconde et la plus éclatante disgrâce de M. Fouché fut motivée par
le refus de livrer des pièces que celui-ci n'avait plus, relativement à
la mission de M. Fagan. Mais le public aimant les mystères, surtout
les mystères sinistres, crut, et beaucoup d'écrivains aussi puérils que
le public répétèrent qu'il y avait là d'affreuses lettres, dont Napoléon
voulait obtenir la restitution, et dont le refus provoqua un nouvel
éclat de sa part. Il n'en est rien, et il n'y a de vrai dans toutes ces
suppositions que ce que nous venons de rapporter.
25: Dans son ouvrage sur les divers siéges de Badajoz, le général
Lamare exprime l'opinion suivante:
«Parmi les beaux faits des assiégeants, nous ne laissons pas que de
trouver aussi des fautes, et la franchise avec laquelle nous allons les
exposer justifiera les éloges que nous venons de leur donner.
»Dans cette hypothèse, les règles du métier lui faisaient une loi
d'ouvrir la première parallèle à 5 ou 600 mètres des fronts (1, 2, 2,
3) et du fort Pardaleras, en appuyant fortement, par de bonnes
redoutes, la gauche de la parallèle à la Guadiana, et la droite au
Calamon.
»On conçoit que ce plan d'attaque eût été préférable à celui qui fut
adopté, et qu'on aurait vraisemblablement épargné beaucoup de
temps et de pertes en hommes et en munitions de guerre, si l'on eût
su profiter des avantages qu'il présentait.
Updated editions will replace the previous one—the old editions will
be renamed.
1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also
govern what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most
countries are in a constant state of change. If you are outside the
United States, check the laws of your country in addition to the
terms of this agreement before downloading, copying, displaying,
performing, distributing or creating derivative works based on this
work or any other Project Gutenberg™ work. The Foundation makes
no representations concerning the copyright status of any work in
any country other than the United States.
1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form,
including any word processing or hypertext form. However, if you
provide access to or distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg™ work
in a format other than “Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other format used in
the official version posted on the official Project Gutenberg™ website
(www.gutenberg.org), you must, at no additional cost, fee or
expense to the user, provide a copy, a means of exporting a copy, or
a means of obtaining a copy upon request, of the work in its original
“Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other form. Any alternate format must
include the full Project Gutenberg™ License as specified in
paragraph 1.E.1.
• You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive
from the use of Project Gutenberg™ works calculated using the
method you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The
fee is owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark,
but he has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty
payments must be paid within 60 days following each date on
which you prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your
periodic tax returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked
as such and sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation at the address specified in Section 4, “Information
Welcome to our website – the ideal destination for book lovers and
knowledge seekers. With a mission to inspire endlessly, we offer a
vast collection of books, ranging from classic literary works to
specialized publications, self-development books, and children's
literature. Each book is a new journey of discovery, expanding
knowledge and enriching the soul of the reade
Our website is not just a platform for buying books, but a bridge
connecting readers to the timeless values of culture and wisdom. With
an elegant, user-friendly interface and an intelligent search system,
we are committed to providing a quick and convenient shopping
experience. Additionally, our special promotions and home delivery
services ensure that you save time and fully enjoy the joy of reading.
ebookultra.com