Morality As Freedom
Morality As Freedom
159
room is left for excuses. For how can we take into account the
terrible temptations to which the wrongdoer was subjected, when
the choosing noumenon was uninfluenced by those temptations?
Finally, the view seems to require an unappealing ontological com-
mitment to the existence of "two worlds/' and to give rise to a
variety of puzzles about how what occurs in the one can influence
the other.
In this paper my aim is to address these problems. In the first
part of the paper, I show why Kant thinks that the moral law is the
law of a free will, and why he thinks we must regard ourselves as
free. I then argue that the supposed problems about responsibility
and ontology arise from a common source: a failure to appreciate
the radical nature of Kant's separation of theoretical and practical
reason, and of their respective domains of explanation and delibera-
tion. When these domains are separated in the way that Kant's
philosophy requires, the problems about responsibility disappear,
and we see that Kant's theory of freedom does not commit him to
an ontological dualism.1 In the second part of the paper I show
what it does commit him to: a certain conception of the moral
virtues.
I LAW AS FREEDOM
2 Kant argues that when you make a choice you must act "under
the idea of freedom" (G 448). He explains that "we cannot conceive
of a reason which consciously responds to a bidding from the outside
with respect to its judgments" (G 448). You may of course choose to
act on a desire, but insofar as you take the act to be yours, you think
you have made it your maxim to act on this desire. If you feel that
the desire impelled you into the act, you do not regard the act as a
product of your will, but as involuntary. The point is not that you
must believe that you are free, but that you must choose as if you
were free. It is important to see that this is quite consistent with
believing yourself to be fully determined. To make it vivid, imagine
that you are participating in a scientific experiment, and you know
that today your every move is programmed by an electronic device
implanted in your brain. The device is not going to bypass your
thought processes, however, and make you move mechanically, but
rather to work through them: it will determine what you think.
Perhaps you get up and decide to spend the morning working. You no
sooner make the decision than it occurs to you that it must have
have no control over the form this difference ultimately takes, then
the motivating thought is genuinely threatened. Postulating God as
the author of the laws of nature is a way of guaranteeing that other
noumenal forces will cooperate with our good intentions, and leaves
our moral interest in place. In the Groundwork, Kant says:
the idea of a pure intelligible world as a whole of all intelligences to which
we ourselves belong as rational beings . . . is always a useful and permissible
idea for the purpose of a rational faith. This is so even though all knowledge
terminates at its boundary, for through the glorious idea of a universal realm
of end-in-themselves (rational beings) a lively interest in the moral law can
be awakened in us. (G 462)
4. But the result of the Argument from Spontaneity may seem too
strong. If the will is free, moral evil is unintelligible, for if this
argument is correct, moral evil is the pure will's wholly unmoti-
vated abandonment of its freedom. However, this is exactly Kant's
view: evil is unintelligible. Neither a good will nor an evil will
admits of explanation, for both must be regarded as grounded in the
person's own free and spontaneous choice. If these choices could be
explained, they would be derived from something else, and then
they would not be the spontaneous choices that they purport to be
(R 21). Yet it is evil that is unintelligible, for it is in the evil choice
that the will falls away from its freedom. Kant says:
Evil could have sprung only from the morally-evil (not from mere limita-
tions in our nature); and yet the original predisposition is a predisposition to
good; there is then for us no conceivable ground from which the moral evil
in us could originally have come. (R 43)
Moral evil is a Fall, in the Biblical sense, and it is exactly as hard to
understand as the Fall in the Bible (R 19,- 4iff.).
In fact, Kant goes so far as to deny that what Sidgwick calls moral
or neutral freedom, the freedom to choose between good and evil, is
really a conception of freedom at all:
freedom can never be located in the fact that the rational subject is able to
make a choice in opposition to his (legislative) reason, even though experi-
ence proves often enough that this does happen (though we cannot compre-
hend how this is possible). . . . Only freedom in relation to the internal
legislation of reason is properly a capacity; the possibility of deviating from
it is an incapacity. (MM 226-27)
The postulates of pure practical reason all proceed from the principle of moral-
ity, which is not a postulate but a law by which reason directly determines the
will. This will. . . requires these necessary conditions for obedience to its
precept. These postulates are not theoretical dogmas but presuppositions of
necessarily practical import; thus, while they do not extend speculative
knowledge, they give objective reality to the ideas of speculative reason in
general (by means of their relation to the practical sphere), and they justify it
in holding to concepts even the possibility of which it could not otherwise
venture to affirm.
These postulates are those of immortality, of freedom affirmatively re-
garded (as the causality of a being so far as he belongs to the intelligible
world), and of the existence of God. (C2 132)
And Kant urges us to "cast the veil of philanthropy over the faults of
others, not merely by softening but also by silencing our judgments"
(MPV466).21
The positive conception of freedom, then, is not to be given a
theoretical employment. The idea of positive freedom is not sup-
posed to show that moral evil is so irrational that it is impossible.
Indeed, Kant does not propose that we should explain actions theo-
retically by referring them to the free choice of maxims in an intelli-
gible world. The role of the idea of freedom and the intelligible world
is, rather, a practical one. It provides a conception of ourselves which
motivates us to obey the moral law.
In Kant's philosophy, freedom of the will cannot be theoretically
II VIRTUE AS FREEDOM
6. But this may not seem to resolve the problem. Clearly it is not
enough that we act for moral ends; we must also do so because they
are moral ends. We must adopt the ends themselves freely, as ends
determined by the moral law. But if we must be free in order to adopt
moral ends, then adopting moral ends cannot be what makes us free.
The answer to this objection lies in the special nature of internal
freedom. To explain the answer, we must take a detour through
another problem about the adoption of moral ends. Kant argues that
the duties of virtue are all of broad obligation; they do not require
definite acts which may simply be discharged (MPV 39o).25 The duty
to advance a moral end is one of broad obligation because it is an
imperfect duty; the law does not say exactly what or how much we
should do to advance the end. But what about the duty to adopt a
moral end? Kant thinks that the adoption of an end is necessarily a
free act, for he says:
Another may indeed force me to do something which is not my end (but is
only the means to some other's end); but he cannot force me to make it my
own end, for I can have no end except of my own making. (MPV 381-82)
will notice facts that are associated with that end in a certain way,
and things that bear on the promotion of the end will occur to her.
This is a general point about ends, and does not apply only to moral
ends. To see this, imagine that I claim that I am Charlotte's friend,
and that I have her happiness as my end. But imagine also that it
seldom or never occurs to me to do anything in particular to make
Charlotte happy. When I see something in a shop window that suits
her taste exactly, I do not think, "now that is something Charlotte
would really like/ 7 and go in to purchase it. When I look at the
calendar on what happens to be her birthday, it does not occur to me
that it is her birthday, and I should telephone. When I hear of some
catastrophe happening in her neighborhood, I do not wonder about
the possible bearing of this event on her safety and comfort. These
things just do not come to me. Under these circumstances, surely
Charlotte would be entitled to complain that there is no real sense
in which I have her happiness as my end.26 It would not be pertinent
for me to reply that I have no direct control over what occurs to me.
To find certain features of the world salient is part of our notion of
what it is to have an end. To have an end is to see the world in a
certain way. But what determines salience most directly lies in our
sensory and representational capacities - and so in the passive part
of our nature. To adopt an end is to perform an internal action. But it
is also to undergo certain changes, changes in your representational
capacities. It is to come to perceive the world in the way that having
the end requires.
When the end is one that is suggested by natural inclination, we
are already inclined to perceive the world in the relevant way. In-
deed, that you are inclined to perceive the world that way is the form
that the incentive takes. Our sensible nature here helps us out. But
when the end is one prompted by reason this may not be the case.
Here, you are imposing a change on your sensible nature, and your
sensible nature may, and probably will, be recalcitrant. Although
adopting an end is a volitional act, it is one that you can only do
gradually and perhaps incompletely.
This is why the duty to adopt an end is of broad obligation. You
cannot, just by making a resolution, acquire a virtue or recover from
a vice. Or better still, we will say that you can, because you are free,
but then we must say that only what happens in the future estab-
lishes whether you have really made the resolution or not. I do not
highest ground of his maxims whereby he was an evil man (and thus puts on
the new man), he is, so far as his principle and cast of mind are concerned, a
subject susceptible of goodness, but only in continuous labor and growth is
he a good man. That is, he can hope ... to find himself upon the good
(though strait) path of continual progress from bad to better. For Him who
penetrates to the intelligible ground of the heart (the ground of all maxims
of the will [Willkiir]) and for whom this unending progress is a unity, i.e., for
God, that amounts to his being actually a good man (pleasing to Him); and,
thus viewed, this change can be regarded as a revolution. (R 47-48)27
The appearance of freedom in the phenomenal world, then, is
virtue - a constant struggle to love and respect the humanity in
oneself and others, and to defeat the claims inclination tries to make
against that humanity. So far from committing him to a mysterious
dualism, Kant's theory of the atemporal nature of freedom permits
him to harmonize freedom with a temporal account of the acquisi-
tion of virtue. One achieves virtue through a gradual habituation,
and, as in Aristotle's ethics, the sign of success is gladness in its
practice. In the Religion, Kant says:
This resolve, then, encouraged by good progress, must needs beget a joyous
frame of mind, without which man is never certain of having really attained
a love for the good, i.e., of having incorporated it into his maxim. (R 2in)
To the extent to which moral ends have really become our ends, we
will take pleasure in the pursuit of them. Indeed we have all of the
emotions appropriate to having an end. In the Metaphysical Princi-
ples of Virtue, Kant speaks of gratitude (MPV 454-56) and even
sympathetic feeling (MPV 456-58) as being required. He is quick to
qualify these remarks, for we have no direct control over our feel-
ings. Yet it is his view that one who does adopt an end will normally
come to have the feelings that are natural to a person who has this
end. If the end were suggested by sensibility, we would already have
had the feelings, but though the end is adopted on moral grounds we
should still come to have them eventually.28 When explaining the
relation between inclination and morality in the duty of benefi-
cence, for example, Kant says:
Beneficence is a duty. Whoever often exercises this and sees his beneficent
purpose succeed comes at last really to love him whom he has benefited.
When therefore it is said, "Thou shalt love thy neighbor as thyself/' this
does not mean you should directly (at first) love and through this love
Kant does not mean that we will come to act solely from the inclina-
tion, but rather that the inclination will be in harmony with reason
and so will no longer be an impediment. As long as we do not act
from inclination, but because the ends are dictated by the law, this is
no detriment to our moral character. On the contrary, it shows that
we have advanced toward the complete control over our sensuous
nature that is implied by freedom.
So we do not exactly need to adopt moral ends freely in order to be
free. If we come, over time, to act purely for the sake of moral ends,
it will come to be true that we are, timelessly, free.
NOTES