Aquinas and The Principle of Sufficient Reason
Aquinas and The Principle of Sufficient Reason
PRINCIPLE OF
SUFFICIENT
REASON
Saint Thomas
Aquinas and the
Principle of Sufficient
Reason
www.ScottMSullivan.com
The volume and page numbers, as well as paragraph numbers (in some
cases) which follow the citations of these texts, are from the editions list-
ed in the bibliography. The Leonine edition citation is also listed where
available.
Table of Contents
CHAPTER I:
Introduction 7
CHAPTER II:
Arguments Against the Principle of Sufficient Reason 47
CHAPTER III:
The Principle Stated and Its Meaning 63
CHAPTER IV:
Dialectical Arguments for the Weak and Mild
Principle of Sufficient Reason 101
CHAPTER V:
Necessary Truths and Our Ability to Know Them 133
CHAPTER VI:
The Reductio Ad Absurdum Argument for the
Principle of Sufficient Reason 161
CHAPTER VII:
Causal Principles and Conclusions 187
CHAPTER VIII:
Replies to Objections 215
CHAPTER IX:
Conclusion . . . < 239
"Leibniz, in his writings, spread out such an abundance of seminal
thoughts that there is hardly another philosopher who can be
compared with him in this respect. A portion of these ideas were
worked out even in his own day, and with his collaboration; another
portion were forgotten but were later rediscovered and further
developed. This justifies the expectation that in his works there is
still a great deal that now appears dead and buried but that will
eventually enjoy its resurrection."1
- Gottlob Frege
(<
The principle of sufficient reason had been formulated long before
Leibnitz.'*2
- Reginald Garrigou Lagrange
3 "Wisdom 1M knowledge ahoul ccrluln causes and principles." Aristotle, Meta 1982al,
7/ic Complete Work$ qf Arlitotl? vol, //, ctl. Jonathan Barnes, Ir. W.D. Ross (Princeton:
Princeton Unlveully Pmi. I MM), IM V
SI, 'lltomas Aquiim* and tin* /V/< 7/>/r ofSuJIicit'iil Reason
ophy and science operate would of course be vindicated, and any conclu-
sions based on it, justified as well.
So what exactly is this principle? In our unreflective, intuitional, ev-
eryday speech, it goes something like "Things do not just happen out of
the blue/ something has to make them happen!" In ancient and medi-
eval times, the principle about which we are concerned was sometimes
implicit, and other times explicit, albeit with various formulations, such
as; "Nothing gives what it does not have," "There cannot be more in the
effect than what was contained in the cause," "Whatever begins to exist
must have a cause," or more frequently, ex nihilo nihil fit - "Out of noth-
ing, nothing comes."
In this work, I will propose that the principle of sufficient reason is the
grand formulation of these intuitions and scholastic dictums, and thus is
I he principle that lies behind all of our casual inferences. Leibniz explicitly
coined this term, yet he claimed not to discover any new principle, rather
only to encapsulate all the implicit formulations used in the history of
philosophy. The principle of sufficient reason is commonly formulated as
such: "Every being has the sufficient reason for its existence (i.e., the ade-
quate ground or basis in existence) either in itself or in another."4 Stated
negatively, "Out of nothing, nothing comes" (being neither comes from
nor can be determined by sheer nothing).5 The principle of sufficient rea-
son, then, is simply an attempt to conveniently summarize, in one ba-
sic formula, the common intuitions of everyday life and what other greal
philosophers have either presupposed or loosely articulated in these more
specialized formulas of the "principle of causality,"
Leibniz once said that without the principle of sufficient reason, very
I i 11 le in philosophy and science could be demonstrated. In a similar vein,
I he contemporary Thomistic philosopher, Norris Clarke, has called the
principle of sufficient reason the dynamic principle of metaphysics, since
II is in virtue of this very principle that enables the mind to pass from
one being to another in order to make sense out of it: "All advance in
'I Some of Leibniz's formulations of the principle of sufficient reason ("Nothing takes
place without sufficient reason/' "Nothing exists without there being a greater reason for
It In exist than for it not to exist," "Nothing happens without a reason why it should be so
ml her than otherwise," or simply, nihil est sine ratione) are perhaps the most familiar.
5 'Ihose propositions may appear to differ; however, I will explain the relationship be-
tween lhe principle of sufficient reason and various causal and ex nihilo principles in
Chapter III.
St. 'Ihomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
thought to infer the existence of some new being from what we already
know depends upon this principled
Although having different formulations, it is fair to say that some for-
mulation of the principle of sufficient reason has enjoyed widespread ac-
ceptance throughout the history of Western philosophy. Yet "nothing is
so true that it cannot be denied [at least] orally."7 The principle has its
share of deniers; most notably Nicholas of Autrecourt in the 14th century,
David Hume in the 18th century, and many philosophers in our age, such
as J. L. Mackie8 and William Rowe.9 In fact, today the common tendency
in academia seems to regard the principle with suspicion, and very often
the phrase "principle of sufficient reason" is loaded with contempt and
derogatory implications. Most contemporary literature is not very favor-
able to the principle, and bashing the principle as "rationalist" seems to
be a sort of current philosophical fad. Indeed, Quentin Smith is correct
in saying, "The Principle of Sufficient Reason has very few contemporary
defenders of any of its versions.. ,"10 The anti-principle of sufficient reason
mentality enjoys such an extensive ascendancy that one can casually dis-
miss the principle with little more than a verbal wave of the hand.11
6 William Norris Clarke, The One and the Many: A Contemporary Thomistic Metaphys-
ics (South Bend: University of Notre Dame Press, 2001), 21. Emphasis mine.
7 St. Thomas Aquinas, In Post. Ana., 1. 19.
8 J. L. Mackie, The Miracle of Theism: Arguments for and Against the Existence of God
(New York: Oxford University Press, 1982).
9 William Rowe, The Cosmological Argument (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1975).
10 Quentin Smith, "A Defense of a Principle of Sufficient Reason," Metaphilosophy, Vol.
26(1-2), January/April 1995,97.
11 For example, we could consider Ginger Lee's 2006 Ph.D. dissertation, David Hume
and The Principle of Sufficient Reason (Marquette University, 2006) which rejects the
principle for apparently no reason other than an uncritical acceptance of Hume's critique
of causality coupled with an assertion about the truth of Schopenhauer's transcendental
epistemology. It declares, "The transcendental position shares with Hume a total lack of
confidence in our ability to access what is out there'", 189. Such cavalier rejections are
commonplace. Rarely are arguments for the principle laken Inlo conuldtfrullon, mid co-
gent arguments offered against it are of equal rarity.
10
Introduction
only presuppose the principle, but also, more importantly, simply could
not survive without it. The first is the common sense intuition shared by
nearly all of us that things do not just happen for no reason. As we men-
tioned, the "out of nothing, nothing comes" principle is very commonly
presupposed in daily inferences, and numerous examples are available
from just a brief reflection. From the sound of a dog barking, we infer a
real dog is the source of that sound; from certain tracks formed in the
mud, we intuit that some animal is responsible for those shapes; from
the sip of coffee, we ascertain that the taste we experience is the result of
that action, and so on. It should be obvious how at least some versions of
the principle of sufficient reason are involved in such everyday examples.
Indeed, it is difficult to see how daily life could function normally with-
out such a presupposition.
What is perhaps less apparent, or at least what seems to escape many
academics, is the frequency with which this principle has been employed
in both philosophy and science. Science and philosophy too to a great ex-
lent require such a principle. Why? That a certain state of affairs can be
explained (that is, reasons given for why it is so) is a fundamental assump-
l ion of nearly any investigation: philosophical, scientific, or everyday com-
mon sense. What we might call a "sufficient reason presumption" is that
reality is intelligible; hence, there is a reason or explanation why things
are the way they are, and so with enough reflection and/or investigation
we can, at least in principle, discover that reason. It seems patently clear
I hat without such a presumption, it is futile to begin any investigation,
therefore making the principle of sufficient reason an imperative starting
point for practically all philosophy and science. Without understanding
how critical such a notion is, one will not grasp the radically foundational
and ubiquitous nature of the principle of sufficient reason. Let us look at a
few examples to clarify this point.
11
•S7. 'Ihomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
121 am reminded of a citation by Maritain taken from Georges Urbain regarding what
scientists might think of philosophical idealism. "There is perhaps not a single chemist
who confuses the reality of barium sulfate with the idea he has formed of it. I was once
curious enough to put the question to some of them. Ihey all found it rather queer. From
the startled looks they gave me I could see they all thought me mad to ask such a ques-
tion." Jacques Maritain, The Degrees ojKnowledge, tr. Gerald B. Phelan (South Bend, IN:
University of Notre Dame Press, 1995), 52, n.38I. This observation correlates my own
experience that philosophers ought not to assume that most scientists gel deeply Involved
in philosophy of science. In the same way, I find thai few malhemflllclumi have bothered
asking themselves aboul ihe ontologlcnl SUUUN of number*,
Introduction
reaction between the two magnets. Iron filings may represent the fields,
but of course the iron filings themselves are not the magnetic fields. What
is a "black hole?" It is a place where ordinary gravity has become so ex-
treme that it overwhelms all other forces in the universe, including light.
But if we cannot see them, how do we know they exist? Scientists infer
their existence by the observed instances of extreme gravitational pulls
confined to a particular area. The black holes are not directly observable.
They are known to exist through their effects. We may also ask, "How did
the universe originate?" Many scientists believe that it happened about
13.7 billion years ago with a massive explosion called the Big Bang. Of
course, no one has directly witnessed the emergence of the universe, but
scientists make the inference nevertheless because they observe a certain
effect (like the expansion rate of the universe), and reason that there must
be a reason for the phenomena, thus something must be the reason why it
is happening at all. Nobody has ever seen the Big Bang that initialized our
universe, but scientists quite reasonably infer that it existed based upon
the effects we see today.
Nor is this presumption of intelligibility confined merely to the un-
disputed success stories. How did human beings arrive on Earth? Many
"old-school" Darwinian biologists tell us that it is the result of a slow,
constant, and consistent series of chance genetic mutation acted upon by
natural selection. But "punk eek" (punctuated equilibrium) evolution-
ists challenge this gradualism. This explanation is not sufficient, they
say, since the evidence from the fossil record does not bear out Darwin's
theory of gradual change. The fossil record shows more sporadic jumps,
hence the process must have occurred in spurts, with periods of little
change ("stasis") and then massive change, leveling out again to a period
of very little change. But again, still other evolutionists challenge both
of these positions. Both the Darwinian evolutionist's explanation and
I he punk eek explanation lack explanatory scope since they do not suffi-
ciently account for the origin of life in the first place. This third group of
panspermia evolutionists holds that life must come from life, and so we
should seek our ancestry in the realm of outer space, being open to the
idea that alien life forms "seeded" the earth with life millions of years
ago. The point here IN that regardless of whichever interpretation has
more merit, it is still assumed by all parlies that something must explain
the arrival of human brings on our planet.
13
St. 'Ilionms Aquinas mul the I'riciple of Sufficient Reason
In all of ihese cases, there are questions about the world - the scientist
asks why something is the case, what makes something happen, etc., and
there are reasons "out there" to be found. The world (at least in itself) is an
understandable and explainable place. There are reasons why these things
occur. If one group gives an explanation that is inadequate in some way
(say, for example, it lacks explanatory scope), another group will point out
the inadequacy in the theory. There may indeed be debate over whether or
not a thesis is adequate, but never once is the scientific mind content with
statements like "One's eye color does not come from anything," "Nothing is
responsible for diseases," "Nothing is causing this extreme gravitational at-
traction," "The human species came from absolutely nothing," and so on. In
all of these cases, reason passes from an observable instance of something to
infer the existence of something else that is not directly observable in order
to explain, ground, and make sense of the first. Without this assumption
that the world is intelligible in this way, science could do very little. A cha-
otic world in which diseases, the human species, not to mention car deal-
erships and supermarkets can just pop into existence out of nowhere, is not
the world in which we live nor the world that science investigates. Ex nihilo
nihil fit is therefore an important scientific principle.13
13 Nagel writes, "Science is driven by the assumption that the world is intelligible....
It seems to me that one cannot really understand the scientific world view unless one
assumes that the intelligibility of the world...This assumption is a form of the principle
of sufficient reason— that everything about the world can at some level be understood,
and that if many things, even the most universal, initially seem arbitrary, that is because
there are further things we do not know, which explain why they are not arbitrary after
all." Thomas Nagel, Mind and Cosmos: Why the Materialist Neo-Darwinian Conception
of Nature Is Almost Certainly False (Oxford University Press, 2012) 17.
14 Plato, Phaedo, 96a. taken from Plato: The Collected Dialo^um, ir. Hugh Tivdennick
(New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1961),7H
14 ._.__
Introduction
about ethics, the mind/body problem, or the nature of God, just where
would the search for wisdom be without a starting principle that things
like these need explaining? Philosophers seek answers and are not typi-
cally satisfied with primitive inexplicable notions. The notion that states
of affairs just do not come into being for no reason and that the universe
is therefore intelligible gives us a sort philosophical "right" to ask "why"
certain things are the way they are. Such a starting point is a critical fac-
tor to the wonder that is specific to philosophy. Without such a principle,
philosophy would not get very far at all.
Before we look at some historical examples, let me clarify a point.
As I briefly mentioned, this assumption of intelligibility, which I am
calling the principle of sufficient reason, comes in many shapes and
sizes. It frequently appears under different formulations, and often is
not explicitly stated at all. It may appear from time to time in what I
will call its logical form, and at other times, in its ontological form.
The point being is that when one goes looking for a principle that pos-
IIs reality as intelligible and require reasons, he ought not to look for
any single formulation of the principle in the history of philosophy.
One needs to be open to different ways of saying (or assuming) the
same thing. So while Leibniz's full-blown statement of the principle
will hardly appear as something used by other thinkers, nevertheless
some version of it is always present in philosophical reasoning. Conse-
quently, the history of philosophy is full of examples that make use of
interpretations of the principle of sufficient reason.
The listing here does not, in any way, claim to be exhaustive of all the
I hinkers who have used the principle. Rather, it is simply a concise attempt
lo show, by only a handful of examples, just how radically important, wide-
spread, and foundational the principle has been in philosophy.
Parmenides' argument against change and multiplicity is a good place to
slart.15 Parmenides argues for the impossibility of change and multiplicity
based on his hard disjunction of being and not-being. Things cannot come
anew from being, nor can they be distinguished from one another by being
(since whatever is already has "being"), nor can things come from or be dis-
tinguished by nothing Hrgo, change and multiplicity of being is impossible.
Parmenides then wunlu us lo conclude that since change and multiplicity
cannot be accounted lor, mich notions should be rejected. But why does
15 Aristotle, 'th$ Phytic** IVinl ivibio,
15
St Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
16 Jonathan Barnes argues that Parmenides* use of the idea that all happenings must
have an explanation, and that explanation must be sufficient for what they explain, is
an application of the principle of sufficient reason. "The phrase husteron e prosthen is
sometimes translated 'later rather than sooner,' or at one time rather than at another/
Thus, Parmenides is applying the Principle of Sufficient Reason." Jonathan Barnes, The
Presocratic Philosophers (London: Routledge, 1989), 187.
17 l'or example, we see this view discussed throughout PIIUO'N Mem).
Introduction
Hod. Plato thinks that the feature of incorrigibility (on the epistemic side)
must be matched or explained by certain features on the metaphysical
side. If the knowledge is necessary and unchanging, so too must be the
objects of that knowledge. The existence of incorrigible knowledge needs
to be explained by the existence of unchanging, eternal, abstract objects.18
'1 hus, from the epistemological fact about certain knowledge, Plato makes
metaphysical inferences. The Forms are the ontological conclusions that are
inferred to exist based upon certain epistemological premises. It is not that
Plato claims that we can see or experience these Forms with our senses;
ml her, Plato thinks that abstract objects must exist because they are the
only sorts of things that can account for episteme. Plato wants to say that the
l;nrms (if we may use the Aristotelian terminology) are at least the material
i atises of our knowledge, even if something else, such as illumination by the
I;orm of the Good, may serve as some sort of efficient cause as well.19
But one might wonder why one should bother with claiming the exis-
tence of unseen abstract objects. Why is it that certain knowledge cannot
jus! exist as an uncaused "brute fact," with no explanation at all? Why
not just say that episteme has no cause or explanation? The only answer
seems to be that Plato just implicitly rules this option out. Out of nothing,
nothing comes - not even episteme. Episteme needs to be explained and
accounted for, and the Forms, although not a sufficient condition, are at
least a necessary condition for its existence.
Aristotle thought the very nature of philosophical inquiry was to know
the principles of things, and so defends the idea of causes as explanations.
Wisdom, he says, not only deals with the causes and principles of things,
lull wisdom actually is a causal understanding of the world.20 That things in
t he world can be explained in terms of their causes is taken for granted, and
I his notion serves as the whole basis of the philosophical enterprise. That
IK "If mind and true opinion are two distinct classes, then I say that there certainly are
IIK'NC sclf-existent ideas unperceived by sense and apprehended only by the mind." Plato,
ihmicus, 51d. Translation taken from Plato Collected Dialogues tr. Benjamin Jowett, 1178.
I y Not to mention other indications that the Forms serve as some sort of formal/efficient
i niisc: 'Tor I cannot help thinking that if there be anything beautiful other than absolute
hnuity, that can only be beautiful in as far as it partakes of absolute beauty - and this I
Nhould say of everything. Do you agree in this notion of the cause?... I leave all that, which
IN only confusing to me, and simply and singly, and perhaps foolishly, hold and am assured
In my own mind that nothing makes a thing beautiful but the presence and participation of
bcHiiiy In whatever way or manner obtained." Plato, Phaedo: lOOb-e. op. cit.
20 ArlNtolle, Metaphysial I VH2«I.
17
St, Ihomtis Aquinas ami the Priciplc of Sufficient Reason
we can and need to explain things in terms of causes and principles enables
Aristotle to frequently make existential inferences from things directly per-
ceived to what must exist to ground those observances. Take motion, for
example. How is it that motion occurs? What must reality be like in order
for there to be motion at all? The Megarics took the position that there is
only actuality; anything that is not actuality is nothingness. But Aristotle
says this view does away with movement and becoming. Since movement
and becoming are obvious facts about the world around us, there must be
more to reality than what the Megarics say. The Megaric dichotomy is false,
and Aristotle goes between its horns by saying there is a third alternative.
There is more to being that simple actuality, another level of being he calls
"potency/' Potency is a level of being that is real but not actual, it is an abil-
ity to be act but which is not act.21
We see here a lucid example of reason moving from the observed to the
unobserved. Aristotle moves from directly observable motion to inferring
the existence of a non-observable level of being called potency. But why
does he posit the existence of this unobservable "potency?" Why say such
a thing exists in any way at all? What is the methodology or reasoning
process behind this inference? There seems to be no other option except
for holding that if a given set of alternatives cannot suffice in explaining X,
another thing must be added until X is sufficiently accounted for and ex-
plained (because X must be explained). But this "adding of entities" meth-
od is really nothing other than presupposing that something cannot come
from nothing. Since what we have cannot suffice for an explanation (and
since "out of nothing, nothing comes," ergo nothing is not a viable option),
21 This discussion occurs in Aristotles Metaphysics, Book IX, 1047a4 ff. Jonathan
Barnes argues that Aristotle makes use of the principle of sufficient reason in the Physics
as well: "Aristotle later applied the Principle of Sufficient Reason: Physics 252a4" Jonathan
Barnes, The Presocratic Philosophers (London: Routledge, 1989), 614. For further discus-
sion on Aristotles use of the principle of sufficient reason in the Metaphysics, Vasilis
Politis argues that "[Aristotle] is clearly working with some version of the principle of
sufficient reason." He concludes by saying that Aristotle's philosophical project, in that
it is a search for explanations or causes, must presuppose an assumption of the principle
of sufficient reason: "If we ask why Aristotle is working with such a strong principle of
sufficient reason, the answer is, evidently, because he wants to push the overall project,
i.e., the project of searching for explanations - reasons, causes - as far is it will go." Vasilis
Politis, Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Aristotle and the Metaphysics (London: Rout-
ledge, 2004) 273-5. Others argue that Aristotle's need to explain motion follows motion s
characterization as an accident. See John F. X. Knasas, "Thomistic Existentialism and the
Proofo Ex Molu at Contra Gentiles I, c. 13," 'Ihe 'lhomist 59 (1995): 591-615.
18
Introduction
another entity must be added, and so on. The idea that motion can be
just an unexplainable "brute fact," without any reason or principle behind
It, seems to be an impossible alternative for Aristotle. This is the same
methodology we also see operative in the philosophical distinctions of
form/matter and substance/accident. Things need reasons, motion needs
a reason, and the doctrine of potency helps to fill that role.22
One could also mention St. Augustine's famous argument from eternal
I ruths to an eternal mind that grounds those truths.23 In short, humans
a re all aware of ideas they have within their souls, ideas which by their
very nature are universal and necessary. But these universal and necessary
Ulcus cannot originate from us, nor can they come from the external ma-
terial world, since these are contingent beings lacking any characteristic
of universality or necessity. Ergo, there must be some necessary being or
denial mind that serves as a transcendent anchor for these truths.
But again, as we asked of Plato, why does Augustine think these truths
need an explanation or ground at all? Why is it that they cannot just be
"eternally true" without any justification or "ontological ground?" Pre-
sumably, it is because he thinks it is simply evident that things (in this
i use, necessary truths) need reasons as to why they are a certain way and
not otherwise. Something must account for these ideas; it cannot just be
"not hing." If nothing accounted for these things, these ideas would be lack-
IIIK a sufficient reason. Since contingent beings insufficiently account for
t hese truths, our minds must look elsewhere and assert the existence of a
holier being can better account for them.
'Ihe Arabic scholastics utilized an idea which in modern times has
been coined, "the principle of determination." Thinkers in this tradi-
llnn frequently invoked a need for some selecting agent to determine
the existence of one possibility over other alternatives. The principle of
determination holds that between things equally possible (to be or not to
he), some sort of determinant, cause, reason, or selecting agent (murajjih)
Is called for to bring into being one possible over the other. We see this
Idea for example in al-Ghazali:
19
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
24 Al-Ghazali, "The Jerusalem Tract," trans, and ed. A.L. Tibawi, The Islamic Quarterly,
9 (1965), 98 (emphasis mine), cited in William Lane Craig, The Cosmological Argument:
From Plato to Leibniz (Eugene, OR: Wipf and Stock, 1980), 58.
25 "Everything that is belongs to one of two kinds. In the case of beings of the first
kind, existence is not involved in their essence. These are called 'of possible existence.' In
the case of being of the second kind, its essence does involve existence. These are called
'necessarily existent."' Alfarabi, Philosophische Abhandlungen, ed. F. Dieterichi (Leiden:
Brill, 1890), 90, cited in Craig, 81.
26 Alfarabi text from Robert Hammond, The Philosophy ofAlfarabi ami Its Influence on
Medieval Thought (New York: Hobsen Book Press, 1947), 20, died In Craig, H<T.
20
Introduction
Along the same lines, Avicenna's argument for the existence of God
is interesting because it seems to anticipate the principle of sufficient
reason by posing a dichotomy that resembles later formulations of the
principle. Avicenna offers an argument from contingency to the exis-
lence of a necessary being, arguing that a series of contingent beings must
terminate into that necessary being.
Whatever has being must either have a reason for its being or have
no reason for it. If it has a reason, then it is contingent... If on the
other hand it has no reason for its being in any way whatsoever,
then it is necessary in its being. This rule being confirmed, I shall
now proceed to prove that there is in being a being which has no
reason for its being.
Such a being is either contingent or necessary. If it is necessary,
I hen the point we sought to prove is established. If, on the other
hand, it is contingent, that which is contingent cannot enter upon
being, except for some reason which sways the scales in favor of its
being and against non-being. If the reason is also contingent, then
I here is a chain of contingents linked to one another, and there is
no being at all, for this being which is the subject of our hypothesis
cannot enter into being so long as it is not proceeded by an infinite
succession of beings, which is absurd.27
I n this passage, Avicenna seems to use the word "reason" in a more restrict-
ed sense to mean "cause." Thus reformulated it reads, "Whatever has being
musl either be caused or necessary." This means that in Avicennas universe,
I lie existence of every existing being is accounted for. Whatever exists is either
i mised by another or it exists a se. There are no tertium quid sorts of beings
I hal have no reason at all, that is, an alleged being that exists neither necessar-
ily nor through a cause. This dichotomy of "whatever exists, exists either from
I he necessity of its own nature or from the causal efficacy of another being" is
what we will later call a "strong" principle of sufficient reason.
'I he Jewish thinker Moses Maimonides assumes the truthfulness of ex
iiihilo nihil fit in his own argumentation for the existence of God. Rabbi
21
,S'/f 'I llamas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
Moses wants to show that the position that no things are eternal is false.
If no things were eternal, then it is possible that all things could cease to
exist, and if that, nothing would exist. But if nothing ever existed, then
nothing would exist now either: "All things therefore must come to an end,
and then nothing would ever be in existence, for there would not exist any
being to produce anything. Consequently, nothing whatever would ex-
ist."28 Whatever one might think of Maimonides' modal inference that all
possibilities must be actualized over infinite time is an entirely separate
issue from the fact that Maimonides assumes and implicitly holds to the
truth of at least some version of the principle of sufficient reason.
Let us move ahead to St. Thomas Aquinas and his well-known Quin-
que Viae. These arguments start with apparent facts about the world,
and proceed by reason into the causes of these apparent facts. Motion,
causation, contingency, degrees of perfection, and things acting for an
end all call for a more complete explanation - a prime mover, a first
cause, etc. But how would these arguments ever get off the ground with-
out presupposing that these sorts of events call for explanation in the
first place? It should be easy for us to see and agree with the words of
Gilson, "Ex nihilo nihil fit; therefore all movement presupposes a mover;
every effect presupposes a cause; every contingent being a being per se;
every series a first term; all order an orderer."29
One can make a similar observation about Aquinas' argument for the
existence and nature of the human soul. Human souls are not the kinds
of things that one can directly observe. Rather, their existence and nature
are conclusions derived from philosophical analysis. Aquinas holds that
the soul is the "first principle of life of those things which live." This prin-
ciple is not a body (for then all bodies would be alive), but the act of a body.
Human souls have the additional properties of being incorporeal and sub-
28 Moses Maimonides, The Guide for the Perplexed, pt. II ch. 1, 2nd ed. rev., trans. M.
Friedlander (London: George Routledge and Sons, 1928), 152.
29 Etienne Gilson, The Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas, tr. Edward Bullough (New
York: Barnes and Noble Books, 1993), 94. Norman Kretzmann concurs that Aquinas' cos-
mological proofs presuppose some version of the principle of sufficient reason: "Aquinas
shows that he assumes or considers self-evident some form of'the Principle of Sufficient
Reason [PSR], a principle that in its strongest form maintains that nothing can exist and
no fact can obtain without there being an explanation for that thing's existence or for that
fact's obtaining.'" Norman Kretzmann, The Metaphysics of Theism: Aquinas'* Natural
Theology in Summa Contra Gentiles I (Oxford: Clarendon Prow, 1W7), 107,
22
Introduction
M) S.T 1.75,1-3 (vol, 5, 150) I Im* Aquinas discusses principles of vital operations (vital-
h ofH'rattonis principiumii AM writ wn ihe principle of intellectual operations (principium
hUcllfctuaUs operation!*), In nlhvr wnnk IIICNC vllal and intellectual operations have a
ground In u *uul which U no! IliflNltcilly observable,
23
St, Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
"Everything that has a possibility of being and of not being, needs something
else to make it be, for, as far as it itself is concerned, it is indifferent with
regard to either alternative."31 Aquinas gives a similar argument ab<out all
composite things, whether composed of form and matter or essence and
existence. They, too, need a cause, but this time he states a different reason:
"For things in themselves different cannot unite unless something causes
them to unite."32 On another occasion, Aquinas uses an act/potericy ar-
gument supporting ex nihilo nihil fit regarding the existence of the entire
universe. He says that the most effective way to prove Gods existence is
from the supposition of the eternity of the world, which being supposed, it
seems less manifest that God exists. "For if the world and movement had
a beginning, it is clear that we must suppose some cause to have produced
the world and movement, because whatever becomes anew must take its
origin from some cause of its becoming, since nothing evolves itself from
potentiality to act, or from non-being to being."33
The perceptive reader of Aquinas will also find a striking anticif ation
of Leibniz's critique of Newtonian absolute time and space. Leibniz a>gUed
that space and time could not be eternal and absolute, since there wovld be
no sufficient reason as to why God created the universe when He di{ and
31 Compendium of Theology Part. 1 Ch. 6, vol. 4. Aquinas also uses this sort of'some-
thing that determines two possibilities" argument to argue for final causality: "I cnswer
that, every agent, of necessity, acts for an end. For if in a number of causes ordained^o one
another, the first be removed, the others must, of necessity, be removed also. Now the}rst of ;
all causes is the final cause. The reason of which is that matter does not receive form, %Ve in
so far as it is moved by an agent; for nothing reduces itself from potentiality to act \ut an
agent does not move except out of intention for an end. For if the agent were not domi-
nate to some particular effect, it would not do one thing rather than another: consequently
in order that it produce a determinate effect, it must, of necessity, be determined Usome
certain one, which has the nature of an end" S.T. I-II.1.2, vol.6, 9, emphasis mine.
32 "..Every composite has a cause, for things in themselves different cannot unite nless
something causes them to unite" S.T. 1.3.7, (vol. 4, 47), emphasis mine. We will eplore
texts like these more thoroughly in a later chapter.
33 "Cum nihil educatse depotentia in actum vel de non esse in esse," S.C.G. 1.13, vol. 3> 33.
Similarly, "Everything which was not always manifestly has a cause whereas this is 0 t so
manifest of what always was." (Si mundus non semper fuit, quam si semper fuisseUmne
enim quod non semper fuit, manifestum est habere causam.) S.T. 1.46.1 ad.6, vol. < 480,
emphasis mine. This should not be confused with Aquinas* frequent disagreemenwith
the ex nihilo nihil fit axiom of the ancient philosophers (i.e., S.T. 1.45.2 ad.l, vol.' 456
and De Pot. q. 3 a. 1) where that statement meant that a material cause musl alw*s be
presupposed. Aquinas thinks of course that God can create ex nihilo and. In such tase,
there Is an cfliclenl cause bul no material cause,
24
Introduction
where He did. Aquinas says something remarkably similar to this idea that
space and time cannot be eternal in response to the claim that the universe
has always existed and thus could not have come into being:
Now God's duration, which is eternity, does not have parts, but is
utterly simple, without before and after... Therefore, the beginning
of the whole of creation is not to be thought of in comparison to
any diverse parts designated in some pre-existing measure... So
that there would have to be a reason in the agent why he brought
the creature into being in this designated part of that duration
rather than at some other preceding or subsequent point. Such a
reason would be required if, beside the totality of created being,
there existed some duration divisible into parts, as is the case in
particular agents, which produce their effects in time, but do not
produce time itself. God however, brought into being both the
creature and time together... Particular bodies are brought into
being not only at a definite time, but also in a definite place; and
since the time and the place in which they are involved are extrinsic
to them, there must be a reason why they are produced in this place
and time rather than in another... Outside the universe of creatures
I here is no time, time having been produced simultaneously with
I hat universe; hence we do not have to look for the reason why it
was produced now and not before...!'34
It is worthy of note that in this text Aquinas seems to recognize what
Leibniz would later; that if space and time were absolute (ie., indepen-
dent beings in their own right) and eternal, God would indeed need a
suilicient reason why He created the universe at one point in space and
I line rather than another. However, Aquinas' response (which is shared
l>y Leibniz, for that matter) is that space and time do not exist inde-
pendently of the divine choice. The divine duration that existed logically
prior to the temporal space-time duration is simple and not composed of
parts, so there is no temporal "before" the creation of the universe with-
in which God must operate. Aquinas' admission of this point suggests
his openness to extending the principle of sufficient reason beyond the
purely ontological level of ens reale to the realm of ens rationis, and even
more particularly, the ratio of choice.
More modern proponents of the principle of sufficient reason frequent-
ly use an exhaustive division In stating the principle: "Whatever exists
25
St Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
26
Introduction
tiny way; and it is from this kind of non-being that nothing is generated,
luntuse in reality out of nothing, nothing comes"36
Aquinas then both implicitly and explicitly accepts and uses an ex ni-
hilo principle, and also has a way of stating something very much like the
principle of sufficient reason. That St. Thomas never explicitly appeals to a
"principle of sufficient reason" here or anywhere else is entirely irrelevant.
I lis argumentation either regularly presupposes it or invokes particular
loi'ins of it. (i.e., "Every changing being needs a cause"; "Every being that
lupins to exist needs a cause"; "Everything that has a possibility of being
in id of not being needs a cause"; "Every finite, composed being needs a
» mi so"; etc.).37 It may be a matter of debate in any of these examples wheth-
rr Aquinas thinks these formulations of the principle of sufficient reason
me* I rue principles in the strict sense or conclusions to an argument. It is
not our concern at this point to show one way or the other. The point at
I his juncture is that Aquinas thinks the principle is true. More will be said
Kiln* on how to categorize the proposition.
I )uns Scotus' argument for the existence of God is an attempt to prove
l hr existence of a divine Being by way of a strict Aristotelian demonstration.
A lulling for Gods "triple primacy" was Scotus' attempt at showing there is
it first in efficient causality, final causality, and perfection. During the course
nl his argumentation, Scotus explicitly appeals twice to an ex nihilo princi-
ple, viz., that something cannot be produced by nothing, for what is nothing
i mises nothing,38 and again later: "From nothing, nothing is able to be."39
Si ol us makes no attempt to defend these statements so critical to his argu-
ment, which suggests he may take them as evident axioms.40
U) "Dicitur enim non ens tripliciter. Uno modo quod nullo modo est; et ex tali non ente
nun fil generatio, quia ex nihilo nihil fit secundum naturam,y> In Meta.} lib. 12 1. 2 n. 14,
t'tnphtisis mine.
S7 ()ne could also add as Aquinas says at S.T. 1.4.2, "Whatever perfection exists in an
rlUvl must be found in the effective cause". We will see that critics of the principle, such as
Will In in Rowe, accuse Aquinas of holding to some version of the principle of sufficient rea-
mm In order for these arguments to be successful. That Aquinas does hold to a principle of
MI Hit/lent reason I certainly agree. That he does so unjustifiably, however, is another matter.
\H "Non a nihilo, quia nullius est causa illud quod nihil est" Opus Oxoniense I dist. II, q. i tr.
In Innnncs Duns Scotus, Philosophical Writings (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett 1987), 39.
.W "... A nullo nihil potest esse." Ibid., 44.
40 William Rowe also crlllclzcH Scotus also on what he seems to think is an unwarrant-
ed itNNcrllon oflhc principle of miflielcnl reason principle. See Rowe, The Cosmological
Argument. 50,
27
St. lliomns Atjuhhis <ind the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
real being, and that nonentity cannot produce any real being, it
is an evident demonstration, that from eternity there has been
something; since what was not from eternity had a beginning;
and what had a beginning must be produced by something else.46
Benedict Spinoza was explicit about his support of the principle. He uses
a common disjunctive style formulation similar to what we saw in Avicen-
na and Aquinas. In The Ethics we read that the proposition, "Everything
which exists, exists either in itself or in something else" is his first axiom.47
Later Spinoza argues that "of everything whatsoever that exists a cause or a
reason must be assigned. .. .This reason or cause must either be contained
in the nature of the thing in question, or external to it."48 Although Spinoza
does not give this axiom a special name, we will see later that it is quite like
what I will call the strong principle of sufficient reason.
Leibniz is the first philosopher to encapsulate all of these various for-
mulations under the term "principle of sufficient reason." He claimed not
to have "discovered" this principle, but only to have recognized its funda-
mental significance. Perhaps the best summary of his view is stated in the
Monadology: "Our reasonings are grounded upon two great principles, that
of contradiction.... And that of sufficient reason, in virtue of which we hold
that there can be no fact real or existing, no statement true, unless there be
a sufficient reason, why it should be so and not otherwise, although these
reasons usually cannot be known by us."49 In the way Leibniz forms the
principle here, we can say that he holds both to an ontological formulation
of the principle of sufficient reason referring to facts "real or existing" as
well as a logical principle of sufficient reason that refers to statements. It
is the ontological formulations of the principle, however, that appear more
frequently in Leibniz's writings, such as "nothing exists without there being
a greater reason for it to exist than for it not to exist,"50 or perhaps more pop-
ularly from this famous passage from the Theodicy:
30
Introduction
M Leibniz, Theodtcy44t Ir. li.M. I luggim! (Peru, IL: Open Court Publishing, 1988), 147.
''2 Leibniz, New Essays on Human Understanding, Ir. Peter Remnant and Jonathan
hennell (Cambridge, New York; (:nmhrUl|(c University Press, 1981), 435.
r
i3 Leibniz, "'Ihe Principles nl'Nitlitre MIUI (iruce Based On Reason," in Philosophical
luHiyi, 210,
31
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
54/fc/d.,321.
32
Introduction
Vi Ibid., 346.
'»ft "To deny this great principle is to do as Epicurus did, who was reduced to deny that
nllitT great principle, namely, the principle of contradiction, which is that every intelligi-
ble enunciation must ell her be (rue or false. Chrysippus undertook to prove that principle
agalnal lipiciirua.bul I think I need not I ml late hi m.T have already said what is sufficient to
jtiMll'y mine, and I might nay nomdhlng more upon It, but perhaps it would be too abstruse
lur thin prcnent dliiput*. And I believe reasonable and Impartial men will grant me that
having forced an tulveriwry to deny that principle IN reducing him nd absurdum" Ibid.
33
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
57 This citation is the translation into English that appears in the end notes to Kant's
Lectures on Metaphysics, 564. Although Kant was critical of this demonstration of the
principle of sufficient reason (claiming that Wolff's argument is guilty of an equivocation
of the term 'nothing/ one meaning the opposite of something and another meaning noth-
ing as non-being), he nevertheless did seem to affirm that the principle was an innate first
principle the human mind.
58 David Hume to John Stewart, February, 1754, in The Letters of David Hume, ed. J. Y.
T. (irelg (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1932), 1: 187.
34
Introduction
forced him to apply this principle only to phenomena and not to the
Ihings in themselves that lie underneath that reality.59
Kant did not get the last word on the matter. The Leibnizian philosopher
lohann August Eberhard attacked Kant's criticism of Wolffian-Leibnizian
metaphysics and argued that anything that was true and valuable in Kants
metaphysics was already contained in Leibniz's writings. Whether or not
(his is true overall is not a matter of concern here, but there is at least one
i onlemporary Kant scholar who does recognize the importance of the prin-
i iplc of sufficient reason in Kant s philosophy and thus, his "debt to Leibniz":
Although not often mentioned by its name in the Critique of Pure
Reason, it would be hardly possible to overestimate the role that the
principle of sufficient reason plays in Kant's new transcendental logic.
That is why in acknowledging his debt to Leibniz in On a Discovery
lie mentioned this principle first. Even if not from Leibniz's point of
view, Kant thought that the principle of sufficient reason was more
important than the Monadology: it provided that backbone around
which all the pieces of Kant's new metaphysics are gathered and in
relation to which they obtained their meaning and validity.60
Schopenhauer's Ph.D. dissertation of 1813, The Fourfold Root of the Prin-
i iplc of Sufficient Reason, critically looked at the natural tendency to view the
world as understandable. Schopenhauer thought this idea pertained to four
11 liferent areas: the principle of becoming, i.e., that an effect must follow from
'V "Hence if the reader will look back at our proof of the principle of causality, he
will become aware that only for objects of possible experience were we able to prove that
principle, viz., that everything that occurs (i.e., any event) presupposes a cause; and it
|»t rsupposes this, moreover, in such a way that we were also unable to prove the principle
I nun mere concepts, but could prove it only as principle for the possibility of experience''.
Iminanuel Kant, The Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Werner S. Pluhar (Indianapolis:
I lurkelt, 1996), 299, A 189 / B 232; A 196 / B 241.
()() Predrag Cicovacki, "Kants Debt to Leibniz" in A Companion to Kant, ed. Graham Bird
((>xford: Wiley-Blackwell, 2010), 86. Anthony Savile attributes Kant's acceptance of the princi-
I >»il of sufficient reason as an assumption of common sense: "Why should Leibniz have thought
it ny such thing? What support can he offer for it? Reflecting on these questions sixty years after
I Hhn 1/s death, Kant observed that before his own consideration of the matter it was just an
assumption of common sense. TO deny It would be to accept the seeming absurdity that some-
thing can come from nothing: ex ulhllo nllquodl Yet, even though we may suppose that to be
« brute Impossibility, reiMon require* Ihul wc should be able to say something to show why it is,
JIIMI LIS we did In the cnnc of lh» Principle of (InntmdkMlon," Anthony Savile, Routledge Philoso-
phydutdtbook to iplbnlutout th* MoiMiMany (New York: Uoulledge, 2000), 34,
35
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
a cause; the principle of being, i.e., that sensible objects belong to time and
space; the principle of knowing, viz., that conclusions follow from premis-
es; and the principle of acting, viz., that actions follow from motives. With
Schopenhauer, all versions of the principle are understood to operate within a
framework of Kantian epistemology, that is, the principle of sufficient reason,
in whatever area, was only applicable to the phenomenal sphere.61
From 1750, many scholastics adopted the phrase "principle of sufficient
reason" from Leibniz/Wolff, but without the epistemology of Kant.62 One
thinker, Benedict Stattler, went so far as to define philosophy in terms of
the principle. Philosophy is, he says, "the science of sufficient reason of
those things which are or become or are able to be or become."63 Similar to
Aristotle, who said wisdom was causal knowledge of the world, Stattler's
definition of philosophy could be said to be knowing the sufficient reasons
of the real and the possible.
Josef Wilhelm Kleutgen is another scholastic worthy of special mention.
Kleutgen was instrumental in initiating the Scholastic/Thomistic revival of
the 20th century, and because he had been so imbibed with the teachings
of St. Thomas Aquinas, he earned the nickname Thomas redivivus from his
peers. Pope Leo XIII was so enamored with his work that he called Kleutgen
the "prince of philosophers," and it has been reported that Pope Leo request-
ed that Kleutgen write the initial draft of the papal encyclical Aetrni Patris.64
61 Perhaps due to Schopenhauer's influence, later Ludwig Wittgenstein also thought
that the principle of sufficient reason was an a priori insight: "All such propositions, in-
cluding the principle of sufficient reason, the laws of continuity in nature and of least
effort in nature, etc., etc. - all these are a priori insights about the forms in which the
propositions of science can be cast." Ludwig Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophi-
cus (London: Routledge, 2001) 81. And again: "Laws, like the principle of sufficient reason,
etc. are about the net and not about what the net describes/' Wittgenstein, 83, 6.35.
62 See John Gurr, The Principle of Sufficient Reason in Some Scholastic Systems, 1750-1900
(Milwaukee, WI: Marquette University Press, June 1959).
63 "Recte itaque Philosophiam definimus esse scientiam rationis sufficientis eorum,
quae sunt, velfiunt, aut esse,fieriquepossunt." Benedict Stattler, (1728-1797), Philosophia
methodo scientiispropria explanata (Augsburg: M. Rieger and Sons, 1769), 721-1,2. Cited
in Gurr, n. 22, 57.
64 "It is highly probable that Kleutgen was one of the authors designated by Leo XIII
to draft the encyclical Aeterni Patris, which became the magna carta of official Thomism
within the Catholic Church. Certainly during the year in which the encyclical was drafted
Kleutgen had been called back to Rome at Leo XIIIs express desire and appointed prefect
of studies at the Gregorian University of the Roman College." Gerald A. McCool, Nine-
teenth-Century Scholasticism: The Search for a Unitary Method (New York: Fordham Uni-
versity Press, 1989), 167.
36
Introduction
ll Is also worthy of mention that, in spite of his strongly Thomistic and Scho-
lnMlc background, Kleutgen did not hesitate to publicly credit Leibniz for
having introduced the principle of sufficient reason into philosophy. It is not
IIwtI the scholastics should be faulted for an oversight, but rather, Kleutgen
thinks Leibniz should be recognized for saying explicitly and with greater
puvision what the scholastics implicitly held under different formulations.
(KI v u I gen explicitly mentions "there is no effect without a cause," as just one
nuiinple).65 Kleutgen also points out, as I have argued above, that although
11 ir scholastics did not specifically mention this principle; nevertheless, their
whole1 Aristotelian theory of knowledge by causation depends upon it, as
wrll us the doctrine of the four causes and the unification of essence and
••Hlslcnce in God and its distinction amongst creation. What the principle
i i«ii 11 y a (firms, says Kleutgen, is that all existing being either exists by itself or
by something else, and so it is important that we do not confuse ratio with
i tiusti. 'I he principle of sufficient reason does not say that all things have a
\ iti isc, only that all things have a reason. The difference is that the concept of
httliK unlike causa, does not imply production:
A being can be a principle or a sufficient reason without being
n cause in the proper sense of the word, which supposes the
production of a thing distinct from the agent-being. If then we
understand these concepts: being and principle of sufficient
reason in the sense explained, we cannot doubt the truth of the
principle: every being has a sufficient reason.66
'lying this to the ex nihilo principle, Kleutgen says the judgment that
••vrrylhing exists by itself or by another can be expressed negatively by
flying that what is cannot exist from nothing
'I ho Suarezian thinker, Juan Jose Urraburu, who received the honor of
hrlng invited to teach philosophy at the Gregorian University in Rome
I mm Pope Leo XIII, also briefly mentions and supports this principle. In
his Institutiones philosophicae quas Romae in Pontifica Universitate Gre-
Xorhma tradiderat, Urr&buru makes the distinction between the broader
principle of sufficient reason and the more restricted principle of causality,
noting an "indifference argument" similar to the one used by Avicenna,
Amilnus, and Leibniz:
ft* Jewel" Wllhclm Klculgcn, />/<• Philosophic Der Vorzett (Inssbruck: F. Rausch, 1878),
vul, 1,45V,
ftft/Wrf..474-»icU#d!n(JurrlI.M,
37
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
38
Introduction
70 "To compile a catalogue of all the truths which are self-evident, and cannot be re-
ihit fil to components simpler than themselves, would be a tedious work, and not helpful
In present purposes. If, however, we are called upon to emphasize any beyond the three
limit Umed primaries, it will be the Principle of Sufficient Reason, so often violated by
pure empiricists, and yet so vital to all philosophy" John Rickaby, The First Principles of
Knowledge (London: Longmans, Green and Co. 1919), 175.
/I "If being is intelligible, there must be a ground for its intelligibility. This ground
It precisely its 'sufficient reason/ that which both determines being to be and renders
II Intelligible. Every being, accordingly, is intelligible because for every being there is a
*»nllulent reason, something that adequately accounts for what it is or has." H.D, Gardeil
* M\ Introduction to the Philosophy of St. Thomas Aquinas: IV. Metaphysics, tr. John Otto
IM Louis, MO: Herder Book Co., 1967), 140.
II I he principle of sufficient reason is the immediate basis of the proofs for the existence
nl (mil, By the appeal to the impossible it resolves itself into the principle of identity. In this
HI'IINI*. II Is an analytic principle....The principle of sufficient reason may be expressed by the
Inllowlng formula: "liverything which is, has a sufficient reason for existing," or "Every be-
ing hiiN a sufficient reanon",...'! HIH principle Is self-evident, and though it cannot be directly
iltMnoiiNt ruled, ll can be Indirectly dcmonM ruled by the indirect method of proof known as
UHIUCIIO ud ttbuurdum," (tarrlgnu Lagrange, Ucglnuld God: His Existence and His Nature I,
tr, I Join Bcdc Roue (Si Loull, MOi llmlrr Book Co., 1V34), 181.
39
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
73 This judgment is based on his BBC debate with Bertrand Russell, BBC Radio Third
Programme Recording, January 28 1948.
74 Etiam principium rationis sufficientis: "Nihil est sine ratione sufficiente", estprincipium
per se notum omnibus....principium rationis sufficientis etprincipium causalitatis reducun
tur ad principium contradictionis" Iosepho Gredt, Elementa Philosophiae Aristotelico-Thorn
isticae, ii (Friburgi: Herder and Company, 1937), para.749,5 151, emphasis mine.
75 "This principle has a far more general scope and significance than the principle of
causality. For the principle of sufficient reason is exemplified in cases in which the efficient
cause plays no part. For instance, man s rationality is the ground, the sufficient reason of his
risibilitas and docilitas. Similarly, the essence of the triangle is the ground of its properties;
and there is no difference of being, no real distinction between the properties of the triangle
and its essence. Again God s essence is the ground of His existence, He exists a se, He is
Himself the sufficient reason of His esse, the ground of His existence, since His essence is
precisely to exist." (Jacques Maritain, A Preface to Metaphysics (New York: Sheed & Ward,
1939) 99). Also: "At a later stage we can reduce, or rather logically attach, the principle of
sufficient reason to the principle of identity, by a reductio ad absurdum. This is a reflex op-
eration which may, for example, be described compendiously as follows. The expression in
virtue of which, when we say that in virtue of which an object is, must have a meaning or be
meaningless. If it is meaningless philosophy is futile, for philosophers look for a sufficient
ground of things. If, on the other hand, it has a meaning it is evident that in virtue of the
principle of non-contradiction, it is identical with the meaning of the phrase that without
which an object is not. If, therefore, anything exists which has no sufficient reason for its
existence, that is to say which has neither in itself nor in something else, that in virtue of
which it is, this object exists and does not exist at the same time. It does not exist because
it lacks that without which it does not exist. This reductio ad absurdum proves that to deny
the principle of sufficient reason is to deny the principle of identity. But the proof is a prod-
uct of reflection. The original manifestation, spontaneous and intuitive, of the principle of
sufficient reason is as I have described it above." Ibid., 101.
76 Because of its lack of a textual basis in the writings of St. Thomas, Gilson was re-
luctant to affirm the phrase "principle of sufficient reason," yet would still write in "Les
Principes et les causes" Revue Thomiste 52:1 (1952), 47-8: "A philosopher whom St. Thom-
as could not have foreseen, Leibniz, later affirmed that there are two first principles, one
for necessary truths - the principle of contradiction - and the other for contingent truths
- the principle of sufficient reason. For Thomists, what is one to do with this second first
principle? Some suggest formulating it as follows: 'Nothing exists without sufficient rea-
son.' In that case it means this: for something to exist in the world rather than not exist,
and for it to exist in a given manner rather than in some other manner, there must be a
cause that determines whether it exists or does not exist, and exists in this way rather
than otherwise. Two reflections now suggest themselves. First of all, this principle cannot
be held to be an absolutely first principle. Indeed if nothing determines that something exist
rather than not exist, or be as it is rather than otherwise, then it is possible for that thing
both to be and not to be at the same time that which it is and something else. Since this
would be contradictory, one can say that the formula of the principle of sufficient reason
leads back to the principle of contradiction. Secondly, and for the Mttmc rcanon, ihls princi-
ple is valid for necessary irulhs nol less than for contingent truth*, 'lhun It IN not necessary
40
Introduction
41
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
went to the manuals of the late 18th century Jesuit and Franciscans thinkers (whom Gurr
claims were the ones responsible for incorporating Leibnizian and Wolffian rationalism
into scholasticism) in order to get their Thomistic material - and in doing so unknowingly
drank in Leibnizian and Wolffian waters! "It was inevitable that many of the authors of the
Thomistic revival, in their lack of contact with a tradition really stemming from St. Thomas
himself, credited the rationalistic manuals of the late eighteenth century with a Thomistic
content and meaning [The revival Thomists] decided that the Wolffian manuals such as
we have examined in this chapter were reliable guides in the perennial task of Scholastic
philosophy itself... .In thus reading St. Thomas into a framework furnished by rationalism
seemed to be the hand of Aquinas, but the voice was that of Wolff, and for many years this
synthetic product received the blessing intended for the great original." Gurr, The Principle
of Sufficient Reason in Some Scholastic Systems, 90. What makes Gurrs position more im-
plausible is that he thinks Pope Leo XIII s Aeterni Patris was an attempt to rescue Catholic
philosophy from this nineteenth century "rationalism," but does not address the fact that
Kleutgen (himself a supporter of the principle of sufficient reason, and one who explicitly
gives credit to Leibniz) is frequently credited to be the primary author of that very encyc-
lical! Finally, to compound the error, Gurr's regret over the prevalent acceptance of the
principle of sufficient reason at the time of his writing (1959) forces him to seek a villain
responsible for this mix-up, and he decides to lay the blame at the feet of the "rationalist'
Garrigou Lagrange, without, even for a moment, pointing the finger at another much more
influential champion of the principle, namely Pope Pius XII! Ibid., 158.
82 Norman Kretzmann, The Metaphysics of Theism: Aquinas s Natural Theology in
Summa Contra Gentiles I (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997), 80. Kretzmann himself is an-
other Thomist who subscribes to a version of the principle of sufficient reason which he
thinks, as I have said here, is fundamental not only for science but for all rational thought,
"I subscribe to PSR2 ('Every existing thing has a reason for its existence either in the ne-
cessity of its own nature or in the causal efficacy of some other beings') interpreting the
expression fa reason for its existence' in the sense of a reason for its presently existing. Not
only the history of science, but even a fundamentally rallonnl nlllludc lowariLs ordinary
reality, presupposes PSR2." Ibicl,t 107.
42
Introduction
M s (Mher recent scholastics, such as Joseph Owens and John RX. Knasas, defend the
|»i Iin Iplc by understanding the initiated thing as acquiring some kind of accident. Since
mi luiklcnt is Ipso facto dependent, ihc need for explanation is provoked. See Joseph
< JwniN, '"Ihc Cuusal Proportion - Principle or Conclusion," The Modern Schoolman, 32
(IUW): 323-39. I'or John V, X, KmiJUtiT dlm'UNNlon of causality from the accidental, see Be-
ing ami Somt 20th Century Vwmlfti (New York: Pordhnm University Press; 2003), Ch. 6.
M4 IMUH XII, Hunuml <!*n*rli (IVflO). 2U,
43
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
sons, scholastics and Thomists need not shy away from using both the notion
and the actual phrase "principle of sufficient reason."85 Just as Aristotle pro-
vided the scholastics with terms such as act and potency to capture a real
ontological situation, I see no reason why Leibniz too cannot provide scho-
lastics with a basic formula and phrase that sums up all of the assumptions
about the intelligibility of the world and the more specialized formulations
of the principle of causality.
This historical overview is sufficient to help the reader grasp both the wide-
spread nature of the issue and its fundamental importance. It is immateri-
al whether the principle is implicit or explicit; it makes no difference if you
phrase it in terms of "the principle of determination" like the Arabic scholas-
tics, the ex nihilo nihilfit of Aquinas and Descartes, the a nullo nihil potest esse
of Scotus, or the principle of sufficient reason of Leibniz or Wolff. As we will
later see, all of these various formulations presuppose at least some version of
the principle of sufficient reason, and without such presuppositions, the philo-
sophical enterprise is a truly crippled and hopeless endeavor.
85 To mention three more problems in Gurr's work: 1) Apart from "essentialist" and
"rationalist" assertions, there is little in the way of argument to support Gurr's impatience (
with the principle and there is hardly any response to arguments in favor of it. 2) He '
seems to focus on the works that explicitly contain the phrase "principle of sufficient
reason" and not the negative formulation "out of nothing nothing comes" (or some equiv-
alent). Such an oversight is considerable if it is true (as I and many others say) that the two
formulations are metaphysically equivalent. 3) Gurr does not ask important questions
about common scholastic principles and methods (like the agere sequilur principle dis-
cussed above) and how they function without covertly presuppowlng (he principle of suf-
ficient reason. Without delving into these deeper Issues, CUxrr'n work U w VCIUTI* historical
overview lacking any deep philosophical significance.
Introduction
86 I-or example, Aristotle thought it important to say some words in the defense of the
principle of non-contradiction (Meta IV), which is arguably the most patently true prin-
ilpleofall.
H7 'I he largest treatment of defending the principle to date is Alexander R. Pruss, The
Principle of Sufficient Reason: A Reassessment (Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University
PIVNN, 2006). Anolher relatively exleiiNlve defense is Reginald Garrigou Lagrange's God:
His Existence and His Nature I, Ir, Demi Hcile Rose (St Louis, MO; Herder Book Co., 1934),
111 232, However, the topic* iltucilNNtfil there are broiuler thun strictly defending the prin-
ilplcul'ftiiflk'knl rcaion.
45
"Perhaps it just expresses an arbitrary demand; it may be
intellectually satisfying to believe that there is objectively, an
explanation for everything together, even if we can only guess at
what the explanation might be. But we have no right assume that
the universe will comply with our intellectual preferences.1"
- J. L. Mackie
1 J.L. Mackie, The Miracle of Theism: Arguments for and A#ain$t the lixlttanv of God
(New York: Oxford University Press, 1982), H6-7,
CHAPTER II:
Arguments Against
the Principle of
Sufficient Reason
W
hen reviewing literature critical of the principle of sufficient
reason, it is important to remember the distinction between
arguments and assertions. It is one thing to support one's po-
ult Ion with evidence, logic, and good reasons. It is another thing to assume
m assert that one's position is true while neglecting to provide supportive
HI Alimentation. A great amount of contemporary material critical of the
principle of sufficient reason does the latter. Little to no attention is paid to
I he Initial intuitive plausibility and arguments that attempt to support the
I irl nciple; and apart from an occasional point about fatalism or an uncritical
i I'lorence to Hume, little or no arguments are offered against it.
I'or Innately, not all critics are guilty of such omissions. Some
philosophers have taken it upon themselves to offer sufficient reasons for
i ejecting the principle of sufficient reason. Hume's arguments against the
ittumil principle are well known and respected, I will cover this series of
arguments first, From there, wc will move on to cover a few contemporary
47
St Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
thinkers who are opposed to the principle. The most careful work in
recent times that attacks the principle in is William Rowe's 1975 work,
The Cosmological Argument2 This work, although primarily focused
on rebutting some of the more popular versions of the cosmological
argument for the existence of God, nevertheless is relevant to our efforts,
since Rowe attacks the cosmological arguments collectively by saying they
all boil down to presupposing the principle of sufficient reason, which in
Rowe's view, either cannot be known to be true or, in some of its stronger
formulations, is demonstrably false.
really do believe the proposition. Hume then begins to question the source of
I his certainty; given "the idea of knowledge above-explained" (viz., Hume's
rpistemology of the "fork"), how can one be certain of this proposition
wilhout fear of error? He then goes on to argue that our certainty of this
principle cannot come from either intuition or demonstration:
But here is an argument, which proves at once, that the foregoing
proposition is neither intuitively nor demonstrably certain. We
can never demonstrate the necessity of a cause to every new
existence, or new modification of existence, without shewing at
I he same time the impossibility there is, that any thing can ever
begin to exist without some productive principle; and where the
latter proposition cannot be proved, we must despair of ever being
able to prove the former. Now that the latter proposition is utterly
incapable of a demonstrative proof, we may satisfy ourselves by
considering that as all distinct ideas are separable from each other,
and as the ideas of cause and effect are evidently distinct, it will be
easy for us to conceive any object to be non-existent this moment,
and existent the next, without conjoining to it the distinct idea
of a cause or productive principle. The separation, therefore,
of the idea of a cause from that of a beginning of existence, is
plainly possible for the imagination; and consequently the actual
separation of these objects is so far possible, that it implies no
contradiction nor absurdity; and is therefore incapable of being
refuted by any reasoning from mere ideas; without which it is
Impossible to demonstrate the necessity of a cause.4
I ft he principle were intuitively or demonstratively certain, the contrary
I imposition would state some impossibility. In other words, unless the
proposition "Something can begin to exist without a cause" can be shown
lu be impossible, one can never be certain of the causal proposition either.
Suppose we call the opposite of the causal proposition, "Something can
lu'l^ln to exist without a cause," the anti-causal proposition. If the causal
proposition is intuitively or demonstratively certain, then the anti-
ttuiNiil proposition must be impossible. But the problem, Hume says, is
thttl the anli-causal proposition can never be proven impossible, because
the Ideas of cause and effect are distinct, and one can imagine them
4/fiW., 19H.
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
50
Arguments Against the Principle of Sufficient Reason
nil her, this alleged being has no causes at all. It is a completely uncaused being,
it nil so to assume this alleged uncaused being has a cause is to assume the
polnI under contention. Additionally, while it may be true that every effect
I ins a cause, it must be shown that everything that begins to exist is an effect:
I believe it will not be necessary to employ many words in shewing
I he weakness of this argument, after what I have said of the
foregoing. They are all of them founded on the same fallacy, and
are derived from the same turn of thought. It is sufficient only to
observe, that when we exclude all causes we really do exclude them,
and neither suppose nothing nor the object itself to be the causes
of the existence; and consequently can draw no argument from
I he absurdity of these suppositions to prove the absurdity of that
exclusion. If every thing must have a cause, it follows, that upon
I he exclusion of other causes we must accept of the object itself or
of nothing as causes. But it is the very point in question, whether
every thing must have a cause or not; and therefore, according to
all just reasoning, it ought never to be taken for granted.5
I hey are still more frivolous, who say, that every effect must have
a cause, because it is implyed in the very idea of effect. Every effect
necessarily pre-supposes a cause; effect being a relative term, of
which cause is the correlative. But this does not prove, that every
being must be preceded by a cause; no more than it follows, because
every husband must have a wife, that therefore every man must be
marryed. The true state of the question is, whether every object,
which begins to exist, must owe its existence to a cause: and this
I assert neither to be intuitively nor demonstratively certain, and
hope to have proved it sufficiently by the foregoing arguments.6
11ume's main point seems to be this: since the anti-causal principle ap-
pears "plainly possible,,> and since the arguments for the causal proposi-
I Ion's necessity are fallacious, how then can one know the causal principle
lur certain? One cannot know it through the only means by which (Hume
thinks) certainty can be had: that is, it cannot be known be intuition or
ilcmonst ration. In response one may appeal to experience and observation,
JW/iM.,200.
ft/Wr/,.201.
51
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
yet it is well known what Hume thinks of induction. Induction cannot es-
tablish certainty, the gap from the individual experiences to the general
proposition is "custom," and if induction from experience is the ground
for the causal proposition, it can only be known through custom as well -
and custom supplied by the human mind is no ground for certitude.
52
Arguments Against the Principle of Sufficient Reason
53
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
11 Ibid.y 76, emphasis mine. Also: "To say, Something has been produced out of [by]
nothing is to say no more than 'Something exists which has not been produced/ If I say of
something, a stone, for example, that nothing produced it, I certainly am not saying - nor
does what I say entail - that the stone was produced. What I am saying of I he slone is that
it was not produced at all." Ibid.y 63.
12 J. L. Mackie, The Miracle of Theism, 92.
13 Rowe, The Cosmological Argument, 94.
54
Arguments Against the Principle of Sufficient Reason
M "A word occurs essentially in a sentence provided that its replacement in every one of
Hum eurrences by some other word will change the truth-value of the sentence. Thus 'lions'
In ihe I rue statement, "I here nre lions In Africa' occurs essentially since its replacement by
Ihe word 'tigers' yields ihe falnc Ntitlcnient, "Ihere are tigers in Africa.' A word occurs vacu-
ously In k\ sentenceJual In cuw ll due* not occur essentially." IbicU 78. Rowe does not explain
how A proposition cun ha both lru», and yet the non logical words still remain "vacuous."
55
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
15/WA83.
56
Arguments Against the Principle of Sufficient Reason
The difficulty with the view that the principle [PSR], in either its
strong or weak form, is necessary is that we do seem able to conceive
of things existing, or even things coming into existence, without
having to conceive of those things as having an explanation or
cause. Unlike the proposition "Some red things are colored," it
does seem conceptually possible that something exists that has no
cause or explanation of its existence.16
Here Rowe again brings up Hume's conceivability criterion. The diffi-
i'lilty with the principle being necessary is that a counterexample seems
possible. The contrary state of affairs referred to by the anti-causal propo-
sition seems possible. There does not seem to be any contradiction in say-
ing that something can come into being without a cause. As with Hume,
It is precisely that the contrary state of affairs can be conceived without
contradiction that should prevent thoughtful people from affirming the
principle of sufficient reason as necessarily true. Thus, Rowe concludes,
since the principle of sufficient reason is neither analytically true nor is it
it synthetic necessary truth, any argument that uses the principle of suf-
lu ic*nt reason as a premise cannot be a proof of the existence of God. An
iirgument is only as strong as its premises. If the principle of sufficient
i ntson is inconclusive, so too is the argument that utilizes it:
l!or unless there is a way of knowing the principle to be true other
Ih an those we have explored, it follows that we do not know the
principle to be true. But if we do not know if one of the essential
premises of an argument is true, then we do not know that it is a
good argument for its conclusion.17
). I*. Mackie makes the same claim. There is no good reason to think
I ho principle is a principle known independently from further experi-
oiu o, UI see no plausibility in the claim that the principle of sufficient
lOiison is known a priori to be true."18 It seems then that these argu-
inonls are stating that if the principle of sufficient reason is an a priori
pi Inciple, (and there are serious disagreements about just what "apriori"
moinis), I hen the anti-causal proposition should assert a contradiction.
I ho contradiction in the anti-causal proposition should be apparent, and
lft/Wr/,85.
I7/W04.
IH Mtwklc, 7/icf Mimvh <)/ 7/IWIW, 84*5.
57
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
since it is not, one should not affirm the principle of sufficient reason as
necessary "a priori" either.
I hat God's causing contingent states is necessary. But that would mean it
Is necessary that there are contingent states of affairs, and Rowe finds this
altogether unworkable:
But if the existence of God is necessary, and God's causing there
to be contingent states of affairs is also necessary, it follows that
it is necessary that there are contingent states of affairs. But as we
noted at the outset, it is contingent, not necessary, that there are
contingent states of affairs. Hence... there can be no explanation
of the fact that there are contingent states of affairs. Consequently,
since PSR implies that there is an explanation of the fact that
there are contingent states of affairs, PSR is false.20
Rowe concludes that no contingent state of affairs can be the suffi-
i lent reason of another set of contingent states of affairs. Neither can it
be necessary that there are contingent states of affairs. Thus, Rowe thinks
i onlingent states of affairs cannot be explained by either contingency or
necessity, and consequently contingent states of affairs cannot have a suf-
ficient reason for their existence.21
We should mention that this is a common contemporary argument
itKiiinst the principle of sufficient reason. It does not stem from Hume,
nl 111 many contemporary philosophers in addition to Rowe (such as James
Uoss, for example22) find it to be a persuasive case against the principle of
mi llicient reason.
wlhitU 101.
,' I Rowe sees the "existential" version of the principle of sufficient reason (sim-
ply accounting for a thing's existence) as avoiding this problem. A principle of
ntilliclcnl reason could be used simply to account for the existence of the thing
IMII m>( ihe mode. See/&/(/„ 112 13
;;. lames F. Rosa, PhlfaiOphh'ttl 'Ihvology (Indianapolis, IN: The Bobbs-Merrill
Company, 1969), 295-304,
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
60
Arguments Against the Principle ofSuJI'tclcnt Reason
cal: "We have no good ground for an a priori certainty that there could
not have been a sheer unexplained beginning of things... .[but insofar as
I his is improbable], we should infer that it must have had some physical
antecedents."25
Summary
In my research of positions critical of the principle of sufficient rea-
son, these arguments, while conceivably not the only arguments one could
muster against the principle, are nevertheless the most credible and fa-
miliar. As we have seen, Hume's first argument was both epistemological
and metaphysical in nature, arguing that the causal proposition cannot
be known to be certainly true because the anti-causal proposition cannot
be shown to be impossible: since the separability of cause from the begin-
ning of existence is possible for the imagination, the actual separation of
I hose two entities is also possible. Hume's second point is that the three
examples he mentions of arguing on behalf of the principle beg the ques-
I ion at issue. Rowe makes two neo-Humean arguments by separating the
claims in Hume's first argument. First, Rowe makes a metaphysical claim
l hat uncaused beings springing into being seems possible, and therefore
I he principle of sufficient reason is not a necessary metaphysical principle.
Secondly, Rowe makes an epistemological claim that since the principle
of sufficient reason cannot be known either through analytic or synthetic
necessity, we do not know the principle to be certainly true. Thirdly, Rowe
(and others) claims that a stronger principle of sufficient reason (one that
a i counts for not only the existence of things, but also their mode or man-
ner of existing) is demonstrably false, since if it were true, there could be
no contingent states of affairs. Finally Mackie seems to admit the princi-
ple to some limited degree in a physical context, but sees no warrant for
a Mi rming it as a true metaphysical principle that transcends all particular
scopes of being. The conclusion to all of these efforts is, of course, to per-
suade us to agree that "there is no sufficient reason to regard the principle
of sufficient reason to be valid."26
61
Russell: So it all turns on this question of sufficient reason, and I
must say you haven t defined "sufficient reason" in a way that I can
understand. What do you mean by sufficient reason? You do not
mean cause?
Copleston: Not necessarily. Cause is a kind of sufficient reason.
Only contingent being can have a cause. God is His own sufficient
reason; and He is not cause of Himself. By sufficient reason in the
full sense, I mean an explanation adequate for the existence ofsome
particular being.
Russell: But when is an explanation adequate? Suppose I am about
to make a flame with a match. You may say that the adequate
explanation of that is that I rub it on the box.
Copleston: Well, for practical pur poses-but theoretically, that is only
a partial explanation. An adequate explanation must ultimately be
a total explanation, to which nothingfurther can be added.
Russell: Then I can only say thatyoure lookingfor something which
cannot begot, and which one ought not to expect to get.
Copleston: To say that one has not found it is one thing; to say that
one should not look for it seems to me rather dogmatic.
Russell: Well, I do not know. I mean, the explanation of one thing
is another thing which makes the other thing dependent on yet
another, and you have to grasp this sorry scheme of things entirely
to do what you want, and that we cannot do.
Copleston: But are you going to say that we cannot, or we should
not even raise the question of the existence of the whole of this sorry
scheme of things - of the whole universe?
Russell: Yes, I do not think there's any meaning in it at all. I think
the word "universe" is a handy word in some connections, but I do
not think it stands for anything that has a meaning.1
1 Transcript of Fr. Frederick Copleston v. Bertrand Russell in their fnnuniN lcMH BBC
Radio debate on the existence of God (broadcast in 1948 on the 'Ihird Program ul the Brit-
ish Broadcasting Corporation. 'I his debate was published In "HunHinlUl"fliuireprinted In
Bertrand KUNMCII, Why I Am Not a Christian (London: Gcorg* AlUll * UnWlll* IWV/),
CHAPTER III:
The Principle Stated
and Its Meaning
T he purpose of this chapter is to clarify, as precisely as possible, what
exactly is meant by the phrase, "principle of sufficient reason." This
effort at elucidation will follow the following order. First, we will de-
line our key terms, namely "principle," "sufficient," and, most importantly,
"reason." We will then examine the various formulations and meaning of
I he principle, in order to clarify that this work will focus on what I will call
I he metaphysical formulation of the principle, most commonly expressed as,
"Whatever exists must have a reason for its existence either in itself or from
another." Next, I will put this statement in its "proper logical form" that is
lo say, I will highlight and make explicit its cognitive aspects and show that
t lie principle, as commonly stated, is actually an implicit compound propo-
sil ion consisting of what I will call a "principal part" and a "source portion."
When analyzed this way, I will show that the principal part of the principle
of sufficient reason is equivalent to the Thomistic doctrine of the act of esse,
and should be regarded as necessarily true. The second "source portion" of
I lie principle is, I will claim, an exhaustive division of the possible options
Ihal could serve an ihc IOCUN or "home" for this reason for existence, that
63
St Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
65
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
/ \
Simpl* su beta nc* Composite substances
Essence signifying the simple Essence signifying the composite;
, „ . . I.e., formal and material causes.
in theology, intnmsc connections
such as the relation of Persons in
the Trinity
VI he ratio "dtcitur esse in re, inquantum in re extra animam est aliquid quod respondet
i omrpttonl animae, slcttf si^niflcatum signo"In I Sent. d. 2 q. 1 a. 3. Parma ed. as found at
llu* (lorpus 'IhomUllcum wclmlte.
'1 Ports of thin dlftgrttm are limplrcd by mid Indebted to Peter Coffey, The Science of
/MX/V (London: Umgmimi, UNMM,, MIU! (In,, ISHH) 56-s>2
67
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
So to clarify, the point here is that reasons are simply that which accounts
for something and so can serve as the basis for either truth-value or being.
Whether logical or ontological, propositions and things proceed from their
"grounds" or "reasons." The truth of propositions is grounded and account-
ed for in their respective truthmaker, while the existence of say contingent
beings is grounded and accounted for by their causes and conditions. If we
focus on the ontological side of this diagram, we can make a distinction
based on whether these ontological reasons exert some positive influence
or not. Ontological principles that do not exert a positive influence on a
being, yet are still required for its existence, are conditions. Conditions are
the negative factors (removens prohibens) that account for the existence of
something and are distinct from causes precisely in that conditions do not
positively contribute anything to an effect, even though they are still neces-
sary. To see this difference between conditions and causes, we can imagine
a sunlit room. Properly speaking it is sun that is the cause of the light in the
room, because it is the thing that positively contributes the light. The win-
dow, on the other hand, is a condition of the sunlit room. Indeed the window
is a necessary condition for the sunlit room, it is a sine qua non factor that
must be realized before we can ever have a sunlit room, even though the
window itself does not positively contribute or cause the light. The light in
the room is really dependent on the condition of the window, yet the win-
dow exerts no positive influence on it. Conditions then can rightly a reason
for a things existence in that they refer to the removal of any obstacles that
would prohibit the being of a thing.
Of those reasons that exert a positive influence on something, we can
make another distinction by saying this can occur intrinsically or ex-
trinsically. Extrinsic principles that exert a positive influence on the be-
ing of another are a type of cause. Causes are the positive factors that ac-
count for being of another. In fact, a "cause" is that which has a positive
influence of any sort on the being of another, and the extrinsic causes
are what the scholastics coined the efficient, final, and exemplary cause.
There can also be causes intrinsic to a being. Material beings, that is
beings composed out of form and matter, have both formal and material
causes. The form makes the matter be of a certain sort, while the matter
reciprocally enables the form to exist in this segment of space/lime and
not some other.5
5 For example, NIT (lolfcy, Ibid.
The Principle Stated and Its Meaning
These distinctions of the term reason leave the door open for the pos-
sibility of a truly simple substance; e.g., a being that is purely one and ex-
isting whose essence is identical with its existence and all other attributes
it may have. In this case we can say that such a being would have a reason,
even though it would not have a cause. There would be nothing extrinsic
to this being that would account for its existence, nor would there be any
plurality of principles intrinsic to this being (neither material nor formal)
that could serve as its cause either. No trace of any potency in this being
would mean that it is an actus purus, existing with true a seity. If such a
being existed it could not be characterized as a causa sui since, as we have
said, a cause is that which accounts in any way for the existence of another,
and we have stipulated that an actus purus would be simple and so could
not consist of any intrinsic "others".6 Yet it would still be correct to char-
acterize such a being as a ratio sui, since anything that exists a se would
account for its own existence and thus be its own reason.7
To sum up, it is hopefully more clear to the reader now what we mean by
the terms "principle," "sufficient," and "reason." Yet the defining of terms
is only the beginning of our attempt at clarification because the principle
of sufficient reasons has been formulated in different ways. For this rea-
son we must now turn to look at the various ways the principle has been
formulated to determine which formulation best suits our purpose here.
ft In the Summa Contra Gentiles, Aquinas also distinguishes ratio from causa when
he says that the divine will can have a ratio but that ratio is not a cause. "Quamvis autem
iiHijuu ratio divinae voluntatis assignari possit, non tamen sequitur quod voluntatis eius sit
illiquid causa "S.C.G. I, 87.
7 In ihe Thomistic view, there can be no causality without an act-potency interaction.
A being that is pure act would contain no potency at all, and although one may say its es-
sence or form is exlilcncc, at 111 I here would be no formal cause since the form in this case
would nol be u dlitlnct principle nerving as a limiting factor (a potency) that channeled
another principle (111 ixlflltfiwe) down to I hi* sort of being.
St Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
70
The Principle Stated and Its Meaning
truth rules for different kinds of propositions. Until we know what kind
of proposition we are dealing with, we will be at a loss for knowing how to
analyze its truth value.
Now unquestionably, the best way to answer this question is to put that
statement into what Parker and Veatch have called its proper logical form
- that is, a rephrasing of the statement to highlight its cognitive aspects by
appropriately isolating the relevant copulas and their subjects and predi-
cates.9 Yet, as soon as we do this, we can see there are actually two propo-
sitions being asserted here, meaning that this statement is actually (and we
should add, implicitly) a compound proposition because the statement as it
stands actually contains more than one claim. How do we know this? Well,
when we isolate the categorical propositions, we plainly see that there are
two factual assertions being made here. The first statement says, "What-
ever exists [is that which] must have a reason for its existence," while the
second and additional claim is that "Every reason is had either essentially
or from another/' Now patently, these are two different claims. The first
claim is that everything has a reason; the second claim is that all reasons
are found either essentially or from another. In fact, it's at least prima facie
possible that the claims could even have different truth values! It might be
the case that not everything needs a reason for its being, meaning the first
is false, but that the things that do have a reason have it from itself or from
another, meaning the second is true. Or it could be vice versa; perhaps
everything does need a reason (meaning the first is true), but the options
of essentially or from another are not exhaustive (meaning that the second
claim is false). When we look at the principle of sufficient reason in this
way, it actually consists of two separate propositions, existing side by side
and joined together by an implicit "and" conjunction.10 Thus, when we
cache this all out, again explicitly in proper logical form, we get the con-
9 See chapter 11 of Francis H. Parker and Henry B. Veatch, Logic as a Human Instru-
ment (New York: Harper and Row, 1959), 153.
10 Scholastics commonly divided propositions into categorical and compound. One
i'un see this for example in John of St. Thomas' treatment on logic in John of St. Thomas
Outlines of Formal Logic tr. Francis C. Wade (Milwaukee: Marquette University Press,
1955) 55. Categorical propositions are simple and unqualified in the sense that they con-
sist of I wo conccplN united by a copula. Compound propositions, however, consist of two
whole categorical proportion* united by something other than a copula verb, like when
we Hay, t,rI he cal wan 1'ttNt ami run up w I ree." One who makes this statement is making two
liutniN: 1) about thtipwdoflh* vftl.rtiul 2) where the cat went,
71
St Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
junctive proposition, "Whatever exists must have a reason for its existence
and every reason for existence is possessed essentially or from another."11
Now recognizing this point is critical, because, as our traditional logic
tells us, the truth value rule for conjunctive propositions is that in orderfor a
conjunctive proposition to be true, both of its conjuncts must be true. It is as if
we had said, "Roses are red and violets are blue." In order for that statement
to be true, both conjuncts must be true. If, for example, violets are yellow,
then the entire conjunctive proposition would be false. So when we apply
that same conjunctive rule to the principle of sufficient reason we see that in
order for the whole principle of sufficient reason to be true, both of its con-
juncts, that is, both "Whatever exists must have a reason for its existence"
and "Every reason is possessed essentially or from another" need to be true.
Since we have two independent propositions, we will likely need two lines
of justification. This recognition by the way, also opens up the possibility
that the principle of sufficient reason, as a whole, is both a principle and
conclusion, if one of its conjuncts is a true first principle and the other is a
conclusion to an argument. Whether or not this is the case seems to me to
depend upon how the source portion is formulated, but we will not pursue
that question here. What is important here is to recognize that the principle
of sufficient reason is, as I have said, a conjunctive proposition consisting of
two statements united by an implicit "and" conjunction, which means that
each constituent conjunct merits our individual attention.
72
The Principle Stated and Its Meaning
essence. Indeed, the notion of essence is certainly critical for the being of
the thing, and although I am inclined to agree with those who hold there
is a principle of sufficient reason in the order of essence, it is in the order of
existence that I wish to pursue this question.12 In other words, we are seek-
ing to answer Leibniz's question as to why there is something rather than
nothing. It appears to me Leibniz's question is best addressed by an exis-
tential philosophy that is centered upon the act of existing. Accordingly,
the Thomistic doctrine on the primacy of existence might give us a strong
avenue of justification for this existential principle. The principle of suf-
ficient reason is, after all, a statement about existence, and the Thomistic
move from an essential metaphysics to an existential metaphysics might
therefore give the notion of a "sufficient reason for existence" a very stable
basis for its justification.
So let us ask, is there a Thomistic answer to why there is something
rather than nothing? Does Aquinas himself have an understanding of
"that which accounts for a thing's being and thus its distinction from noth-
ing?" In the course of his own defense of the principle, Maritain says that
a sufficient reason for a thing's existence is simply "that in virtue of which
an object is"13 with "in virtue of which," meaning "that without which an
object is not."14 But is there an adequate grounding in the texts of Aqui-
nas for Maritains claim? In short, what might Aquinas say in response to
Leibniz's question, "Why is there something rather than nothing?"
In response to this query, Aquinas would likely appeal at some point to
his doctrine of esse or "the act of being."15 What exactly is this doctrine of
12 Gredt for example argues there is a principle of sufficient reason in the order of
essence as well as in the order of existence. See Gredt, Elementa Philosophiae Aristo-
tvllco-Thomisticae, ii op. cit., 151. A principle of sufficient reason in the order of essence
would he that which makes a thing be a certain kind of thing while the principle in the
order of existence would be that which makes the thing be, in an unqualified sense. This
distinction of the two orders of sufficient reason corresponds well with Aquinas' position
I lull ihcre is an act in the order of existence (what we might call "existential act") a notion
which we will cite extensively below, and a formal act, that is, an act in the order of form,
which Is a topic that is also quite important but beyond the bounds of our discussion here.
\} Jacques Maritain, A Preface to Metaphysics: Seven Lectures on Being (New York:
Mcnlor Omega, 1962), 97.
\ A Ibid, 99.
I!i "Dkendum quod esse dupllcltcr dicltur, uno modo, significat actum essendi" S. T. I,
t, 4 ail 2; vol. 4, 42, 'Ihlii i«?n»e OIVJUU* «M "an acl of being" is what we mean by esse in this
wvllon, For another philosopher who hold* thul Aquinas' doctrine of esse is an appropri-
ate rcNponNc to Ldbnln'l quiitlnn, NW )ohn I', Wlppcl, "'I nomas Aquinas on the Ultimate
73
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
esse7. Aquinas calls this esse "that by which a thing is,"16 he says the esse is
the "act of a being,"17 and "that by which something is." By way of analogy,
just as you could not have running without an act of running, Aquinas
tells us that neither could a thing exist without an act of existing.18 Making
a similar point, Aquinas says that just as motion is the act of mobile thing
insofar as it is mobile, so esse is the act of an existing thing insofar as it is a
being.19 This ''esse is the act by which something is" 20 and it is an act that
pervades everything, meaning that "this act of being is common to every-
thing that is."21 On more than one occasion, Aquinas affirms that this act
of being is universal, and is said of everything that is 22 and so whatever
exists must have esse.23 Indeed, Aquinas goes so far as to say that "it is im-
possible that some being exists which does not have esse."24 The reason is
because "Each thing exists through its own esse"25 and "Every thing exists
because it has an act of being "26 The existence of the thing then is founda-
tional for Aquinas, so much so that the act of a being is the very act that
makes a thing be, "Being is or exists insofar as it participates in this act of
being (actus essendi)"27 and this act of being in a thing is the very reason
why a thing is denominated a being in the first place!28 "Being simply is
Why Question. Why Is There Anything at All Rather than Nothing Whatsoever?" Review
of Metaphysics 60 (2007), 723-45. Maritain also seems to connect esse with reason when
discussing the principle of sufficient reason. See Maritain, A Preface to Metaphysics, 99.
16 "Ipsum enim esse est quo aliquid est." S. T. I, 75, 5 ad 4; vol. 5,202.
17 "Quod esse dupliciter dicitur: quandoque enim esse idem est quod actus entis." Quod.
XII, q. l a d l .
18 Nam ipsum esse est quo aliquid est, sicut cursus est quo aliquis currit" Quaest. de.
Ani., q. 6.
19 "Sicut autem motus est actus ipsius mobilis inquantum mobile est; ita esse est actus
existentis, inquantum ens est.3'In I Sent, d. 19 q. 2 a.2., c.f, Alio modo dicitur esse ipse ac-
tus essentiae; sicut vivere, quod est esse viventibus, est animae actus; non actus secundus,
qui est operatio, sed actus primus." In I Sent., d. 33 q. 1 a. 1 ad 1; Parma ed., emphasis mine.
20 "Esse est actus et quo est." S.C.G.. II, 54, n. 7; vol.13, 392.
21 "Omnibus autem commune est esse" S.C.G. II, 15, n.4; vol.13, 295.
22 "Esse autem dicitur de omni quod est "S.C.G II, 15; vol.13, 295.
23 "Omne autem quod est, esse habet." De substantiis separatis, ch. 9; vol. 40, 57.
24 "Impossibile est quod sit aliquod ens quod non habeat esse."De Ver. q. 21, a. 2; vol. 22,596
25 "Unumquodque estpersuum esse." S.C.G. I, 22, n. 5; vol. 13, 68
26 "Omnis res est per hoc quod habet esse." S.C.G.. I, 22, n. 9; vol. 13, 68
27 "Itapossumus dicere quod ens, sive id quod est, sit, inquantum partIvt/nit actum es-
sendi "In. DeHeb. 1. 2
28 "Quod ens sumiturab actu essendi\ sed nomen rei exprimlt tiuttitilttlttni v*\ mentlum
entis" De Ver.t q, 1, u. Is vol. 22, 5 "tins autem rum dicit qumlMmi ltd mlum actum
74 _ _
The Principle Stated and Its Meaning
that which has esse!'29 This Thomistic doctrine of the primacy of being is
said to be quite unique amongst scholastics,30 indeed esse is called "the act
of being insofar as it is a being, that is, that by which it is denominated as
an actual being in reality."31 Distinguishing things from the nothingness
of mere possibility, esse "is compared to all things as that by which they are
made actual," and this esse is "that which actuates all things." 32 This act
of being is so metaphysically important that Aquinas calls it "the act of
all acts and the perfection of all perfections."33 Since a thing cannot have
any properties prior to its own existence, "esse is the first among all acts."34
Stronger words can hardly be claimed for the act of esse. It is no exag-
geration to say that this notion is foundational to his whole metaphysical
line of thinking. Numerous other texts could be listed as well "Nothing is
more formal or simple than esse"35 Esse is also the source for intelligibility,
since "each thing is knowable to the extent that it has being."36 "Esse is the
act of that which we can say exists,"37 and "Each thing is through its own
act of being."38 This series of very strong statements about the role of esse
shows us, in the clearest of terms, that in the mind of Aquinas, esse is the
essendi", In. Sent., lib. 1 d. 8 q. 4, a. 2, ad. 2. "Nomen autem entis ab actu essendi sumltur,
non ab eo cui convenit actus essendi"De Ver. q. 1, a. 1, ad. 3; vol. 22,6 "Hoc vero nomen ens,
imponitur ab actu essendi" In. IVMeta. Led., 2, n. 6
29 "Ens simpliciter est quod habet esse" S.T. I-II.26.4; vol. 6,190.
30 "No one else in the 13th century would say that a thing is called an ens because of
lis esse" William E. Carlo, The Ultimate deducibility oj: Essence to Existence in Existential
Metaphysics. (The Hague: M. Nijhof, 1966), 12.
31 "Esse dicitur actus entis in quantum est ens, idest quo denominatur aliquid ens actu
in rerum natura." Quod IX, 2, 3.
32 "Esse est perfectissimum omnium, comparatur enim ad omnia ut actus. Nihil enim
habet actualitatem, nisi inquantum est, unde ipsum esse est actualitas omnium rerum, et
el lam ipsarumformarum." S.T. 1,4,1, ad. 3; vol. 4, 50
33 "Unde patet quod hoc dico esse est actualitas omnium actum, et propter hocperfectio
omnium perfectionum." De Pot. q. 7, a. 3, ad. 9., c.f. ". .. Sed hoc quod habet esse, efficitur
actu existens. Unde patet quod hoc quoddico esse est actualitas omnium actuum, et propter
hoc estperfectio omnium perfectionum." De Pot. q.7, 2, ad 9.
34 "Primum autem inter omnes actus est esse." S.T. I, 76, 6; vol.5,229.
35 "Nihil enim estformalius aut simplicius quam esse." S.C.G. I, 23; vol.13, 70.
3ft "Unumquodque, quantum habet de esse, tantum habet de cognoscibilitate."S.C.G. I,
Vl.n. 16; vol. 13,207.
37 "Quia ipsum esse non est pwprius actus materiae, sed substantiae totius. Eius enim
mtus est esse de quo possumus dlcere quod sit" S.C.G II, 54, n. 3; vol.13, 392.
3H "Unumquodque #tt per tuum vssc. Quod igltur non est suum esse, non est per se
newtst-MSt"&CXS /• 22, n,5i vul, 13, <\H
75
St. 'Ihomas Aquinas and the Priilplv aJ'SuJIicicnt liaison
reason why there is something rather than nothing, since it is only by this
act of being that something can be real in the first place.
But lets push this point a little further by looking at what other con-
temporary scholars of St. Thomas take texts like these to mean. In oth-
er words, how do recent interpreters of Aquinas interpret the Thomistic
doctrine of esse7. Well, for starters, Jacques Maritain says, "To exist is to
maintain oneself and to be maintained outside nothingness; esse is an act,
a perfection,"39 and that things are "made real by the act of existing - that
is to say, placed outside the state of'simplepossibility"40 Norris Clarke says
that without this interior act of being a thing would be "indistinguishable
from nothing'*1 John R X. Knasas says that it is the "individual esse's that
make various things more than nothing"42 Joseph Owens is particularly
helpful on this score because he so frequently emphasizes the point. Ow-
ens says that since all things, whether sensible or supersensible, are said to
be in some way, that "being then, may in one way or another be attributed
to all things without exception."43 But what is this being? Owens replies,
"It is at least the characteristic that makes a thing differ from nothing"44 In
the realm of the sensible, "Being emerges as the cause that makes a thing
more than mere nothing!*45 And again, in sensible things, "Being is the
76
The Principle Stated and Its Meaning
cause that makes a thing differ from nothing"46 Because if a thing did not
exist, no other attribute of it would exist either; the act of being is also "the
primary consideration in meaning."47 Owens continues, "Without its being,
I he thing would not exist, it would be nothing. Being, therefore, may be re-
garded as a perfection that makes a thing exist and as an act that the thing is
able to enjoy/'48 "Being, then, is universally what makes a thing differentfrom
nothing. It may therefore the act of all acts and the perfection of all perfec-
tions/*49 "Being is conceived as an act or perfection that makes a thing differ
from nothing"50 This idea that the act of being is what sets a thing apartfrom
nothing is also present in Owens' earlier work, where he says, "In every case,
[existence] sets a thing apart from nothing."51 The being of the thing is "the
actuality that gives the thing existence,"52 and that this act is most prior and
most basic in a thing, it is the act of all other actualities in the thing since,
"unless the existence is presupposed, the thing would not be there at all."53
" Without existence a thing is nothing. Z*54 since "existence is what makes it a
being."55 Without this act of all acts that sets the thing apart from nothing,
II would be nothing; "Without existence, it is nothing"56
vSo in light of these texts from both Aquinas and his contemporary in-
terpreters, it should be clear to us that the Thomistic doctrine of esse would
play a critical role in how Aquinas might respond to Leibniz question
and, consequently, how he might go about formulating his own take and
)uslideation of the principle of sufficient reason. But that Aquinas would
appeal to this doctrine is one thing, whether or not such a doctrine is true
because it has being. In this way, being emerges as the cause that makes a thing more than
mere nothing. It is the cause that makes a thing something. At the deepest of levels it an-
swers I he question why." Ibid, 24, emphasis mine.
•\h I bid, 29.
•17 "Without existence, either real or cognitional, nothing else matters for a thing. Be-
lti}41 hen is the primary consideration in meaning." Ibid, 44. By "meaning," Owens means
whatever is intelligible in a thing.
>\Hlbid, 59, emphasis mine.
>\K) Ibid, 60, emphasis mine.
'>() Ibid, 61, emphasis mine.
M Joseph Owens, An Interpretation of Existence (Houston, TX: Center for Thomistic
SI ml ION, 1985), 38, emphasis mine.
'»; Ibid, 51.
S.t Ibid, 7ft.
M Ibid, 52, emphasis mine.
M/toif.Al.
?>f> Ibid, 75, cmpluulN mine,
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
is another matter. For this reason, if we are going to invoke Aquinas' help
on this matter, we have to first see whether or not there is any justification
for this doctrine of esse.
57 Gilson himself acknowledged that the existence of the thing is not always recog-
nized by Thomists as an act, and some have accused Gilson of "theologizing" Aquinas'
metaphysics. In response to this charge, Knasas has argued "Taken in context, his [Gil-
son's] insistence upon the benefits of revelation for reason is not meant to supplant or
preclude an authentically philosophical development of the science. The philosophical
development begins with the judgmental grasp of the esses of sensible things, moves to
an apprehension of ens in the habens esse sense, and competes itself in the demonstration
of Ipsum Esse!' see John RX. Knasas "Does Gilson Theologize Thomistic Metaphysics?"
Thomistic Papers V (Houston: Center for Thomistic Studies, 1990), 17. Moreover, other
thinkers who claim for themselves the label "Thomist" (such as Peter Geach) think that
the term esse in Aquinas is to speak only of form and not some additional act of a. form.
For response to Geach and other "analytical Thomists" who hold this view, see John RX.
Knasas "Haldane's Analytical Thomism and Aquinas' Actus EssendC in Analytical Thorn-
ism (Burlington: Ashgate Publishing, 2006) 233-282. For the development of judgment
approach to Thomistic metaphysics see Joseph Owens, "Aquinas on Knowing Hxislence,"
The Collected Papers of Joseph Owens, ed. John Catan (Albany N.Y.i Slrtlr University of
New York Press, 1980), 20-33 and John RX. KIUIHBN, Being and Sam* Wh t butitry Ihom-
ists (New York: I'ordhum University PKCNH; 2003), 173-212,
78
The Principle Stated and Its Meaning
58 "Furthermore, this fact or truth about real things must be rooted in some intrinsic
property, some real act of presence within the thing itself, which grounds and justifies my
Judgment about it that 'it is, is real.' Here we pass from the mere fact of existence to the
Inner act of existence grounding it - a crucial passage in understanding which leads us
I nl o I he Thomistic vision of what it means to be, to be an actual existent." Norris Clarke,
'///«• One and the Many, 79.
!i9 'lb be precise, the initial esse that makes a thing be a substance and thus distin-
guished from mere potency is "substantial existence" {esse substantiale) while any addi-
tional accidental qualities would be esse "in a certain respect" (secundum quid): "Since
bring properly signifies that something actually is, and actuality properly correlates to
polcntliility; a thing is, in consequence, said simply to have being, accordingly as it is pri-
marily distinguished from that which is only in potentiality; and this is precisely each thing's
substantial being. Hence by its substantial being, everything is said to have being simply; but
by tiny further actuality It Is said to have being relatively. Thus to be white implies relative be-
ing, lor lo be while do«« not lttk«? « thing mil of simply potential being; because only a thing
I lml nduully hftH being cmi rwrlv* ihU mode of being. (Nam cum ens dicat aliquid proprie
79
Si Ihomti* Atjuhnik tttnl thr Vrhlplc ofSujIicicnt Reason
esse in actu; actus autem proprie ordinem habeat ad potentiam; secundum hoc simpliciter
aliquid dicitur ens, secundum quodprimo discerniturab eo quod est in potentia tantum. Hoc
autem est esse substantiate rei uniuscuiusque; undepersuum esse substantiate dicitur unum-
quodque ens simpliciter. Per actus autem superadditos, dicitur aliquid esse secundum quid,
sicut esse album significat esse secundum quid, non enim esse album aufert esse in potentia
simpliciten cum adveniat rei iam praeexistenti in actu) S.T. 1.5.1 ad.L Emphasis added.
60 "Many metaphysicians seems to imagine that an essence cannot exist, so long as it
has not received all its determinations, that, as soon as it has received them, it is bound
either to burst into existence or, at least, to receive it. Now, a twofold error is responsible
for such an illusion. The first is not to see that to be fully completed in the order of essen-
tiality does not bring an essence one inch nearer actual existence. A completed perfected
possibility still remains a pure possibility. The second error is to forget that the essence
of a possible being necessarily includes the possible existence through which alone it can
achieve its essential determination " Etienne Gilson, Being and Some Philosophers, Toron-
to: Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies, 1952,182.
61 "Undepatet quod hoc quod dico esse est actualitas omnium actuum, etprop-
ter hoc estperfectio omnium perfectionum" De Pot. q.7,2, ad 9.
62 Of course we mean here a priority of being, not necessarily a priority of time; "...for
those things are prior in being which are not destroyed when other things are destroyed,
although when they are destroyed other things are destroyed." In Meta. VII, 1. 15.
63 Nor would it matter to say that if a certain thing exists it must have a ccrlnin proper-
ty, say for example, that if a cup of coffee exists it must have a certain tcmpernlure. Such a
claim would be irrelevant since the truth of that statement does nol convert In every cup
of coffee with a temperature exists! Something in addition to a thing1! noolblr qunlllies
must be added to set the thing apart from mere possibility,
The Principle Stated and Its Meaning
any other property. Hence, the Thomistic doctrine of esse stands on excep-
tionally solid philosophical grounds.64
Now for our purposes here, establishing this doctrine is of no small
importance. For this doctrine of esse provides us with a central beachhead
from which we can launch our justification of the principle of sufficient
reason. And by no means are we the first to recognize this. Following
(iarrigou-Lagrange, this notion of distinction from nothing is possibly the
clearest and most persuasive way of understanding the principle of suffi-
cient reason.65 With this in mind, we can say that a sufficient reason for
64 Even Kant s initial speculations can help point us to this same conclusion. What is the
il illcrence between a real hundred dollars and a possible one hundred dollars? In the order of
essence alone, there is no difference at all. But Kant's criticism was based on simple apprehen-
sion or conceptualization, but conceptualization is not the only way we can know reality. After
nil, one hundred real dollars is a very big difference than one hundred possible dollars (One
hundred dollars difference!). When we make a judgment (what the scholastics call the "second
operation of the intellect") we are saying that this thing is and the addition is not a mere qual-
itiil ive addition, it is an attribution that a thing is set apart from nothingness. Existence is very
meaningful - in fact, it has the deepest meaning for anything is to exist. Without existence,
nolhing else matters for a thing, since all of its possible properties mean nothing if il does
iml In fact exist. For the Thomistic view opposing Kant, see Owens, An Elementary Christian
Metaphysics, 44. Along these same lines, Maritain argues, "The most fundamental and most
eharacteristic metaphysical thesis of Aristotelianism as re-thought by Thomas Aquinas, the
diesis of the real distinction between essence and existence in all that is not God - in other
words, the extension of the doctrine of potency and act to the relation between essence and ex-
igence, is directly connected with this intuition. This is, in truth, a thesis of extreme boldness,
lor In il potency (essence, or intelligible structure already achieved in its own line of essence)
IN completed or actuated by an act of another order which adds absolutely nothing to essence
tt.s essence, intelligible structure or quiddity, yet adds everything to it in as much as it posits it
rxtm causas or extra nihil" Jacques Maritain, Existence and the Existent tr. L. Galantiere and
(iernkl B. Phelan (New York: Image Books, 1958), 45. For further criticism of the "fact-under-
Mumling" of existence, see Knasas, Being and Some 20th Century Thomists, 174-182.
65 "Omne ens debet habere rationem propter quam sit potiusquam non sit. ...Si quodlibet
vns non haberet rationem essendi, rationem propter quam sitpotius quam non sit, non dis-
ih\£ueretur a nihilo, quia proprium nihil est non habere rationem essendi, cum opponatur
mil" Reginald Garrigou Lagrange, De Revelatione (Romae: Libreria Editrice Religiosa,
I *M !>), 122, A similar approach to defending the principle of sufficient reason can be found
In John Van Der Aa's Praelectionum philosophiae scholasticae brevis conspectus (end Ed.
I.onvnIn: Fonteyn, 1888). Gurr summarizes Van Der Aa's position this way: "Since being
d lifers from non-being, this being from that being, and existent being from possible be-
Ing. I his difference cannot be because of nothing. Therefore it is due to something either
ex I rl lisle or Intrinsic Vhich is called ihe suflicient reason.' The causal principle here is
dear because, being a mere possible before existence, something cannot determine itself
In ex Is I and so, 'as In all analytic Judgment*/ It Is easy to conclude In the abstract from
existence of died in existence of cause," (Jurr, ISO,
HI
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
0* ••-—-•••
The Principle Stated and Its Meaning
will argue later, that all beings must possess a reason for existence. Like the
act of being, a reason for existence is also universal to all beings. Just as one
might say nihil est sine ratione, one might also just as well say nihil est sine
esse. The scope and meaning of the terms are the same.
For this reason then we can put to rest any fears that we are in error
when we call the act of being a "reason" for existence. Hence, "reason"
and "act of being," as I am using the terms here, are interchangeable.69
'ftiis means we could now, if we were so inclined, give this principal part
of the principle of sufficient reason a more Thomistic formulation. Cast
in Thomistic terms, the principle would state that "Whatever exists must
have an act of being (esse).irjQ Regardless of whether one uses the term "rea-
son," "act of being," or "that which sets the being apart from nothing," the
result and meaning is the same. Thus, we are entirely justified in calling
the act of distinction from nothing a reason for existence.
So this is the principal part of the principle of sufficient reason. It can
be phrased in various ways, like, "Whatever exists must have a reason for
existence," "Whatever exists must have that in virtue of which it is distin-
guished from nothing," or the Thomistic formulation, "Whatever exists
69 To put the point syllogistically, "That which accounts for a thing's being is a reason
lor existence, esse accounts for a thing's being, therefore, esse is a reason for existence."
A nolher prominent Thomist, at least implicitly, seems to be making the same connection
between esse and a reason why something exists in discussing the difference between
essence and existence and the different kinds of questions they answer. <CI would ask the
reader evaluating my approach to distinguish two questions and, corresponding to this,
I wo kinds of intelligibilities. One question searches for that by reason of which something
is recognized as real or as sharing in being. Another seeks after that by reason of which
something enjoys a certain kind of being. If these are two different questions, it seems
Ihnl one is justified in offering two different answers for them. That intelligible content
hi (i thing by reason of which it is recognized as enjoying reality or being should be distin-
guished from that intelligible content by reason of which it is recognized as enjoying this
or I hat kind of being. Without presupposing that there is any being which is not living
it nil material and mobile, we can still ask why any thing which we experience enjoys being.
To nsk this is very different from asking what kind of being it enjoys. If these two ques-
I Ions are not identical, it follows that the answer to the one does not have to be identified
with I lie answer to the other. That by reason of which something is recognized as enjoying
hdng needs not be identified with that by reason of which it enjoys this or that kind of be-
ing." (John F. Wippel, The Metaphysical Thought Of Thomas Aquinas (Washington D.C.:
(Inlhollc University of America Press, 2000), 60-1, emphasis mine.)
70 Since it is Aquinas' view that "impossibile est quod sit aliquid ens quod non habeat
enc" (De Ver, Q. 21 A, 2; vol. 22, 596) we can say that Aquinas held, with the utmost con-
fidence, Ihwt "whatever «XU(N IIUINI luwe mi act of being (esse)"
83
St Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
must have esse" All of these formulations, I claim, are equivalent. They
merely say the same thing with different words. For the sake of clarity
however, it seems to me that the formulation the explicitly says what a
reason is will be the most useful for our purposes, namely, "Whatever ex-
ists must have that in virtue of which it is distinguished from nothing."
Presumably this is the clearest and least controversial way of stating the
principal part of the principle of sufficient reason, and so throughout the
rest of this work it will be the most common way I formulate it.
Having said that, and before we move on to the next part of the prin-
ciple, we need to say at least a few words here regarding the truth of this
statement. For reasons I will elaborate on later, but which are probably
already apparent to the reader, I will argue that the principal part of the
principle of sufficient reason, is a necessarily true proposition, that is to say,
a proposition that is known to be true immediately from the meaning of
its terms, such that a denial of this proposition would result in a patent
self-contradiction. In other words, this part of the principle is what the
scholastics call a necessary per se notum proposition and it will be defend-
ed as such via a reductio ad absurdum argument in a later chapter.
a false dilemma. In other words, its good practice to make sure we dont
leave any openings for an interlocutor to point out a possible tertium quid.
The best way to ensure this is through contradictory opposition, but some-
times contrary opposition will work just fine (as when we say every whole
number must be either even or odd).
So with this in mind we can take the first division, namely, that "in
itself or from another." This is clearly an exhaustive division, for there is
nothing in the universe that is neither this thing itself (that I now des-
ignate) nor something else. Indeed everything that exists is covered by
cither "this thing" or "something else." So the first division is a complete
exhaustive disjunction. If all things need a sufficient reason, then that rea-
son must be located either in some thing we now designate, or something
else, for there simply are no other possible options.72
The next way of stating the source portion says that a reason for ex-
istence must be possessed either essentially or non-essentially. In other
words, the act of being either falls within what the thing is or it does not.
Now, this distinction is clearly one of contradictory opposition; that is, it
is an opposition of the strongest type. It is based on a simple affirmation or
denial of the same property, and so it should be easy to see that this type of
division is both exclusive and exhaustive. It is exclusive because both can-
not be true, and it is exhaustive in that there are no alternatives between
1 his stated pair. Just as something is either red or not red, a property must
ho possessed either essentially or non-essentially. Because of this, one of
I he disjuncts must be true and the other false.
When we apply this distinction to the having of esse, this esse must be
possessed either essentially or non-essentially. It cannot be neither, it cannot
be both; it must be one or the other. Essentially or non-essentially is the only
way a being can possess anything, and if an act of being must be possessed,
II follows that it can only be possessed essentially o r non-essentially.
But what does having something "essentially" mean? The scholastic
notion of having a property essentially means that the said property falls
within the very definition of the thing (for example, as the property of "ra-
tional ity" falls within the definition of "man"). Just as a thing cannot fail
In he itself, a man cannot fail to be rational by nature. Thus, essential prop-
er! Ics are characteristics that belong to the very essence of what the thing
72 'I hose who argue that only contradictory opposition provides certitude are simply
wmng» Nlncc again, sometime* contrary opposition does exhaust all of the alternatives.
85
St Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
is, that is, what it is necessarily and not contingently. To have existence
essentially, then, would be to have existence by nature, and thus to exist
necessarily. To have existence in this way is to have existence in a way that
one cannot lose it. It is an ens a se, and such a being cannot be deprived of
existence. If we express this notion of a necessary being in possible world
semantics, we can say that a necessary being exists in every possible world.
Just as the number nine has the property of being divisible by three in ev-
ery possible world (since divisibility by three is an essential property of the
number nine), so a being whose existence belongs to its very essence exists
in every possible world and cannot not exist.73
What would it entail to possess an act of being non-essentially? This is
just the opposite of necessary! To have existence in a non-essential way is
to have it non-necessarily, which of course means, to have existence in a
way that one can lose it Such a being is capable of not being. This would
mean that such a being is contingent^ that it may or may not exist, and that
existence does not fall within the nature or essence of that thing. Again to
borrow a phrase from possible worlds semantics, contingent beings exist
in some possible worlds but not others. If a being is not necessary, it has
non-essential existence and is therefore contingent.
The upshot then of the essential versus non-essential distinction is not
only that this is an exhaustive disjunction, but in addition to that we can see
that all being is either necessary or contingent. However one chooses to put
it, all being is either capable of not existing, or not, a thing can exist either
essentially from the necessity of its own nature, or not, necessary or contin-
gent, etc., the result is the same. There are no third options here.
Likewise we can say the same for the intrinsic versus extrinsic division.
If some quality is not intrinsic to a thing, then it must be, by definition,
extrinsic to it. There simply is no third option here. This division, like the
other two, is exclusive and exhaustive.
With these explanations of the possible sources behind us, it may not
matter which one we use. They are all exhaustive and seem to say the same
thing using different words. Yet my preferred way of making the disjunction
will be between the thing itself or by another. Everything then will be either
self-distinguishing (its own sufficient reason) or other-distinguishing. I pre-
73 For a relatively recent defense of the notion of essence by I'rnm mi mutlytlc philos-
opher, see Alvin Plantingu, The Nature of Necessity (New Yorki Oiritiril UnlviTslly Press,
1974), 54-77,
Vic Principle Stated and Its Meaning
fer this way of stating the disjunction for two reasons. l;irst, "by another"
gives us a positive reference to some other being rather than a mere negation
like "not itself" or "non-essential".74 Secondly, such a formulation has the
benefit of being more "metaphysically generic," that is to say, this disjunc-
tion prescinds from any particular ontology. Unless one is a radical monist,
all metaphysicians should agree that "this thing itself or something else" is
an exhaustive and non-controversial disjunction. All we need to do at this
point is to reunite what we have distinguished. Taking the first principal
part of the principle of sufficient reason and joining it to the second, when
you join these two propositions together, you get the full blown principle of
sufficient reason: "Whatever exists must have an act of being (a reason, that
by which it is distinguished from nothing) either in itself or from another."75
hollowing Kleutgen from the text cited in Chapter I, what this principle re-
ally means is that all existing being either exists by itself or by something
else. Not one being escapes having a reason for its existence because no be-
ing escapes the necessity of being distinct from nothing. Thus, every being
must have a reason for its existence, and no being is without one: Omne ens
1 alionem sufficientem habet: nee ens sine ratione. We can graphically illus-
l rate the distinctions made in this section with the following diagram:
(exhaustive division)
87
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
76 The Thomistic way of saying this is that God s essence would be identified with
existence, viz., what God is and that God is are one and the same. Such a being does not
"cause itself \ Cause by definition means something that exerts a poult Ivc Inlluniccon the
existence of another. Saying that a being causes its own existence lcfidn In absurdity (since
a thing cannot act as cause unless it first exists), but a being ihftt en lulu a *f (IN Its own
sufficient reason) docs not sullcr llnil difficulty.
The Principle Stated and Its Meaning
77 Wc Nnw an example of ihU died nbovc where Berlrand Russell asserted this point
rtgnlnnt (loplcdlon In thtflrfamou*MIU: clclnUc,
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
without a reason, since the will chose it! So whether the mere existence of a
will choosing is a sufficient condition for choice can remain a matter of de-
bate without calling into question the principle of sufficient reason. Hence,
in our efforts to defend the principle of sufficient reason, we do not need to
maintain that an act of the will must always have a motive.
90
The Principle Stated and Its Meaning
91
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
In other words, if it were true that the strong principle of sufficient reas<on
were false, that would not by itself entail that the weak or mild versions were
false. So the defender of the principle of sufficient reason has a pitfall to
avoid, viz., one cannot argue for a strong principle of sufficient reason usiing
only mild or weak principle of sufficient reason evidence! If we show only
that whatever begins to exist has a cause, we have not necessarily shown tlhat
all beings need a reason (all the time).79
With this point in mind, our main concern is the truth of what Ronve
calls the strong principle of sufficient reason. As I formulated it, "What-
ever exists must have an act of being either in itself or from another." TThis
principle, as I have said, will be defended in a later chapter, but given wlhat
has been said here, if an argument can establish the strong principle of
sufficient reason (and I will argue that it can), then, because of their asym-
metrical truth value, it would also entail that all three degrees are trae.
Some of the dialectical arguments in the next chapter, however, will oinly
aim to establish a weak or mild principle of sufficient reason. I will indicate
which version the various arguments support at the appropriate point.
79 This is not to say that there may not be good arguments to show that once one accepts a
more modest principle that they are also committed to a stronger version. In fact, Alexander
Pruss has argued that to accept a weaker version of the principle of sufficient reason entails
accepting a stronger formulation, "that as soon as we accept even a relatively weak version
of the principle, such as that ex nihilo nihil fit (nothing comes from nothing), we should for
the same reason accept the stronger one that every contingent proposition luis an explana-
tion. This will allow us to harness the intuitions behind the ex nihilo nihil fit principle and
argument specifically tailored to this principle as evidence for iho full I'SU once we move
on to giving arguments for the l\SR." Alexander Pruss, 7h$ Principle qlStlJIItltftil Reason: A
Reassessment (New York, (aimbrldge University Press 2006, II.
M
The Principle Stated and lis Meaning
ing of the ex nihilo principle is compatible with the mild principle of suf-
ficient reason, since if it is true that nothing results from nothing (in a
non-temporal sense), then every contingent being has a cause whether it
began to exist or not.80
A third ex nihilo principle, ex nihilo nihil est, "from nothing, nothing is,"
or "nothing that exists is from nothing," is the strongest version. This princi-
ple, properly expressed and expounded, is equivalent to the strong principle
of sufficient reason. The ex nihilo nihil est principle is universal and appli-
cable to all being, albeit indirectly in the sense that this ex nihilo principle
speaks universally when it says, "out of nothing, nothing is," meaning there
is no being whose existence is attributable to nothing. By "from nothing,"
I mean that a being s existence would be attributable to nothing; neither to
I he necessity of its own nature, nor to the causal efficacy of some other be-
ing. Conversely, to be "from something" means that a beings existence is at-
I ributable either to its own nature or the causal efficacy of some other being.
According to ex nihilo nihil est, if things cannot exist "from nothing," then
I hey must exist "from something," which is simply another way of stating
I he strong principle of sufficient reason.81
HO I'or example, we saw in Ch. 1 that Etienne Gilson uses ex nihilo nihil fit in this broad
wmv when explaining Aquinas' five ways. Scotus too, as we saw in that same chapter, uses
un r.v nihilo principle in this broad sense as well since, like Aquinas, his proof does not
iti MIU* I hat the universe began in time.
HI (Ordinal Gerdil (1718-1802), in his "Reflections on a 'Memoir of Monsieur Beguelin
I inm/miing the Principle of Sufficient Reason and the Possibility of a System of Chance*,"
held thai ihe principle of sufficient reason is different in nature from the principle of
linn contradiction. Along with it, truths like these lay at the foundation of human un-
i Ic ml in id ing. He argued that another maxim, "Nothingness produces nothing" is imme-
tllnldy evident without supposing a more exact knowledge of the principle of non-con-
lirtillillon. He concludes that the principle of sufficient reason is nothing other than the
rtKlom, "Nothingness produces nolhlng," and is as legitimate principle as the principle of
linn omlnidlctlon. CSurr, 105- ft.
93
St. 'Ihomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
like, "If the principle of sufficient reason is true, then there are no "brute
I acts," and it is the absence of "brute facts" in the world that is supposed to
be undesirable and clearly false.83 But what exactly are "brute facts," and
what intuitions are we trying to preserve by holding them? Now it seems
lo me that when someone appeals to a brute fact, there are at least four
different senses one might mean by that term:
1. Self-explanatory brute fact - This is the sense of brute fact that means
something that is self-evidently true, no further appeal or evidence is
needed, and a fact that is obvious and in need of no further support.
For example, necessary propositions are true in a "brute fact" sort of
way because they are true in themselves ("Every triangle has three
sides" or "the whole is greater than the part") Facts known through
immediate sense experience, like "fire will burn you if touched," can
also be true in this way.
H J Ibis alleged conflict with "brute facts" and the infinite regress it is supposed to en-
gender, is something that has convinced more than one thinker that the principle of suffl-
t leu I reason is necessarily false! "This provides an occasion for pointing out that the Prin-
i l|»lc of Sufficient Reason, from which Leibniz developed his Cosmological Argument, is,
mi liir from being necessarily true, necessarily false. For Leibniz that great principle' was
"11 mt 'Nothing happens without sufficient reason,' But the truth is that every explanation
MI why things happen as they do is, and cannot but be, in terms of explanatory principles
U'\i>llcantes) that explain but which, at least at that stage, are not themselves explained
Uuv nol things needing to be explained—explicanda). So, however far the process pro-
i mis- -particular happenings explained in terms of general laws, general laws in terms of
ill III more general theories, and so on—there must always be something, or perhaps some
things, that will have to be accepted as the ultimate and inexplicable brute facts; the ulti-
nitilr explicantes in terms of which all the explicanda which can be explained have to be."
Antony Flew, Atheistic Humanism (Buffalo, NY: Prometheus Books, 1993) p. 47. Pope
iiguvs with Flew's criticism, "Why should the principle of sufficient reason be true? The
ilrlnulcrs of the cosmological argument feel that the Universe must at bottom be rational,
hul uguln, why should it? Antony Flew, who is the most profound of the contemporary
11II Us of theism, points out that not only is the principle of sufficient reason unjustified,
lull It Is actually demonstrably false! Any logical argument must start, with some as-
imiiptinns, and these assumptions must themselves be unjustified. We might of course
I if »il>lc lo justify these particular assumptions in the context of another demonstration,
I nun which the particular assumptions are deduced, but this just pushes the problem to
ii higher level; the basic underlying assumptions in the higher level argument are them-
M'lvi'N unjustified. At some point we have to just accept some postulates for which we can
glvr no reason why they should be true. Thus the nature of logic itself requires the principle
of nuJIklvHt reason to be false" A. Pope, "Two Design Arguments," in TheAnthropic Cos-
molo#hvl Principle, ed. John I). Barrow, Frank J. Tipler, and John A. Wheeler (New York:
(Word University Prow, 1V8H), 104, emphasis mine.
95
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
events. So it is only the "brute fact" in the fourth sense that is opposed lo
Ihe principle of sufficient reason. It is only this sort of "brute fact" that is
Incompatible with the principle of sufficient reason. This is what I will call
it "brute fact" in the strict and proper sense.
So the proponent of the principle of sufficient reason then can hap-
plly affirm that brute facts in the first three senses can exist; he or she
only needs to rule out the possibility of brute facts in the fourth sense.
lUil what, may we ask, is wrong with that? The notion of a brute fact as
a being whose existence is utterly unexplainable by any reason is hardly
an intuition we need to preserve. On the contrary, in the next chapter we
will argue just the opposite! That the principle of sufficient reason is in-
\ nmpatible with such "brute facts" in that sense is hardly a strike against
II. Whether or not there can be such beings remains to be shown when
we j^el to defending the principle of sufficient reason, but the point here is
•Imply to clarify in what sense the principle of sufficient reason rules out
"hrule facts" and the only kind of brute fact it does rule out is precisely the
highly counterintuitive one that our common sense intuitions don't need
anyway. All the other senses of "brute facts" are quite compatible with the
pi ineiple of sufficient reason.
Summary
So in this this chapter I have attempted to explain as precisely as
possible what is meant by the principle of sufficient reason. Most im-
port a nl in this discussion is the concept of "reason." If you'll remember,
"reasons" are that which account for something, and consequently there
tan be reasons in both the metaphysical and logical order, along with
a t<^responding logical and metaphysical version of the principle. It is
I he metaphysical version that is the focus, and the formulation I support
("Whatever exists must have a reason for its existence either in itself or
f t c 1111 another"), when stated in its proper logical form, is actually a con-
luik live proposition consisting of a "principal part" that establishes the
iun essily of having a sufficient reason in the first place ("Whatever exists
imi.Hl have a reason for its existence") and a "source portion" that claims
lu exhaustively delineate the manner in which a being can possess the
iruNnn for its being ("A sufficient reason is had either in itself or from
mini her"). vSpeaking metaphysically, I said that "a reason for a things
rxUlcnec" means simply that which accounts for the existence of some
97
wS7. 'Iliomas Aquinas and the Prkiple of Sufficient Reason
particular being, and that by which a being is distinct from nothing. This
notion of "reason for existence" can be explained in Thomistic terms by
an "act of being," that is to say, an actuality that makes a being distinct
from nothing or mere possibility. The principal part of the principle of
sufficient reason, I have said, is a necessarily true proposition that can be
known through the meaning of its terms while the source proposition is
an exhaustive disjunction.
I have also made it clear that causes are not to be completely identified
with reasons. A cause is a type of reason, and so the scope of "reason" is
broader than that of "cause." Also, by affirming the principle of sufficient
reason, no cognitive competency by human beings is implied. The princi-
ple affirms that there must be sufficient reasons for a thing's existence, but
it does not entail that we must always know what those reasons are.
When we acknowledge the tertium quid between Rowe's division, there
are three degrees of the principle of sufficient reason. The weak principle
of sufficient reason is a principle of becoming, the mild principle of suffi-
cient reason is a principle governing all contingent being, and the strong
principle of sufficient reason encompasses all being whatsoever. These var-
ious degrees are equivalent with various ex nihilo and causal principles.
Finally, I argued that of the many senses of "brute facts" that are avail-
able, only one of them - that a being exists without any sufficient reason
- is prohibited by the principle of sufficient reason. All the other common
sense usages of "brute fact" can be preserved while still maintaining a
strong version of the principle.
Now that we understand the meaning of the principle and its various
degrees, it is time that we proceed to argue on behalf of its truth. This re-
mainder of this work will proceed in five steps. First, we will look at a se-
ries, indeed a cumulative case, consisting of various dialectical arguments
showing that the weak and/or mild versions of the principle are true. In this
section, we will also look at the probative force of such dialectical arguments
and how they might serve as a road to recognizing first principles.
The second step of this case for the principle of sufficient reason will look
at what necessary truths are and how we know them. This step is obviously
helpful since we are claiming that the principle of sufficient reason is a nec-
essary truth. Hence, it will behoove us to delve into precisely what we mean
by necessary truths, that we are able to know necessary trullm, unci even go
so far as to say something about how we come to know n#cimiitry t rulhs.
The Principle Stated and Its Meaning
Armed with this information about necessary truths we will then argue
(hat strong principle of sufficient reason itself is a necessarily true, per se
notum proposition, and can be shown to be such by a reductio ad absurdum
argument. This argument, if successful, will establish the strong principle
of sufficient reason, "Whatever exists has an act of being (reason why it is
distinct from nothing) either in itself or from another." Once this strong
principle of sufficient reason is established, it would also follow, given what
wo have said above, that the weak and mild versions are also true.84
In the fourth step of this effort, we will show how the insights gained
from the principle of sufficient reason could also be employed in other
arguments showing that the principle of causality, viz., that "every contin-
e n t being has a cause" is also necessarily true and thus cannot be denied
wil hout contradiction. To this end we will look at examples from the texts
of Aquinas and defend the arguments he makes there.
Finally, to round out our discussion we will answer all of the objections
I hal have been raised here against the principle of sufficient reason. In
I IK* end, I hope to show that there are very strong dialectical and demon-
s Ira live arguments for the principle of sufficient reason, and there are no
good arguments against it. Reason then would demand that we hold this
principle with a firm conviction.
H'i All hough I make use of scholastic/Thomistic style reasoning, the method here
IIMIUIIIIN strictly systematic. This work is not intended as a work of historical scholar-
ship, 1 hits, Ihls present work, to use the words of Norris Clarke, claims only to present a
"ihnmlNllculy Inspired metaphysics" with the possibility remaining that I am only mak-
ing u "creative retrieval" of hU thought.
"Of course, some philosophers think that somethings having
intuitive content is very inconclusive evidence in favor of it. I think
it is very heavy evidence in favor of anything myself I really do not
know, in a way, what more conclusive evidence one can have about
anything, ultimately speaking"1
- Saul Kripke
} I'm* rxitmplc, HCC Murlhn NuNNbnum, Ihe Fragility of Goodness (Cambridge: Cam-
101
S(. 'Iliomns Aijuintts arid the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
Which view is correct is not clear, and thus we will not pursue this
historical question here.3 What is clear is that Aristotle does say that
dialectic is a "road" to reaching first principles.4 The purpose of dialec-
tic is to cross-examine what we might call "common sense opinions"
or "common beliefs" (endoxa). Aristotle also calls these common beliefs
"appearances."5 Aquinas, at least, is clear that "the sole intent of a dia-
lectician is to proceed from things that are most probable, and these are
things that appear to the majority or to the very wise."6 Aquinas is also
clear that dialect, in itself, is a type of probabilistic reasoning that does
not attain scientific certitude:7
The philosopher differs from the dialectician in power, because
the consideration of the philosopher is more efficacious
than that of the dialectician. For the philosopher proceeds
demonstratively in dealing with the common attributes
mentioned above, and thus it is proper to him to have scientific
knowledge of these attributes. And he actually knows them
with certitude, for certain or scientific knowledge is the effect
of demonstration. The dialectician, however, proceeds to treat
all of the above-mentioned common attributes from probable
premises, and thus he does not acquire scientific knowledge of
them but a kind of opinion''8
If we take both Aristotle and Aquinas at face value, dialectic is
a type of probable reasoning that is nevertheless a "road" or "path"
to first principles. To put this another way, it seems that dialectical
argumentation "helps" us reach certain knowledge of first principles,
even if it does not take us all the way Following Aristotle and Aquinas,
my intent in this chapter is to offer various dialectical arguments for the
bridge University Press, 1986) and May Sim ed., From Puzzles To Principles: Essays On
Aristotle's Dialectic (Boston: Lexington Books, 1999).
3 This topic is thoroughly discussed in Terence Irwin's Aristotle's First Principles (Ox-
ford: Clarendon Press, 1988).
4 "Dialectic is a process of criticism wherein lies the path to the principles of all inqui-
ries/' Topics L, 101b3-4.
5 See for example EE 1216b26-8, EN 1123b22-4,1145b2-3, and Topics l()5bl.
6 In. Post Ana. Lectio 31 Caput 19; vol. 1, 263.)
7 By "scientific certitude" Aquinas means that which is the rcmill of u demonstrative
syllogism, resulting in a causal knowledge of something which cannot hr otherwise.
8 In Meta, IV, 1.4, emphasis mine.
102
Dialectical Arguments for the Weak and Mild Principle of Sufficient Reason
103
St Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
9 John of St. Thomas, Cursus Philosophicus Thomisticus, Volume I, Ars Logica, as ap-
pears in The Material Logic of John of St. Thomas, tr. Yves Simon (Chicago: University of
Chicago, 1955), 525. The cited text in Aquinas* Commentary on the Sentences is In Sent
III.23.2.2 sec.3.
10 "When there is such an accumulation of motives that credibility becomes evident
and no room remains for disbelief, all extrinsic fear is removed." Poinsot, ibid, 528.
11 Whether or not this lesser kind of "certitude" itself can serve as the basis for Aristote-
lian science, I leave to the Aristotelian scholar. It does not matter here, si live In the chapter
to follow, I argue that the strong principle of sufficient reason IN mclttphynk'ully necessary,
and thus, a contradiction to deny, which, if true, would clearly b* siittii tonl In urotmil an
Aristotelian notion of scientific knowledge.
104
Dialectical Arguments for the Weak and Mild Principle of Sufficient Reason
105
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
guments taken collectively can show this, this builds an even stronger cumu-
lative case against such denials The individual probabilities of each argu-
ment accumulate, converge, and produce a degree of certitude that is greater
than any argument taken independently In the same way that individual
steel bands taken separately have a certain degree of strength to them, that
degree of strength is multiplied when all of those bands are woven into a
steel cable, so too the cumulative force of all of these arguments results in an
argument much stronger than any one argument taken in isolation.
12 So we need to distinguish this sense of the word "intuition" an iwcil hrre In u fallible
or defeasible sense, from (he stronger infallible sense of Intuition thttl AI|IIIIUIN culls Intel-
lectus. We will, however, muke use of this stronger »cnM of Inlulllnn In tt lulor chapter,
106
Dialectical Arguments for the Weak and Mild Principle of Sufficient Reason
The idea that things can just "pop" into being uncaused out of nothing is
a patently unreasonable position to hold. Such a metaphysically radical
position just seems obviously false. Asserting the possibility of something
popping into existence uncaused out of nothing would be considered ri-
diculous and out of the question in any aspect of everyday life (save for
philosophy). Imagine a man on trial telling the court that he has no idea
how the stolen $10,000 was found in his car. Perhaps it popped into being
out of sheer nothing? No one would accept this, nor should we entertain
(he possibility. Just like our metaphysical intuitions that tell us things re-
main in existence when they are not being observed, or that the world
was not created five minutes ago with an appearance of age, so too do we
have a fundamental intuition for ex nihilo nihil fit. The principle seems
so patently true, that to be skeptical and demand further proof should
be considered a textbook case of the fallacy of shifting the burden of proof
When something such as this seems so overwhelmingly obvious, surely it
is not up to those who hold it to prove there can be no exceptions, rather
I hat burden lies with those who argue against such certitudes.
107
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
15 Contrary to what some may think, it's actually not true that inductive arguments
never produce certain conclusions. The scholastic logicians distinguished between sev-
eral types of induction, two of which (viz., the complete enumerative induction and the
"virtually complete" induction), both establish their conclusions with certitude. Howev-
er, the inductive argument I am making here is a standard empirical "inductive general-
ization" which makes an inference that moves from an adequate sampling of things to a
conclusion about the whole. So there is no claim here being made of establishing the con-
clusion with absolute certitude since these arguments only claim to establish a conclusion
with a respectable degree of probability.
16 "For the fact that the validity of a proposition cannot be logically guaranteed in no
way entails that it is irrational for us to believe it. On the contrary, what is irrational is to
look for a guarantee where none can be forthcoming; to demand certainly where proba-
bility is all that is attainable." AJ. Ayer, "The A Priori" in Paul MoHer'a A Priori Knowledge
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987), 27. In fact, Bcrlrnnd Kimnrll, 'Ihr Problems of
Philosophy (London: Oxford University Press, 1979), 68-9, aryiltfil ihe imimil principle
was as certain a« any other physical law Yet IUIMCII wanU to mlnlmltfe the mope of ihc
108
Dialectical Arguments for the Weak and Mild Principle of Sufficient Reason
To borrow again from Hume, those who would assert that this posi-
tion is not universally true nor without exception have a quick and an
easy method of refuting it; provide an example of a being, which in their
opinion, is one that comes to be from sheer nothingness.17
However, it is not just the weak principle of sufficient reason that is sup-
ported by induction. This same argument that supports a weak principle
of sufficient reason can also be used in a different way that supports a mild
principle of sufficient reason ("Every contingent thing has a cause"). Just as
in all of our common experience, we never know of a being popping into
being from nothing, so too in all of our experience we know of no being that
is dependent on nothing for its existence. The existence of horses, for exam-
ple, presupposes a tremendous amount of causal factors necessary for their
continuance in being (not just their coming to be). In a similar way, just as
we intuitively recognize things that come into being need an explanation,
so loo we often recognize that contingent being needs an explanation, even
1 f we never witnessed it's coming into existence. This principle seems uni-
versally true for any observable substance. There is no physical being, for
example, whose existence does not presuppose a set of conditions such as
I he fundamental forces of physics, that are necessary for its existence. To put
111 is point another way, there is clearly more to causality than just becoming
unci we have good reason then to invoke Aquinas5 distinction between the
muse of becoming (causa fieri) and the cause of being (causa essendi)}8 A
home builder is the cause of the home s becoming, but he does not cause the
i onlinued being of the home, since the builder of the home may no longer
exisl while the being of the home continues to depend upon other causal
I tu tors (such as the law of gravity, a certain temperature range, the nature of
I he building materials, etc.). So our inductive experience goes further than
|iisl cases of becoming, we also know that all of the observable substances
In I he physical universe need causes for the maintenance as well as a cause
lor 1 heir coming to be. Thus, our inductive generalization also supports the
I it liu Iplc, claiming that the principle is a physical principle, and not a true metaphysical
Inilghl. 1 bis last move is erroneous, as I will explain later.
1/ ()r to borrow a point from Adler, "having an open mind about future possibilities
tlmuM noi be equated, as unfortunately it sometimes is, with having an undecided mind
about present actualities; for we are obliged, at any time, to judge in the light of the evi-
IUMKT thai Is then available." Morlimer Adler, The Difference of Man and the Difference It
Mttkr* (New York: Meridian, IV73). 113.
IMS//'. 1 II, 104,1.
109
St Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
110
Dialectical Arguments for the Weak and Mild Principle of Sufficient Reason
1K) 1 he classical view is that we understand things by knowing their causes. Things of a
i crlu In nature or type behave in similar ways, and there is a certain uniformity and com-
innimlily that underlies and grounds our inductive inference. What is unarguable is that
In likluclion we rise from facts to laws, because we are seeking reasons or explanations for
1111111' phenomenon. We look for the similarity amongst the variety, and seek the how and
why things happen.
JO To pui the point in Aristotelian terms, there is no science of the accidental. "That
I here IN no science of the accidental is obvious; for all science is either of that which is al-
ways or of lhal which is for ihe most part. For how else is one to learn or to teach another?
I he ihlng must be determined us occurring either always or for the most part, e.g. that
honey water Is useful for a pal taut In n fever Is iruc for ihe most part." Meta. VI, 1027a20.
Ill
St Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
21R. Garrigou Lagrange, God: His Existence and His Ntitur** /, I .18,
2TSi igitur res creatai* nan habeant actiones ad productndoi ifl'wtu$t miitctunjttod nun
quam natura allcuitts rrl creator poterlt co^nosclptntffMtum? &(.'.<•, Ill, 0Vi vol,12 ,200,
Dialectical Arguments for the Weak and Mild Principle of Sufficient Reason
113
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
114
Dialectical Arguments for the Weak and Mild Principle of Sufficient Reason
M For the different takes on "explanation* see for example, "Theories of Explana-
tion," by G. Randolph Mayes, The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ISSN 2161-0002,
lillp://www,iep.utm.edu/explanat/, retrieved Sept. 30th 2012.
15 See Walter Sinnott-Armstrong and Robert Fogelin, Understanding Arguments: An
Introduction to Informal Logic, 7th ed. (Belmont, CA: Thomson Wadsworth, 2005), 254-8
lor ii laudable attempt at listing all the criteria for the best explanation. Their list reads:
I, I ho explanation should really explain the observations (not lack explanatory scope).
.'. '1 he explanation should be deep in that if it is just as obscure as the thing that needs to
be explained, no progress is made.
V "I he explanation should be powerful in that it should apply to a wide range of cases or a
wider range of phenomena. 'I he explanation that explains more is better than one that
cxplultiN ICHH.
115
,S7, ihotiuis Aquinas and the Priciplc of Sufficient Reason
explanations than are needed to explain some event. If rain suffices to ex-
plain the wet grass, it would be unreasonable to invoke the additional el-
ements of a sprinkler, busted water pipe, and open fire hydrant to explain
the water on the ground.
So to summarize this point so far, we can make three unassuming and
uncontroversial claims:
1. It is entirely reasonable to give explanations for phenomena.
2. Not all explanations have equal explanatory power. Some are better
than others and it is more reasonable to seek the best explanation.
116
Dialectical Arguments for the Weak and Mild Principle of Sufficient Reason
lb Of course, the recognition of the importance of "Ockham's Razor" did not begin
wllh William of Ockham. In fact, Aristotle attributes the principle to Empedocles, "And
II IN belter to assume a nmttllcr and finite number of principles, as Empedocles does."
/>/i>'j/a, I, l88al7-l8(nec*Uo Phyilu 189a, 15-18),
117
St Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
entities; the principle simply holds that we should only do so when "ne-
cessity" demands. This prohibition of invoking entities has been called the
"negative edge" of Ockham's razor, yet as stated, this principle also implies
also a "positive edge." "Do not multiply causes without necessity" implies
that when there is "necessity," one ought to multiply causes. Sometimes
called Walter Chatton's "anti-razor,"27 viz., "If three things are not enough
to verify an affirmative proposition about things, a fourth must be added,
and so on." Ockham's razor principle clearly implies that when insufficient
reasons are present, a positive edge of the razor is invoked. That is to say,
Ockham's razor is a meaningful and helpful principle if and only if it also
implies that positive edge that spurs us onward to "add more." After all,
if we are to avoid multiplying causes even when there is an apparent lack
of necessity, the principle devolves into a pointless assertion of simply "do
not multiply causes," for any reason, which is a position that no serious
thinker would want to maintain. So the "necessity" involved here in Ock-
ham's razor when we say don't multiply causes beyond necessity, hinges
upon a recognition of sufficiency and insufficiency in explanation. If we do
not have enough entities to explain event X, we are to invoke more; if we
do have enough entities, we should not invoke more.
Now with this obvious point understood, we can again see the subtle pre-
supposition of the principle of sufficient reason at play here, and it is precisely
the same problem as it was in the prior problem regarding explanatory scope.
The very "necessity" that would motivate us to add more entities would do so,
indeed could only do so, because some prior explanation was somehow seen as
insufficient. It would only be because the current explanation lacked explana-
tory scope that we would be justified in seeking more explanatory entities. But
again, how can an explanation ever be faulted for lacking explanatory scope if
the principle of sufficient reason were false? Brute facts do not need explana-
tions. What would it mean to say "do not multiply causes beyond necessity"
when there can never he any necessity? There is no reason why we would ever
feel compelled into fortifying an explanation by adding more entities if we are
entirely content with the idea that things do not need sufficient explanations
in the first place. If the principle of sufficient reason were false, then there is
absolutely nothing wrong with insufficiency and lack of comprehension in
explanation. Just like the demand that a good explanation be comprehensive,
27 See Rondo Keeles cnlry on Waller Chatlon In the 8tttr\ford Hmyvhimltu of Philoso-
phy: found nt hllp;//pluLablUillui'd^
118
Dialectical Arguments for the Weak and Mild Principle af Sujlhient Hatmw
-}.H At least the weak version of the principle, but I am also inclined to think they show
the mild version to be prcauppoHcd as well since explanation is not always restricted to
hreumlng but can alio r»f*r It) I hi? being of a conllngcnt event. It is not only the becoming
ol green In the plant thlt m|ulr#» eitplaiwtlnn, but the maintenance of thai color as well.
119
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
Note that both necessary and sufficient conditions are explanatory - they
tell us why an event occurs. Another way to say this is that both necessary
and sufficient conditions are reasons as to why something happens. Usually
when we use these terms we are talking about causes of some kind. To say
oxygen is a necessary condition of fire is to say oxygen must be present in
order for the fire to be, in other words, oxygen is a necessary albeit partial
cause of thefire.But once we deny the principle of sufficient reason, if things
do not need reasons to make them happen, what could ever justify such talk
about necessary or sufficient conditions?
The problem is that inherent in any appeal to necessary and sufficient
conditions, is the presumption that things are intelligible and do happen for
reasons. The universe does not operate haphazardly, and things do not occur
"brute factily" If they did, the usage of the necessary or sufficient condition
distinction would be terribly problematic. To underscore this difficulty,
suppose we ask just what are the grounds for holding that there is such a
thing as a "necessary condition?" How can any condition be "necessary"
if at the same time, it is posited that things can be without any reason?
If no reasons are needed, then there can be no such thing as a necessary
condition, and the term becomes meaningless. In a similar way, how can
an appeal to something like a "sufficient condition" be substantiated if one
also denies things do not need sufficient reasons? After all, what is the
difference between a sufficient condition and a sufficient reason? The two
seem remarkably similar in meaning. A sufficient condition is something
that, if satisfied, is enough to bring about the occurrence of something, but
that just states what a sufficient reason is using different terms. A sufficient
reason is that by which something is; a.k.a., that which, when met, is
enough to make something be. The only difference here is a difference
in words. Hence, if things do not need sufficient reasons, for either their
becoming or their being, they do not need sufficient conditions either. To
summarize this point we can argue:
If the principle of sufficient reason is false, the appeal to necessary
and sufficient conditions is unintelligible.
120
Dialectical Arguments for the Weak and Mild Principle oj Sujlhlent Retitim
121
JN W»Nrt1rfl A^fffrM' urn/ f/ii« ft-U-lph of Sujlidrnt Reason
No problem NO far - after all, this is how the scientific method should
work, lUil suppose 1 also say that not everything that is contingent needs
tin explanation. This changes things entirely, for if not everything needs
an explanation, the modus tollens fails, for it maybe that ~E is one of those
happenings that has no explanation. If so, it is not explained by anything,
including the failure of H. Therefore, it is possible that H could be true
(<>H). Then we have (~H & <>H), which is a contradiction, so the modus
tollens has failed. Denying the principle of sufficient reason, in at least its
weak form (if not also its mild form), then destroys the applicability of
modus tollens to the scientific method, which seems to jeopardize the sci-
entific enterprise itself.
Of course, the same could be said for modus ponens. If p, then q, p
therefore q - but how can this be valid without presupposing the truth of
the principle of sufficient reason? Again, q could be one of those events
that are not explained by anything, including the success of p. Under the
hypothesis of denying the principle of sufficient reason, the positing of p
may in some instance, for no reason whatsoever, not produce q. P for no
reason whatsoever does not produce q, and q itself can be for no reason at
all. Modus ponens has failed.
At this point, some modern logicians may object saying that all that is
needed for the truth of modus ponens is that the antecedent not be true
and the consequent false. In other words, why do we need to presuppose
that there is any connection between consequent and antecedent? Impli-
cation, it may be argued, can get along just fine without such a presuppo-
sition. All one needs to do is posit that this material implication is the best
way to understand implication and that with material implication, there
need not be any connection between the consequent and antecedent. So by
taking this tack, one might think t,hey can avoid the above argument and
in so doing, avoid presupposing the principle of sufficient reason when
using hypothetical syllogisms.
In response we can say that there are very strong reasons to think that
material implication is not correct and that strict implication is a much
more realistic and plausible method of how implication should be under-
stood. Because of this difference in understanding implication, and be-
cause the question of which side is correct is very important to under-
standing the role that the principle of sufficient reason play* In conditional
syllogisms, this topic is worthy of some exlenalve nntmrku hrrr.
122
Dialectical Arguments for the Weak and Mild Principle of Sufficient Hen»on
'I he debate over the nature of implication goes back to the Megarian
jiiid Stoic logicians. Diodorus stressed the need for a necessary connection
In implication, and it is this understanding of the nature of implication
Ihal has predominated throughout the scholastic era and remains today
with logicians who prefer the traditional logic. With "strict" or Diodorean
Implication, the conditional proposition is true when the antecedent can-
nnl be true without the consequent also being true. This is because for a
i onditional proposition to be true, the connection between the antecedent
and consequent must be necessary in some way such that the consequent
must really follow from the antecedent. To put it another way, in Diodor-
nm implication, the antecedent and consequent must be causally related*
I.e., if P is true then Q must be true.31
However, Philo argued for what is today known as "material implica-
llon," viz., that a conditional proposition is true when it is not the case
I hal it begins with the true and ends with the false. This "Philonian" un-
derstanding of implication, known as "material implication," is the com-
mon way implication is described and understood in most modern logic
lexis. Philonian implication differs from Diodorean implication in that
Phi Ionian implication cares nothing about causal connections. Philonian
Implication prescinds from looking at connections between consequent
and antecedent and instead focuses on the abstract "truth values" of each
rlement.32 All that is needed for a conditional proposition to be true is that
II Is not the case that the antecedent be true and the consequent false.
An example may help the reader better grasp the difference. The
proposition, "If it rains, the ground will be wet" is true in a Diodorean
sense because rain causes the ground to become wet. The Diodorean
understanding of conditional propositions is that what is asserted is a
connection between P and Q. This "causal connection" understanding of
Implication in a proposition signifies a real causal connection in reality. In
I >iodorean implication, there is a relation of sequence and dependence in
hypothetical propositions, and one would have to know what the elements
were about in order to determine the truth value of the statement, since
123
St Thomas Aquinas and the I7 r leipie of Sufficient Reason
"If naturalism is all the rage these days, then Mozart was an
outstanding musician."
Such strange and uncanny propositions are all true under the Philonian
understanding of implication, but all false under a Diodorean sense.
Focusing on the independent truth-value of statements without regard as
33 By "material content" here I mean what the proposition is about (what scholastics
called the "matter" of propositions). This use of "material" here is different from what the
modern logician means by "material implication." This latter sense of "material" is an
attempt to capture what is meant by the English phrase "If...then" in a way that no real
connection is suggested between the antecedent and the consequent. All that is being
asserted in material implication is that, as a matter of fact, it is not the case that the an-
tecedent is true while the consequent is false. As used by Copl and Cohen, "we propose
to translate any occurrence of the "if-then" phrase into our logical uymbol... This means
that in translation conditional statements into our symbolt$m> wt trmt tlwm all as merely
material Implications" Copl nnd Cohen, Introduction to Logict JM, unphmU added.
124
Dialectical Arguments for the Weak and Mild Principle of Sufficient Reason
to how they are connected allows for any highly counterintuitive "true"
propositions that contain such weird accidentally joined elements.34 The
mere fact that Philonian implication justifies such bizarre examples,
nhould be enough to convince us that something is seriously wrong with
I his understanding of implication. But if that is not enough to convince
one that Diodorean implication is to be preferred, there is also this
devastating criticism of Philonian implication by the medieval scholastic
Icihn Buridan:
"If no proposition is negative, then some proposition is negative."35
'I his is surely a knockout blow to the Philonian understanding of
Implication. The statement itself is entirely nonsensical, self-contradictory
In fact, yet since the antecedent is false (necessarily), and the consequent is
I rue (necessarily), then this bit of nonsense is "true" in a Philonian sense!
Iluridan decisively shows here, (correctly to my mind) that Philonian
Implication justifies this nonsense as a valid inference.
But just as Buridan points out serious problems with the truth of
^Moments under Philonian implication, we could also analogously point
mil serious problems regarding the validity of arguments under a Philonian
hike on implication. If we ignore the connection between antecedent
itiul consequent, as Philonian implication suggests we do, suddenly we
lose any justification for the rules of validity. Consider, for example, the
In I lacy of affirming the consequent. This fallacy arises precisely from the
recognition that the relationship between antecedent and consequent is
not bidirectional. "If it is raining, then the ground is wet" does not mean
that "if the ground is wet then it is raining". But if we do not consider
i rial ions between antecedent and consequent, what justification is there
lor saying such a move is fallacious? If we can truthfully say, "If 2+2=4,
then Chicago is a big city" why cant we also say that "if Chicago is a big
i It y, t hen 2+2=4"? If causal connections are disregarded in the former, why
should the latter proposition be faulted for assuming such connections
are bidirectional? That is to say that if relations between propositions are
i»J Surely Veatch is right in dividing compound propositions into conjunctive com-
I urn nils and implicative compounds. Implicative compounds are ones where one P implies
»tmil her, whereas In conjunctive compounds two Ps can be joined accidentally. Henry B.
Watch, "Aristotelian mul Mnlhcninllcal Logic," The Thomist, 13 (Washington D.C.: The
IhomUt [>rcH«, 1953), 71,
t!S AM reported In I.M. Hoilwukl, A History of Formal Loglct 196.
125
St Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
36 Hie same goes for the fallacy of denying the antecedent, since this fallacy too results
from misunderstanding the direction of the conditional relationship.
37 Yet even if these arguments against Philonian implication fail, still clearly condi-
tional statements like "If I touch fire, I will burn" and other common sense phrases im-
plying strict implication are meaningful and useful. We need Diodorean statements even
if Philonian implication can be reasonably defended. For a full critique of material impli-
cation, see Henry B. Veatch, "Aristotelian and Mathematical Logic," The Thomlst, vol. 13
(Washington D.C.: The Thomist Press, 1953).
38This seems applicable to both the weak and mild principle of milllclcnl rciiHon, since
not all causality brings a thing into being, but maintains a thing In III being,
126
Dialectical Arguments for the Weak and Mild Principle of Sufficient Reason
experience etc. with logical certitude. This leaves the door open for the
possible exceptions, that the principle of sufficient reason could still pos-
Nlbly be false. Future evidence may reveal that the principle has been vi-
olated. For this reason, part of our confidence in the conclusions of these
arguments comes from our estimation of how reasonable it is to expect
I hat the principle of sufficient reason will ever be overturned by future ev-
idence. For this reason, let us now take a moment to consider the question
ill' falsifying the principle of sufficient reason and whether or not we can
reasonably expect that the principle of sufficient reason will ever be under-
inined by a counterexample. As I see it, there are three difficulties involved
In falsifying the principle of sufficient reason.
Difficulty #1:
Past Experience and Popper's Law
1 his argument is based on the first inductive argument above. There
it iv no known cases of a being that violates the weak or mild principle of
Millicient reason. In the history of the human race, there is no single clear
example. Popular claims about quantum physics mistakenly claim that
events occur "uncaused" at the subatomic level.39 This is not at all the case
lor a couple of reasons. First, not all scientists agree that quantum events
iu air without a cause. There are at least ten different interpretations of
i|tiantum mechanics, some being fully deterministic. To date, no one can
nhow which is correct. Secondly, even on the "Copenhagen" interpreta-
I Ion, particles do not into being from true nothing. On the contrary, par-
I li los arise from fluctuations of energy in the subatomic vacuum, which is
tint a metaphysical "nothing," as it is a sea of fluctuating energy governed
by physical laws. Hence, there are no grounds for appealing to quantum
physics as a basis for denying the principle of sufficient reason.40
W Peter Atkins, for example, thinks that "a particle and its anti-particle can be gen-
nulal out of essentially nothing." Peter Atkins, Creation Revisited (Hardmondsworth:
IViiKiiln Books, 1994), 139.
•10 As (>aig states, "This objection [that quantum physics shows something can come into
lu'lnn from nothing], however, is based on misunderstandings. In the first place, not all sci-
I'MltalN agree that sub-atomic events are uncaused. A great many physicists today are quite
iflMitllNficd wilh this view (the so-called Copenhagen Interpretation) of quantum physics
unil are exploring deterministic theories like that of David Bohm... Second, even on the
itmlltlonal liulclermlnlnllc interpretation, particles do not come into being out of nothing.
Ihry urine an uponlBncuui UucUmtUniH of I he energy contained in the sub-atomic vacuum,
127
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
Difficulty #2:
Any Case Brought Against the Principle of Sufficient
Reason Must Assume the Principle of Sufficient Reason
Those who deny the principle of sufficient reason must make a case
against it. To make a case against something is to bring forth reasons
why it should not be believed. These reasons must be either sufficient or
insufficient. If the reasons are insufficient, it cannot amount to a proof.
Therefore, any successful criticism of the principle of sufficient reason
must itself make use of a sufficient reason, and in so doing, assume the
very same principle it denies, meaning that any such argument would be
trapped in self-referential inconsistency.
128
Dialectical Arguments for the Weak and Mild Principle of Sufficient Reason
Difficulty #3:
The Difficulty of Ever Proving Something Came
from Nothing
Even if we were to set aside the previous argument and allow for the
possibility of a real counter-example to the principle of sufficient reason,
what would this violation of the principle of sufficient reason look like in
reality? The clearest case of something existing without a sufficient reason
would be the observance of a being that begins to exist, unambiguously,
without any cause whatsoever. A being just popping into existence
uncaused out of nothing would be a patent violation of the weak principle
of sufficient reason, and thus, would be a good candidate for undermining
I he universality of this principle.
But per Anscombe,42 how could it ever be shown that something really
did come into being from nothing? Suppose our hidden stash of cash tri-
41 For example, at least the real causation needed for knowledge would be necessary,
since if we cannot know that our mental processes are reflective of and caused by real things,
we would be cut off from knowing the external world. Moreover, without real causation,
conditional syllogisms could not reflect real world causation, and would become useless in
explaining real world phenomena. Essential to any criticism of the principle of sufficient
reason is the hypothetical proposition, "If sufficient reasons are brought against the prin-
ciple of sufficient reason, we should regard the principle of sufficient reason as false." But
purportedly any alleged "evidence" showing the principle of sufficient reason to be false
would itself have to presuppose some real world examples that would cause us to reject the
principle of sufficient reason, meaning that a real world to mental causal interaction would
always be required for any Hrjtuincnl against the principle of sufficient reason to succeed.
42 (i. H. M, Amicombtfi 'Whrtlrver HUN a beginning of Existence Must Have a Cause:
I lumi\H Argument ltxpoml/' Analytic Vol, Ht No, 5 (April 1974), 145-51.
129
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
pled since the last time we looked at it; or a magician pulled a rabbit out
of a hat; or a basket that once only contained five loaves and two fish sud-
denly now had enough fish to feed a crowd offivethousand? We would not
typically be inclined to accept that something literally came from nothing
in these circumstances, but would offer alternative explanations that seem
more intuitively plausible, i.e., that we were originally mistaken about the
amount, the hat had a secret pocket, a miracle from God has occurred,
etc. Our willingness to accept these other alternatives as more plausible
speaks to the strength of the original metaphysical intuition - that some-
thing cannot come from nothing. That is not to say this intuition cannot
be overthrown, but it's difficult to see how one could ever show that some-
thing really did in fact come into being from absolute nothing.
This three difficulties show that 1) it is very unreasonable to expect a
violation of the principle of sufficient reason, 2) any argument aimed at
establishing a violation of the principle of sufficient reason would itself
have to presuppose the principle of sufficient reason and 3) it could never
be conclusive shown that something really did in fact come from nothing
in the first place, Leibniz issued a challenge to those who denied the
principle of sufficient reason over 300 years ago: give just one example
of some entity in our experience that does not abide by the principle of
sufficient reason. To this day his challenge has never been answered, and
there are strong reasons to think that answer will never come.
130
Dialectical Arguments for the Weak and Mild Principle ofSuJIUiviit Reason
knowledge without any fear of error, we should, by the same token, accept
the principle of sufficient reason with an equal degree of certitude.
At the beginning of this chapter I cited John Poinsot's distinction
between intrinsic and extrinsic certitude. The arguments in this chapter
have not attempted to show that the principle of sufficient reason is
intrinsically certain (true in virtue of the terms themselves). What they
do attain, however, is an extrinsic certitude, and this certitude is increased
when the arguments are taken cumulatively. These arguments converge
and provide us with a very strong degree of confidence that the principle
of sufficient reason is true. That confidence is again strengthened when
we consider that there are also three complementary reasons for thinking
ihe principle will never be shown to be false. In total then, we have a
converging accumulation often lines of dialectical reasoning that provide
a very powerful cumulative case on behalf of the principle of sufficient
reason. This convergence is more than enough to remove any extrinsic
fear of error, and thus allow us to be certain, in a sense, of the weak and
mild principle of sufficient reason.
"Those who admit nothing destroy discussion and reasoning in
general and thus there is no reasoning with such men."1
- Aristotle
"If you hold that nothing is self-evident, I will not argue with you
for it is clear that you are a quibbler and are not to be convinced."3
- Duns Scotus
4 I'or a llsl of examples written for a more popular audience, see Mortimer Adler, Ten
Philosophical Mistakes (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1985),
133
SI, 'I bourns Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
truths, that is, what necessary truths are, that we know them, and how we
know them.5 Since we are claiming that the principle of sufficient reason is
a necessary truth, and given that our current academic climate is, to say the
least, very confused about such things, it is important that we spend some
time discussing this question here. Thus, in this chapter we will cover three
topics, namely; what necessary truths are, that we are able to know them,
and finally we will say a few words on how we come to know them.
5For a more complete account of this problem, see Henry II, Walch, '/too Logics: The
Conflict between Classical and Neo-Analytical Philosophy (UvamUoit. IN; Northwestern
University Press, l%y),
134
Necessary Truths and Our Ability to Know 'llicm
135
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
tions that are "synthetically" true. When propositions are analytically true,
they are said to be "true by definition," that is, via a relation of ideas within
the proposition. (So far so good, as far as a scholastic may be concerned.)
But the problem rears its head when we ask about details about that "defi-
nition" When we say something is "true by definition," what exactly does
that mean? Of course, it depends on whom you ask, but the ordinary answer
that some modern thinkers give is problematic. More often than not, mod-
ern thinkers influenced by Kant and Hume simply take "true by definition"
to be true by a mere relation of ideas, such as the form "All AB s are B."
The word "mere" here is important, for far too often, analyticity degenerates
into subjectivity A mere subjective relation of ideas compels many of these
thinkers to adopt the position that necessary propositions do not refer to
anything in the real world (sometimes stated as "analytic truths cannot be
synthetic truths")! In this epistemically handicapped view, "analytic" truths
are just about relations of ideas, which usually entails they are just products
of human convention. The problem is that justifying necessary truths based
on linguistic convention or definition deprives them of their strength, since
the necessity in such cases is merely subjective. When the modality is sub-
jective, the certitude of the relation between subject and predicate is based
on convention, and the loss of realism is replaced with a surrealism, which
interestingly enough is not all that necessary.8 If the necessity of these prop-
ositions is based on something entirely subjective, then of course there are
no grounds for claiming an objective necessity.
The lesson to be learned from this is that you do not explain things if
you are only explaining words. Talk about how a proposition can be known
"prior to experience," and talk about the containment of the predicate in
the subject is all well and good as far it goes, but it does not go far enough
to adequately express what a necessary proposition really is.
Let us repair this modern notion of propositional necessity with a more
traditional one. When a scholastic meant a proposition was necessarily
true, it meant it was a judgment based on "necessary matter" {in necessar-
ia materia), as opposed to a judgment based on "contingent matter" (in
materia contingenti).9 The "matter" of these judgments naturally refers
8 The failure of such alternatives like these were no doubt pnrl of Quine's mo-
tivation to rejecting a priori justification altogether.
9 See for example, John of Si. Thomas, Outlines of Formal Logh\ fine Mnllcr of Prop-
ositions") 59.
136
Necessary Truths and Our Ability to Know l\\pm
to what the judgment is about. Pace the Kantian dogma, i.e., necessary
judgments refer only to thought, judgments referring to necessaria ma-
teria are both necessary and refer to reality. The "necessary matter" was a
reference to the way things really are. This is an objective, reality-based
necessity.10 How does reality provide a basis for necessity? It is obvious
t hat things are what they are, and if we can know what things are, we can
make necessary propositions about them11. In virtue of the principle of
identity, everything is what it is, and necessarily so (everything is neces-
sarily itself). That which a thing is (meaning it could not be itself without
il), is what it is essentially. When we predicate something essential about
a thing, we are saying that it has something that it must have, that it has
I hat property essentially. Thus when a proposition is necessary, this simply
means that to deny it would be to say that the subject is not itself- that it is
not what it is essentially. In this way, to deny of a subject what it is essen-
1 ially is not merely false, but a contradiction.
10 Many moderns reject the idea that necessary propositions can be about reality, but
we are almost never given a good reason for accepting this dogmatic claim. Surely some
propositions are both necessary and refer to the real world. What about the oft repeated,
"Nothing can be red all over and green all over at the same time?" There are numerous
other examples, like "There are no round squares," "All cubes have 12 edges," or even the
principle of non-contradiction itself. All of these seem necessary and refer to the real
world. Moreover, it seems apparent that there is at least one necessarily true statement
nbout the world, since the statement that "There are no necessary facts about the world"
Is ilself necessarily false! Thus, by contradictory opposition, it must be the case then that
I he statement, "Some proposition is a necessary fact about the world" is necessarily true.
More argumentation for this position is given below.
11 Aquinas says per se notum propositions and first principles are known from abstract-
ing intelligible species of things: "Quidam vero crediderunt intellectum agentem non esse
tillud quam habitum principiorum indemonstrabilium in nobis. Sedhoc esse non potest, quia
rtlum ipsaprincipia indemonstrabilia cognoscimus abstrahendo a singularibus, utdocetphi-
losophus in I Poster. Unde oportet praeexistere intellectum agentem habitui principiorum
slcut causam ipsius; quia vero principia comparantur ad intellectum agentem ut instrumenta
(fiiaedam eius, quia per ea,facit alia intelligibilia actu? Quaest. De anima , Q. 5. See also
S.'i, HI, 51, 1. As the later Thomist, John of St. Thomas puts it, "It is not the signification
of I he terms but the connection of the things signified which causes a proposition to be de-
monstrable by a middle term or devoid of a middle term and consequently immediate or
Nt'lf- evident." John of St. Thomas, Cursus Philosophicus Thomisticus, Volume I, Ars Logicay
us appears in The Material Logic ofJohn of St. Thomas, tr. Yves Simon (Chicago: University
of (Chicago, 1955), 463, emphasis added. Also, Owens puts the point this way, ""all the sim-
ple natures that are known to man come to the intellect from sensible things through simple
apprehension, these immediate judgments of essence are all based upon the way things are
In the HciiNlblc world." Oweim, UkmvnUiry Christian Metaphysics, 273.
137
St Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
In the scholastic view then, necessary truths are based on a real mate-
rial necessity. The key difference here is that the necessity involved does
not depend upon the subjective state of ones knowledge or even the ad-
equacy of ones concepts.12 In other words, the scholastic position rejects
the modern bent of making necessity subjective via conventional or nom-
inal understandings of definitions. Nominal definitions are definitions of
words, in that they directly refer to how a word is used (often based on
convention). Real definitions, on the other hand, relay information about
the actual thing signified, saying what something is (defining the essence).
So when we really define a triangle as a "three-sided polygon," we do not
just imply that the word "triangle" conventionally means that; we mean
that this is what triangles really are. We are stating that the essence of a tri-
angle is to have three sides, and something could not be a triangle if it had
any more or any less. In other words, to say that a triangle drawn on the
chalkboard is not a triangle is not just false, it is necessarily false because
the statement entails a contradiction:
Moreover, when one undertakes to say what any particular kind
of thing is - say, that a triangle is a three-sided rectilinear figure,
or that a human being is a rational animal - then one cannot put
12 Per se propositions can be per se "in itself" {in se) or for us {quoad nos). This distinc-
tion acknowledges that there could be necessarily true propositions that we do not yet or
may never know (it does not have to be self-evident that P is self-evident). These would be
true "in themselves," meaning that the objective situation to which they refer would be
such and such a way, even if nobody ever knew it. In this way, John of St. Thomas answers
an objection he attributes to Scotus, saying that Aquinas doesn't consider just the formal
proposition or merely the signification of the terms, rather he also considers the founda-
tion that self-evident propositions have as grounded in things. So it is not the signification
of the terms but also the connection of the things signified that makes a proposition self-ev-
ident "in itself"; "There is no impropriety in considering it [the proposition] objectively
rather than formally, in other words, from the standpoint of the thing signified... It is
now easy to answer the argument used by our opponents. Let it be said that in St Thomas
'self-evident proposition' designates not only proposition formally understood but also in
an objective sense and in the foundation of its truth. A proposition is self-evident in itself
when there is an immediate connection in the object, and it is self-evident to us when this
connection is manifested and explained by terms of such nature that without discourse
and by the mere understanding of the terms we come to know the connection." John of St
Thomas, Material Logic, 464 emphasis added. That a perse proportion that Is known by
us can be known by nearly all or only to the wise: "Some thlngn, however, HIT Immediately
evident only to those with trained minds, who know th« m i n i n g of the terms, whereas
ordinary people do not know them." De tor,, 10» 12i vol, 23, MO,
138
Necessary Truths and Our Ability to Know Uttm
139
,S7. 'llwnniM Aquinas tttnl (he I'rlclplc of Sufficient Reason
140
Necessary Truths ami Our Ability to Know Ihnn
is the proper subject of that property.20 Aquinas says this second mode of
per se predication implies a relationship of material cause since, in this
case, "number" is the proper subject of the properties "even or odd". Take
another example, "Man has the ability to laugh." Aquinas says this prop-
osition is also necessarily true in the second mode because "man" is the
proper subject of the property "able to laugh." Accordingly, just as we have
a necessary connection when the predicate is contained in the definition
of the predicate, we also have a necessary connection when the subject is
contained in the definition of the predicate. Just as you cannot take away
from "man" that he is an animal (first mode of per se) so too you cannot
take away from the notion of number that it be even or odd (second mode
of per se).21 The necessary connection runs both ways.22
With that being said however, there are a couple of important differ-
ences between the first and second mode predication that are worthy of
mention. The first difference is that, although the second mode of per se
predication is a necessary one, still in second mode predication, one can
conceive of the subject without conceiving of the predicate. In other words,
when considering the definition of the subject, the predicate need not be
considered. This might sound counterintuitive to modern ears but the ra-
I ionale Aquinas gives for this point is compelling and to understand it we
have to remember precisely what the claim is here. The claim is that second
mode per se predication is predicating proper, or we could say necessary,
accidents to a subject. In such cases, the predicate is an accident in the
sense that it is a non-essential quality, yet it is still necessary. This notion
of a "necessary accident" is not a contradiction in terms. These properties
are truly accidents in the sense that they do not enter into the definition or
20 "In another way, a proposition is called necessary whose subject, on the other hand,
is placed in the definition of the predicate; as when we say that a nose is snub or that a
number is even. For a snub nose is nothing else than a curved nose, and an even number
Is nothing else than a number divisible by two" In II de Anima, lect. 14.
21 "Whatever belongs to a thing in virtue of itself cannot be taken away from it. For
example, you cannot take away from man that he be an animal, nor can you take away
I rum number that it be even or odd." Quaest. De anima, 14.
11 "We judge a thing to be absolutely necessary from the relation of the terms... as
when Ihc subject belongs to the notion of the predicate: thus it is necessary that a number
he either odd or even." SX I. 19.3. Again, "there is absolute necessity [necessitas absoluta]
In things from the order of their essential principles to the properties flowing from their
nuttier or form; a saw, heciuinc It Is made of iron, must be hard; and a man is necessarily
umuble of learning" S,c;,C#\ ILK).
141
St. 'lliomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
essence of the thing, but they are necessary in the sense that they are prop-
erties that naturally and necessarily arise from that essence.23 So their acci-
dental characteristic comes from the fact that they are non-essential, but
their characteristic of necessity comes from the fact that such an essence
cannot possibly exist without its proper accident. The proper accident is
a natural concomitant of the essence, that is to say, it is a property that is
necessarily derivative, or, to use Aquinas* terminology, a "certain natural
resultance" from the essence of the thing.24
The justification for claiming a thing can be conceived of without its
proper accident but cannot be said to exist without its proper accident cor-
responds well with Aquinas' teaching on the two acts of the mind. The
first act of the mind, called by logicians "simple apprehension", merely
considers what something is without affirming or denying anything about
it. There is no truth value assigned to the first act of the mind, since no
affirmations or denials are being made here. The second act of the mind,
called "judgment", is where truth value comes into play. In the act of judg-
ing, we either unite or divide two concepts and say this is the way they are
in reality, and this judgment is the mental act that produces propositions.
Relating this back to the second mode of per se predication, one can, for
example, conceive of number without having to conceive of either even or
odd. Likewise, one can conceive what a man is without having to think
about his ability to laugh. Such conception in the first act of the mind
occurs by way of simple apprehension and only considers the essence of
the subject, nothing else. The necessary accidents that are natural con-
comitants of that essence are not included in the essence and so therefore
are not considered. Accordingly, one can conceive of the subject without
conceiving of the predicate when we are talking about second mode pred-
ication, but it would be erroneous to infer from that fact that therefore such
a thing can exist without that necessary accident. How a thing must be
conceived of essentially does not give us all that is necessarily entailed by
142
Neiwutry l)vth» ml Uut Ability M KhttW fftlfft
its existence. Simple apprehension can leave out any neceMimry y*t IU)I1*M*
sential properties, while judgment, the second act of the mind thai relrw
lo existence, cannot. It is true that one does not need to conceive of "even
or odd" when you think about the nature of number, but that does not
mean that there could be a number that was not even or odd. Likewise, one
can conceive of a man without thinking of his risibility, but it would be a
contradiction to say a man exists without this property of risibility.25 The
contradiction arises precisely here in the second act of the mind because
although the property is not in the essence, still, that property is a neces-
sary concomitant of that essence and so that essence cannot exist without
t hat property To put this point most succinctly, simple apprehension can
leave out properties but judgments cannot. We can know what it is with-
out thinking about any of its proper accidents but we cannot say that it is
without its proper accidents.26 The proper accidents of a thing necessarily
follow from the essence even though they are not included in that essence,
and this connection is immutable.27
The second important difference between first and second mode per se
predication is that while first mode predication is immediately necessary,
in second mode propositions the predicate mediately belongs to the sub-
ject by way of a middle term. In other words, second mode propositions are
necessary but they are conclusions to a demonstration. The proper accident
Is a necessary resultance of that essence, but that property belongs to the
25 As Aquinas says, "Therefore, although what the soul is can be understood without
I hem, yet that the soul be without them is neither possible nor intelligible." Quaest. De
ttttlnia, 12, ad. 7.
J.6 "The activity of the mind is twofold... One whereby it understands what something
IN: and in such an operation of the mind the essence of a thing can be understood, both
iipnrt from a property and apart from an accident, since neither of these things enters into
I lu* essence of the thing... The other activity of the mind is combining and dividing;... By
II lis |sccond] activity of the mind, however, a substance cannot be understood without its
property; for that man has not the power of laughing is not intelligible, nor that a triangle
«lncs not have three angles equal to two right angles; for here there is a repugnance of objects
t if thought [repugnantia intellectuum], since the opposite of the predicate depends upon the
mil urc of the subject." De Spiritualibus 11 ad. 7, emphasis added. Again, "So in the first op-
nul Ion of the intellect the essence of the soul is understood apart from its powers, but not
In I he second operation - that is, so that it is understood not to have powers." Ibid. Also, "If
mimcoiic thinks man, not thinking of his power of laughter, he is not in error; but he would
be II'he ihought man is not capable of laughter." De Spiritualibus 3 ad 14.
11 "Whatever is present In a thing necessarily [per se] is either part of its essence or
rrnuIlN from lis eHMenLlMl prlnciplcH." /V Pot. 10,4.
143
W WlHWrti AtjUhhl* Hful the hit (pie ofSulliviunt Reason
illh|*tt via it middle lerm. "Risibility" belongs necessarily to man, not di-
rn tly, Iwl by way of the middle term, "rational animal." Such propositions
I hen should not be called "immediate", or "self-evident" principles, for
I hey are ultimately known as conclusions to a demonstration. They are
necessary however because they proceed from self-evident principles.28
Finally, there is a rarely mentioned but importantfourth mode of neces-
sary per se predication.29 This fourth mode is very important precisely be-
cause this is the type of proposition that Aquinas says is the major premise
of a demonstration,30 However, Aquinas tells us very little about this sort
of per se. All we see is that this notion ofper se designates a relationship of
efficient cause and occurs when the "predicate is the proper attribute, and
whose subject is the definition which contains the principles of the prop-
er attribute.31 In other words, the subject is the principle that necessarily
causes the proper attribute, which means the fourth mode, at least at first
glance, seems very much like the second mode! Here again in the fourth
mode we are talking about a necessary, non-essential property being pred-
icated of subject. The only difference here is that in the second mode, we
saw that the property belongs to the subject by way of some middle term
but in the fourth mode the property belongs to the subject directly. That is
to say, in the fourth mode the essence of the subject serves as an immedi-
144
Necessary 'Druthi mil Our Ability hi KHUW 1h$m
32 Aquinas even implicitly acknowledges the close resemblance between these two
((inns of per se necessity when he says that conclusions to demonstrations, which are
I rue in the second mode of per se predication, can also be said to be true in the fourth
mode as well. "But first it should be noted that, since science bears on conclusions, and
understanding bears on principles, the scientifically knowable are, properly speaking,
I he conclusions of a demonstration wherein proper attributes are predicated of their ap-
propriate subjects. Now the appropriate subjects are not only placed in the definition of
til I rlbulcs, but they are also their causes. Hence the conclusions of demonstrations involve
I wo modes of predicating parse, namely, the second and the fourth." In I Post. Ana., 1.10.
33 Indeed there arc undoubtedly other types of necessary truths we have not discussed,
much UN certain dtujunctlvp proportion* like, "Hither horses are possible or they are not,"
145
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
reader that in addition to the radical difference between the way a scho-
lastic grounds necessary truths, it is also the case that the scholastic has
a very different and indeed more refined understanding of propositional
analyticity than what we see in the typical "predicate contained in the
definition of the subject" idea. Even though these fine distinctions may
appear complicated to some readers, we cannot let the complexity of care-
ful nuancing to cause us to overlook its importance. The gravity of these
scholastic distinctions will become apparent later when we see how Aqui-
nas anticipated David Hume s objection to the principle of causality by
about five hundred years.
or universal negative propositions such as, "No man lltt«U>n»," 'I him. I he three modes
mentioned here should not he taken as an cxhaunllvf lilting,
Necessary 'Ihiths timl Our Ability hi KmtW IHm
M The alleged "collapse" of Euclidean geometry does nothing to undermine the truth
of these statements. The question of whether or not space is really curved (whether or
nol Euclidean space is a valid description of our own three-dimensional space) is not the
.sit me question as whether a triangle may or may not have three sides. Even if space really
IN non-Euclidean, that IIOCN nol mean that the proposition, "All triangles have three sides,"
U nol necessary, ll would only mean there are no actual instances of Euclidean triangles.
147
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
repugnant.35 But now suppose one says there are no necessary truths
about the world. If that is true then all bets are off, because at that point
the principle of non-contradiction cannot be universally true either. A
person who made such a claim would have to be open to the possibility
of things like a round square, five sided triangles, or anything else that
is a self-contradiction. No absurdity is off limits for anyone who denies
that the principle of contradiction is necessarily true. But of course, if
anything is patent nonsense, it is this. To deny that we know necessary
truths would mean that we do not know if there could really be things
like a round square or not, and this is evidently absurd. Nothing more
needs to be said about this point.
Another absurdity of denying per se notum truths is that, as both
Aristotle and Aquinas recognized, such a denial would result in the de-
struction of all knowledge. The reason is because if there are no first
principles that are directly known, then everything must be known on
the basis of something else. But if everything is known on the basis of
something else, then that entails that anything one claims to know must
be based on knowing an irresolvable infinite regress of other things,
which cannot be done and thus, all knowledge at that point becomes im-
possible.36 So in order to avoid the destruction of all knowledge, we must
admit there are some things that are knowable per se and not known
through another.37 To put this point formally we can say:
148
Necessary Truths and Our Ability U) Know HiPtn
Either all propositions are known through another {per all ltd)
or there are at least some propositions that are known through
themselves, (perse).
It is not the case that all propositions are known through another.
NI ruble principle is thai "the same thing cannot be affirmed and denied at the same time,"
which is based on the notion of "being" and "not-being": and on this principle all others
ktre based, as IN Hinted In Mrtafih, Iv, text. 9" S.T. HI, 94.2. Also, "Among these principles
I here Is a certain order, NO that wine are contained implicitly in others; thus all principles
are reduced, MM to th#lr ttril principle, lo I IIIN one: "'I he same thing cannot be affirmed and
denied ttl the nam* tlmti" «« lit* Philosopher ululca {Metaplh Iv, Icxl. 9)." S.T, I MM.7.
14V
.S7 'Ihtimn* Aq\ilm\* mitt the h'lciplc of Sufficient Reason
38 See Duns Scotus: Metaphysician, William A. Frank and Allan Wolter, (Purdue Uni-
versity Press, 1995) 80-81
39 "For not to know of what things one should seek demonstration and of what things
one should not shows want of education. For it is altogether impossible that there should
be demonstration of all things, because there would then be an infinite regress so that
there would still be no demonstration. But if there are some things of which it is not
necessary to seek demonstration, these people cannot say what principle they think to be
more indemonstrable." Aristotle, Meta, IV 1006a5-10
40 "For first principles become known through the natural llghl oi'lhc ugent Intellect,
and they are not acquired by any process of reasoning but by having llwlr icrma become
known." Aquinas, In Meta IV, 1.6
150
Necessary Truths arid Our Ability to Know litem
no necessary truths. What in the world could this mean? If it's true that
u
No truths are necessary," then, by obversion, the statement, "Every truth
is contingent" must also be true. But if every truth is contingent, then so is
I hat truth that says, "Every truth is contingent!" Now a contingent truth is,
obviously, one which could have been false. In other words, a contingent
truth is one that is true in some possible worlds but false in others. So if
"Every truth is contingent" is itself contingent (which it must be in order
lo avoid self-contradiction), then there must be some worlds in which that
statement is false. In that case, the contradictory statement, "Some truths
are not contingent" would have be true, which can only mean, by obversion
again, that "Some truths are necessary." But a necessary truth, by definition,
is true in all possible worlds. So if "some truths are necessary" is true in at
least one possible world, then it must be true in all possible worlds. But this
contradicts the original hypothesis, "No truths are necessary." It cannot
possibly be the case that both, "No truths are necessary" and "Some truths are
necessary" are true, since these are contradictory assertions. Thus, the claim
u
No truths are necessary" ends up resulting in a manifest contradiction.
Apparently there is no escaping the dilemma. Either we affirm that there
are some necessary truths, or we become trapped in self-contradiction.
Affirming necessary truths is unavoidable.41
So to summarize, the whole point of this discussion is to show that there
must be at least some propositions that are necessarily true. Equally, some
of these propositions are those which we know "immediately" through the
lerms themselves. There are not only obvious self-evident examples that
show this, but also the denial of this claim entails absurdities, the destruc-
I ion of all knowledge, and outright contradiction. Consequently, reason
demands that we maintain the classic Aristotelian position, namely, that
some of the things we know are not known on the basis of knowing other
I lungs, but are intuitively seen as necessarily true. Philosophy will always
have its share of verbal deniers who continue to argumentatively deny such
1 hings, but we have seen that they cannot reasonably do so. "What a man
says, he does not necessarily believe." Aristotle reminds us.42
41 To put it a different way, the statement, "There are no necessary facts about the
world" is itself a universal and necessary fact about the world which is blatantly self-re-
lull ng and thus neccHtmrlly false. This means that, via contradictory opposition, "Some
proposition Is a necewmry fuel uboul Ihc world" would have to be true.
42 ArlHlollt, M$t* /V, clU. KH)5b25
St. 'Ihomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
43 "The certitude and the ontological validity of primary ideas and first principles is nat-
urally and logically prior to that theory by which the philosopher seeks to explain how this
certitude is acquired, how our intellect comes into contact with being, and is determined
and measured by it." Garrigou Lagrange, God, His Existence and His Nature, op. cit, 155-6.
44 "...not all knowledge depends on previous knowledge, for that would involve an
infinite process." In I Post Ana. 1.1
45 "The knowledge of principles does not come about in us from pre-existing knowledge
in the same way as things which are known through demonstration...Hence he concludes
that there do not pre-exist, any habits of principles in the sense of being determinate and
complete... rather the habits of principles come to exist in us from pre-existing sense." In
II Post. Ana. 1. 20. "The Philosopher, speaking of the intellect, says (De Anima iii, 4) that
it is like 'a tablet on which nothing is written*... Now we observe that man sometimes
is only a potential knower, both as to sense and as to intellect. And he Is reduced from
such potentiality to act through the action of sensible objccl* on hla MCIIHCH, lo ihe act of
sensation-by instruction or discovery, lo the act of undemanding. Wherefore we mual
say thai ihe cognlllve soul IK In potentiality bolh lo lha lmagtM which are Ihe principle* of
152
Necessary lYutht ami Our Ahillty In Know Ihm
priori knowledge of any concepts until it comes Into contact with rraltty.
Take the axiom, "Every whole is greater than its part." Some experience
is required in order to know what the concepts "whole" and "part" mean.
We have to experience things like pizzas and six packs in order to come to
know the meaning of these terms. Yet once one has acquired knowledge
of those terms, no further experience is necessary. Once experience has
enabled us to understand the meaning of "whole" and "part" we can now
know for certain that the statement, "Every whole is greater than its part,"
is necessarily true. The proposition is known to be true through the very
meaning of the terms.46 Knowledge of necessary truths begins with, but is
not limited to, our experience.
Now an objector might think all of this is wrongheaded for the sim-
ple fact that one cannot possibly know about all things by observing only
some. And if one is not certain about this, an objector may say, then
Aquinas' claim to know universal truths by past experience is hopeless-
ly flawed. In other words, we have here the classic problem of induction.
What is the justification for claiming to know a universal truth based only
on particular observances?
In response to this contention, we need to first point out that the ob-
jection presupposes that the only way to be certain of a universal is by
knowing all of the individual instances. But is this true? In other words, is
complete enumeration the only way to know universal truths? It is interest-
ing to note that both Aristotle and Aquinas agree that empirical observa-
sensing, and to those which are the principles of understanding/' S.T.L84.3. "At first, all
our cognition consists in the knowledge of first undeducible principles. But the cognition
of ihese arises in us from sense, as is clear from the Posterior Analytics. Therefore, all our
knowledge arises from sense." De Ver. 10.6. "For certain seeds of knowledge pre-exist in
us, namely, the first concepts of understanding, which by the light of the agent intellect
arc immediately known through the species abstracted from sensible things. These are
I'll her complex, as axioms, or simple, as the notions of being, of the one, and so on, which
llic understanding grasps immediately. In these general principles, however, all the con-
sequences are included as in certain seminal principles." De Ver. 11.1
46 "There are two ways of acquiring science: one is through demonstration, and the other
Is 1 hrough induction [inductionem]... it is impossible that universals be known scientifically
wllhout induction... the principles of abstracted [isolated] things, from which demonstra-
I Ions regarding them are formed, are not made manifest to us except from certain particu-
lars which we perceive by sense. Thus, from the fact that we see some single sensible whole
we are led to know whnl n whole is and what a part, and we know that every whole is greater
ihnn ItvS pari by conHldcrlng ihlN In many. Thus the universals from which demonstration
proceeds are mud* known In UN only l hrough Induction." In 1 Post Ana, 1.30
153
,S7. 'I ho mas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
47 Aquinas concurs that "induction' (in the sense of looking at just the enumerat-
ed instances and not their nature) is inadequate for knowing a certain conclusion. "It
might be remarked here that he quite fittingly compared division to induction. For in
both cases one is required to suppose that he has listed all the things contained under
some general heading; otherwise, the person inducing could not conclude a universal
from the singulars he assumed, nor could the person dividing conclude to one member
just because the others have been eliminated. Thus it is obvious that one cannot in vir-
tue of the fact that Socrates and Plato and Cicero run, induce of necessity the conclusion
that every man runs, unless his audience concedes that nothing more is contained un-
der man than the ones listed." - In I Post. Anal, 1. 4. Aristotle says the same; "...even if
one prove of each kind of triangle that its angles are equal to two right angles, whether
by means of the same or different proofs; still, as long as one treats separately equilat-
eral, scalene, and isosceles, one does not yet know, except sophistically, that triangle
has its angles equal to two right angles, nor does one yet know that triangle has this
property commensurately and universally, even if there is no other species of triangle
but these. For one does not know that triangle as such has this properly, nor even that
'all* triangles have it — unless *aIP means 'each taken singly*! If'nil' menus 'us a whole
class', then, though there be none in which one doei not ricognlxv thin properly, one
does not know it of 'ftll iiianglciT Post. Ana. /., ch, S., 74i2M0
154
Necessary Truths and Our Ability to Know litem
155
St ViuiHttt Atjulmtx ami the I'rlclplc of Sufficient Reason
by way of judgment returns by analysis to first principles, in the light of which it examines
what it has found." S.T. I, 79, 8; vol. 5, 274. These principles that are immediate and known
in this way are better known than the conclusions derived from them. "Now it is plain that
the principles of demonstrations are better known than the demonstrated conclusions, as
was established in Book I. Moreover, it cannot be through science that we have those prin-
ciples, because science is the result of reasoning, namely, demonstrative, whose principles
are the very things about which we are speaking. Therefore, because nothing can be truer
than science and understanding (for wisdom is included In them), what follows from our
consideration of the foregoing is thai, properly speaking, the knowledge of principles U
understanding \intellectu$lH In, U Post, Ana., 1.20 ch, lty vol. MOA.
156
Necessary 'Ituilt* timlOui Ability In Ktww llwm
lures of things can have only a temporary value. All we could »«y IN thai
"so far" such and such is the case but there is no warrant for any universal
claims here. Reference to a mere empirically observed collection in the
past gives us no basis upon which we can make necessary judgments about
possible instances in the future.50 The lesson to be learned here is as old as
Aristotle; the collective universal is not an abstract universal If empiricism
cannot account for necessary truths, then the reasonable thing to do is not
lo call necessary truths into question, rather we should scrap empiricism.
The second problem is as old as Sextus Empiricus. If complete enu-
meration is necessary to know universal truths, then the validity of all
syllogistic reasoning is destroyed. This is because if the enumerative uni-
versal is our only way of knowing universal truth, then every syllogism
commits a patent begging of the question. For example, if the only way
we can know, "Every man is mortal" is by enumerating each and every
individual man, then the conclusion, "Socrates is mortal," must already
have been included in that initial enumeration. Consequently, if the hu-
man mind only had access to the enumerative universal, there could never
be any valid syllogistic reasoning, for one could never know the major to
l)c true without already explicitly knowing the conclusion.51 This problem
is so severe that it completely undermines any empiricist's demand for
complete enumeration since such a position is self-destructive and can
only be maintained if the following syllogism is sound:
All universal truths can only be known by complete enumeration
50 As put by Coffey, "As long as we have any doubt about the completeness of our enu-
meration - which is nearly always, - and still rely on it alone for our conclusion, we can
only have provisional and probable, not absolute and certain, knowledge of the truth of
11 u* latter as a really general proposition." Peter Coffey, The Science ofLogic, v. II. (London:
Longman, Greens and Co., 1938), 32.
.ri I By contrast, Aquinas* position of what we are calling the virtually complete induction
(lot's not suffer from this problem. We can know the nature of man without having to know
nidi and every individual. Thus, Socrates would be included only virtually in the proposi-
tion, "livery man IN mortal" and not actually. In this way, the syllogism simply makes actual
what was only potential In the premises. Thus the syllogism, under Aristotle and Aquinas'
uiuliTHlundlngof how Ihr imlvrnml proposition is formed, does not beg the question.
157
HI VutHhii Aijuiittt* mut the Ptlciplc o/SuJIkicnt Reason
IhU nrguniciU Calls and will always fail because anyone who asserts
Ihr major Is placed In Ihe self-refuting position of not being able to meet
their own demands. If all universal truths are known only by complete
enumeration, then the same goes for the major premise in this argument.
Since this cannot possibly be done, anyone who asserts the major premise,
paradoxically, cannot say the major itself is true.
Live by enumeration, die by enumeration. It is simply not the case that
complete enumeration is needed to know a universal truth. If we are going
to hold that we do in fact know necessary truths, as I have argued we must,
Aquinas' point that we can know these truths from reality via a rational
intuitive insight is certainly a cogent account of how we come to know
such things.52
52 For a more recent work on the inadequacy of emplrlclim U> ttccmml lor necessary
truths, see Laurence Bonjour, In Defense of Pure Reasom A RtitlomlUt Account of A Priori
Justification (New York: Cambridge University Pr«n), IWOM.
158
"And if [the one] were the same as another, it would be that other
and not be itself331
- Parmenides
"Does not everything which comes into being of necessity come into
being through a cause?"2
- Plato
161
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
6 Note that the principle of sufficient reason being self-evident in this way does not
entail that our dialectical arguments in favor of the principle were misguided. As we said,
dialectical arguments are probabilistic arguments and give extrinsic reasons for joining
the predicate to the subject. Appealing to self-evidence appeals to Intrinsic reasons and
the reductio ad absurdum is intended to indirectly show this IntrhiNlc connection.
7 As we saw earlier, Aristotle argued that the second mode u( per se predication was
necessary, but a demonstrable conclusion. The other I wo mode*, llntl and fourth, were
necessary and IndcmonNlrnhlc. Post, Anal, 73«34-b26,
162
The Reductio AdAbsurdum Argumentfartht PflMtpb </fH|lf fflff
163
SI llinmiis Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
9 A propter quid demonstration is a syllogism consisting of premises that are true, pri-
mary, immediate (per se), prior to the conclusion, better known than the conclusion, and
the cause of the conclusion. In I Post. Ana., 1.4.
10 To claim that this subject and predicate are immediately connected does not commit
one to also being certain on the mode of that connection. We saw earlier that there are
two modes of immediate per se predication. In this case, the intellect cannot tell which
mode the principle of sufficient reason is. The reason for this is the nature of the subject
"being." As Scotus well recognized, the primary attributes and disjunctions of being are
indemonstrable for three reasons. First, the concept of being is irreducibly simple and
transcends the Categories, meaning that being cannot be properly defined in terms of
genus and specific difference, which means there cannot be a definition to serve as a mid-
dle term. Indeed, being is always inherently indefinable since to define is to set limits, and
being as such is unlimited. The second reason the properties of being are indemonstrable
is because even if some attribute were not immediate, it is difficult to see what attribute
could be a middle term to link it with being since it is not easy to discern order among the
attributes of being, and finally, even if we knew of such an order among them, any prop-
osition that used them would hardly seem more evident than their conclusion. See the
selection in Duns Scotus, Philosophical Writings (Indianapolis: Hacked, 1987) 8. For these
reasons, we cannot say if a predicate like "having a reason for exigence" IN ihc "essence" of
being or just an immediate property. But it does not matter, forlhln In merely an academic
question, for our poinl Is to show that the principle IN ntceiurlly true mid Nhnwlng the
contradiction entailed by denying the principle U lufflclf 111 for ihlft ttmk,
164
The Reductio AdAbsurdum Argument for the Principle of Sufficient Reason
pies do not make the intrinsic connection between subject and predicate
directly known. Rather, in a case where the impossibility of denying I hem
is better known, one can argue for it indirectly via reductio ad absurdum
by showing, as we said, that such denials entail a contradiction.
165
St Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
denies or doubts the principle of sufficient reason, one must also, to that
same degree, deny or doubt the principle of non-contradiction.
With that being said, let us now undertake the reductio proper. To defend
the principle of sufficient reason in this way, we assume the denial of the
principle of sufficient reason is correct. Let us assume that there could be
a being that does not have a sufficient reason for existing, in fact, we will
call this possible being a "PSR defiant being/* Let us assume a PSR defiant
being is possible. But just would this PSR defiant being have to be? Any PSR
defiant being is, by definition, a being that exists without a sufficient reason
for its existence; that is to say, it would be a being that exists and yet lacks any
distinction from nothing But once we understand what a PSR defiant is, we
can see that such a being cannot possibly exist. For it is immediately obvious
that it is impossible that anything actually exists but at the same time has
absolutely nothing, no reason by which it could be said to be distinguished
from nothing. To say something exists, but yet simultaneously has nothing
in virtue of which it is distinct from absolute nothing or even mere
possibility isflagrantnonsense. Such a thing is utterly inconceivable because
it is metaphysically impossible. To say, "A PSR defiant being exists" refers
to impossible matter and is every bit as necessarily false and intellectually
repugnant as saying, "A triangle hasfivesides." With this understanding in
mind, we can formalize our reductio this way:
Whatever is not distinct from nothing, is nothing.
13 "What is neither positively Its own reason for exlitonci nor derive* tIIIH reason from
something else, IN not only unintelligible hut aliottbiurd«tul ImpuMlhlc aiul cunnot be
166
The Reductio Ad Absurdum Argument for the Principle of Sufficient Reason
167
St, IhotiHis Aquinas and the I'rkiplc of Sufficient Reason
14 In the game of elenchus, one called the "answerer" admits a thesis and the "question-
er," or opponent, tries to refute and trap him in contradiction from his own mouth. The
rules disallowed the questioner to "ask" for the conclusion from the beginning, such as
if it were disguised by synonyms. What this "fallacy" is here Is a debuting trick - getting
someone to admit something he does not want to admil by pulling 11 In another form
and then telling him you have proved ll. See Richard Robimon, "Hewing ihc Question,"
Analysis 1\ (4) (1971): 113-17.
The Reductio Ad Absurdum Argument far tht Print tpb nf Snftii IfM kMMti
ment, that argument fails to establish its conclusion? 'Ihe Intuition Wfllll
entirely justified. A "question" is a disputed proposition, and one of I he dl«j
putants has the burden of proving it to the other. A petitio principii argu-
ment tells us nothing new; it provides no independent reason for accepting
an already denied conclusion. After all, the whole point of an argument is to
make a non-evident conclusion become evident by means of more evident
premises. Assuming the conclusion is true by covertly using it as a premise
to "prove itself" fails to fulfill this burden. Assuming a conclusion to be true
when an opponent has already denied it argues "in a circle," and so cannot
remove the doubt about that conclusion. The disputant who has attempted
to prove the proposition has not really done so, but merely took that con-
clusion for granted and used it again (often in covert form) as a premise.
Accordingly, when this happens, a fallacy of sorts seems to have occurred,
as the disputant has failed to meet the burden of proof.
This all sounds perfectly acceptable when speaking at the general lev-
el, but if one presses the issue to define more precisely when such a fal-
lacious move occurs, we can quickly see this as another example of "the
devil is in the details."
15 Irving Copi and Carl Cohen, Introduction to Logic, 10th ed. (New Jersey: Prentice
Hull, 1998), 186.
16 Following Douglau Walton's terminology in Begging the Question: Circular Reason-
ing as a Tactic of Arguttumttitkm (Wcutporl, CT: Greenwood Press, 1991),
169
St. 'lluwHis Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
17 To pursue the difficulties of what constitutes propositional identity further, see Da-
vid H Sanford, "Begging the Question" Analysis 32 n. 6 (1972): 197-99. After pointing out
the difficulties with coining up with a workable notion of propositional identity, Hoff-
man goes on to say that even if an adequate understanding of propositional identity were
found, still there are more problems. Take for example, "God has all the virtues, therefore
he is benevolent." This statement does not make use of identical propositions (they are at
least not orthographically identical), yet the statement would be commonly regarded as
question-begging. Or consider the following:
John says something
Indeed, John says something false
Therefore, John says something false
Sanford says this argument would be begging the question according to the propositional
identity thesis, but there are other examples that seem to skirt around that criterion:
John says something
Either he says something false or he says nothing at all
Therefore, he says something false
Since the conclusion Is not identical to a premise, Sanford nrgUM again lluil something li
amiss with the proportional Identity position regarding hinging llu> i|urmlon. I bid, 19H.
170
The Reductio Ad Absurdum Argument for tlw Print Iph nf Sitflkbnt NMIMH
Bill: But you're wrong, and I can show you so. Here's my argument:
All men are mortal, Socrates is a man, and therefore Socrates is
mortal.
John: You just begged the question! Since I deny that Socrates is
mortal, it begs the question to assume that set of premises.
We need only to ask two questions here to make our point. First,
does the conjunct of the major and minor premise make a proposition?
Secondly, if so, is that conjunctive proposition "equivalent" to the con-
clusion? The answer to both questions seems to be a definite "Yes." If
I his is correct, then either all syllogistical forms of reasoning formerly
regarded as valid commit the fallacy of "begging the question," or there
is something seriously wrong with the propositional equivalence con-
ception of this fallacy.18
In case one is still not yet convinced that the propositional equivalence
conception of the fallacy is fatally flawed, there is one final nail for its
1H Just because a premise implies a conclusion does not mean it is an inevitable ques-
I Ion begging. As Russell put it: "In all correct deductions, if the conclusion is false, so is at
Ini.sl one of the premises. The falsehood of the premises presupposes the falsehood of the
II inclusion, but it by no means follows that the truth of the premises presupposes the truth
affile conclusion. The root of the error seems to be that, where a deduction is very easily
drawn, il comes to be viewed as actually part of the premises; and thus the very elementa-
ry iirgumcnls acquire the appearance, quite falsely, of petitiones principal Bertrsmd Rus-
ncll, '"Ihc Axiom of Infinity," In Essays in Analysis, ed. Douglas Lackey (London: Allen
mul Unwln, 1973), 256-9, AN cited In Wallon, 259,
171
St. 'Iltonuis Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
coffin. The clearest and most decisive method of refuting the propositional
equivalency interpretation of the begging the question fallacy is to provide
clearly sound arguments that consist of the very propositional repetition
that this theory regards as fallacious.19 If this can be done, the propositional
equivalence conception will be soundly refuted. Surprisingly enough,
such counterexamples are not hard to find.20 All that is needed are clearly
sound arguments that follow a "P therefore P" form. The good thing about
using the "P therefore P" format is simply that one cannot get much more
"equivalency" between a premise and conclusion than the same identical
phrase that was stated as a premise, repeated as a conclusion. Here we
show that since propositional identity between premise and conclusion is
not always fallacious, a fortiori, neither is any lesser kind of equivalency
always fallacious.
What arguments show this, one may wonder? Suppose we simply
consider examples of self-validating arguments:
1. Some arguments are in black ink, therefore some arguments are in
black ink.
19 By "argument" here I mean in the loose sense, namely, where w conclusion is estab-
lished from a supporting premise or premises.
20 Roy Sorensen lists several In "P Iherefore P Without Circularity," 7/icr Journal of
Philosophy vol. 88, (1991), 245-66. We ll»l «omc mmplfl from him h m .
172
The Reductio Ad Absurdum Argument Jar the hltulfilp \)j SuJtU itnt M'HKMf
of arguments! 21 Maybe not all arguments like this arc valid, bill ihry nr*
certainly not all fallacious either.
For the above reasons, it should be very clear at this point thai I lie
propositional equivalence conception of the begging the question fallacy
is at best suspect and should probably be entirely rejected. Why focus
on "equivalence" when not even a strong orthographic identity between
premise and conclusion (the greatest form of "equivalence") is a sufficient
condition for the occurrence of this fallacy? Could it be that some form
of equivalence, while not a sufficient condition for begging the question,
still be a necessary condition for the fallacy? This is quite possible, and
if so, the error pointed out here is conflating a necessary condition for a
sufficient one.
Accordingly, we should reject the equivalence understanding of the
fallacy; however this does not mean we are finished quite yet. Walton
lists another conception of the fallacy, what we can call the "propositional
dependency" conception of begging the question. 22 In the propositional
dependency conception, begging the question occurs when a premise
Is actually proved from the conclusion. In other words, one would only
believe a premise if they already believed the conclusion. In this case, when
someone provides an argument where the premise can only be known if
I he conclusion were known, one commits a fallacy.
What should we think of this "take" on the fallacy? At first glance,
II looks certainly more promising that the propositional dependency
conception, yet some problematic counterexamples can be shown too.
'Ihere are arguments which seem clearly valid, yet one could arguably
21 Now some may object that these are not truly "arguments" in the classical under-
sluncling since there is no movement in the mind. The objection may run that since, in
I hesc examples, one does not move from one thing to knowing something else, that there-
lore these "arguments" could hardly be said to constitute "reasoning." However, this ob-
|(Tl Ion seems to be false. There is some mental movement here with these self-validating
iii^uinents. The conclusion is established by the argument with necessity. We move from
not knowing the conclusion to knowing the conclusion with absolute certitude. It is not
I he lack of mental movement in, for example, saying "The dog is black therefore the dog
IN black." Rather the conclusion in these examples is established with necessity by the
iirjtimicnl itself, as when we say, "Some arguments appear in footnotes, therefore some
iirnimicnls appear in footnotes." Admittedly, the movement here is not like the mental
inovcnicnl wc see in standard argumentation, but there is enough discursive movement
here to consider these "arguments" at least in an analogous sense.
11 Walton, op. cit„ page 2.
173
Si. Ihomns Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
make the claim that a premise could be known only if a conclusion were
known. For example:23
If there are syllogisms, then information can be combined,
23 Sorenson, ibid.
174
The Reductio AdAbsurdum Argument for the Principle oJ SuJ/hfant liptixon
175
St Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
Back to Aristotle
I think we can find that better understanding if we return to Aristotle.
Not in the Topics (as some might be prone to do), for there Aristotle says
he is only giving an account of the fallacy on the level of popular opinion.24
To get the true account of this fallacy, we need to look at the Prior Analyt-
ics. The relevant passage is worth quoting at length:
To beg and assume the point at issue is a species of failure to
demonstrate the problem proposed; but this happens in many
ways. A man may not deduce at all, or he may argue from
premises which are more unknown or equally unknown, or he
may establish what is prior by means of what is posterior; for
demonstration proceeds from what is more convincing and prior.
Now begging the point at issue is none of these; but since some
things are naturally known through themselves, and other things by
means of something else (the first principles through themselves,
what is subordinate to them through something else), whenever a
man tries to prove by means of itself what is not known by means of
itself then he begs the point at issue. This may be done by claiming
what is at issue at once; it is also possible to make a transition to
other things which would naturally be proved through the point
at issue, and demonstrate it through them, e.g. if A should be
proved through B, and B through C, though it was natural that C
should be proved through A; for it turns out that those who reason
thus are proving A by means of itself.25
After saying what the petitio principii fallacy is not, Aristotle gives
the necessary and sufficient condition for the fallacy. First, he recalls the
fact that some propositions are known through themselves {per se), while
others are known through something else {per aliud). This is an essential
distinction to make, for if all propositions were known through others, a
vicious infinite regress would result. Next, he indicates that when a man
tries to prove something that is not known per se as if it were known per
sey he begs the point at issue. In other words, if one, either directly or indi-
24 "Of the ways in which a questioner may postulate the point al INNUC and postulate
contraries the true account has been given in the Analytic*; hut an waounl on the level of
opinion must be given now." Topics, Bk. 8,162b31-163*28,
25 Prior Analytics Bk. 2 64b29-65u9, emphttiU mlntr
176
The Reductio Ad Absurdum ArguntPHtftir lh* PrlMlpb ttf *H(lltl$Ht NMMff
rectly, treats a proposition that is really known per aliud (through Mlllthff)
as if it were known per se (through itself), he commit* the fallacy of hfg*
ging the question.
Let us call this the per aliud as per se conception of begging the ques-
tion. To put this conception in a nutshell, to beg the question is to assume
that a P which is knowable only through independent reasons be known
through itself. What does this definition get us? First, we see inherent in
I his understanding the need for an independent reason for accepting the
conclusion. When disputed, per aliud propositions need an independent
reason for their acceptance, and the reason is simply that it is the kind of
proposition that by its very nature it is known through another, Aristot-
le's definition captures our positive intuitions about begging the question,
viz., that oftentimes a reason other than the conclusion is needed. Indeed,
I he demand for an independent reason for accepting the proposition un-
der question is "built in" to this understanding of the fallacy.
Not only does this "take" on the fallacy capture what we would want
lo preserve about the petitio principii fallacy, but it also avoids all of the
problems we saw with the alternative explanations of this fallacy, Take im-
mediate inference, for example. Immediate inference is a means by which
only one other proposition is needed to make an inference. So if we say,
"No snakes are squirrels" is per aliud, the "aliud" in this case can simply be
I he proposition, "No squirrels are snakes." In this way, immediate infer-
ence does not seem to beg the question under the Aristotelian definition of
I he fallacy since it does not treat the per aliud as if it were per se.
What about the "begging the question" charge regarding the nature of
I he syllogism? One might say that the conjunct of major and minor is not
really "other than" the conclusion, and no set of premises in a valid argu-
ment can ever serve as a "per a/iW7independent reason for knowing the
conclusion. Is this a valid counterexample to Aristotle s understanding of
IwIiHo principii fallacy?
It seems to me that Aristotle could maintain his definition of the fallacy
and answer this charge by his robust understanding of the syllogism. Ar-
Islotle could respond that no individual premise is equivalent to the con-
i-kision. Moreover, the premises in any good argument should be better
known than the conclusion, and thus knowable on independent grounds.
So the premises taken individually are not the same as the conclusion,
and can validly function as true per aliud reasons for the conclusion. As
177
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
far as taking the two premises and conjoining them, that is precisely what
a syllogism accomplishes. Syllogisms, by design, take a potentially known
conclusion contained in the premises and make it actually known. The act
of conjoining those premises creates a syllogism and, of course, a conjoined
proposition that contains those two premises is somehow "equivalent" to
and/or entails the conclusion. But it is a complete misunderstanding to
think that the act of actualizing what was previously only potentially known
is fallacious. At no point in this process is the per aliud treated as per se.26
What about those curious "P therefore P" without circularity exam-
ples? With those we could say that just as some propositions are known
through themselves, so too some arguments can be known through them-
selves in that they are self-validating. "Some arguments really only consist
of 17 words, therefore some arguments really only consist of 17 words" is
an argument form that is knowableper se and not per aliud, thus the beg-
ging the question charge need not apply here either.27
What about Socrates' argument above about the nature of triangles? For-
mally this argument was not really P therefore P, but rather —P therefore
P, but still, under the per aliud asperse conception of begging the question
no fallacy occurs here either since the proposition "All triangles have three
sides" really is per se in the first place, so it cannot fall under Aristotle's defi-
nition of the begging the question fallacy either. Aristotle's understanding
of the fallacy is that it can only occur when one uses the per aliud statements
as per se. If one is using per se to begin with, there is no fallacy.
So it seems to me that Aristotle's definition of begging the question can
maintain all of the positive intuitions regarding a failure of proof that mo-
tivates us in saying there is a petitio principii fallacy while at the same time
avoiding the pitfalls and shortcomings inherent in the competing concep-
tions of this fallacy. Hence, Aristotle's definition of begging the question
is to be preferred.
26 This explanation is available to anyone who accepts Aristotle's take on the syllogism,
including those who might also accept what I have argued was a flawed understanding of
the petitio principii fallacy. Not every logician (i.e., Empiricus and Mill) thinks of syllo-
gisms in Aristotelian terms. So those that hold an equivalence or dependency notion of
begging the question could also make use of this response, In such a case, other reasons
against those notions of begging the question would need to be conaUiercd.
27 This explanation is an expansion of what Aristotle meant by per tc% bul li still solve*
the problem while remaining faithful to the definition af'helny "known through Itself"
that he laid out,
178
The Reductio Ad Absurdum Argument for the Principle ofSuflkleut Kenton
Socrates: If lomclhlng were called a triangle but did not have three
sides. It would both b# uml nol be n triangle - which is absurd! (~~P)
179
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
Socrates: If some being was said to exist, but did not have a
sufficient reason for its existence, then it would both exist and not
exist - which is absurd! (~~P)
180
The Reductio Ad Absurdum Argument for the Principle of Sufficient Reason
alence (or identity) between premise and conclusion does not prove that a
fallacy has occurred. Moreover, just as there are clear examples showing
clearly valid "P therefore P" arguments, there are also good examples that
show there are clearly valid —P therefore P arguments as well. For exam-
ple, there is no fallacy in any of these inferences:
Every triangle has three sides; therefore, every triangle has three
sides. (P therefore P)
Every triangle has three sides; therefore, whatever does not have
three sides cannot be a triangle. (P therefore ~~P)
the question," because we do not treat the per aliud as the perse. Quite the
opposite; we are treating the per se as the per se.28 To stress this point, let
us look at that reductio argument for this part of the principle of sufficient
reason in its syllogistic form once more:
Whatever is not distinct from nothing, is nothing.
28 There is, of course, a danger of misconstruing all reductio proof of self-evident prin-
ciples as "begging the question" - and this danger is quite obvious. The man who rejects
the self-evident statement wants an independent reason for accepting the principle. Yet
self-evident principles are by nature known per se and not per aliud. If a man demands
an independent reason for a proposition that is not known through independent reasons,
conflict and charges of "begging the question" are highly probable.
29 Again, we showed earlier that in what the scholastics called intellectus, one does not
"assume" a necessary connection - they clearly see it. The clarity ofint uiting the necessary
connection is far cry from a mere assumption or "leap In the dark," Quite the contrary, It
is an intuited necessity. There Is no lack of justification or evidence In uuch cnse«; rather,
it is the best kind of Justification and evidence.
182
The Reductio Ad Absurdum Argument for the Principle of Sufficient Reason
that the argument "begs the question?" Which premise and in what way?
The objector cannot merely point out propositional equivalency or propo-
sitional repetition, as we have shown these to be deficient understandings
ofthe fallacy. He cannot prove that we "assume" it to be true as opposed to
clearly seeing it to be true. What the objector now needs is a non-question
begging argument to show that the reductio argument begs the question.
How will he do this?
Given the correct understanding of the petitio principii fallacy, the
objector needs to show that the principle of sufficient reason is not a per
se notum proposition, but that it must be made known through another
{per aliud). Of course, he needs to show this, not assume it. For it is not
self-evident that the principal part of the principle of sufficient reason is
not self-evident, so the statement, "The principle of sufficient reason is not
self-evident," if it is true, it must be shown through another. The objector
cannot assume this per aliud statement as per se> or he would be commit-
ting the very same "begging the question" fallacy with which he wants to
charge his opponent.
M) AugiiNlUN Do Morgan, Vormtil Logk (London: Taylor and Wallon, 1847). Reprinted
Im ulinllc (Honton, MAi AiUmnnl Med!A (lorporutlon, 2005), pngc 255,
183
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
184
The Reductio Ad Absurdum Argument for the Principle of Sufficient Reason
31 "Dicit ergo quod illud principium, quod necesse est non solum per seipsum esse, sed
rlium ulterius necesse est, ipsum videri, scilicet communis animi conceptio vel dignitas, non
est neque petitio neque suppositio. Quod sic probat. Petitio et suppositio exteriori ratione
ivnfirmari possunt, idest argumentatione aliqua. Sed communis animi conceptio non est
ad exterius rationem, quia non potest probari per aliquam argumentationem..." In Post.
An. 11,1. 19, n. 3.
32 Although dialectic usually starts and ends only in mere opinion, sometimes dialec-
IU" can lead one to an insight into the starting points of a science. As Aristotle says, dia-
led ic "is also useful for [discerning] the first things of every science. For it is impossible,
111 whatever science is put forth, to say anything about these [first things] from the proper
principles because the first Ihings are the principles of all the others; so it is necessary
lo come near to I hem \twnxkP peri ant on dielthein] through the reputable opinions [dia
iflti rudoxdn] In reference In each |sdcncc|. And this is a property of, and most of all be-
longs to dialectic, l'or Hud (being skillful at scrutinizing things, [dialectic] bears the path
\hotbn\ toward lh« principle of nil Mih«ei|iicnt paths \methoddn\." Aristotle, Topics I, 2,
H)lu3ri-b4,
185
"Whatever a thing has besides its essence must be caused either by the
constituent principles of that essence. . . .or by some exterior agent,
as heat is caused in water byfire.Therefore, if the existence of a thing
differs from its essence, this existence must be caused either by some
exterior agent or by its essential principles. Now it is impossible for
a things existence to be caused by its essential constituent principles,
for nothing can be the sufficient cause of its own existence, if its
existence is caused. Therefore that thing, whose existence differs from
its essence, must have its existence caused by another"1
- St. Thomas Aquinas
187
SI Ihitmtt* Atfuliiii* <uul lit? Vihljilc of Sufficient Reason
188
Cnuaul Piltntpht iitutt'>omhuliin*
I SX 1.44.1. BmphttilMiliM.
189
If fttitfftfl AilUlHto Mitt flip h tit/tic oj Sujlivlvnt Reason
MPfMlrtllnil, A» IhlM lii'Nl objection shows, Aquinas was well aware of the
Ulri I lumrMii argument that a thing can be conceived of without thinking
ul' ttN cause. In fact, Aquinas anticipates this objection of Hume by about
live hundred years. We will return to this important objection below. As
for now, here is Aquinas' general response in the article:
I answer that, it must be said that every being in any way existing
is from God. For whatever is found in anything by participation,
must be caused in it by that to which it belongs essentially, as iron
becomes ignited by fire. Now it has been shown above when
treating of the divine simplicity that God is the essentially self-
subsisting Being; and also it was shown that subsisting being must
be one; as, if whiteness were self-subsisting, it would be one, since
whiteness is multiplied by its recipients. Therefore all beings apart
from God are not their own being, but are beings by participation.
Therefore it must be that all things which are diversified by the
diverse participation of being, so as to be more or less perfect, are
caused by one First Being, Who possesses being most perfectly.3
Key texts are italicized here. After arguing that there can be only one
self-subsisting being, Aquinas says all other beings must be "beings by
participation" and that whatever is found in something "by participation"
must be caused. These beings by participation are defined here as "beings
that are not their own being" {omnia alia a Deo non sint suum esse, sed
participant esse). To formalize Aquinas' argument succinctly, we can say:
Every being by participation is caused (by God)
3 "Respondeo dicendum quod necesse est dicere omne quod quocumque modo est, a Deo
esse. Si enim aliquid invenitur in aliquo per participationem, necesse est quod causetur in
ipso ab eo cui essentialiter convenit; sicut ferrum fit ignitum ab igne. Ostensum est autem
supra, cum de divina simplicitate ageretur, quod Deus est ipsum esse per se subsistens. Et
iterum ostensum est quod esse subsistens non potest esse nisi unum, sicut si albedo esset
subsistens, non posset esse nisi una, cum albedines multiplicentur secundum recipientia,
Relinquitur ergo quod omnia alia a Deo non sint suum esse, sed participant esse. Necesse
est igitur omnia quae diversificantur secundum diversam participationem essendi, ut sint
perfectius vel minusperfecte, causari ab una prlmo entf, quotl pvrfectissime est.n Ibid. Iim-
phasis added,
190
Causal l>rlmlpb» ami Coihhniom
The key premise for our purpose is the major premise and we need
lo clarify what is being said here. Presumably the only ambiguous term
here is a "being by participation" but we have seen that Aquinas thinks
of such beings as a "being that is not its own being." Combining this with
our previous discussion of esse, a "being by participation" is one that does
not have esse essentially. Such a being can be or not be, that is to say, its
non-existence is possible. Such a being then is contingent because it does
not exist necessarily. With this definition in hand, the premise, "Every
being by participation is caused," means the same thing as, "Every being
(hat is not its own being is caused," or even "Every contingent thing has a
cause." The conclusion here in this passage then, if established, would be
establishing a mild principle of sufficient reason.
But it needs to be asked, how does Aquinas know, "Every being by
participation is caused?" While we will discuss this question in more
detail below, for now we point out that two clues here are important in
providing an answer. First, Aquinas follows the above argument with a
reference to Plato, saying "Therefore Plato says that it is necessary to place
unity before every multitude."4 On the face of it, this might seem like
n rather strange insertion. Upon investigation here however, Aquinas is
appealing to a principle that appears several times throughout his works.
We will return to this principle and those supporting texts later. As for
now, another important clue for understanding Aquinas' argument comes
from his answer to that first objection we saw above. The response to that
objection is truly valuable and deserves a full citation here:
Though the relation to its cause is not part of the definition of a
thing caused, still it follows, as a consequence, on what belongs
to its essence; because from the fact that a thing has being by
participation, it follows that it is caused. Hence such a being cannot
be without being caused, just as man cannot be without having the
faculty of laughing But, since to be caused does not enter into the
essence of being as such, therefore is it possible for us to find a
being uncaused.5
4 "Unde et Plato dixit quod necesse est ante omnem multitudinem ponere unitatem"
Aquinas also refcrH to it Plutonic sounding passage in Aristotle, "and Aristotle said that
wluUcver Is greolcil In helny unittyrcntcstin truth, is the cause of every being and of every
truth; Just us whatever IN lh« j|r«?tttf«l In heal Is the cause of all heal," Ibid.
5 Ibid, Hmphnili ttdtltd.
1VI
ill VHMM* Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
192
Causal Principles and Conclusions
formal logic, that the predicate of the conclusion, in this case, "caused,"
must appear as the predicate of the major premise. If "caused" appears in
(he conclusion, it must also appear in the premises. So if there is a causal
conclusion, there must be, given the very laws of formal logic, a causal
premise that is not a conclusion but a self-evident first principle. For this
reason it would be impossible to have a demonstrated causal conclusion
without there also being a self-evident principle of causality, a principle
I hat would be necessary, as we saw above, in the fourth mode J
We will evaluate this argument for a principle of causality later. Our
immediate task is to pull out the significant features of this passage. The
important things to learn here are; first, the causal argument here ends
up with a conclusion in the second mode of per se necessity. Second, this
means that, pace Hume, that we should not expect "cause" to be contained
i n the definition of the subject, yet this fact does not undermine its necessity.
Third, the notion of a "being that is not its own being" is important for
understanding the principle of causality. And finally fourth, the argument
rests entirely on some principle of unity that Aquinas attributes to Plato.
7 This insight resolves many of the scholastic disputes about whether or not the caus-
al proposition is a self-evident principle or a conclusion to a demonstration. For further
illscussion, see the exchange between Joseph Owens and John Cahalan. Joseph Ow-
ens, "The Causal Proposition - Principle or Conclusion." The Modern Schoolman, 32
(I l>55): 323-39 and John Cahalan, "On the Proving of Causal Propositions." The Modern
Schoolman 44 (1967): 12-20. Also of help in this area is Henry Veatch's "St. Thomas and
I he Question, "How Are Synthetic Judgments A Priori Possible?", The Modern School-
man 42 (3): 239-263. Veatch and Cahalan are surely correct in saying the laws of logic
show that any causal conclusion demands a causal principle that is self-evident, howev-
er they mistakenly ihlnk such a causal principle is true in the second mode (Cahalan)
or first mode (Veatch), l-'or I he reasons given above, such a causal principle would have
to he true In the fourth mode ui'prrtr necessity given how it is explained by Aquinas in
his Commentary on th* ftnt*rlor AfialyUcs,
K "Omri* tjuod Hi pMilM* mi *t turn I»MI«, habrt causam alkjuam: quia in se consider-
193
St. Ihomas Aquinas antl lite Priciple of Sufficient Reason
We see here the same idea mentioned in S.T. 1.44.1. The idea of a being
that is not its own being, something that is "able to be and not be", needs
a cause for its existence, because, in and of itself it is indifferent to either
existing or not existing. There is an appeal here to the inherent metaphysical
indifference to existence that all contingent beings have. The idea is that
this metaphysical indifference needs to be overcome, and one can almost
see an implicit "scale analogy" being employed here, as we saw in chapter
one with Avicenna and Leibniz, where there must be some determination
to account for why the metaphysical scale tips one way over another. Since
these kinds of things are existentially indifferent, there must be some cause
that overcomes this indifference if such a being is to exist.
De Potentia IIL5
To take another example of an argument aimed at showing all
contingent beings are caused, we now turn to the Disputed Questions
on the Power of God (Quaestiones Disputate De Potentia Dei) As in the
previous examples, the context here is the same, "Whether there is able
to be anything that is not created by God?"9 Several arguments are given
here; we look at only the first:
First, if in a number of things we find something that is common
to all, we must conclude that this something was the effect of some
one cause: for it is not possible that to each one by reason of itself
this common something belong, since each one by itself is different
from the others: and diversity of causes produces a diversity of
effects. Seeing then that being is found to be common to all things,
which are by themselves distinct from one another, it follows of
necessity that they must come into being not by themselves, but
by the action of some cause. Seemingly this is Plato's argument,
since he required every multitude to be preceded by unity not only
as regards number but also in reality}0
Aquinas is saying that if we find some element that is common to
all things, that commonality cannot be accounted for in virtue of those
atum ad utrumlibetse habet; et sic oportet esse altquod aliud quod ipsum ad unum deter'
minet." S.C.G 11.15. Emphasis added.
9 "Quaeritur utrum possit esse aliquid quod non ilt a D$o outturn" I>r Pot III.5.
10Ibid. Emphasis added,
194
Causal Principles and Conclusions
195
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
But whatever belongs to a thing and is yet not of its essence belongs
to it through some cause; for, if things that are not one through
themselves one are joined, they must be joined through some cause}2
So what was seemingly implicit in the De Ente is explicitly stated in the
parallel. Like we have seen in ST. 1.44.1 and in De, Pot III.5, again we see
an unambiguous appeal to a need for some unifying factor necessary for
all for composed beings. If things are not one through themselves they
must be made one by something else. Again we are not given any further
justification for this principle, however we will examine and attempt to
justify this claim below.
12 "ea enim quae per se non sunt unum, si coniungantur, oportet per aliquam causam
uniri. Esse igitur convenit illi quidditatiper aliquam causam."S.C.G, 1.22, emphasis added.
13 "Comp. Theo. 1.7
14 S.C.G. T.ch.13.
196
Causal Principles and Comlutlant
reason and one line of argument for weak principle of NiiHidcnl rcuNon.11
First, and most commonly, in three of the passages we see thiil Aquinas
appeals to some "unity principle" he often attributes to Plato. This we
saw in Summa Theologiae 1.44.1, De Potentia 3.5, and it was presumably
implicit in the De Ente ch. Ill text (as evinced by the parallel text in Summa
Contra Gentiles 1.22). Secondly, in one passage, namely Summa Contra
Gentiles 11.15, Aquinas offers a different line of reasoning. Here he says,
"Everything which is able to be and not-be has a cause; for considered
in itself it is indifferent to either, so that something else must exist which
determines it to one." 16 Here the argument is not based upon the notion
of two things needing a source of unity, but rather upon the metaphysical
indifference of something that is able to "be and not be." This seems to
me to be two different lines of argumentation and I will proceed on that
presumption. Thirdly, there seems to be some significance to the fact that
(he being of these things is accidental. This is not explicitly stated but
I he implicit understanding of the accidental character of being seems to
nlso be in the background. Finally, we saw at least two instances where
Aquinas appeals to his act/potency doctrine to support a weak principle
of sufficient reason.
With this brief examination of texts behind us, we now move to con-
sider whether or not these arguments succeed in showing either that every
contingent thing has a cause or whatever begins to exist has a cause.
I .s '1 his is not to say that these arguments cannot do "double duty" and serve the other
wnik or mild principle of sufficient reason respectively. The point here is that the context
hi which these argument appear do so in one that is either on behalf of the weak or mild
VIM'NIOII of ihe principle.
Ift"Omrie quod tit ptmlblb pnt el noti esse, habet causam aliquam: quia in se con-
nlderatum ad utrumUbit $0 htibtti *t */<' ofnwtei esse alhjuod aliud quod ipsum ad unum
d?tmntnet"S,C.U II,It, Hmphmilft NiUkd,
197
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
gives are properly explained. In order to show this, we will look at each
one of the causal arguments in order.
17 "ea enim quae per se non sunt unumy si coniungantur, oportet per aliquam causam
uniri. Esse igitur convenit Mi quidditatiper aliquam causam." SCG 1.22, emphasis added.
18 S.C.G. 1.18
19 Ibid.
20 Haec autempositio est omnino impossibilis. Si enim diversa in aliquo uniantur, necesse
est huius unionis causam esse aliquam, non enim diversa secundum si1 uniuntur. S.T. 1.65.1
21 S.T. 1.3.7
22 This does not mean contingent things connlitu of two illfhwul things In their own
right, only of two MXmnl principles, yd the r«iionln( tijuit M upplti-uhk.
198
Causal Principles and Conclusions
existence. But since nothing can be separated from itself, the thing and I lie
existence are non-identical, and if that, a multiplicity absolutely must be
present - that to which the contingent is identical, and that to which it is
not. To deny this point would be to deny the very principle of identity itself
and would land one is self-contradiction, for such a denial would be saying
that "a being both is and is not its own being" which is evidently impossible.
Since the contingent itself and its existence are different in themselves,
whenever we posit a contingent being in existence, we are necessarily
saying that these two different entities are now united. The contingent
thing would have to join with existence in order for it to be. It would be
impossible for a contingent thing to exist if it did not have existence. To
deny this point would, again, land one in a flat out contradiction. So given
(he existence of any contingent thing, there would have to be a unification
of two different principles. To put this same point in different words, if a
being that is not its own being exists; it must be a composite unity. It is,
as Aquinas says, an undeniable, metaphysical necessity then that every
contingent being must be a composed unity of itself and its existence.23
Having established a unified composition for any existing being that
is not its own being, we have now laid the foundation for understanding
why all such entities need a cause. Through a little metaphysical reflection,
we should be able to intuit the insight that things different in themselves
cannot unite unless something causes them to unite. In other words, the old
scholastic axiom, "multitude cannot give the reason for unity" (multitudo
turn reddit rationem unitatis) is applicable here. In no way can diversity,
qua diversity, account for unity. Differing things cannot, as differing
things, account for why those things are one.24 Unity cannot be grounded
23 It is not to our present purpose to present everything that can be said about Aquinas*
position on the real distinction of essence and existence, but what we have said so far is suffi-
cient to show all existing contingent beings are composites. "If something can exist only when
several elements come together, it is composite. But nothing in which the essence is other than
the being can exist unless several elements come together, namely, the essence and the being.
I lence, everything in which the essence is other than the being is composite." S.C.G. 1.22.
24 '1 his dictum would apply to every instance of causal interaction, even when the same
Mibstance acts upon itself".,, even if the same thing might be acted upon by itself, this still
does not happen hmol'iir UN It IN the same, but insofar as it is other. Now this potency is
reduced to afirNtactive potency, hci'iuiHo when anything undergoes change this is caused
by un agent, And for thin rewncm pwAAlve potency Is also reduced to active potency." (etsi
Idem patiatur a $0lpiQ> mm tnm*H mundttm idem, sedsecundum aliud. Haec autempo-
tMttttt mlucitur &dprtmm potthtltim tuttvum, quia passlo ah a^entc causatur. Et propter
199
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
200
Causal Principles and Conclusions
earlier chapter. The major premise being true in the fourth mode ofperse necessity, while
I he minor premise is certainly an essential definition of a contingent being and thus nec-
essary in the first mode of per se necessity. The conclusion is true in the second mode of
perse, all of which is consonant with what we saw about the causal principle in S.T. 1.44.1.
27 "Omne quod est possibile esse et non esse, habet causam aliquam: quia in se con-
sideratum ad utrumlibet se habet; et sic oportet esse aliquod aliud quod ipsum ad unum
determineC S.CG 11.15
28 "Omne autem quod est possibile esse, causam habet: quia, cum de se aequaliter se
httbeat ad duo, scilicet esse et non esse, oportet, si ei approprietur esse, quod hoc sit ex ali-
iliuj causa"S.CG. 1.15
29 "Omne quod est possibile esse et non esse, indiget aliquo alio quodfaciat ipsum esse:
quia quantum est in se, se habet ad utrumque. Quod autem facit aliquid esse, estprius eo.
liiyo omni quod est possibile esse el non esse, est aliquid prius" Comp.Theo. 1.6
M) "omne auttm quod *»t possibile esse, habet causam" S.CG. 1.16
M "quod auttm #*f pouihiht indict aliquo quo reducatur in actum; oportebit igitur
l*onere aliquam cfiUMM fun flat ut tflpvtu* reducatur in actum" S.CXi II, 32
201
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
Now we must note that by "possible" here Aquinas means a being which
is not necessary, i.e., a being that is capable of being or not being.32 We are
not using the term "possible" in the broader sense that would include the
necessary (in the sense that all necessary things are possible). Here we
are using the more restricted sense of the term, meaning by "possible"
that is able to be and not be. These beings are rightly called "possible" in
this sense simply because their existence is non-essential and therefore
merely possible and not necessary. In other words, we are talking about
contingent beings or beings by participation. So these possibles do not, in
and of themselves, account for their own existence.33
Thus to bring the issue directly to the fore, what justification is there for
Aquinas' claim that all possibles need a cause? To answer this question, it
will not be amiss to reiterate a point we have regularly made above, namely
it is necessary for everything existing thing to have a fundamental act of
esse in order to be. There cannot be a PSR-defiant being. But by definition,
the possible being does not contain in itself (as possible) the note of actual
existence. So if we conceive of a possible being as actually existing, we
cannot even conceive of it as actually existing in virtue of what it is in
itself, that is, what is contained in its concept qua possible. So where is
the actual reason or distinguishing act from mere nothing to be found?
By definition again, it is emphatically not in virtue of the possible being
as possible. Yet since it must be something; which means in this case it
must be something else. For any being that is not its own being, that is, any
possible, it simply must be the case that its being comes from outside and
other than itself This is simply another way of saying the being is caused.
The alternative is not only metaphysically impossible; it is also, contra
Hume, actually inconceivable. To conceive of actually existing possible
32 "Now in order to understand this we must note that the word possible is used in
two senses: (1) It is used, first, in contradistinction to the necessary, as when we call those
things possible which are capable either of being or not being...The word possible is used
in a second sense inasmuch as it is common both to those things which are necessary
and to those which are capable of being or not being, according as the possible is distin-
guished from the impossible." In IXMeta, 1.3, c.f., S.C.G. 111.86.
33 "Everything, furthermore, exists because it has being. A thing whose essence is not
it's being, consequently, is not through its essence but by participalion in something,
namely, being itself. {Omnis res est per hoc quod habet esse, Nulla igltur res cuius essentia
non estsuum esse, est per essentiam suam, sed participation* altculus, scilicet ipsius esse),
S.C.G. 1.22. "It is true lhai what has Its being from another IN nothing amnklered In itself,
if It be distinct from the being ihul It receive* from Mfilhir.,." DP hit,, 1,3,13 acl.4.
202
Causal Principles and Conclusions
Every being that is not its own being is distinguished from nothing
by another
34 If an objector asks for the justification of attaching the property "caused" to a contingent
being, we can say thai I lint It Is not because "cause" is contained in the definition of the subject
l>ul l he property neccmmrlly wises from such an essence as existing simply because of the lack
ni'csse in that CNHCIICC. 1 he rtlwnce o f i w In the essence calls for a positive non-essential esse
property If such a thing IN in exUL So It U not the positive presence of "cause" that grounds the
iKWNHiu'y connection bf twtfi) Ntihjwt ttiul predicate, it IN the luck of esse In the essence that
nerve* m the JunllAcitlcm farMylug "VMUHHI" IN H neieumry accident,
203
St Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
35 Garrigou Lagrange, God, v. I, op. cit., 193. As Maritain also argues, "contingent
being posited in existence', the other what I shall term caused/ that is to say, 'having
ground, a sufficient reason other than itself. When our mind contemplates these two
notions we see that in being outside the mind they are necessarily identical. Accordingly
we formulate the axiom: Every contingent being has a ground other than itself, exterior
to itself, that is to say an efficient cause. It Is a self-evident Nxloin »uul, like the principles
we have already examined, can be al Inched by A rtductlo ad abiurdum In ihc principle of
Identity." (Maritain, Metaphysics, op, clt„ 133),
204
Causal Principles and Conclusions
that everything else has a composition of act and potency.36 He then moves
to discuss all of these latter things whose existence is not identical to their
essence.37 It is important to note that the discussion is now restricted to
what we can call non-necessary or contingent beings. With this setting in
mind, Aquinas gives the following argument, cited again here in full:
"Now, whatever belongs to a thing is either caused by the principles
of its nature, as the ability to laugh in man, or comes to it from
some extrinsic principle, as light in the air from the influence of the
sun. But it cannot be that the existence of a thing is caused by the
form or quiddity of that thing -1 say caused as by an efficient cause
- because then something would be its own cause, and would bring
itself into existence, which is impossible. It is therefore necessary
that every such thing, the existence of which is other than its nature,
have its existence from some other thing."38
To simplify Aquinas' argument for our purposes, we can state it this
way:
Whatever belongs to a thing non-essentially is either caused by
the essence or comes to it from something else.
36 "Unde relinquitur quod talis res, quae sit suum esse, non potest esse nisi una" Aqui-
nas, De Ente Et Essentia, Caput 3. Textum a L. Baur Monasterii Westfalorum 1933 editum,
cmendatum a J. Koch ac translatum in taenias magneticas a Roberto Busa SJ. Source listed
ul www.CorpusThomisticum.org; vol. 43, 377.
37 "Whence it is necessary, that in everything other than this one its existence be other than
Its quiddity, or its nature, or its form." {"Unde oportet quod in qualibet alia repraeter earn aliud
sit esse suum et aliud quiditas vel natura seu forma sua") De Ente, Ibid.; vol. 43,377.
38 "Omne autem quod convenit alicui vel est causatum exprincipiis naturae suae, sicut
rislbile in nomine, vel advenlt ab aliquo principio extrinseco, sicut lumen in aere ex influen-
tia soils. Non autem potest esse quod Ipsum esse sit causatum ab ipsa forma vel quiditate rei
(tllco sicut acausu efficient?) quia >'/<" allqua res esset sui ipsius causa et aliqua res seipsam
In esse producmtt quod t$t Impouiblle, lir#o oportet quod omnis talis res, cuius esse est
aliudquam nature IWM HtbMt Ml* lib alio" Ibid, cl., S,CXl» I, 22 para. 6; vol. 13, 68, and
.SV/: 1.3.41 vol. 4, 42,
205
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
39 "At first sight, Thomas' argument simply begs the question. The esse of a thing must
arise from its essence or from outside. In saying this, Thomas leaves out precisely the op-
tion an opponent who denies the CP will choose: the esse of a thing not being caused by
anything, and not following from the thing's essence. A simple explanation why Thomas
does not feel obliged to discuss this option, crucial as it appears to philosophers these
days, might be that it is intuitively obvious to him that if you have a composition of two
factors (in this case the existence and the essence), there has to be an explanation of why
there is such a composition. Obviously, this will not do if we are trying to find an ar-
gument for the CP in Aquinas." Alexander Pruss, The Principle of Sufficient Reason: A
Reassessment, 28.
40 It could not be that the whole being comes from nothing since that would presup-
pose the thing could exist without any reason or act of being at all, and we have already
seen this is impossible. If a thing does not have esse, it does not exist. It is this notion that
is presupposed by this reasoning in the De Ente, "Nothing can he described as existing
unless it has esse." (Quia nihil potest did existens nisi hubmt me.") Si, 'Ihomas Aquinaa,
De divinis nominibus, cap, 51. 2. Owens alao nay* that thli r#Monln||o! Si. Ihomas "starti
from being as a common and neceiwary characltfrUHc of thlngM," |n*eph Owens, "The
206
iUiMMlft'lHilph*tiHtlComluifan*
being itself comes from "nothing," that is, neither from the CSMCIICC nor
from some extrinsic principle? If it can be shown that a non-essential
act of being can come from mere nothing and have no reason at all for
its existence, then the dilemma that Aquinas gives us here is a, false
dilemma. If on the other hand, Aquinas' disjunction does exhaust all the
options, his argument successfully goes through. This is the question
that needs to be addressed.
In order to answer this question, it is crucial to understand that the act
of being is a prior accidents All accidents by nature are modifications of
things, that is, they modify substances, and do not exist in their own right.
Redness, for example, exists in red things; the property of weighing 150
pounds does not exist on its own but in a thing that weighs 150 pounds,
and so on. The point is that an accident, by its very nature, must and
without exception, exist in things and there is no way to remove this note
of dependency on a substance from an accident.42
So all accidents exist only in substances, but which substance? Clearly
it cannot be dependent upon the very substance it actuates, since the act of
being must be is ontologically prior to that thing. Unlike other Aristotelian
accidents that are posterior to the substance, the act of being is accidental
in a prior sense, meaning that as the primary act in a being, it cannot come
"later." It must be the first act of a being before anything else the being
possesses; it is the act of all its other acts and the perfection of all its other
perfections. "If its being were not presupposed, there would be no nature. It
Analytics and Thomistic Metaphysical Procedure," Mediaeval Studies vol. 26, 1964, 94.
Lhis is not to say the Owens called this proposition a "principle of sufficient reason," but it
is to say that he found that statement to be a necessarily true proposition and the starting
point for Aquinas' reasoning here.
41 Comp. Theol LXVI; vol. 42,102. Also, "Only that which does not enter the definition of
A thing seems to be outside its essence or quiddity; for the definition signifies what a thing is.
I kit it is only the accidents of a thing that do not fall in the definition; and therefore only the
accidents in anything are outside its essence." S.C.G. 1.21.1 am greatly indebted for recogniz-
ing the notion of an act of being as accidental to Fr. Joseph Owens and John F. X. Knasas.
42 "As Owens puts it, "The note of dependence, accordingly, cannot disappear from the
notion of an accident without completely destroying the accident. The very presence of
an accident involves 1U dependence on something else." Joseph Owens, "The Accidental
and lissenttol-ChnrmMcr of Being," Salnl Thomas Aquinas On the Existence of God: The
Collected Pap$r$ oflonph ()wpti»t ed. John Calan (Albany, N.Y.: State University of New
York PreiM, 1VH0)« 77«H, A||«ln. "liy 11N very nnlurc il [an accident] is dependent upon a
NunNlunce," OwilMi Ah thnmitiryChrhtittn Metaphysics, 75-6.
207
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
would be nothing/'43 This sort of accident is the most basic and fundamental
reality in the thing. Because the esse is what brings that substance into being
in the first place, it is not possible that this accident also depends on that
same substance it brings into being, for that would be tantamount to saying
the accident causes its own existence, which is clearly impossible.44
So having established the fact that the major premise is speaking about
accidents, and that the sort of accident in question is prior to the thing
it actuates, we can see why Aquinas is entirely justified in refusing to
consider "nothing" as a possible third option. With these clarifications in
place, we can summarize the Thomistic Dilemma this way:
Every accidental esse must depend upon the substance it actuates
or upon another
208
Causal Principles and Conclusions
It is fitting at this point to point out that the above texts of Aquinas have
given us three different lines of justification for the mild principle of
sufficient reason. Granted they all lead to the same conclusion, but they do
so by means of different starting points. Taking any contingent being, one
can look at that contingent as a whole, one can look just the contingent
part of that thing as possible, or one can start by looking at the other part
of an existing contingent being, namely the being of that contingent as
prior accident. Whichever way one chooses to begin, one winds up with
the same conclusion, "every contingent being has a cause."
209
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
46 "Thus that which is actually hot, as fire, makes wood, which IN potentially hot, to be
actually hot, and thereby moves and changes it, Now it in not pomillilc I hut the same thing
should be at once in actuality and potentiality in the N«m« Ptfupoct, but only in different
respects. For what 1H actually hot ennnot »lnuilUn*ouily hf potentially hot," S.T, 1.2.3,
210
(lausttl ft'int'lplr* tttitl (.nttihiihni*
Conclusion
In a survey of several relevant texts in Aquinas we find compelling
argumentation in favor of various formulations of the principle of causality.
47 "That which comes to be anew must take its origin from some innovating cause;
since nothing brings itself from potency to act, or from non-being to being" S.C.G. I,
ch.13. "It is therefore impossible that in the same respect and in the same way a thing
should be both mover and moved, i.e. that it should move itself. Therefore, whatever is in
motion must be put in motion by another. S.T. 1.2.3.
48 "A being, then, which begins to be must have part of its sufficient reason for exis-
Icnce in some being outside itself, or, in other words, must have a cause. In this way we
can arrive at the principle of causality: Whatever begins to be must have a reason for its
existence outside itself. But though this principle is thus shown to be a special application
of the Principle of Sufficient Reason to a special class of beings, i.e., beings that begin to
he, it is really self-evident in its own right, for the two concepts, "to begin to be" and "to be
wilhout a cause" are evidently contradictory. For that which begins to be must first have
been in a state of potentiality, and as we have seen above, potentiality cannot become ac-
I ual without the intervention of some already actual being." John McCormick, Scholastic
Metaphysics (Chicago: Loyola University Press 1928). 141
49 The same reasoning nl.so Justifies the negative formulation ofthis principle, "out of noth-
ing, nolhlng come*" (r.v nlhilo nihil Jit), Iflhcre is nothing, there is not even the potency for
something to comn Into UtUty llcimnlng In lhal case would therefore be impossible. There
iiumt be ut u Icttll bfttpottiuy fur mining to be, unci thai potency cannot be mere nothing. Yet
potency, filboll niCHHfy, U mil miltkltml for becoming, and NO an act IN ulso needed.
211
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
From these texts, one can distill three lines of support for the mild principle
of sufficient reason, "every contingent being has a cause." These three lines
of support are based on the three possible ways of looking at any "being
that is not its own being." Thefirstargument looks at such a being as a whole,
that is, as united with being. Such a composite of different elements requires
some cause for unification, leading to the conclusion that "every composite
has a cause," which gives us a composition based principle of causality The
second argument commences from just the contingent part of a "being that
is not its own being." Such an entity is a metaphysically indifferent possible
in need of some other reality to make it actual, leading to the conclusion
"every possible being has a cause," giving us an indifference based principle
of causality. The third argument looks at the being part that actualizes any
being that is not its own being, and since this act must be both prior to the
contingent that it actuates and is nevertheless accidental in character, such
an entity depends upon a prior substance other than the one being actuated,
leading to the conclusion that "everything with accidental existence has
a cause," giving us an accidental based principle of causality. All three of
these formulations are metaphysical equivalents to the expression, "every
contingent being has a cause."
Finally, we saw similar argumentation in Aquinas on behalf of a
weak principle of sufficient reason, "whatever begins to exist has a
cause." Given that act and potency are irreducibly distinct metaphysical
principles, that every beginning of existence requires an actualization
of potency, and that every actualization of potency must be exercised
by something in act, we are inexorably led to the conclusion, "whatever
begins to exist has a cause."
At this point it is helpful to review the ground we have covered. We
have addressed what the principle of sufficient reason is and its various
modes. We have given several lines of dialectical argumentation on
behalf of the weak and mild principle of sufficient reason. We have
explained what we mean by a necessarily true proposition, delineated
various modes of propositional necessity, argued that we know such
things, and have offered some explanation as to how we come to know
them. We have defended the strong principle of sufficient reason as a
self-evident and metaphysically necessary principle by way of reductio
ad absurdum. We have also defended the method of reductio ad
absurdum from the charge of begging the qumllon. Having established
212
(.'iimil/ ft hit f/i/jfi Mid ( HMr/to/HHI
215
St Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
216
lii'l'lle* to Objection*
217
St. Ihoinits Aquinas arid the Pridple of Sufficient Reason
218
Replies to Objections
can conceive of these two states of the rabbit, potential and actual, as
remaining two distinct states, without there being any difference between
them. Something must be different about the actual state in order to avoid
a real identification with that possible state. Yet the moment you add that
"something,'* i.e., some real difference to that merely possible state, you
have just stipulated something by which that rabbit is distinctfrom nothing.
In other words, conceiving of an actual rabbit without any distinction
from a mere potential rabbit is impossible even for the mind. One may
choose not to say what the reason of difference is. One may refuse to
indulge in the quest to determine which property of that rabbit suffices
to account for its distinction from mere possibility. To be sure, one can
always refuse to consider these deeper metaphysical questions, but the one
thing one cannot do is conceive of an actual existing rabbit that lacks any
distinction from mere possibility.
As we have seen Aquinas argue above, before the rabbit begins to be it
must first be in potency, and if we add nothing to this potency, potency
is all that remains. In order for potency to be actualized, in order for
that potential state to really be different, something must be added to it.
"That which comes to be anew must take its origin from some innovating
cause; since nothing brings itself from potency to act, or from non-being
to being."5 This is not only true for reality, but it is also true for the mind,
given the conceptualization goes deep enough. The only reason why
Hume thinks that cause and effect are separable in the imagination is
because the imagination is capable of some very hazy concepts that would
not really exist in that way. Humes conception stops at the level of simple
apprehension and is therefore far too superficial about actual existence.
This is why his point succeeds only at a very superficial level, but it is the
deeper level to which we must descend if the argument is going to have the
real-world relevancy that he wants.
5 S.C.G. I, ch.l 3.
220
Replies to Objections
221
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
222
Replies to Objections
7 Quine's notion of analyticity is a good example of what is wrong with modern no-
lions of propositional necessity, as it seems to be based solely on a "true by definition"
model with no further extension to real things. Such limited views of necessity are, to
my mind, erroneously based on nominal definitions and come from a logic that, in the
words of Veatch, "Can't say what anything is." It is interesting that Rowe chose Quine's
notion of analyllclly, when 1( was the failure of such alternatives that were, no doubt, part
of Quine's molivwllon In \v\w 11 w^o priori justification altogether.
8 As wc have won wllh Knwc unii Ross above. For another defense of the principle of
Nulliclcnl rcttnon ugaltml IIIIH nrtiumrul, ntx Lloyd Gcrson, "Two Criticisms of the Principle
of Sufficient RIMCM" tnbrmUoml humuil for Philosophy of Religion 21 (1987), 129-42.
VRowi.HKMOI.
,—^. 223
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
10 This would commit a petitioprincipii fallacy In thf tru» Arlnlotdlwn sense which we
discussed In I he previous chapter,
224
Replies to Objections
being otherwise7. Can there be things that have a sufficient reason for their
existence, yet their existence still remains contingent? This is the question
we have to explore.
The best place to start is with the notion of "necessity." Necessity can
mean lots of things. First, there is the physical necessity of the laws of
nature, i.e., gravity, the strong force, etc., but nobody thinks that this
kind of necessity is incompatible with contingency. The physical necessity
inherent in the law of gravity does not take away our intuition that things
could not be otherwise (even that power of gravity itself could have been
different). It is not physical necessity to which we refer when we say that
necessity eliminates contingency. Necessity could also mean what the
scholastics called suppositional or hypothetical necessity (e.g., given that
Socrates stands, it is necessary that Socrates stands). But this notion of
necessity does not do away with contingency either, since after all, it is a
conditional necessity after all (e.g., if Socrates stands, it is necessary that
Socrates stands - but he need not stand!). This notion of necessity does
not mean that whatever is chosen could not have been otherwise in the
sense that it was impossible so this notion of necessity is compatible with
ontological contingency. In fact, there is only one sort of necessity that is
incompatible with contingency - what we can call logical or metaphysical
necessity, where the denial entails a real impossibility. Whatever state
of affairs is true with metaphysical necessity cannot be otherwise,
since that state of affairs obtains in every possible world.11 There are no
counterfactuals to a metaphysically necessary state of affairs - things just
have to be that way, and that is all.
So it is not just any sort of necessity that is incompatible with a
contingent state of affairs; it is only the metaphysical sort that entails the
impossibility of any alternative. Applying this to the principle of sufficient
reason, it is only if a sufficient reason accounts for a state of affairs with
metaphysical necessity that such a state of affairs is necessary and not
contingent. Again: necessity eliminates contingency if and only if that
necessity is a metaphysical necessity.
This means there is some truth to the contingent state of affairs
dilemma. In other words, there could be a scenario where having
11 Some may pr«l<?r to mil (IIIN n logical necessity. In either case, ihe meaning is the
same, via,, thm which t'MUinl not he. l'or Ihe Nuke of cortNlslency, we will use the phrase
mcl«phyilctl nihility In my lit* Mine tiling with illlfcrcnl words,
225
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
226
Replies to Objections
EXPLANATORY FILTER
FOR DETERMINING THE MODALITY OF A STATE OF AFFAIRS
existence of P
metaphysically
necessary?
yes
act of P
metaphysically
necessary?
yes
4
product of P
metaphysically
necessary?
yes
necessary
state of
affairs
The vertical sequence all the way through is exactly what the relation
of explanans to explanandum must look like if that explanans is to entail
metaphysical necessity in the explanandum. In other words, this is the
model thai musl always he the case if this argument against the principle
of sufficient rcuiiun IN to succeed.12
12 Of couraii ihli dtA(Mm nml mil need rcprcticnt a temporal order, but rather a pri-
ority of being,
227
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
The big question now of course is this: does insisting on the principle
of sufficient reason as a universally valid principle mean that all causal/
explanatory sequences must follow that vertical path of metaphysical
necessity? In other words, has the contingent state of affairs dilemma
given us good reason to think that this path must always be the case? This
is the question that must be answered.
13 Such as philosophers who adopt what is commonly labeled the "libertarian" posi-
tion on the will. Scotus is a classic example, holding that the will IN nn "active potency",
meaning that the will has the power to determine itself. Sec Allan H. Woller, trans. & ed.,
Duns Scotus on the Will and Morality (Washington, D.C.i Catholic Unlvcmlly of America
Press, 1986).
228
Replies to Objections
of other beings. Thus, this necessary being has the ability to make free
choices or simply refrain from action altogether. In this sense, the a se
being's choices are contingent. Here we have a necessary being that
nonetheless has a contingent power. Having the properties of both necessity
in existence but contingency in action allow us to say two things. First, this
beings existence is self-explained, viz., the reason why it exists is because
it is of such a nature that it cannot not exist. The existence of this being
does not violate the principle of sufficient reason. Secondly, if this being
decides to produce something through its contingent powers, that product
will be contingent and dependent upon this action. The existence of the
product would be contingent, since its existence would be dependent upon
the contingent actions of the a se being. In such a case, the existence of the
product has not violated the principle of sufficient reason either.
Let us say that this a se being freely decides to exercise its causal power
and produces three apples. These three apples do not have to exist; after all,
the being could have decided to make watermelons, grapefruit, or simply
make nothing at all. Thus, the existing three apples are a contingent state
of affairs. Referring to the explanatory filter above might help us see the
modality of this result. In step one, we have metaphysical necessity, i.e.,
the existence of the being is metaphysically necessary, but in step two,
this being has volitional freedom and need not cause anything. Already we
have contingency, and if we assume in step three that the being possesses
enough power that it could have made just two or four apples, or a set of
watermelons, a second layer of contingency will be established. Thus, we
have a workable counterexample to the argument, viz., a cogent case of
a necessary being causing/explaining a contingent state of affairs via a
contingent power.14
14 Does this mean that the a se being cannot be simple? It is not my intention here to
defend any particular position on divine simplicity. The recognition that a necessary be-
ing can have a contingent act of the will is held by philosophers who hold to a strong sense
of divine simplicity and those who do not. For example, Aquinas, a champion of divine
simplicity and a se existence, nevertheless was insistent that God willing things apart
from Himself Is not absolutely necessary {S.T. 1,19,4, ad. 4), and that such a contingent act
of the will docs nol Inlroclucc division into the divine nature (even if we cannot explain
how this 1« HO wc cnn know thai II is so). Scotus, on the other hand, opposed Aquinas'
view by polling In (itul «n ud mil formal distinction prior to any act of the mind (Oxon,
L, d.2 q,7,), 'lh« rtiullitlon ol thin debate IN not germane to the discussion, since both sides
admit Ihftl * nwiflftiry bflng inn have n free act of the will. Whether or nol the '1 horn 1st,
the Scotiit, thl lUirilllft (Mr Mint* ulhf r nhool for llnil mutter) IN correct IN Nlmply not
. _ > — . . 2 2 9
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
an issue that concerns us. In other words, if it turns out that a necessary being having
a free act of the will does introduce some sort of distinction in the divine nature, all it
would show is that some non-Thomist view of a necessary being is correct, not that a suf-
ficient reason cannot be a combination of necessary and contingent factors. For a defense
of Aquinas* view of divine simplicity see, J. F. X. Knasas* "Contra Spinoza: Aquinas on
God's Free Will," American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 76 (2002), 417-29. For an
alternative defense of Aquinas, see Norris Clarke's "A New Look at the Immutability of
God," Explorations in Metaphysics: Being-God-Person (South Bend, IN: University of No-
tre Dame Press, 1995). For a sympathetic analysis of the classical theists view of God, see
Barry Miller, A Most Unlikely God: A Philosophical Inquiry into the Nature of God (South
Bend, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1996). For a contemporary analytic defense
of the classical notion of divine simplicity, see William Vallicella's "Divine Simplicity: A
New Defense," Faith and Philosophy 9(4) (1992), 471-78 and Eleonore Stump and Norman
Kretzmann, "Absolute Simplicity," Faith and Philosophy 2(4) (1985), 353-82.
15 We can characterize the problem another way through formal notation. The contin-
gent state of affairs dilemma stands or falls on the validity of the following argument:
DP
P>£L
• Q
The nuances of normal language are hard to capture in formal notation. The "neces-
sarily" part of P can refer to P's mode of existing (not P's actions). There is no inherent
problem with saying a necessary being can act contingently. ThuH, P exists necessarily, but
can act contingently, and therefore can entail or cause Q conllngcnlly. If this is possible,
then the argument is invalid since Q In that caic would hi conllnyenl,
16 As argued above, In ouch a CUMC the mere exlulinci of itn A gen I chonning would he the
230
Replies to Objections
in any way to say that all beings need a reason, while also maintaining
that the will is a self-actualizing power and therefore can choose without
any motive at all. All that is required for our formulation of the principle
of sufficient reason is that there be two - and only two - kinds of beings:
necessary beings that exist from their own nature, and contingent beings
whose existence is caused by something other than themselves.
If an objection is raised that the act of the will of such a being is a
contingent fact, and no contingent fact can fully explain others, I say it is
not just that contingent act of the will alone that explains the contingent
state of affairs, but a combination of a necessary and contingent factor,
viz., a being that exists necessarily but which can contingently choose to
create. Moreover, it may also be the case that this a se being freely willing
X can be self-explanatory; contingent but self-explanatory. Premise two
assumed, as we said, without warrant, that no contingent act of the will
could be self-explained.
Limitation Attempts
While not usually explicitly stated as an independent argument
against the principle of sufficient reason, some thinkers, perhaps feeling
persuaded by the plausibility of the principle, opt for a more "hedged"
response by admitting the principle of sufficient reason to be true, albeit
limited in scope. This limitation of scope usually comes in two ways - some
say the principle is true, but limited to thought (the "it is just a law of
thought" response), while others degrade the scope of the principle down
to the physical world only ("it is just a physical law"). In this section I will
address these limitation attempts.
,••-«-• 231
St Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
"real outside world." The denier would argue that the principle of sufficient
reason is only a "law of thought," but not a reality.
But if we are required to think that the principle of sufficient reason is
true, yet the principle of sufficient reason is not really true, then we are in
a very sorry epistemic position, indeed. For that means nothing else than
we are forced to think of reality in a way that reality is not, in other words,
we are forced to think of reality falsely. Our minds only "work" when
reality is literally twisted and construed in a way different than it really is.
If this is true, how can it be said that our minds "work" at all? How can a
mind be a reliable true belief-producing faculty when it must operate on
presuppositions that are actually false? For this reason, the objection that
the "principle of sufficient reason is just a law of thought" reduces to the
claim that our minds are unreliable. To put the point formally:
If the principle of sufficient reason is "just a law of thought," then
we must think of reality falsely.
232
Replies to Objections
Categorical assertions can be met with categorical denials, and one mans
modusponens is another mans modus tollens:
If the principle of sufficient reason is "just a law of thought," then
we must think of reality falsely.
17 On* mightttUocall ihU (he "Kantian" argument, because Kant would deny that
principle! lUtihft!111* urliulpl* ul nulllilcnl rcuimn could he known lo apply lo anything
hcynndflfMMJipfrlfWf.
233
St. Ihomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
world" presupposes that these principles must also apply to that very same
non-physical world, or else such a distinction would be meaningless. In
order to say such things one must hold that this is not that Thus, to say
for example that the principle of non-contradiction applies only to the
physical world and not the non-physical is self-refuting, as it presupposes
what it denies.
Now pointing out other examples of other known metaphysical laws
does not, by itself, demonstrate that the principle of sufficient reason is
also a metaphysical principle, but it does undermine a possible reason
for denying its metaphysical status. If principles like the principle of non
contradiction, the principle of identity, and the law of excluded middle
can be applicable to a possible non-physical realm, why not the principle
of sufficient reason?
• Whatever exists must have a sufficient reason for its existence (true).
• Whatever exists must have a sufficient and material reason for its ex-
istence (false).
Nothing stated in these principles calls for such an arbitrary restric-
tion, nor is physicality necessitated in any of these formulations.
234
Replies to Objections
233
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
Summary
A critical examination of the four most popular arguments against the
principle of sufficient reason shows that these arguments all contain seri-
ous defects. None succeed in subverting the metaphysical intuition that
things cannot come into being from nothing, and thus, there are always
reasons for a thing s existence. The argument from David Hume rested
on demonstrably false premises in both his epistemic argument and his
imagination argument. The Neo-Humean argument fared no better in
trying to impose a Quineian notion of necessity and analyticity that is
problematic and would not be accepted by thinkers in the scholastic tra-
dition such as Aquinas. The contingent state of affairs dilemma asserted
a false dichotomy by overlooking a third possibility; namely, that the ne-
cessity of a being's existence can be separated from the contingency of its
actions, thus allowing for the possibility of a necessarily existing being
contingently producing and being the reason for a contingent state of af-
fairs. Finally, both limitation attempts suffered from serious defects. To
limit the principle of sufficient reason to "just a law of thought" is an un-
substantiated assertion resulting in the absurd claim that our minds are
forced to think of reality falsely in order to work properly. The attempt to
limit the principle of sufficient reason to just the physical world ran into
numerous difficulties as well, such as the fact that denying the principle of
sufficient reason results in a contradiction and so must be true in all pos-
sible worlds (not just our physical world). Finally, limiting the principle of
sufficient reason to the physical realm seemed to entail the impossibility
of different "species" of nothing. Hence, we have not seen any reasons to
cause us to doubt that the principle of sufficient reason is a necessarily true
metaphysical principle.
236
"One cannot take the principle of sufficient reason for granted:
one must prove it. And that is something that neither Leibniz nor
anyone else has ever done."l
- David Blumenfeld
239
St. Thomas Aquinas and the Priciple of Sufficient Reason
240
Conclusion
self-evident, and defended that view with the standard scholastic weapon
for such a purpose, the reductio ad absurdum argument. I then stated that
this reductio argument, contra what others have said, does not commit the
petitio principii fallacy when that fallacy is properly understood.
Subsequently, we looked at various texts in Aquinas that argued on
behalf of the weak and mild principles of sufficient reason. There we saw that
four arguments could be distilled from the texts of Aquinas. The first three
were on behalf of the mild principle of sufficient reason, "every contingent
being has a cause/' We saw that a contingent being can be considered in
three ways; as a whole, as the contingent part, or as the act part. In each way
we demonstrated an equivalent of the mild principle of sufficient reason;
respectively, "Every composed thing has a cause," "Every possible has a
cause," and "Everything with accidental existence has a cause." We then saw
how Aquinas' doctrine of act and potency can demonstrate a weak principle
of sufficient reason, "whatever begins to exist has a cause."
In the final section I responded to the arguments against the principle
of sufficient reason. There, for the various reasons presented, I argued (hiU
none of the four arguments we looked at were successful in undermining
our certitude regarding the principle, nor were they successful In
convincingly limiting that principle to just the mind or the physical world.
Noted philosophical atheist J. L. Mackie once said, "There is no
sufficient reason to regard the principle of sufficient reason to be valid."'
Have I shown Mackie's statement to be false? That is something every
reader must decide for themselves.
31.1.. Mftcklfi 1k$ Mthuh of'lheiami Arguments Ivr and Against the Existence of God
(New Yorki Onfttni Unlwitty Prm, tutu), ui\,
The principal aim ol ihis essay, however, is tmi i«> dcirriiiiiie ihc
historical pedigree ol an idea. I I civ we are eoiuvmrd with a single
question; namely, what good reasons are there for dunking die pi im ipl.
of sufficient reason is true? Ihis all-important question must he handled
by arguments and not historical surveys. Given the above, 1 hope it is
clear that this question is of fundamental importance to philosophy.
Many laypeople will find this purpose silly. Our metaphysical intuitions
tell us that or course, something cannot be caused or determined by
nothing. Almost all of our day-to-day actions presuppose that something
cannot come to be from nothing. We hear a knock on the door and seek
to see who is doing the knocking. We get sick and wonder where we
caught the disease. Everyday life is literally inundated with causal
inferences. On this score, the layperson has a good point; the principle ol
sufficient reason certainly enjoys a tremendous amount of intuitive
plausibility.
uw
ISBN 9781534982253
AQUINAS
© 2016 Aquinas School of Theology - All Rij'Jiis Reserved
For More Resources Visit: www.ScottMSiilliwin.rnm
9 781534"982253