Lecture++Two+on+Theories
Lecture++Two+on+Theories
THEORIES OF ETHICS
Ethical issues are better explained from a theoretical perspective than from a layman
point of view. This chapter addresses the various ethical theories and how they
Explain the utilitarian theory of ethics with focus on act and rule utilitarianism
persons as ends
Introduction
Throughout the history of philosophy, thinkers have addressed the question of what
makes an act moral or immoral. In this context, the terms “moral” and “ethical” will
be justified using the utilitarian theory. This chapter addresses theoretical issues as
is no single view in general ethics of what makes something right or wrong. People or
theories (Victor & Cullen, 1988). The theory-based criteria contain information about
the recommended action and about the reasons for that recommendation. These
criteria comprise the logic for action, "the underlying assumptions, deeply held, often
unexamined, which form a framework within which reasoning takes place" (Horn,
1983). Broadly speaking, ethicists put ethical theories under two main categories:
Teleology
consequential theories. The notion behind such theories is that the morality of
action is evident only in the consequences of that action: whether a lie is good or bad
depends upon the consequences of that particular lie at the time. Utilitarianism, for
for everyone affected by a particular action (‘the greatest good for the greatest
Consequential Theories
Many theorists contend that the moral rightness of an action can be determined simply
by looking at its consequences. If the consequences are good, the act is right; if the
consequences are bad the act is wrong. Consequential theories measure the morality
of actions on the basis of their non-moral consequences (Barry, 1979). Simply put,
therefore determine good or bad action simply by looking at the ratio of goodness or
badness the action produces; and eventually choose the course of action that would
seem to produce the most good. Under consequential ethics, egoism, utilitarianism
Egoism
the self as opposed to others (Tsalikis & Fritzsche, 1989). Egoism is a moral act
which promotes the individuals best long-term interests. In determining the morality
of an action, egoists use their best long-term advantage to measure the action’s
goodness (Barry, 1979). Egoism measures the morality of a behavior by the extent to
which the behavior promotes one’s own interests. Under this approach, an action that
an action that does not is considered unethical. There are a few variations of the
theory; one school of thought views two forms of egoism and these are psychological
behavior that holds that people are naturally programmed to behave only in their own
self-interest. Ethical egoism is the normative theory whereby people ought to act
exclusively in their self-interest (Reidenbach & Robin, 1990; Jones et al., 2007).
Thus, the moral principle of ethical egoism suggests that an act is ethical when it
promotes the individual's long-term interest (Shultz & Brender-Ilan, 2004; Jones et
al., 2007). Note that it is possible for people to help others, follow the rules of society,
and even grant gifts if they believe that those actions are in their own best interest.
Some moralists also distinguish between two kinds of egoism: personal and
impersonal. Personal egoists claim that they should pursue their own best long term
interests and impersonal egoists also claim that everyone should follow their own best
long term interests (Barry, 1979). Hinman (2007) on the other hand sees three
categories of ethical egoism; personal ethical egoism which believes that “I am going
to act only in my own interest, and everyone else can do whatever they want.”
Individual ethical egoism also believes that “everyone should act in my own interest.”
and universal ethical egoism contends that “Each individual should act in his or her
own self-interest.” Ethical egoists sometimes maintain that if each person took care of
himself/herself, the overall effect would be to make the world a better place for
everyone.
Utilitarianism
The theory most commonly associated with the teleological approach is known as
utilitarian theory. Utilitarianism is the philosophical approach which says that the
moral act is the one that creates the greatest happiness or good for the greatest number
of people. To Rachels (1993), the belief that actions should be appraised in terms of
greater ratio of good to evil for everyone and therefore emphasizes the best interests
of everyone concerned. Lewis (1991) defines it as society’s net benefit over harm. To
way that will produce the greatest overall amount of good in the world. Conversely,
individuals receive, or produce more benefit for some people than for others. In terms
of organizational policies, utilitarianism holds that rules are ethical if they promote
behaviours that maximize the benefit for all members and other stakeholders, and are
Utilitarianism has been linked to the modern welfare state which has found some
special interest for students of philosophy and society. It has also been associated with
applying the utilitarian theory to the outcome of an action or decision, the principle is
that everyone should act to generate the greatest benefits for the largest number of
people. The ultimate goal of utilitarianism is not the happiness of the individual, but
the happiness of society (Rossouw, 2002). Are the greatest happiness and the greatest
Utilitarianism focuses on ends and not on the means required to achieving those ends,
and it takes into account all present and future benefits and harms that accrue or might
accrue to anyone who is affected by the action, including items that may be difficult
whole, where the net social benefit equals social benefits minus social costs
(Bentham, 1789; Mill, 1957; Brandt, 1979; Rachels, 1999; Velasquez, 1998;
The primary way of assessing “the greatest good for the greatest number” is by
performing a social cost/benefit analysis. All possible benefits and costs of the
assessed act are listed and summarized as the net of all benefits minus all costs. If the
net result is positive, the act is morally acceptable; if the net result is negative, the act
which may in part be due to its tradition in economics. The ensuing economic
material good for the greatest number, get to be considered ethical from the
perspective of the traditional economic philosophy. It should be noted here that the
utilitarian analyses of moral philosophers extend beyond material good to the much
Bentham (1748-1832) and John Stuart Mill (1806-1873). In expressing the theory of
Nature has placed mankind under the governance of two sovereign masters,
pain and pleasure. It is for them alone to point out what we ought to do, as
well as to determine what we shall do. On the one hand the standard of right
and wrong, on the other the chain of causes and effects, are fastened to their
throne.
interest is in question: or, what is the same thing in other words, to promote or
The creed which accepts as the foundation of morals, Utility, or the Greatest
Happiness Principle, holds that actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote
intended pleasure, and the absence of pain; by unhappiness, pain, and the privation of
pleasure. To give a clear view of the moral standard set up by the theory, much more
requires to be said; in particular, what things it includes in the ideas of pain and
pleasure; and to what extent this is left an open question. But these supplementary
explanations do not affect the theory of life on which this theory of morality is
grounded – namely, that pleasure, and freedom from pain, are the only things
desirable as ends; and that all desirable things (which are as numerous in the
utilitarian as in any other scheme) are desirable either for the pleasure inherent in
Although it could be interesting to actually sit back and think about what our ultimate
ends might be, in most cases we make decisions based on more immediate concerns –
a manager may add six new salespeople because he/she is persuaded that the
additional revenue they generate will not only cover their own costs, but also provide
an increment of profits to the company. Also, we choose to go to the dentist and have
a root canal performed not because we enjoy pain as an ultimate end, but because the
temporary pain of the dental procedure will result in a longer pain-free period
afterward.
When we decide on the morality of an action based on the results that will be
because it is simply the right thing to do. Thus, the charge is sometimes raised that
utilitarianism is wrong because it is based on the notion that the end justifies the
means.
For too many people, the statement “the end justifies the means” is the same as “a
good end justifies any means.” Increased profit for my business is a good end, but it
does not justify my employing eight-year-old children for twelve hours a day and
paying them a dollar an hour. It also does not justify ignoring safety concerns and
bankrupt due to uncompetitive pricing caused by labour costs, reducing either wages
or staff, or both, may well be justified in order to keep the company operating and
teleological ethics) are problematic in that they focus on ends as opposed to means
(Tsalikis & Fritzsche, 1989). That is, a behavior might achieve an outcome that is
way that is detrimental to long-term well-being, for example. It can also be argued
that a utilitarian outcome is not always a fair outcome in that some people may
contribute above-average inputs to a task, but receive equal shares of the resulting
benefits.
Types of Utilitarianism
Act utilitarianism
Is the theory stipulating that the morally right act is the one that produces at least as
much overall happiness in the circumstances as any alternative act. This means that
when deciding which act would be ethically right, a person must investigate the
reasonably foreseeable consequences of the different possible acts she could perform;
the act that would produce the most overall happiness is morally right and must be
carried out.
Example: this scenario involves two parties and two alternative courses of action.
Consider a request made by your aunt in the local retirement home that you visit her
one evening. She can be a difficult person and you do not particularly like visiting,
though you know she is lonely and your visits do her a world of good. If you agree to
her request and visit her, she will be very happy, but you will miss your favourite
decide not to visit her, she will be extremely disappointed, but you will be able to
watch your television programme, gaining some happiness (though a twinge of guilt
takes away just a bit of that happiness). Act-utilitarianism requires this sort of
thinking – analyzing the effects on the happiness of the individuals involved for each
alternative course of action. The morally right action is the one producing the most
Notice that the amount of happiness gained or lost is quantified. However, in line with
the formal definition of act-utilitarianism provided here, it should also be pointed out
that in the case where there is a “tie” in that two alternative courses of action would
produce the most happiness, either of the two acts may be performed. This sort of
possibility is covered by the specification that the right act would produce “at least” as
much overall happiness as any alternative act. If, for example, the total effects on
happiness would be identical for ACT X and Act Y (if, say, each would produce a net
gain of 5 units of happiness), then either of those two actions would be morally
permissible. To say that an act is morally permissible, is to say that it is allowed but
not required; the performance of the act is not morally wrong, but neither is the failure
to perform it. However, performing one of those two acts, instead of Act Z (that
would, say, produce an overall gain of only 2 units of happiness), would be morally
required.
suggest that this is commonsensical, that what we mean by the morality of actions is
just the consequences that those actions might bring about. Thus, in what other ways,
they ask, could morality be assessed except by appealing to the consequences? (b) It
is relatively simple and (all things considered) easy to apply; the principle “maximize
basic moral theory that can be applied to real-life cases without undue difficulty. (c)
act-utilitarianism possesses the characteristics that are important for a viable moral
theory.
Rule-Utilitarianism
beyond the immediate circumstances. Instead, it calls for a closer look at the long-
term consequences that would be generated by performing the act in all relevantly
conforms to the rule which, when followed, produces at least much overall happiness
over the long run as any alternative rule. More broadly, that rule must then itself be a
member of a set of rules that would produce at least as much overall happiness as any
alternative set.
The claim made by rule-utilitarianism is that their theory will generate rules, and will
thus prescribe actions in accordance with those rules, that are much more in line with
our intuitions. For example, the rule requiring people to keep their promises is likely
others to keep their word will be happier than a society in which promises are broken
on a regular basis. Keeping one’s word will thus be a fairly stringent moral obligation
any alternative rule pertaining to promise-keeping, and that rule can likely be
integrated into a set of rules that would maximize overall societal happiness. Thus,
when a lawyer agrees in principle to a settlement in a lawsuit and then goes back on
that agreement just before the schedule trial date (in order to cause confusion on the
part of the opposing lawyer), rule-utilitarianism could perhaps be used to show that
Conclusion
Criticizing utilitarianism is not enough to demonstrate that it should not be used in
advertisements are examples of this; the faults of the other candidate are often
highlighted rather than the merits of the candidate himself.) Utilitarians sometimes
acknowledge that their theory is not perfect, but they challenge their critics to point to
a better one. After all, they say, there is not perfect moral theory; rather, it is the best
moral theory that is sought. The following theories are attempts to provide alternative
spending money, time and effort might be justified by the results to be achieved, but it
might not. Since this sort of analysis is future-oriented, it will necessarily be less
precise than analysis of expenditures that have already been made and results that
not make good business sense to plan to spend money, under either expense or capital
budgets, that will not yield a benefit at least equal to the expenditure. The budget
process is often conducted with a good deal of politics involved and, as the saying
goes; the devil is in the details. However, when money could be spent in one of
several ways, but not all of them, then aiming to get the biggest bang for the buck is
not really different than aiming to create the greatest good for the greatest number, at
least in principle.
While cost-benefit analysis is utilitarian in spirit, it is narrower in scope. Whether in
revenues or reduce enough future financial cost, then it is approved. The principal
generate the most output with the least input? While it might legitimately do so, cost-
benefit analysis does not always take into account impacts beyond expenses and
revenues. To give one example frequently raised in business ethics textbooks, a cost-
benefit analysis of a plant closing in a small town might not address the impact on the
town’s unemployment rate or tax base, while in utilitarian analysis would also factor
in these issues.
expenditures are sometimes approved on the basis of necessity rather than amount of
dollar benefits. One relatively small hospital group with which I am familiar recently
decided to spend tens of millions of dollars integrating its more than twenty software
follow-ups. The executives of the hospital group felt that they simply could not
continue to provide adequate service without such systems integration. The project
was approved on the basis of necessity rather than of quantified savings or additional
revenue and profits. It appears that, in deciding to spend this amount of money on
systems integration, they were aiming in a broad sense to achieve the greatest good
Deontology
One school of thought emphasises duties, things that must be done (or refrained from)
goodness or badness is evident only in the action itself: that, for example, lying is bad
because it is bad in itself. Thus, deontological approach to the study of ethics differs
from teleological approaches in that it does not focus solely on consequences when
assessing the morality of actions. Instead, this approach places more emphasis on the
morality such as rules and rights. Deontology deals with actions, which are inherently
right or wrong, without taking their consequences into account. In order to define the
probable outcomes. The foundation of moral duty is an “a priori” belief. Reason can
reveal the basic moral principles. In order to define what I should do, I must consider
what all rational beings must do. Moral laws are valid for all rational beings.
and on the intentions associated with a particular behaviour, rather than on its
whether or not an action is ethical. They also feel that individuals have certain
the way we deal with ethical issues in everyday life. Unfortunately, however, they are
very different ways of reasoning, which can lead to contradictory outcomes in some
cases. An exclusively duty-based view of ethics, for example, must sooner or later run
into problems such as absolutism, or the difficulty of deciding which duty should take
precedence over others in a particular situation. If, for example, both lying and killing
are held to be inherently wrong, is it acceptable to lie in order to avoid a killing? And
The approaches of two leading deontologists will be discussed in this course. The first
providing the details of the theory. In fact deontological ethics is sometimes thought
can believe that deontology is the best moral theory without agreeing with the
specifics of Kant’s claims. This was true of Sir W.D. Rose (1877-1971), a more
certain actions or policies are ethically right, wrong, or permissible. Example, Martell
Welch, Jr. attacked Deletha Word because she accidentally dented his car. He stripped
and beat her in broad daylight on the Bell Isle Bridge in Detroit, Michigan. While he
beat her, over forty people watched him and, according to reports, at times cheered for
him. No one on the bridge offered any kind of assistance to Word, not even a phone
call for help. To escape from Welch, she threw herself over the side of the bridge and
drowned. It seems to us, according to our moral vision that Welch’s actions were
ethically wrong, and it also seems that the other people on the bridge were wrong for
failing to act on her behalf. A moral theory, though, is supposed to test these sorts of
intuitions to see if they reflect moral truth; it is supposed to clarify things, so that we
From Kantian perspective, the determination of whether Welch’s action was morally
right, wrong or permissible requires carefully consideration of the act under the
following thematic concepts. According to Kant, the answer to each question is a
The first question, which is very basic, is: what makes a person morally good? Kant
posits that the intention (motive) one chooses makes one morally good. When we
judge people as morally good or bad, we do not look at whether they happen to
achieve their goals. People often fail to accomplish set goals through no fault of their
own. You may set yourself the general goal of helping others, and this may mean that
when the man next to you has a heart attack, your specific goal is to save his life. It
may be, however, that despite your best efforts to save him, the man dies nonetheless.
It should be clear that the man’s death does not mean you are morally bad. Instead, it
is more plausible to claim that you are morally good because your goal – your
intention – was to save his life. This is the idea behind Kant’s first proposition; to
Next is what sort of intentions makes one morally good? This leads to Kant’s second
proposition of morality. Specifically, Kant indicates that there is a right and a wrong
way to answer this question. The wrong way pertains to happiness. It is a fact of
human nature that people are inclined to act so as to make themselves happy. Perhaps
you have the intention of doing well in school, and this is because you have the yet
person’s structure of intentions. Kant points out, however, that being happy is not
necessarily the same thing as being a morally good person. After all, some things that
make you happy may be unethical. Therefore, it is not the intention of bringing about
happiness that makes one morally good. Instead, it is acting with the intention of
being dutiful – of acting from the motive of duty itself, and not from the (misguided)
motive of bringing about happiness. Stated formally, Kant’s second proposition is that
a morally good intention (the possession of which makes a person morally good) is
The second proposition (acting from motive of duty) gives rise to a third question:
what exactly, does this mean? What does it mean for a person to intend to act from the
motive of duty? Kant’s answer which is his third proposition is that acting from the
motive of duty is acting out of respect for the moral law. The moral law to Kant is
that which morality requires. Specifically, the moral law is what morality itself
(objective moral truth) requires of us, and acting out of respect for the moral law
means not allowing anything-not happiness, not fear, not love, not even government’s
law – to get in the way of doing what is morally right. This commitment to doing
what is right, and being willing to sacrifice happiness along the way, is what Kant
In brief, Kant’s views about morality or ethics is that a person is morally good
(performs moral actions) if he acts from a morally good intention, and an intention is
morally good if the motive is duty itself, meaning respect for the moral law. First, for
Kant, doing the right thing can be a somewhat complex operation. Acting from the
right motive is crucial. Some Kantians take this to mean that acting from the right
motive is a necessary part of performing the right act-that one cannot perform the
right action unless she acts out of respect for the moral law. Others believe that the
two notions are separate, that one must perform the morally right action, and in
addition, must do so with the right motive (respect for the moral law). Against this
backdrop, it is possible to perform the right action without doing so out of respect for
than respect for the moral law. Kant believes that when determining the ethical course
of action, inclinations can get in the way; they can skew one’s thinking and lead to
misguided conclusions about what is ethical. Inclinations should thus be set aside.
Despite this elucidation about a morally right action, we are unable to determine what
this moral law is? To understand this, Kant proposed an answer in his famous moral
In ethics, moral theories serve as tools for sharpening our moral vision, for helping us
to better see things (ethically) as they really are (objectively). The tool of Kantian
deontology focuses on motive, but the more complete account of theory entails
us what to do. In fact, it tells us what we must do if we are to act ethically, and in this
way it tells us what the moral law really is. Second, it is a mechanism for testing
actions or rules to see whether they are ethically right, wrong, or permissible.
First, the theory is premised on the idea of universalizing maxims. In Kant’s words,
the command is, “Act only according to that maxim by which you can at the same
time will that it should become a universal law.” Putting into context, if we asked
Martell Welch why he beat Deletha Word, he might respond by saying, “she made me
angry, and beating her made me feel better.” His motive in some sense pertains to
alleviating the anger she caused him. The second step is to use this motive to ascertain
reason for acting, but it is expressed as a general rule that applies to all future actions.
Welch’s motive in the specific case can be expanded into the following general
guiding rule: “Whenever anyone angers me, I will beat that person so that I can feel
better.” This is Welch’s maxim; it is the general rule that he was following in this
particular case. The third step would be to universalize this maxim, which means
restating it not just for the individual but for all people (or, as Kant says, for all
rational beings). The universalized maxim would then be: “Whenever anyone angers
any person, that person who is angry will beat the person who caused the anger.” The
fourth step is to assess whether this universalized maxim can be a moral law. If this
inconsistency – then it can be a moral law. This would mean that the original action
performed is not wrong. If, on the other hand, the universalized maxim generates a
contradiction and is thus inconsistent, then the original act performed is wrong and
may not be performed. In the example, a natural result of the universalized maxim is
that there would be a lot of beatings occurring; it is a natural fact that people get angry
from time to time, and so numerous beatings would be expected to follow. When
people get beaten, they often experience anger (among other emotions), and herein
Following from the earlier example, Martell beat Deletha because she made him
angry and he wanted to feel better. Thus, on the one hand, he wants his anger to be
alleviated. The maxim underlying his action, however, generates a world in which
more anger would come about. This would be true for him as well, since the people he
angers would beat him, causing him to experience anger at being beaten. In short, he
is seeking to lessen his anger, and this is straightforwardly inconsistent. Another way
to characterize the situation is to say that Martell is acting on a maxim which, when
universalized would be self-defeating, since it would negate the very goal he is trying
Simply, an act can be said to be morally right in the opinion of Kant based on the
following four basic steps (a) ascertain the individual’s motive; (b) ascertain the
individual’s maxim; (c) universalize the maxim; and (d) assess the universalized
According to Kant “Act so that you treat humanity, whether in your own person or in
the person of any other, always as an end and never as a means only”. In this context,
the difference between means and ends is closely related to the difference between
people and things. An inanimate object-a “thing”-has value only insofar as someone
values it; it does not have value “in itself,” meaning it would have no value at all
without someone to value it. It is therefore permissible to use things as I see fit in
order to accomplish my goals. A computer for example, is a thing and so has no value
in itself. Therefore, since you own your computer, you can use it as a means to your
ends-as a tool for helping you achieve what you want. Treating your computer as a
mere stepping stone in this way does not morally wrong the computer, for it is not the
sort of thing that can be wronged. You can even choose to throw it out the window if
you get frustrated with it (as long as no one outside the window will be injured).
In all these ways, people are different. People do not need to be valued by others in
order to have value. This formulation underscores Kant’s belief that every rational
creature has inherent worth. This worth does not result from any quality other than
the sheer possessing of rationality. Rational human being possesses what Kant termed
an “autonomous self-legislating will.” In other words, they can evaluate their actions,
make rules for themselves, and direct their conduct according to these self-imposed
rules. Kant sums his “categorical imperative” as “one ought never to act unless one is
willing to have the maxim on which one acts to become a universal law”. To Kant
(1959) therefore, good will, and only good will, can be universalized.
Again Kant indicates that you may not treat another person as a mere means. You
may not simply use another person in an effort to further your own goals. People,
unlike computers, are not mere stepping stones and may not be treated as such. This is
Kant’s idea behind the moral command that we are always to treat people as ends and
never as means only; we must always recognize that people are valuable in
themselves (are ends in themselves). He also uses the terminology of respect and
dignity to capture this idea; we are always and everywhere to demonstrate respect for
persons, to recognize the inherent dignity they possess (because of their rational
capacities). Kant also makes clear that this is why all people are moral equals. Each
person is an end in himself or herself to the same degree as all other persons, and so
Nonetheless, duties and principles clearly do inform our views of how people should
treat each other at work. An exclusively consequentialist view of ethics also entails
much larger number. Again, however, we can hardly deny that our assessment of the
likely consequences of different actions plays a part in our view of acceptable and
emphasis on the unit cost savings to be achieved by moving the operation to a lower-
cost area, provided that the required quality of service can be maintained. Other things
being equal, lower unit costs obviously allow higher margins and improved rewards
to shareholders. However, the assessment would also take into account the possibility
Furthermore, this view would also consider the competitive implications of the
decisions: if other suppliers all outsource and reduce their prices to customers, a
decision not to do the same could damage the company. On the other hand, being
particularly if some customers are concerned about reduced quality of service from
off shoring: at one point, NatWest in the UK seemed to take this stance in its
advertising.
A deontological approach to the ethics of off shoring would focus on aspects of the
proposal that might be in breach of clear principles and duties. While no business can
reasonably accept a general duty to keep existing employees on the payroll for ever, a
the impact of the job losses, including the possibility of internal transfer, retraining,
would seek to identify all who would be affected- anywhere in the world – by the
proposed off shoring decision and then assess the impact (positive or negative) on
each person (or, more realistically, group). This would allow a sort of “trial balance”
happiness. Necessarily in this method, the reduction in happiness for others, such as
those who are made involuntarily redundant, is offset by the extra happiness created
for some-those who get offshore jobs, for example. Obviously, this is of little comfort
to the former group, which illustrates one of the important criticisms of the utilitarian
approach.
How, then, are ethical choices to be made by people working for organizations? No
simple and universal answer is available – ethical awareness is something that can be
cultivated and the different perspectives will often help to shed light on a particular
in thinking about how a company should act, it is also clear that duty-based (or ‘moral
compass’) arguments must also weigh heavily in thinking about the ethical treatment
of people such as employees. The German philosopher Kant’s view that we should
always treat other people as ends in themselves and never simply as means is surely
an important principle for decent human resource management and one that would
Personal integrity and individual values are important elements in ethical decision-
codes of conduct may also provide support and guidance. This is not to say that these
ethical ‘resources’ will always provide clear and comfortable guidance – sometimes,
people in organizations will experience tension between conflicting demands of, say,
their own personal values and the demands placed on them by their organization. If
these conflicts become intolerable and cannot be resolved through normal means, then
the high-risk approach of placing the problem in the public domain for resolution.
Code of conduct can help reduce the risk of painful situations like this by providing a
published set of values to which the individual can appeal, rather than taking the risk
wholly personally.
Ethical Reflections
Case 1:
Imagine that you are an office manager in a law firm. Your responsibilities include
scheduling the only two administrative assistants, Tom and Sue. (You must make sure
they do not take the same lunch hour or schedule the same week for vacation, for
example.). Next Monday is a holiday, and you know from past experience with this
holiday that this coming Thursday and Friday will not be busy at all; the lawyers at
this firm like to take this opportunity for an extended weekend. Thus, giving each
administrative assistant an extra day off, one on Thursday and one on Friday, would
cause no problems at all in the firm and would be a nice gesture. But critics of act-
utilitarianism argue that in this sort of example a more detailed analysis is needed.
Imagine that Tom enjoys days off, but only moderately, he might do laundry or catch
up on errands, but the happiness he derives from a day off is limited. Sue, however,
derives much more happiness than Tom when she gets a day off, since she likes to go
to the beach, the mountains, or into the city. So if you are the office manager, do you
necessarily give both Tom and Sue one day off apiece?
Case 2
I imagine you are a doctor. At the moment, you are administering a routine physical
examination, and the patient is in excellent health. Your mind, however, is really on
more troubling matters; there are five patients in the critical care wing of the clinic
who are desperately in need of organ transplants. Acceptable donors have not been
found, and these particular patients are now critical; they do not have much time. As
you are completing the physical exam of the healthy patient, it occurs to you that you
have a certain choice. It would be possible for you to administer a shot to this patient
that would cause him to fall asleep and then die painlessly. (You could tell him it is a
flu shot or some similar standard precaution). Because you are very clever, you could
concoct an injection that would accomplish this task without anyone being able to
discover the true cause of death. The reason for even considering such an act is that
you are an act-utilitarian and you see the possibility of an overall gain in happiness
here. You surmise that it might be possible to take various organs out of the healthy
patient and redistribute them into the five critical patients as needed – a liver, tow
kidneys, a heart, and a lung. Because you want to be sure about the utilitarian
calculations, you quickly do some informal research and learn the following: the
patient’s organ would be excellent matches for the five needy patients (so the
likelihood of successful transplant is very high); the patient has no friends or family to
speak of, as he just moved here from the coast, “to begin with” as he says (so the
unhappiness generated by his death would not be felt by others); each of the five
needy patients has children and other family members and friends (so the unhappiness
generated by the death of each would be felt by many people). Given all of these
circumstances, it seems clear that the overall happiness would be maximized by going
ahead and killing the innocent, healthy patient in order to save the lives of the five
others. After all, there would be a net gain of four lives (four saved, one lost), and
consideration of the effects on the happiness of tangential parties (friends and family)