GARLANDTHOMSON MisfitsFeministMaterialist 2011
GARLANDTHOMSON MisfitsFeministMaterialist 2011
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Cambridge University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Hypatia
ROSEMARIE GARLAND-THOMSON
This article offers the critical concept misfit in an effort to further think through the
lived identity and experience of disability as it is situated in place and time. The idea of
a misfit and the situation of misfitting that I offer here elaborate a materialist feminist
understanding of disability by extending a consideration of how the particularities of
embodiment interact with the environment in its broadest sense, to include both its
spatial and temporal aspects. The interrelated dynamics of fitting and misfitting con
stitute a particular aspect of world-making involved in material-discursive becoming.
The essay makes three arguments: the concept of misfit emphasizes the particularity of
varying lived embodiments and avoids a theoretical generic disabled body; the concept
of misfit clarifies the current feminist critical conversation about universal vulnerabil
ity and dependence; concept of misfitting as a shifting spatial and perpetually
the
This article offers the critical concept misfit in an effort to further think through
the lived identity and experience of disability as it is situated in placeand time.
oppression in this view emanates from prejudicial attitudes that are given form
in the world through architectural barriers, exclusionary institutions and the
unequal distribution and access to resources.1 Similar to the useful distinction
between sex and gender proposed by early feminists such as Gayle Rubin
(1975), the terms impairment and disability distinguish between bodily states or
conditions taken to be impaired, and the social process of disablement that
gives meaning and consequences to those impairments in the world.2 Although
such binaries have limits, shifting disability from an attributed problem in the
body to a problem of social justice was theoretically groundbreaking. The term
and concept misfit contributes to the work of more recent disability theorists,
such as Jackie Leach Scully and Tobin Siebers, who develop accounts of
embodied aspects of disability such as pain and functional limitation without
I propose the term misfit as a new critical keyword that seeks to defamiliarize
and to reframe dominant understandings of disability.^ Fitting and misfitting
denote an encounter in which two things come together in either harmony or
disjunction. When the shape and substance of these two things correspond in
their union, they fit. A misfit, conversely, describes an incongruent relationship
between two things: a square peg in a round hole. The problem with a misfit,
then, inheres not in either of the two things but rather in their juxtaposition,
the awkward attempt to fit them together. When the spatial and temporal
context shifts, so does the fit, and with it meanings and consequences. Misfit
emphasizes context over essence, relation over isolation, mediation over orig
ination. Misfits are inherently unstable rather than fixed, yet they are very real
because they are material rather than linguistic constructions. The discrepancy
between body and world, between that which is expected and that which is,
produces fits and misfits. The utility of the concept of misfit is that it defini
tively lodges injustice and discrimination in the materiality of the world more
than in social attitudes or representational practices, even while it recognizes
their mutually constituting entanglement.6
The theoretical utility of fitting and misfitting comes from its semantic and
grammatical flexibility. Similar to many critical terms, misfit offers layered rich
ness of meaning. According to the Oxford English Dictionary, the verb fit
denotes a relationship of spatial juxtaposition, meaning "to be of such size and
shape as to fill exactly a given space, or conform properly to the contour of its
receptacle or counterpart; to be adjusted or adjustable to a certain position."
Moreover, the action of fitting involves a "proper" or "suitable" relationship
with an environment so as to be "well adapted," "in harmony with," or "sat
what severe but transitory attack (of illness, or of some specified ailment)."
environment that sustains that body. A misfit occurs when the environment
does not sustain the shape and function of the body that enters it. The dyn
amism between body and world that produces fits or misfits comes at the spatial
and temporal points of encounter between dynamic but relatively stable bodies
and environments. The built and arranged space through which we navigate
our lives tends to offer fits to
and functioning and create misfits
majority bodies
with minority forms of embodiment, such as people with disabilities. The point
of civil rights legislation, and the resulting material practices such as universally
designed built spaces and implements, is to enlarge the range of fits by accom
modating the widest possible range of human variation.
cide, and incest. People with disabilities become misfits not just in terms of
social attitudes—as in unfit for service or parenthood—but also in material
ways. Their outcast status is literal when the shape and function of their bodies
comes in conflict with the shape and stuff of the built world. The primary neg
ative effect of misfitting is exclusion from the public sphere—a literal casting
out—and the resulting segregation into domestic spaces or sheltered institu
tions. The disadvantage of disability comes partly from social oppression
encoded in attitudes and practices, but it also comes from the built and
arranged environment. Law or custom can and has produced segregation of
certain groups; misfitting demonstrates how encounters between bodies and
subjectivity. The
performing agent in a misfit materializes not in herself but
rather literally up against the thingness of the world. Misfitting focuses on the
disjunctures that occur in the interactive dynamism of becoming. Perform
ativity theory would rightly suggest, of course, that no smooth fit between body
and world ever exists. Nonetheless, fitting and misfitting occur on a spectrum
that creates consequences. To use the iconic disability access scene of misfitting
as one illustration of those consequences: when a wheelchair user encounters a
Fitting and misfitting are aspects of materialization, as Butler has used the
term, that literally ground discursive constructivism in matter (Butler 1993).
Fitting occurs when a generic body enters a generic world, a world conceptu
alized, designed, and built in anticipation of bodies considered in the dominant
perspective as uniform, standard, majority bodies. In contrast, misfitting
against a stair; someone passes fingers across the brailled elevator button; some
body else waits with a white cane before a voiceless ATM machine; some other
blind user retrieves messages with a screen reader. Each meeting between sub
ject and environment will be a fit or misfit depending on the choreography that
plays out.
Fitting and misfitting extend the concept that shape carries story, an elegant
phrase that I borrow from medieval historian Caroline Walker Bynum (1999).
In considering the philosophical question of continuity in human identity over
time, Bynum draws from her personal experience of observing her father's long
term progressive dementia. Perhaps unknowingly, Bynum asks a disability the
ory question about how we can maintain a continuous sense of self as our
bodies change over time. Her response expresses an inherent and mutually
constitutive relationship between body and narrative, between nature and cul
ity; the shifting of our shapes knits one moment to the next and one place to
A good enough fit produces material anonymity, a version of the visual ano
unrecognized being in
way ofthe world, a way that Harvey Sacks calls "doing
being ordinary" (1984). Such a phenomenology yields the privilege or social
capital conferred by accessing spaces, performing tasks, and establishing rela
tions that enable one to exercise the rights of citizenship in democratic orders.
Linda Martin Alcoff s 2006 account of identity formation, Visible Identities,
corresponds with my concept of misfitting in that it is relational, experiential,
and contingent. How look at each
we look, other, Alcoff insists, deter
and
mines in large part howour way through the world and how we treat
we make
one another.9 Like misfitting, Alcoff's version of identity formation as "a per
ceptual habit" (Alcoff 2006, 188) fuses a materialist with a constructivist
theory of identity formation. As with fitting and misfitting, Alcoff's version of
identity is discursive-material. That is, identity is at once performative and
narrative, emerging as particular material bodies interact in particular social
locations and moments. Identity, for Alcoff, does not reside in visible features
but emerges from shared, dominant interpretations of "visual markers on the
body" (6). This perception of identity is a "learned ability" that is context
dependent, complex, and fluid (187). Alcoff suggests that we are called into
subjectivity through an exchange of mutual recognition, which may of course
often be misrecognition. Misfitting adds to this primarily perceptual field
stronger elements of materiality; our bodies move, meet, negotiate, and come
into direct contact with the built and natural worlds. The degree to which that
shared material world sustains the particularities of our embodied life at any
given moment or place determines our fit or misfit. Our particular embodi
ments are as unchosen as the narratives of our identities upon which
Alcoff focuses. Identities are narratives accessed through visual perceptions
for Alcoff; fitting and misfitting are largely tactical navigations through space
and time. Both these visual and tactile relations make up the process of
not choose our particularities, but as Alcoff reminds us, the meaning and the
changing the shape of our bodies. People with quadriplegia, for example,
should be provided with sustaining environments that allow them to partici
pate fully as equal citizens rather than urging them toward normalization
through medical scientific cure. Deaf people, similarly, should not be made
high-tech hearing aids but rather should have access to communication with
both the hearing and the deaf through sign language and other forms of non
verbal communication that create a fit between them and their world. Alcoff
aims to mute identity or reshape our bodies in order to achieve
not social jus
tice, but rather to "make identities more visible" in order to transform their
meanings so that they provide their bearers with a coherent and positive nar
and properly into the world, we forget the truth of contingency because the
world sustains us. When we experience misfitting and recognize that dis
juncture for its political potential, we expose the relational component and the
fragility of fitting. Any of us can fit here today and misfit there tomorrow.
In this sense, the experience of misfitting can produce subjugated know
much of the disability rights movement grew from solidarity born of misfitting.
Even the canonical protest practices of disability rights, such as groups of
wheelchair users throwing themselves out of chairs and crawling up the stairs
of public buildings, act out a misfitting.10 So whereas the benefit of fitting is
material and visual anonymity, the cost of fitting is perhaps complacency about
status and value accordingly.11 Our bodies and our stories about them reach
toward tractable states called normal in medical-scientific discourses, average in
consumer capitalism, ordinary in colloquial idiom, and progressive in develop
mental accounts.12
Although misfit is associated with disability and arises from disability theory,
its critical application extends beyond disability as a cultural category and
social identity toward a universalizing of misfitting as a contingent and funda
mental fact of human embodiment. In this way, the concept of misfitting can
enter the critical conversation on embodiment that involves the issues of con
tingency and instability. These concepts have been thoughtfully elaborated
recently within feminist theory under the terms dependence and vulnerability.
Such concepts allow us to put embodied life at the center of our understanding
of sociopolitical relations and structures, subject formation, felt and ascribed
Western culture (Fineman 2005; 2008). The concepts of misfitting and fitting
guarantee that we recognize that bodies are always situated in and dependent
upon environments through which they materialize as fitting or misfitting.
Vulnerability is a way to describe the potential for misfitting to which all
human beings are subject. The flux inherent in the fitting relation underscores
that vulnerability lies not simply in our neediness and fragility but in how and
vulnerability theory, Fineman argues that the fact of embodiment creates uni
versal vulnerability and defines dependency as the need in all human beings for
care. Although the ethics of care has been a concern in feminist theory for a
number of years, Fineman moves the conversation toward politics and law by
arguing for responsibility for dependency
collective and mitigating the social
nerability lies in the fact that we all need to eat, be sheltered, and be comforted;
Butler's vulnerability lies in the fact that we must grieve and die. Aloneness
contingency of human existence is the basis of human rights for Turner. The
derstands as ontological
contingency is the fragility of the material
body, its
vulnerability to wounding, injury, pain, suffering, dying. The concept of rights
accorded equally to all humans regardless of their particularity that Turner
finds central to his theory is exemplified in the first comprehensive human
rights treaty of the twenty-first century, which is the United Nations' Con
vention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities and its Optional Protocol,
treaty's language implies that the misfit between "persons with impairments"
and an unsustaining environment made up of "barriers" materializes our in
herent vulnerability.
The relational and contingent quality of misfitting and fitting, then, places
vulnerability in the fit, not in the body. This concept also accounts for the
body and world is rangier than this. A misfit occurs when world fails flesh in the
environment one encounters—whether it is a flight of stairs, a boardroom full
of misogynists, an illness or injury, a whites-only country club, subzero temper
atures, or a natural disaster.
A theory of fitting and misfitting includes, then, the premise of universal
vulnerability, but it has the virtue of expanding the conversation from the
threat of what Fineman calls "the ever-present possibility of harm, injury, and
misfortune from mildly adverse to catastrophically devastating events"
(Fineman 2008, 25). Our enfleshment certainly makes us mortal, open to loss,
and exposed to suffering. But our bodies are also the agents of our lived expe
rience and subjectivity. An embodied engagement with world is in fact life
itself.
have occurred. To misfit into the public sphere is to be denied full citizenship.
The aspirational goal of creating a universally sustaining environment would
position from which, a progressive politics might arise. The form, function,
comportment, and sensory modes of human bodies inform the ways we interact
with human, built, and natural environments. This interaction between self
and world can produce politically liberatory, material effects. Such "epistemic
significance" Cherri'e Moraga calls "theory in the flesh" (quoted in Moya 2000,
sociologists call one's achieved and ascribed identities (Alcoff 2000, 337).
Such politicized potential results from the dissonance between what I call felt
and attributed identity, the jolt of what W. E. B. Dubois terms "double con
sciousness" (Dubois 2008, 6). Misfit moves this idea of dissonance from
epistemology into phenomenology.
her body. And someone whose body does the configuration of a key
not fit
board will not turn out text in the same way that ten nimble fingers produce. In
other words, inequality occurs not purely from prejudicial attitudes but is an
A Bioethics of Resourcefulness
The most pressing question for a feminist materialist disability theory is devel
access to those rights, at the same time advanced technologies such as medical
normalization and pre- and post-embryonic eugenic selections work toward
eliminating the particularities of embodiment we think of as disability. Misfits
who fall into varied devalued social categories have been purged through forms
of eugenic eradication such as the European Holocaust, American lynching,
the prison-industrial complex, and coercive
heteronormativity.
This paradoxical but virulent cultural mandate to expunge disability has
been countered over the last thirty years by civil and human rights initiatives
such as the United Nations Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabil
ities, the Americans with Disabilities Act, and other similar national
legislation. The misfitting that would exclude people with disabilities from the
world is also countered by the kind of positive
identity politics in a postpositive
(Scully 2008, 128). Misfits are the agents of these strategies through the process
of misfitting.
Misfits can also be agents of recognition who by the very act of misfitting
engage in challenging and rearranging environments to accommodate their en
trance to and participation in public life as equal citizens. Attending to the
dynamics of misfitting and fitting urges us to cultivate the rich particularity that
makes up embodied human diversity. Although modernity presses us relentlessly
toward corporeal other forms of standardization, the human body in fact
and
varies greatly in its forms and functions. Our experience of living eventually
contradicts our collective fantasy that the body is stable, predictable, or con
trollable, creating misfits for all of us. What we call disability is unavoidable,
insistent in its misfitting. Our conventional
response to disability is to change
the person through medical technology, rather than changing the environment
to accommodate the widest possible range of human form and function. The
concept of misfitting shifts this model. The body is dynamic, constantly inter
acting with history and environment; sometimes it fits and at other points or
moments, it does not. We evolve into what we call disability as our lives de
velop. The misfits that constitute the lived experience of disability in its
broadest sense is perhaps, then, the essential characteristic of being human.
Rather extirpating disability to achieve
than fits in the world, we should
attend to
processes of fitting and misfitting to which we are all vulnerable in the
interest of accommodating and ultimately valuing disability in its broadest
sense as a form of human variation. First of several reasons is that we might see
might accept that fact. Third, we might better approach social justice by inte
grating disability into our knowledge of human experience and history and
integrating disabled people into our societies. Fourth, we might more fully rec
ognize interdependence rather than independence by becoming more aware
that all people rely on one another for life tasks and survival. Fifth, we might
response to paralysis. The philosopher Jiirgen Habermas recently wrote that the
experience of having a cleft palate and the accompanying multiple surgeries
positively shaped his intellectual development (Habermas 2004).
The resourcefulness and adaptability that can emerge from the interactive
dynamism between world and body I've named here as misfitting answers
Wendy Brown's proposal that our politics should not focus on what we are but
what we want (Brown 1993). To get what we want, it is not necessary to sac
rifice identity or identity politics as Brown suggests, to frame identity as a
"wounded attachment." The critical concept of misfitting emphasizes location
rather than being, the relational rather than the essential. Understanding
identity as a set of variable fits and misfits, a potentially productive fusion of
coincidence and disparity between particularity and the material status
one's
Notes
1. See, for example, Davis 1995; Wendell 19%; Thomas 1999. For an overview of
these arguments, see Barnes, Barton, and Oliver 2002.
16. See Habermas 1991 and Arendt 1998 on the political significance of the pub
lic sphere.
17. The complex question of the relationship between reproductive freedom and
eugenic discrimination is a topic I cannot fully address here but only gesture toward. For
fuller discussions, see Saxton 1998; Parens and Asch 2000; and Scully 2008. I have
argued for conserving disability as a form of biodiversity in "Welcoming the Unbidden:
The Case Conserving Human Biodiversity" (Garland-Thomson
for 2005).
18. This is what Maria Lugones calls "world traveling" (1987).
References
Alcoff, Linda Martin. 2000. Who's afraid of identity politics? In Reclaiming identities:
Realist theory and the predicament of the postmodern, ed. Paula M. L. Moya and
Michael R. Hames-Garci'a. Berkeley: University of California Press.
. 2006. Visible identities: Race, gender, and the self. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Arendt, Hannah. 1998. The human condition. 2nd edition. Chicago: University of Chi
cago Press.
Barad, Karen Michelle. 2007. Meeting the universe halfway: Quantum physics and the en
tanglement of matter and meaning. Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press.
. 2008. Post-humanist performativity: Toward an understanding of how matter
comes to matter. In Material feminisms, ed. Stacy Alaimo and Susan Hekman
Indiana University Press.
Barnes, Colin, Len Barton, and Mike Oliver. 2002. Disability studies today. Cambridge,
UK: Polity Press.
. 2004. Precarious life: The powers of mourning and violence. London: Verso.
Bynum, Caroline Walker. 1999. National Endowment for the Humanities Jefferson
Lecture in the Humanities, March 22. Washington, D.C. http://www.neh.gov/
news/archive/19990322b.html (accessed February 9, 2011).
Canguilhem, George. 1991. The normal and the pathological. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press.
Clare, Eli. 1999. Exile and pride: Disability, queemess, and liberation. Cambridge, Mass.:
South End Press.
Collins, Patricia Hill. 2000. Black feminist thought: Knowledge, consciousness, and the pol
itics of empowerment. New York: Routledge.
Davis, Lennard J. 1995. Enforcing normalcy: Disability, deafness, and the body. London:
Verso.
Dubois, W. E. B. 2008. The souls of black folk. Radford, Va.: Wilder Publications.
Fausto-Sterling, Anne. 2000. Sexing the body: Gender politics and the construction of
Habermas, Jurgen. 1991. The structural transformation of the public sphere: An inquiry into a
category of bourgeois society. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
. 2004- Public space and political public sphere: The biographical roots of two
motifs in my thought. Commemorative lecture. Kyoto, Nov. 11. http://home
page.mac.com/gedavis/JH/Kyoto_lecture_Nov_2004.pdf (accessed February 9, 2011).
Hacking, Ian. 1990. The taming of chance. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Haraway, Donna. 2003. The Haraway reader. New York: Routledge.
Harding, Sandra. 1986. The instability of the analytical categories of feminist theory.
Signs: Journal of Women and Culture in Society 11 (4): 645-64.
Keller, Evelyn Fox. 2002. The century of the gene. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
Press.
Kittay, Eva Feder. 1999. Love's labor: Essays on women, equality, and dependency. New
York: Routledge.
Linton, Simi. 1998. Claiming disability: Knowledge and identity. New York: New York
University Press.
Lugones, Maria. 1987. Playfulness, "world"-traveling, and loving perception. Hypatia 2
(2): 3-20.
McRuer, Robert. 2006. Crip theory. New York: New York University Press.
Miller, William Ian. 1997. The anatomy of disgust. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
Press.
Mitchell, David, and Sharon Snyder. 2006. Cultural bcations of disability. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Mohanty, Satya. 2000. The epistemic status of cultural identity: On Beloved and the
postcolonial condition. In Reclaiming identities: Realist theory and the predicament of
the postmodern, ed. Paula M. L. Moya and Michael R. Hames-Garci'a. Berkeley:
University of California Press.
Moya, Paula. 2000. Postmodernism, "realism," and the politics of identity: Cherrfe
Moraga and Chicana feminism. In Reclaiming identities: Realist theory and the predic
ament of the postmodern, ed. Paula M. L. Moya and Michael R. Hames-Garcia.
Berkeley: University of California Press.
Nussbaum, Martha. 2006. Frontiers of justice: Disability, nationality, species membership.
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Parens, Erik, and Adrienne Asch. 2000. Prenatal testing and disability rights. Washington,
D.C.: Georgetown University Press.
Rich, Adrienne. 1986. Notes toward a politics of location. In Blood, bread, and poetry:
Selected prose 1979-1985. London: Little Brown and Company.
Rubin, Gayle. 1975. The traffic in women: Notes on the "political economy" of sex. In
Toward an Anthropology of Women, ed. Rayna R. Reiter. New York: New York
Monthly Review Press.
Sacks, Harvey. 1984. On doing "being ordinary." In Structures of social action: Studies in
conversation analysis, ed. J. M. Atkinson and J. Heritage. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Saxton, Marsha. 1998. Disability rights and selective abortion. In Abortion wars: A half
century of struggle (1950-2000), ed. Ricky Solinger. Berkeley: University of
California Press.
Schweik, Susan. 2009. The ugly laws. New York: New York University Press.
Scully, Jackie Leach. 2008. Disability bioethics: Moral bodies, moral difference. New York:
Rowman and Littlefield.
Shapiro, Joseph. 1993. No pity: People with disabilities forging a new civil rights movement.
New York: Times Books/Random House.
Siebers, Tobin. 2008. Disability theory. Ann Arbor, Mich.: University of Michigan
Press.
Thomas, Carol. 1999. Defining disability: The social model. In Female forms: Experienc
ing and understanding disability. Buckingham, UK: Open University Press.
Turner, Bryan S. 2006. Vulnerability and human rights. University Park: Penn State
University Press.
United Nations convention on the rights of persons with disabilities. http://www.
un.org/disabilities/default.asp?id=260 (accessed February 10, 2011).
Warner, Michael. 2000. The trouble with normal. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
Press.
Wendell, Susan. 1996. The rejected body: Feminist philosophical reflections on disability.
New York: Routledge.
Wilson, Elizabeth. 2004. Gut feminism, differences: A Journal of Feminist Cultural Studies
15 (3): 66-94.